Theft
Theft
The offence contains five elements, each of which must be proved by the
prosecution. The first five comprise the actus reus:
(i) There must be property (i.e. something capable of being stolen)
(ii) That property must belong to another
(iii) D must appropriate the property
The final two elements comprise the mens rea:
(iv) D must intend permanently to deprive another person of the property,
and
(v) D must act dishonestly.
Section 3: ‘Appropriates’
(1) Any assumption by a person of the rights of an owner
amounts to an appropriation, and this includes where he has
come by the property (innocently or not) without stealing it, any
later assumption of a right to it by keeping or dealing with it as
owner.
(2) Where the property or a right or interest in property is or
purports to be transferred for value to a person acting in good
faith, no later assumption by him of rights which he believed
himself to be acquiring shall, by reason of any defect in the
transferor’s title, amount to theft of the property.
The act of appropriation gives you possession, which you intend to
maintain.
You can come by a property honestly in the first instance and later
appropriate it. You can appropriate it after initial honest taking.
An exception to that is: if you pay money for it and you subsequently find
out someone else has a better claim to it, and the seller had no right it sell
it to you; to keep the property then is not theft.
Appropriation = an assumption of the rights of the owner. That was
intended to mean something more narrow than merely coming by and
receiving property. E.g. if he gives one of us a watch, that should rule out
(leaving aside honesty) any finding of assumption of the right of the
owner on our part, because you have not assumed anything, you have
just taken or received what you were given. In 1968, theft was originally
conceived as theft on its face. Notion of assumption involves something
unauthorised, which the owner had not consented to.
This concept of assumption was argued in the case of R v Morris.
THEFT
Theft is defined in s1 of the Theft Act 1968.Further provisions flesh out the
general definition. To commit theft D must dishonestly appropriate
property belonging to V intending to deprive V of his property
permanently. Most instances of theft are straightforward, but some
complex issues can arise when ascertaining whether D has stolen V’s
property.
It was held that here that D was assuming just one of the rights of the
owner, not the entirety of the owner’s rights: here the right to price the
goods.
It was sufficient to do that provided the D meant/intended at that time to
physically acquire the goods by some subsequent act. This is a crucially
important decision. The conduct, which on the facts is preliminary to the
act of theft – becomes the act of theft in its own right.
Restrained the appropriation to true assumptions, but broadened the act
to things prior to the act of taking goods themselves.
This was the first extension of actus reus.
There is one limiting feature: the decision is merely hard to defend and
not indefensible - this was the fact that a voidable title and not a perfectly
valid title for all the time that it was conferred on D. Surely it can never be
the case that when a person acquires a completely valid title, he can steal
by the very act through which he acquired that ownership – that is a
genuine oxymoron: valid owner/and by the same token can steal the
property. This was put to the test in Hinks.
Lawrence v Metropolitan Police Commissioner [1972] AC 626
D, a taxi driver, drove a newly arrived foreign student with little English
from Victoria station to an address in London. The student had offered a
£1 note for the fare, which D said was not enough before extracting a
further £6 from the student’s open wallet. In truth the legally authorised
fare for the journey was approximately 50 pence. Although the student
had permitted D to take the excess money, the House of Lords upheld D’s
conviction for theft. The student’s consent was irrelevant.
“That there was appropriation in this case is clear. Section 3(1) state that
any assumption by a person of the property rights of an owner amounts to
an appropriation. Here there was clearly such an assumption…[an
appropriation may occur even though the owner has permitted or
consented to the property being taken”.
Once the goods are appropriated they cannot be stolen again by the same
person. Appropriation is a preliminary act and can continue until it is
made complete and constitutes an act of theft. It continues until the act of
possession is effected. In Morris it was made complete as soon as label
was switched. Once this stage is reached, appropriation is over.
Property
It can take tangible or intangible forms.
The Theft Act 1968 section 4 brings all forms of property within the
purview of theft although there are restrictions imposed on the ambit of
theft in relation to land, wild plants and wild creatures. The property
appropriated may take an intangible form such as the appropriation by D
of the credit balance in V’s bank account. Appropriations of intangible
property merit special discussion.
Intangible property
Bank accounts
What first of all is the property in a bank account?
V is a company who has the account in question. As we speak that bank
account is in credit to the tune of £10,000. The company does not own
any money. “Money in the bank” is a complete misnomer. What the
company has when it is reduced to its essence, is the right to sue the
bank for the value of £10,000 should the bank rely on its contract to its
customers. It is that right to sue the bank that is the intangible property,
which can be stolen.
