Really Distinguishing Essence From Esse
Really Distinguishing Essence From Esse
Really Distinguishing Essence From Esse
Volume 6
Also available in the series:
Volume 1: The Immateriality of the Human Mind, the Semantics of Analogy, and
the Conceivability of God
Edited by
Volume 6
Medieval Skepticism, and the Claim to Metaphysical Knowledge
Volume 6: Proceedings of the Society for Medieval Logic and Metaphysics,
Edited by Gyula Klima and Alexander W. Hall
All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system,
or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or
otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner.
Introduction ................................................................................................. 1
Alexander W. Hall
Contributors............................................................................................. 163
REALLY DISTINGUISHING
ESSENCE FROM ESSE*
DAVID TWETTEN
*
The author and editor would like to thank The Catholic University of America
Press for permission to reprint “Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse,” which
appears in Wisdom’s Apprentice: Thomistic Essays in Honor of Lawrence Dewan,
O.P., ed. Peter A. Kwasniewski (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of
America Press, 2007), 40-84.
1
Baruch Brody, “Why Settle for Anything Less than Good Old-Fashioned
Aristotelian Essentialism?” Nous 7 (1973): 351-64; Gyula Klima, “Contemporary
‘Essentialism’ vs. Aristotelian Essentialism,” in Mind, Metaphysics, and Value in
the Thomistic and Analytic Traditions, ed. J. Haldane (Notre Dame, 2002), 175-94.
Klima is quick to observe that a metaphysical theory of essence will have to be
accompanied by revised theories of predication and semantics. See Gyula Klima,
“The Changing Role of Entia Rationis in Medieval Philosophy: A Comparative
Study with a Reconstruction,” Synthese 96 (1993): 25-59; Gyula Klima, “Ontological
Alternatives vs. Alternative Semantics in Medieval Philosophy,” European
Journal for Semiotic Studies, 3 (1991): 587-618. For a defense of Realism, see
Michael Jubien, Contemporary Metaphysics: An Introduction (Oxford, 1997).
80 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
substantial forms. I wish to consider one such dispute, that over the ‘real
distinction’ between essence and esse,2 most famously ascribed to Thomas
2
When speaking of Aquinas, I normally retain the Latin term esse rather than use a
translation or paraphrase such as “being,” “existence,” “act of existence,” or “act of
being,” each of which, though defensible, is destined to raise objections where
there should be none. In this practice, I intend esse not in every sense, but in one of
the four significations distinguished by Aquinas following Aristotle; see Thomas
Aquinas, Scriptum super libros Sententiarum [=Sent.], ed. P. Mandonnet and M.
Moos (Paris, 1929-1947), 1, d. 33.1.1 ad 1 (quoted below in n. 94); Aquinas, In
duodecim libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis expositio [=In Met.], ed. M.-R.
Cathala, R. Spiazzi (Turin-Rome, 1950), 5.7, lect. 9. According to this
signification, esse, as the verbal noun corresponding to est just as running (currere)
corresponds to runs (currit), signifies an act, “that by which it is said [of
something] that it is” (Questiones de quolibet [=Quodl.] 9.4.1c, ll. 117-121, in
Aquinas, Opera omnia: iussu impensaque, Leonis XIII. P.M. edita [Rome, 1882-],
vol. 25; Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles [=SCG], ed. C. Pera et al. (Turin-
Rome, 1961), 2.54, n. 3 [Secundo autem]), or “. . . that it is in act” (Sent. 1, d.
8.1.1c; Sent. 2, d. 3.1.1c); “the act of an existing x insofar as it is a being” (Sent. 1
d. 19.2.2c); “that by which [x] subsists in the nature of things” (Aquinas, De ente et
essentia 4, ll. 163-64, in Opera omnia, vol. 43) or “by which each thing formally
is” (De ente 5, ll. 27-28); “that which first falls in the intellect through the mode of
actuality absolutely speaking; since ‘est’ said simply signifies actually to be, . . .
[signifies] the actuality of every form” (Aquinas, Expositio libri Peryermenias [=In
Peryerm.] 1.3, lect. 5, ll. 393-399, in Opera omnia, vol. 1.1*). Esse, then, pertains
to the question ‘whether x is’ and is not an essential predicate of a thing; Aquinas,
Quaestio disputata de spiritualibus creaturis [=QDSC] 8 ad 3, ll. 340-349, in
Opera omnia, vol. 24.2. As a result, “that which has esse is rendered an actually
existing thing;” Quaestiones disputatae de potentia Dei [=QDDP] 7.2 ad 9, in
Aquinas, Quaestiones disputatae, ed. P. Bazzi et al. (Turin-Rome, 1953), vol. 2.
As some of these texts indicate, Aquinas at times uses ‘existens’ or ‘existentia’ as
synonymous with this signification of ‘ens’ or ‘esse’; see also, for example,
Aquinas, Quaestiones disputatae de veritate [=QDDV] 1.2 ad 3, in Opera omnia,
vol. 22; SCG 2.84, n. 17 (Secundo quia); Aquinas, In librum beati Dionysii De
divinis nominibus expositio, ed. C. Pera (Turin-Rome, 1950), 2 (73-75), lect. 6, nn.
216-18; c. 4 (188), lect. 14, nn. 474-475; c. 5 (284), lect. 3, nn. 669-73; c. 6 (286-
287), lect. 1, nn. 678-79; In Peryerm. 1.6 (17a26-29), lect. 9, ll. 63-70; In Met. 7.17
(1041a27-32), lect. 17, nn. 11, 13-14 (1658, 1660-1661); In De generatione et
corruptione 1.2, lect. 4, n. 4 (29), in Aquinas, In Aristotelis libros De caelo et
mundo, De generatione et corruptione, Meteorologicorum expositio, ed. R. Spiazzi
(Turin-Rome, 1952). Nevertheless, since in many contemporary contexts, ‘exists’
and ‘existence’ have a debased sense, I shall use, where possible, ‘is’ and ‘to be’ to
translate est’ and ‘esse’; or, I shall use ‘actually to be’ to specify this one among
the four senses of ‘to be’. For the purposes of this paper, it remains an open
question whether ‘esse as the act of all acts, perfection of all perfections’ (QDDP
David Twetten 81
7.2 ad 9) signifies more than ‘the act and perfection by which all other features—
whether logically or really other—are or have esse’.
3
I use the terminology ‘real distinction’ between ‘essence and esse’ (=‘Real
Distinction’) as familiar labels. Aquinas speaks literally only of a “real diversity”
or “real composition” (Sent. 1, d. 13.1.3c; QDDV 27.1 ad 8), although he also says
that esse “differs in reality” (differt re) from that of which it is the act (Sent. 1,
d. 9.2.2c); that esse and ‘that which is’ “really differ” (differunt realiter) or are
“really other” (aliud realiter), as opposed to that which “differs in conception”
(differunt secundum intentiones) or to that which is “really one and the same”
(unum et idem realiter); Thomas Aquinas, Expositio libri Boetii De ebdomadibus
[=In De ebdom.] 2, ll. 198-220, in Opera omnia, vol. 50.2. Cf. Joseph Owens,
“Aquinas’ Distinction at De ente et essentia 4.119-123,” Mediaeval Studies 48
(1986): 264-87, at 266-73; Cornelio Fabro, “Circa la divisione dell’essere in atto e
potenza secondo San Tommaso,” in Esegesi tomistica (Rome, 1969), 109-36;
Cornelio Fabro, “Neotomismo e neosuarezismo: una battaglia di Principi,” ibid.
137-278, at 190-97. Some, of course, claim that Aquinas affirms only a conceptual
distinction; see Francis Cunningham, Essence and Existence in Thomism: A
Mental vs. “the Real Distinction”? (Lanham, MD, 1988). Aquinas does not hold
that esse and essence are two subsisting things as if we should then ask with Giles
of Rome, Can God cause one to be without the other? But ‘something’, ‘thing’ and
‘real’ for him are terms that transcend the categories, as does ‘being’; cf. Sent. 1, d.
8.5.1-2; Sent. 2, d. 37.1.1c; QDDV 1.1c, ll. 129-150. I take ‘real’ in ‘real
distinction’ to mean ‘in the nature of things’, prior to an act of the mind (without
necessarily being separable in reality). Ultimately it would be preferable to speak
of a ‘real distinction between the individual substance (or supposit) and its esse’;
cf. SCG 2.52-54; Quodl. 2.2.1c, ll. 73-76; 2.2.2c, ad 1-2, ll. 93-102, 145-149, 154-
158. Yet, even when Aquinas makes such precisions he also speaks of a
“composition of essence and esse;” cf. Quodl. 2.2.1, ll. 5-12, 73-76; 2.2.2c, ll. 99-
100.
4
Cf. thinkers as disparate as Henry Leonard, “The Logic of Existence,”
Philosophical Studies 7.4 (1956): 49-64; J. L. Mackie, “The Riddle of Existence,”
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 50 (1976): 247-67; Peter
Geach, God and the Soul (Oxford, 1981), 65-74; Gareth Evans, The Varieties of
Reference, ed. J. McDowell (Oxford, 1982), 345-48; William L. Craig, “Is
Presentness a Property?,” American Philosophical Quarterly 34.1 (1997): 27-40;
Barry Miller, The Fullness of Being: A New Paradigm for Existence (Notre Dame,
2002).
82 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
5
For a contemporary defense, see James Ross, “The Fate of the Analysts:
Aristotle’s Revenge,” Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical
Association 64 (1990): 51-74.
David Twetten 83
In Aquinas’ judgment, the real problem with this argument is that it begs
the question.6 Most contemporary critics attack Steps (1) through (3),
whereas Aquinas concedes that it is possible to think of TTW, and that if
TTW is thought, it exists in the mind.7 For him, the problem lies in Step
(4). The contradiction derived there, that TTW is not TTW, results only if
one has already assumed:
As Aquinas puts it, that TTW is not TTW is no problem for one for whom
there is no TTW in reality in the first place. That a centaur is not a centaur,
we may say, or that a square-circle is not a square-circle is of no
consequence outside logic. For Aquinas, then, the conclusion that either
TTW exists in reality or it is not TTW depends on the question-begging
assumption that there is in reality a TTW in the first place.
6
SCG 1.11, n. 2 (Nec oportet): “[N]on enim inconveniens est quolibet dato vel in
re vel in intellectu aliquid maius cogitari posse, nisi ei qui concedit esse aliquid
quo maius cogitari non possit in rerum natura.” See also Sent. 1, d. 3.2 ad 4; ST
I.2.1 ad 2.