The same applies to overdrafts. Lets assume V Ltd is overdrawn by
£2000 but has an agreed overdraft to the value of £10,000. V Ltd owns
property to £8000 in the form of the right to enforce this overdraft
agreement. If V has suffered through the fraudulent machinations of D
and ends up as a consequence more indebted to its own bank than would
otherwise have been the case, nonetheless there would be no theft
against V unless V had a credit balance or the theft diminished his agreed
overdraft facility.
The logic is clear: if D has drawn check on V’s accounts in a dishonest
way, but it simply takes V past his overdraft limit without making the best
of a bad job, it would still enforce the debt. To the bank there will have
been no theft on the power of D because he would have acquired no
property.
On the other hand, and in defence of the current law, it may be argued
that by pretending to deal with V’s bank account, D ‘assumed’ the right of
an owner over the account and therefore appropriated it within section
3(1). Moreover, V will still normally suffer the disadvantage of a wrongful
debit against their account, which will remain in place, and cause an
effective loss to V, until the forgery is discovered (if ever). So, although
the law on this point is problematic, it is not without justification.
The analysis is different where the check is not a nullity. Chan Man-sin
may be contrasted with Kohn where D had the authority to draw
cheques. He abused that authority by withdrawing money for personal
gain. In that case, the cheques were valid and not mere forgeries, so that
the company’s bank account was rightfully debited. Thus D was
properly convicted of theft from the company by appropriating its
bank account.
Confidential information
When does information become property?
Effectively only when it can be patented or if it falls under a copyright or it
is information of a kind that be trained (?). There is an important strand of
equitable authority that has extended the legal conception of proprietary
information to cover information received by a trustee or person in the
position of a trustee where that information has economic value –
industrial espionage.
Outside patents, copyrights and trademarks and confidential information
of economic value acquired by person in position of trust, the criminal law
has rightly refuse any invitation to regard unauthorised accessing of
information (computer hacking offences etc) by hackers as acquisition of
property.
The divisional court dismissed the prosecution’s case and stated that it is
not property stolen under the Theft Act. There was no extrapolation of
theft in this delicate area of access to information. Civil law should be
given that area and not criminal law.
Significance: mere information, even a trade secret does not qualify for
protection as intangible property.
Policy argument: extending the law of theft to include appropriation of
information raises difficult questions concerning the property scope of
protection. Should all confidential information be protected, or just trade
secrets? When is information sufficiently confidential? What if the
information is a matter of public interest?
BELONGING TO ANOTHER
Property belongs to you in terms of section 5(1) not merely if you are the
owner of the property but it also extends to rights of possession and
control i.e. those rights, which may be enjoyed by persons who are not the
owner of the property.
It must still be the case, that if you have come by property honestly and
you are the owner then any subsequent dishonesty in relation to property,
which reconfirms its retention cannot be regarded as an act of theft.
Beatson and Simester, “Stealing One’s Own Property” (1999) 115 LQR
372; Bogg and Stanton-Ife “Protecting the Vulnerable: Legality, Harm and
Theft” (2003) 23 Legal Studies 402.
On the other had, where the premises are open to the public, the
occupier’s position is weaker and she gains prior title only if she has (b)
manifested an intention to exercise control over the things that are or
might be on the premises. In Parker v British Airways Board [1982]
the Court of Appeal held that Parker’s rights as finder could be displaced
only if British Airways could show as occupiers an obvious intention to
exercise such control over the lounge and things in it that the bracelet
was in their possession before the claimant found it. On the evidence
there was no manifestation of such an intention as would give the
defendants a right superior to that of the claimant; the airline’s instruction
to staff for dealing with lost articles were not published to users of the
lounge, and it did not carry out searches for lost articles.
Equitable Interests
The Theft Act 1968 s5 (3) provides for situations where D receives money
(or other valuables) from V under an obligation to V to deal with the
money in a particular way. Even if the effect of the transfer of money from
V to D is to make D the legal and equitable owner of the money at civil
law, if s5 (3) applies the money can still be stolen by D.
Whilst the mistake in this case was of the same type as that in Moynes v
Coopper, no legal obligation to make repayment arose in Gilks because
the overpayment was in virtue of a wager. Thus Gilks would not fall within
the ambit of section 5(4).
Although the decision in Moynes was much criticised at the time, its
undoing by section 5(4) seems something of an overreaction. The
defendant in Moynes is a mere debtor, section 5(4) effectively makes
personal liability the stuff of debt. This surely, is the misuse of the concept
of theft.
Dishonesty
This is only partially defined in the act.
The willingness to pay is immaterial, you can still be guilty of theft. Often
a willingness to pay precludes dishonesty, but sometimes it does not.