7
Aquinas’ concession of Step (3) is only implicit. But in one place he apparently
concedes what in any case one must concede who grants Steps (1) through (3): that
if TTW is thought, it cannot consistently be thought not to exist, and so must be
thought to exist. Still, it follows not that it exists in reality but only that while
thought, it must be thought to exist in reality. See Thomas Aquinas, Lectura
romana in primum Sententiarum Petri Lombardi, ed. L. E. Boyle, OP, and J. F.
Boyle (Toronto, 2006), d. 3.1 ad 2. On this reading, just as only if TTW is thought
does it follow that either it must be thought to exist in reality or it is not truly TTW
in thought; so only if TTW exists in reality does it follow that either it must exist in
reality or else it is not truly TTW, but only TTW in thought.
8
Aristotle in Metaphysics Z.17 famously identifies individual essence or to ti ēn
einai with a substance’s form. Aquinas ascribes to Aristotle, based on Metaphysics
H.1-2, 6, the doctrine that essence includes both form and matter. Aquinas takes
the conclusions of Metaphysics Z to be provisional insofar as the investigation is
preliminary to that of Book H; see In Met. 8.1, lect. 1, n. 1 (1681); Lawrence
84 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
of the mind, the act of judgment. Hence, that things are is not reducible to
the conceptualizable principles of form and matter.
10
For this acknowledgment (not this reaction), see Joseph Owens, “Aquinas on
Being and Thing,” in Thomistic Papers, vol. 3, ed. L. Kennedy (Houston, 1987), 3-
24, at 10-13; cf. also n. 36 below. For Owens, existence as known through
judgment prior to the Real Distinction is not esse as actuality or perfection, which
is conceptualizable, but is the composing or synthesizing of matter and form or
substance and accident reflected in the (non-propositional) ‘judgment’ that ‘x is’—
a judgment that is always temporally simultaneous with, though naturally prior to,
conceptualization; Joseph Owens, “Aquinas on Knowing Existence,” Review of
Metaphysics 29 (1976): 670-90, at 678, 681-2; Joseph Owens, “Judgment and
Truth in Aquinas,” in Owens, St. Thomas Aquinas on the Existence of God:
Collected Papers of Joseph Owens, C.Ss.R., ed. J. Catan (Albany, 1980), 34-51, at
35, 43-44, reprinted from Mediaeval Studies 32 (1970): 138-58; Joseph Owens, An
Elementary Christian Metaphysics (Milwaukee, 1963), 47-55, 73-75; Joseph
Owens, Cognition: An Epistemological Inquiry (Houston, 1992), 168-70, 181, 192-
96.
86 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
11
For the charge developed in this paragraph, see especially Hans Meyer, in
Thomas von Aquin: Sein System und seine geistesgeschichtliche Stellung, 2nd ed.
(Paderborn, 1961), 103, 120-26, 131-33.
12
See especially the work of Richard C. Taylor, “Aquinas, the Plotiniana Arabica,
and the Metaphysics of Being and Actuality,” Journal of the History of Ideas 59
(1998): 217-39.
13
See especially Alain De Libera, “Albert le Grand et Thomas d’Aquin interprètes
du Liber de causis,” Revue des sciences philosophiques et théologiques 74 (1990):
347-78.
14
Cf., for example, Anton Pegis, “St. Thomas and the Origin of Creation,” in
Philosophy and the Modern Mind (Detroit, 1961), 49-65.
15
For a contrast of Aristotle and Aquinas, see Armand Maurer, “Form and Essence
in the Philosophy of St. Thomas,” in Being and Knowing: Studies in Thomas
Aquinas and Late Medieval Philosophy (Toronto, 1990), 3-18.
David Twetten 87
The De ente presents the fullest version of a form of argument that stands
on its own in at least one other place, in Aquinas’ early Scriptum on
16
They themselves are indebted to, among others, Norbertus del Prado, De veritate
fundamentali philosophiae christianae (Freiburg/CH, 1911), 23-70; M.-D. Roland-
Gosselin, Le “De ente et essentia” de S. Thomas d’Aquin (Paris, 1926; repr. 1948),
187-89; Joseph De Finance, Être et agir dans la philosophie de saint Thomas
(Rome, 1960), 94-107.
17
Three arguments are both distinguished and united, for example, in Cornelio
Fabro, “Un itinéraire de saint Thomas: L’Établissement de la distinction réelle
entre essence et existence,” in Esegesi tomistica, 89-108, at 94, 99, reprinted from
Revue de Philosophie 39 (1939): 285-310; Cornelio Fabro, La nozione metafisica
di partecipazione secondo S. Tommaso d’Aquino, 2nd ed. (Turin, 1950), 218-19.
88 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
(2) Hence, [if such a feature belongs to a thing,] it must enter into
composition with it [as really distinct from it, whether the feature
is caused by the essence itself or] comes to it from without.19
(4) Therefore, the ‘to be’ of an essence [that exists] enters into
composition with it as [really] distinct from it.
There are a number of problems with this argument, some of which can be
resolved. Here I am interested only in the Question-Begging Objection.
The argument proceeds from the absence of our knowledge of ‘to be’ or
esse in knowing essences to the presence of esse as really distinct from
essence. But the argument presupposes that esse is something that must
belong to the essence of a thing in order that it be. Esse as act of an
essence is assumed to be part of our ontology. Consequently, the absence
from an essence of its esse leaves that essence nonexistent. Thus, there is a
tacit Step (5) between Steps (3) and (4) that may be spelled out thus:
18
Aquinas, De ente 4, ll. 94-103; Sent. 2, d. 1.1.1c; Sent. 2, d. 3.1.1c (for this
passage as a “God to Creatures Argument,” see below, n. 45). In three other early
passages, though not again after 1260, Aquinas employs in a comparable way the
principle that esse is not found in the understanding of a thing. See Sent. 1, d. 8.3.3
expos.; Sent. 1, d. 8.4.2c; QDDV 10.12c, ll. 174-178.
19
For this step, see De ente 4, ll. 94-96, 127-130. The De ente makes no distinction
between Steps (1) and (2); I have added material in brackets to bring out the
argument, on the assumption, again, that a Real Distinction is intended.
David Twetten 89
(5) ‘To be’ (esse) is a feature that must belong to essences in order
that they be.
The Aristotelian objector, however, denies Step (5). For the Aristotelian, it
is not the case that things exist because of a ‘to be’ that, in the words of De
ente 4, ‘belongs to’, ‘comes to from without’, ‘enters into composition
with’, or ‘is received by’ essence and that thereby actualizes that essence
so as to be. ‘To be’ for material things is simply for form to actualize
matter. For an essence to have its constituent parts is for it to be. The
Aristotelian, then, can explain one’s ignorance of ‘to be’ in knowing
essence merely by appealing to individual matter. Knowing what a
whooping crane is does not tell me whether one is, because individual
material instances are not known in knowing essences. Whether there are
whooping cranes is known only by perceiving individual instances of that
species. One need not affirm a really distinct ‘to be’ to explain the
difference between knowing a species and perceiving its instances. As a
result, the Aristotelian’s ontology is sparser here than the Thomist’s,
requiring only form, matter, and the relevant acts of knowing universals
and particulars.
Most interpreters agree that the First Stage of De ente 4 fails to establish a
real distinction between essence and esse. John Wippel is well known for
his vigorous defense of the Second Stage,20 and he has recently isolated
and identified the argument of this Stage as a distinct form of argument for
the Real Distinction.21 On at least six other occasions, four in mature
20
John Wippel, Metaphysical Themes in St. Thomas Aquinas (Washington, 1984),
107-32; see also Scott MacDonald, “The Esse/Essentia Argument in Aquinas’s De
ente et essentia,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 22 (1984): 157-72.
21
John Wippel, The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas: From Finite Being
to Uncreated Being (Washington, 2000), 137, 143, 150-57. For the Second Stage
as an independent argument, cf. Fabro, “Un itinéraire,” 97-99; La nozione
metafisica, 219, 221. Wippel groups under this category six instances of the “God
to Creatures Argument” as categorized by Leo Sweeney, “Existence/Essence in
Thomas Aquinas’s Early Writings,” Proceedings of the American Catholic
Philosophical Association 37 (1963): 97-131. Although four of these affirm God as
actually existing, not as a mere hypothesis as in the De ente, the logic of their
argument, based on the uniqueness of subsistent esse, does not require this
affirmation, as Wippel observes (Metaphysical Thought, 136-37, 151-55, 585); for
their reasoning, see below, nn. 41-44. Nevertheless, I include in the “Hypothetical
90 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
(1) Suppose that there is something in which esse (‘to be’) is not
other than essence, but whose essence is its own esse.22
a. This would be ‘esse itself’,23 that is, subsisting esse,24
which is not received in another, but is ‘esse alone’ (esse
tantum).25
b. Such a thing cannot participate in anything else; for, esse
is the ultimate act, which is participable by all but does
not itself participate in anything else.26
Essence That Is Esse Argument” only those seven passages that actually proceed
without the explicit affirmation of God’s actual existence. In fact, of the nearly
twenty instances of the “God to Creatures Argument” that can claim to be
complete (besides De ente 4), most have a similar argumentative structure to that
of arguments based on the mere hypothesis of God. And, all but one argue from
the fact that nothing but God can be its own esse, or esse itself. Even where this is
not explicitly defended within the argument, in most cases it could be taken to have
been previously established systematically within the work in question. In other
words, if any instance of the “God to Creatures Argument” that employs the actual
existence of God should be grouped with the Second Stage of De ente 4, a good
case could be made that nearly all of them should be so grouped. Yet, the “God to
Creatures” approach is well attested in Aquinas and is worth retaining as a distinct
mode of arguing, a point that I develop below, in Section II.K.
22
Aquinas, De ente 4, ll. 103-126, specifically ll. 103-114; cf. Sent. 1, d. 8.5.2c;
Thomas Aquinas, In octo libros Physicorum Aristotelis expositio [=In
Phys.], ed. P. M. Maggiòlo (Turin-Rome, 1950), 8.10, lect. 21, n. 13 (1153).
23
In Phys. 8.10, lect. 21, n. 13 (1153); In De ebdom. 2, ll. 216-258, specifically ll.
218-220. The latter passage forms an integral part of an argument that I present
separately below, in Section II.E.