A person’s appropriation of property belonging to another is not to be
regarded as dishonest -
Section 2 deals with three situations where a person is not to be found
dishonest:
(a) if he appropriates the property in the belief that he has in law the right
to deprive the other of it, on behalf of himself, or on behalf of another
person
If he or she has a belief in their right to take the property and that means
the term is entirely subjective. Maybe your belief is wrong and you have
no right, but if you believe that you have a claim of right, then taking it is
not theft.
This makes Hinks even harder to follow: Hinks had a right to the
property in civil law, if she had gone to a lawyer to see where she stands
and had been told that she could keep, and she believed him/her, it was
not theft. If she had a positive belief that she was entitled to it she could
not be found dishonest for the law of theft.
(b) If he appropriates the property in the belief that he would have the
other’s consent if the other knew of the appropriation and the
circumstances of it.
If D believes that V would consent to the taking had he been aware of it.
This is belief in consent, however, ill founded. Hinks, had the consent of V.
He did hand over his money with consent, which makes the decision
stranger, because presumably she did not apply her mind to the matter
and just took the money.
This was corrected in Ghosh; the guidance in Ghosh was in two parts.
1. An entirely objective evaluation for the jury against the facts of the
case. They asked themselves: ‘was this conduct dishonest according to
normal community standards? Would ordinary members of the community
(not saints/sinners) do the same?’
… If they come to the conclusion that it was not dishonest, the case falls
then and you do not get to the second stage. If they find that the conduct
was dishonest by the standards of ordinary people, the next question is…
The Ghosh test has been criticised, but helps with Article 7 compliance.
Ghosh test has advantages in terms of compliance with Article 7 that a
person will only be convicted of theft in a contested case, if she is on
notice that her conduct is dishonest.
Griew, “Dishonestly – the objections to Feely and Ghosh” [1985] Crim LR
341; Elliot “Dishonestly in theft: A dispensable concept” [1982] Crim LR
395; Halpin, “The Test for Dishonesty” [1996] Crim LR 283.
Conditional intention
Easom [1971] 2 QB 315
Question was whether there was intention to deprive, as there is
appropriation.
D and V are in the cinema and they do not know each other. A seat is
unoccupied between them. On the unoccupied seat is a handbag
belonging to V who is a policewoman and the handbag is attached by a
cord to her little finger. Sure enough D picks up the handbag, opens the
handbag and has a rummage through it and it did not contain anything
that D wanted. There was no money or a credit card, so he has his
rummage and puts the handbag back and is then promptly arrested by
policewoman and charged with theft.
Was there an intention to deprive permanently of the property in that
case?
It was held that there was no intention to deprive at this point. The
intention has not coalesced around an object that he wants to keep. He
has theft on his mind, but has not made up his mind to steal a particular
object at this point. Is it attempted theft? No, that does not work either
because you need a particular object; it cannot be abstract.
Many burglars go into property to see if there is anything worth stealing.
The definition of burglary is entering property as a trespasser with the
intention to steal. One of the seeming ramifications of Easom, was that a
burglar does not have the intention to steal, because he lacked an intent
to deprive permanently. It would have many effects if this were the case.
On the facts of Easom: there was no intent to deprive, and the conviction
was quashed.
The Court of Appeal quashed his conviction ruling that: ‘if the
appropriator has it in mind merely to deprive the owner of such of his
property as, on examination, proves worth taking and then, finding that
the booty is valueless to the appropriator leaves it ready to hand to be
repossessed by the owner, the appropriator has not stolen’.
The decision is probably right, but only in terms of the precise charge of
stealing ‘the purse, notebook etc...inside the handbag’ that was brought.
D certainly appropriated those items. However, at no time did D intend to
deprive the owner of such things. He was looking for something else.
What he intended was to permanently deprive the owner of whatever he
found of value. The general view is that the defendant could have been
convicted if eth charge had been carefully drafted. If had been charged
with theft of the contents of the handbag he could have been convicted
on the basis that he intended to deprive the victim of the contents (if he
found them valuable). To avoid any possible difficulties an attempted theft
charge may be best in cases of this kind.
The charge should have been intending to steal some or all of the
contents of a bag. That way they do not charge him with theft of a specific
item he did not want, instead land a fish and charge him with theft of
some or all the contents of a bag. Does that solve the Easom problem?
See A-G’s Ref (Nos 1 and 2 of 1979) [1980]
This was a worry in the case of a burglary in A-G’s Ref (Nos 1 and 2 of
1979) [1980]. It was this case that resolved the issue: it was stated in
terms that, the persons entering property with intent to steal anything
inside worth stealing were guilty of burglary for the purposes of the law of
burglary, a conditional intent would suffice. This case suggested that as
the law stands it would be better if D were convicted of theft of the
contents.