24
De ente 4, l. 115; In Phys. 8.10, lect. 21, n. 13 (1153); SCG 2.52, n. 5 (Item. Si).
25
De ente 4, ll. 114-117. It needs to be explained why esse could not be merely
one conceptually distinct feature of a first essence even though not a really distinct
feature; this feature could be unique to it, ‘its own’. In other words, why must an
existing essence in which there is no Real Distinction be identical to esse itself? It
also needs to be explained whether identifying an essence with ‘its own esse’ is a
necessary and/or sufficient step prior to identifying an essence with ‘esse itself’.
Cf. Sent. 2, d. 3.1.1c: “Alia autem natura invenitur de cujus ratione est ipsum suum
esse, immo ipsum esse est sua natura.”
26
Thomas Aquinas, Quaestiones disputatae de anima [=QDDA] 6 ad 2, ll. 268-
277, in Opera omnia, vol. 24.1. Cf. also In De ebdom. 2, ll. 85-102, 249-251. This
David Twetten 91
(2) All other things are distinct from this hypothetical being.
a. For, something either is or is not its own esse, esse
itself.27
i. But if there is something that is not its own
esse, it must acquire its esse from another;
hence, in itself it is possible with respect to
esse.28
b. Also, there could be only one thing that is its own esse.
i. For, it could not remain ‘esse alone’ and be
pluralized in any conceivable way of
pluralizing, such as by adding a differentia, or
by being received in some subject, such as in
matter.29
ii. Also, it would be similar to a separate form,
which would be unique.30
iii. Also, subsistent esse must be infinite and
therefore unique.31
c. Also, to be caused belongs to other things but cannot
belong to subsistent esse. Otherwise, to be caused would
step, just as Step (3.a), below, n. 33, forms a “Hypothetical Essence That Is Esse
Argument through Participation,” an argument that in QDDA 6 ad 2 does not
expressly use uniqueness. For this form of argument, cf. below, nn. 48-49, and
below, Sections II.H-J.
27
Sent. 1, d. 8.5.2c; In De ebdom. 2, ll. 219-220, 249-251; In Phys. 8.10, lect. 21,
n. 13 (1153). The argument in these passages based on Step (2.a) can be called the
“Hypothetical Essence That Is Esse Argument through Disjunction,” which is
completed by Step (2.a.i), (2.b.ii), or (3.a).
28
Sent. 1, d. 8.5.2c. For what Aquinas regards as Avicennian reasoning from
‘being caused’ to the Real Distinction, see below, n. 73.
29
De ente 4, ll. 105-121; In De ebdom. 2, ll. 249-258. In these passages together
with those in the following two notes is found the “Hypothetical Essence That Is
Esse Argument through Uniqueness,” comprising Steps (1) and/or (1.a), and (2.b),
perhaps together with Steps (2.a) or (3.b). For this form of argument, cf. below, nn.
41-42.
30
Thomas Aquinas, Super Librum de causis expositio [=In LDC], ed. H. D. Saffrey
(Louvain, 1954), 4, pp. 29.27-30.30, at 29.27-30; In Phys. 8.10, lect. 21, n. 13
(1153); cf. De ente 4, ll. 110-113. For this step, cf. below, n. 43.
31
In LDC 4, p. 30.18-20. This step is completed by Step (3.b). For this form of
argument, cf. below, n. 44.
92 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
Or, even were one to grant subsistent ‘to be’, why affirm in Step (3) that
all other things also have ‘to be’ in the sense required; namely, as an
actuality over and above what they are? Why not say that such things are
judged to be, but that to account for this judgment one need not affirm in
reality any feature other than their essence?35 Even if there were a
32
SCG 2.52, n. 5 (Item. Si). The argument of this passage, constituted by Steps
(1.a) and (2.c), is singular in Aquinas’ corpus, a “Hypothetical Essence That Is
Esse Argument through Causality,” relying on neither uniqueness nor
Participation. For other arguments through causality, see below, Section II.G and
n. 73.
33
In LDC 4, p. 30.2-8, 28-29; In De ebdom. 2, ll. 234-250; cf. In Phys. 8.10, lect.
21, n. 13 (1153). This step is implicit in QDDA 6 ad 2. Cf. above, n. 26.
34
In LDC 4, p. 30.18-30. This step is the completion of Step (2.b.iii); cf. above, n.
31.
35
Cf. Daniel Utrecht, “Esse Means Existence,” in Saints and Scholars: Studies in
Honor of Frederick D. Wilhelmsen, ed. R. A. Herrera, et al. (New York, 1993), 87-
94, at 87: “It is one thing to say that something exists. It is something else to say
David Twetten 93
subsistent ‘to be’, then, that ‘to be’ would not compete with other things
whose ‘to be’ is likewise taken to be indistinct from their essence; for,
such things ‘have to be’ only in the sense that their essence is judged to be
instantiated. Thus, the Aristotelian can insist that ‘to be’ is simply for there
to be form instantiated in matter—and that Thomist esse is nowhere in the
picture. Joseph Owens has leveled a similar objection against Wippel’s
reading of this Second Stage: “Nothing has been introduced to show that
existing adds a positive content of its own over and above the quidditative
content of the thing.”36 Without ‘to be’ in the picture as an ontological
component, the objector is not compelled to draw the consequence that
there can be only one instance of what lacks a composition of essence and
esse. Instead, for the objector, all things lack this composition.
that it exists because it ‘has’ something called esse actuating it. . . . The Thomist
needs to show how he knows there is such an act.”
36
Owens, “Aquinas’ Distinction,” 282. Of course, Owens’ point is a different one:
he rejects the Second Stage only because, for him, it operates with a concept of
esse, not with esse grasped in judgment, and its reasoning ends as it begins with
purely mental distinctions; see Joseph Owens, “Stages and Distinction in De ente:
A Rejoinder,” The Thomist 45 (1981): 99-123, at 108-10, 114-21. Only after the
esse that is grasped in judgment is known to exist as a nature as in the Third Stage
is it possible to establish the Real Distinction. Nonetheless, the reasoning of the
Third Stage relies on that of the Second; ibid. 109; Elementary Christian
Metaphysics, 101 (although it could also use the infinity of pure being, as in ibid.
103, 106-8). And, Owens sees the first two stages as part of one continuous
argument for the Real Distinction; ibid. 68-71, 77-82, 101-8; “Aquinas’
Distinction,” 276, 281, 286. In fact, according to Owens, each of the two Stages
could be separated out and taken as concluding to the Real Distinction after it is
known that God exists whose being is a nature; Joseph Owens, “Quiddity and Real
Distinction in St Thomas Aquinas,” Mediaeval Studies 27 (1965): 1-22, at 19.
37
Owens, Elementary Christian Metaphysics, 71-75, 101-8, 351; for the Third
Stage as an independent argument, cf. also Fabro, “Un itinéraire,” 104; La nozione
metafisica, 220. Owens’ reading of the Third Stage, as beginning only with a
94 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
(1) As is shown elsewhere, something exists that is its own ‘to be’ or
esse, that is esse itself or esse subsistens.38
a. God alone is such a thing.39
conceptual distinction between a thing and its being, faces the interpretative
problem that the reasoning in De ente 4 appears to involve the reception of real
esse from another. If, as is true, an argument could be mounted without such
reasoning, that argument would still have to address the Question-Begging
Objection, as must any “God to Creatures Argument.” In other words, what entitles
one to infer from the judgment that God exists to the fact that God’s esse is a
nature? Precisely at this point esse as an ontological act is introduced. Why is not
God understood merely as pure form, which is judged to exist without introducing
any further ontological components? The Third Stage at this point runs the risk of
arguing from a mental operation to reality in a way that Owens himself has sharply
criticized; see Joseph Bobik, “Some Disputable Points Apropos of St. Thomas and
Metaphysics,” New Scholasticism 37 (1963): 411-30, at 425.
38
All instances of the “God to Creatures Argument” have some version of this
step, affirming one or more of these designations of God—whether through proof
or not. ‘Subsisting esse’ by itself in Aquinas, Quodl. 12.4.1c, ll. 16-26 (1272)
grounds a distinct version of the “God to Creatures Argument;” see below, n. 49.
On the classification of arguments using something whose essence is esse, see
above, n. 21.
39
Apart from the aforementioned Quodl. 12.4.1c, all instances of the “God to
Creatures Argument” use some version of Step (1.a), which affirms divine
David Twetten 95
(2) But other beings exist, whose essence is not esse itself.45
a. For, there is a plurality of other beings,46 whose esse is
received, contracted to what receives it, and as a result is
limited.47
b. Also, when some feature, in this case, esse, belongs to
something according to its own nature, it belongs to all
others only by participation.48
44
This step together with some version of Step (2.a) forms the “God to Creatures
Argument through the Uniqueness of Infinite Esse,” used in SCG 2.52, n. 4 (Adhuc.
Impossibile); QDSC 1c, ll. 357-408. For this argumentation, cf. above, n. 31.
45
All instances of the “God to Creatures Argument” use Step (2), but some argue
simply through it and Step (1.a) alone: Sent. 1, d. 8.5.1c; Quodl. 7.3.2c (1256);
Quodl. 9.4.1c, ll. 115-121 (1257); SCG 2.52, n. 7 (Item. Cum); cf. ST I.47.1. This I
call the “God to Creatures Argument Simplified.” One “God to Creatures
Argument” is unique, defending Step (2) by means of the “Understanding of
Essence Argument:” Sent. 2, d. 3.1.1c. Hence, I do not introduce it here as a
special form of the “God to Creatures Argument,” but instead I refer the reader to
Section II.A above. This passage, just as Sent. 2, d. 1.1.1c, uses reasoning of both
the First and Third Stages of De ente 4—although the two passages use different
parts of the Third Stage: the passage from Distinction 1 argues for the existence of
subsistent esse, whereas that from Distinction 3 offers proof that all things other
than God, including angels, have essence really distinct from esse.
46
This point is barely made explicit, but is used by all of the passages that reason
through Step (1.b); see above, nn. 41-44. The conclusion of the Third Stage in De
ente 4 reasons thus (especially on Owens’ interpretation), relying on the conclusion
of the Second Stage; see De ente 4, ll. 121-126; 143-145.
47
Quodl. 7.1.1 ad 1, ll. 143-159; QDSC 1c, ll. 357-408.
48
This step, together with Step (1.a) forms the “God to Creatures Argument
through Participation,” whose purest form is found in SCG 2.52, n. 8 (Amplius.