Often a thief has no particular agenda regarding the fate of the property
he steals. If D means to pawn the stolen goods, or to use them before
discarding them, he may not intend that the original owner be
permanently deprived, sometimes it may be quite likely that the owner
will recover the property. In order to make it explicitly that the act
extends to such cases, Parliament enacted section 6.
The better view of this section (there are two schools of thought – it is an
unresolved issue): the taking must in substance deprive the item of its
value, prior to the point of physical restoration. Only then, you are
treating the thing as your own to dispose of regardless of another’s rights.
You have effectively deprived it of any value. This is not made out
correctly in case of Lloyd.
The Theft Act 1968 s6 provides that in certain circumstances D will in law
have an intention to deprive V permanently of a particular object even if
he intends at some point to restore the object to V or anticipates that it
will be restored by some other means. The terms of s6 allow ample scope
for interpretation. There are appellate decisions, which read s6 narrowly
but other decisions take a wider approach.
Contrast this with the wider view has been taken in Chan Man-Sin,
Lavender and Marshall. They hold that the moment you treat the thing as
your own i.e. make use of it peculiar to the owner, you by law under terms
of section 6, intend to deprive permanently.
Compared with the narrow reading in Mitchell section 6(1) does say,
inter alia, that a defendant is ‘to be regarded as having the intention of
permanently depriving the other of it if his intention is to trat the thins as
his own to dispose of regardless of the other’s rights’. Although the word
‘dispose of’ can read in a narrow sense, as meaning to ‘get rid of for once
and for all’, it can also be read in a wide sense, to mean ‘to deal with’. And
there are cases where the courts have taken it in the wider sense, thereby
converting into theft acts by defendants who did not really mean for the
owner to lose his property rights at all.
The Divisional Court ruled that D had committed theft. Although the
council had not in fact been deprived of the doors, D had nonetheless
‘disposed’ of them within the meaning of section 6(1). With respect, this
result seems odd. There was no disposal of the doors in the narrow sense
– they were not thrown out, destroyed or sold. They were merely moved
and there was not suggestion by his conduct that D intended to treat
them as his own, since they continued o be affixed to council property.
Another case to take this line was Marshall [1998] 2 Cr App R 28. In
this case, D had been making money in the London underground by
begging unexpired day tickets from passengers who had completed their
last journeys of the day and reselling them to other passengers. For this D
was convicted of theft of the tickets from London transport, which had
issued them. On appeal, he sought to argue that, as he knew the tickets
would eventually find their way back to London Transport at the end of
the day, he had no intention permanently to deprive. Rejecting the narrow
construction that was put on section 6 in Lloyd, the Court of Appeal
upheld the conviction.
The Courts have also taken a broad view of section 6 when dealing with
those who have improperly interfered with other people’s bank accounts.
In Chan Man-Sin [1988], discussed earlier, D dishonestly drew cheques
on his employer’s bank account. The Privy Council ruled that D had dealt
with the company’s property (i.e. its chose-in-action against the bank) as
if it were his to dispose of without regard of the company’s rights. But if
unauthorised drawings of this sort are a nullity, then arguably D did not
disposed of this account at all. At law nothing done by D in any way
affected the relationship between the company and the bank. D merely
tricked the bank into crediting D’s own account (and purporting to debit
V’s account). The Privy Council seems to have equated ‘purporting or
pretending’ to dispose of the thing as one’s own with ‘disposing of the
thing as one’s own’. The decision is debatable. Nonetheless, as things
stand, this is the law: the intent to make and apparent to pretended
disposal is sufficient for section 6(1).
What can be said with some degree of certainty is that section 6(1) covers
both the ‘ransom principle’ and the ‘essential quality’ principle, by which
the courts extended the concept of intention to permanently deprive
before 1968. An example of the first is Raphael, where D’s conviction for
theft was affirmed where he had taken V’s car away from him by force
and then attempted to sell it back to him. And an example of the second
is DPP v J, in which the defendants forcibly took V’s headphones,
snapped them, and returned them to V. On appeal, it was held that the
magistrates had been wrong to accept a submission of no case to answer:
a person who took something and dealt with it for the purpose of
rendering it useless demonstrated the intention of treating that article as
his own to dispose of. But a definitive answer to the question of how much
other ground(if any) the section covers is obscure, and destined to remain
so until the day –if it comes – that the matter is finally resolved by the
Supreme Court.