Ipsum); see also Thomas Aquinas, Expositio libri Posteriorum 2.7 (92b8-11), lect.
6, ll. 43-50, in Opera omnia 1.2*; cf. Sent. 2, d. 16.1.1 ad 3; Sent. 2, d. 37.1.2c; In
Phys 8.10, lect. 21, n. 14 (1154); and especially In De ebdom. 2, ll. 234-250,
recorded in Step (3.b) in Section II.E, below, where participation in esse is
ascribed to any determinate form, including Aristotle’s separate substances, as a
condition for its distinction from other things. In other places, the argument is
formed with some version of Step (1.b), using uniqueness; hence I call it the “God
to Creatures Argument through Uniqueness and Participation:” in fact,
participation is defended in this version almost exclusively as an alternative to the
uniqueness of subsistent esse. This argument is found in CT I.68, ll. 18-30; ST
I.44.1c; De malo 16.3c, ll. 164-174; De sep. sub. 9, ll. 102-118; and Quodl. 3.8c, ll.
37-48; cf. SCG 2.15, n. 5 (Item. Quod). The same argument is found in one
“Hypothetical Essence that is Esse Argument:” In Phys 8.10, lect. 21, n. 13 (1153).
David Twetten 97
But even if one admits Thomist esse in Step (1), is it necessary to affirm
Thomist esse in Step (3)? Grant, according to Step (2), that other beings
exist whose essence is not esse itself. How does it follow that they are not
mere essence, but that they also have a really distinct esse? In two versions
of the “God to Creatures Argument,” Aquinas even adds a step between
Steps (2) and (3):
For arguments through Participation, see above, n. 26, and below, sections II.H-J,
in addition to the following note.
49
Quodl. 12.4.1c, ll. 16-26. This step forms a “God to Creatures Argument” that
does not use divine otherness or uniqueness, but is completed, instead, only by
Steps (1) and (3.b). The resulting argument, distinct from the one identified in the
previous note, is a “God to Creatures Argument through Participation and
Becoming.” On this argument, see Lawrence Dewan, “St. Thomas and the
Distinction between Form and Esse in Caused Things,” Gregorianum 80 (1999):
353-70. For similar reasoning, cf. above, n. 40.
50
Step (3.a.i) is found in Quodl. 7.3.2, ll. 24-35; and 9.4.1, ll. 115-121; Step (3.a.ii)
is found in Sent. 1, d. 8.5.1c; whereas many passages witness both (a) and (b):
Sent. 2, d. 3.1.1c; De ente 4, ll. 147-166 (Third Stage); De sep. sub. 8, ll. 164-187;
Quodl. 3.8c, ll. 37-48.
51
Participation in the “God to Creatures Argument” may be a consequence of
rather than a means to establishing the Real Distinction, as for Step (2.b): QDSC
1c, ll. 357-408; cf. In LDC 4, pp. 29.27-30.18-30.
52
Sweeney, “Existence/Essence in Aquinas’s Early Writings,” 130.
98 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
The Aristotelian rejects Step (4) in Aquinas’ sense: there is no ‘to be’ or
esse as a component to be had. That esse is a component of reality to be
possessed must be proved and not merely assumed. A similar difficulty
arises for the version of the “God to Creatures Argument” that uses
Participation: does it not presuppose that esse is a component of things that
is really distinct from essence or substance? Only if so is it necessary to
affirm a distinct participation in esse as opposed to a thing’s participation
in substance.
(1) [Every essence, with one possible exception, has at least one
genus that is predicated essentially of it (namely, its ultimate
category), and there is no real distinction between an essence and
its genus.]55
53
De sub. sep. 8, ll. 183-184: “Omne autem quod est esse habet;” Quodl. 12.4.1c,
ll. 23-26: “Unde esse est completiuum omnis forme, quia . . . habet esse cum est
actu; et sic nulla forma est nisi per esse.” See also the quotation below, in n. 65;
and SCG 1.22, n. 9: “Amplius. Omnis res est per hoc quod habet esse.”
54
Sent. 1, d. 8.4.2c; De ente 5, ll. 5-14; QDDV 27.1 ad 8; ST I.3.5c. The other three
passages are CT 1.14, ll. 12-19; SCG 1.25, n. 4 (Item. Quidquid); QDDP 7.3c. Cf.
the allusion in Sent. 2, d. 3.1.1 ad 1; Thomas Aquinas, Super Boetium De trinitate
6.3c, ll. 133-137, in Opera omnia, vol. 50.
55
A step of this kind is presupposed in Aquinas’ reasoning.
David Twetten 99
But as it first appears in the argument, esse may signify nothing more than a
particular actually existing member of a generic or specific class, that is, a
particular concrete existent. One cannot yet assume what remains to be
proved, i.e., that esse already signifies an act principle which is really
distinct from the essence principle of each particular substance.58
56
De ente 5, ll. 10-13; SCG 1.25; ST I.3.5c.
57
QDDP 7.3c; De ente 5, ll. 13-14.
58
Wippel, Metaphysical Thought, 161.
100 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
59
Fabro, La nozione metafisica, 217, 222, 243-44. According to Fabro,
Participation is used in a fully systematic way in Aquinas’ arguments for the Real
Distinction only in the mature works, such as in the last argument of SCG 2.52
(ibid. 217, 221); yet, this use represents not a new argument, but merely a
modification of earlier arguments (ibid. 243; but cf. below, nn. 67, 88). Only in
later writings, however, does Fabro take up the apparent consequence that
Aquinas’ Exposition of Boethius’ De hebdomadibus, as opponents of the Real
Distinction have charged, is itself marked by Avicenna’s ‘extrinsicist’, dynamic
causal reasoning (ibid. 217, 222, 227). As Fabro later observes, the Exposition
evidences the logical and formal character of Boethius’ non-intensive notion of
esse, and we see Aquinas there actually contradicting his own metaphysics, for
example, in agreeing with Boethius that “esse is not yet;” Cornelio Fabro, “La
problematica dello esse tomistico,” in Fabro, Tomismo e pensiero moderno (Rome,
1969), 103-33, at 104-8, reprinted from Aquinas 2.2 (1959): 194-225; Cornelio
Fabro, Participation et causalité selon S. Thomas d’Aquin (Louvain, 1961), 268-
80.
60
For these versions, see above, n. 48.
61
Aquinas, In De ebdom. 2, ll. 48-63, 114-146, 204-212.
David Twetten 101
Aquinas explicitly draws attention to the fact that the early stages of this
argument, as he discovers it in Boethius, conclude merely to a conceptual
distinction between esse and essence, not to a real distinction (ll. 36-39,
198-220). For, the early stages focus on properties of language, on the
‘modes of signifying’ of words and concepts. ‘Esse’ (‘to be’) unlike ‘that
which is’, says Thomas, signifies in an abstract rather than in a concrete
mode; ‘esse’ signifies as ‘that by which’ rather than ‘that which’, and as a
formal part rather than as a subject whole.63 Accordingly, we do not say
that ‘to run’ (currere) runs or that ‘to be’ (esse) is, but ‘what runs’ (id
quod currit siue currens) runs and ‘that which is’ (ens siue id quod est) is.
Similarly, we do not say that a human is humanity or that ‘that which is’ is
‘to be’ or esse itself. It follows that ‘to be’ is conceptually distinct from
‘that which is’, although not that it is really distinct, observes Thomas.
At the same time, Aquinas believes that his argument establishes a Real
Distinction merely by introducing ontological components in place of ‘that
62
In De ebdom. 2, ll. 206, 209, 212-213.
63
In De ebdom. 2, ll. 39-45, 48-65, 87-102, 116-146.
102 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
(1) All things [except one] must have ‘to be’ (esse) that is finite.65
a. [For, only one thing can be ‘to be’ itself.]
64
Wippel, Metaphysical Themes, 157-61; Metaphysical Thought, 170-76; yet the
argument was previously identified by Battista Mondin, St. Thomas Aquinas’
Philosophy in the Commentary to the Sentences (The Hague, 1975), 52. See also
Giles of Rome, Theoremata de esse et essentia, ed. E. Hocedez (Louvain, 1930), V
and XX, 24.21-25.18, 141.16-142.16. The argument was recognized by
renaissance scholastics as central to Aquinas’ exposition; see Cajetan, In De ente et
essentia D. Thomae Aquinatis commentaria, ed. M.-H. Laurent (Turin, 1934), 5, q.
12, n. 100.
65
“Omnis creatura habet esse finitum;” Aquinas, Sent. 1, d. 8.5.1 sc. See also
above, n. 53. I modify Step (1) and add Step (1.a) to show that the reasoning as
such does not depend on the actual existence of God. It is evident, in any case, that
all bodies are finite.
David Twetten 103
(2) But ‘to be’ that is not received in something subsists as absolute
and infinite.66
a. For, as is true of any form, ‘to be’ is of itself common,
so that it is limited only by being received in some
subject.67
(3) Therefore, ‘to be’ must be received in something other than it so
as to limit it.68
(4) Or, therefore, ‘to be’ must be limited by something other than it
that is in some way its cause [formal].69
(5) [Consequently, ‘to be’ and the essence that receives and limits it
are really distinct.]
66
Sent. 1, d. 8.5.1 sc; SCG 1.43, n. 8 (Amplius. Ipsum). Cf. also n. 44 above.
67
See Sent. 1, d. 8.2.1c: “[E]sse enim recipitur in aliquo secundum modum ipsius,
et ideo terminatur, sicut et quaelibet alia forma, quae de se communis est, et
secundum quod recipitur in aliquo, terminatur ad illud; et hoc modo solum
divinum esse non est terminatum, quia non est receptum in aliquo, quod sit
diversum ab eo. . . . [I]llud enim in quo non est esse absolutum, sed terminatum per
recipiens, non habet esse perfectum sed illud solum quod est suum esse: et per hoc
dividitur esse aeternum ab esse rerum immobilium creatarum, quae habent esse
participatum, sicut spirituales creaturae.” Cf. also ST I.7.1c; I.7.2c. Notice that
Fabro grounds his own résumé of the “Participation (Mode of) Argument” on the
finitude of all created substance; see above, n. 59; Fabro, La nozione metafisica,
243-44; cf. also Cornelio Fabro, “Sviluppo, significato e valore della ‘IV via’,” in
Esegesi tomistica, 351-85, at 366-69, reprinted from Doctor Communis 1-2 (1954):
71-109. In fact, Fabro’s exposition of esse as act in which all things participate as
in a ‘separate perfection’ seems to fit well with the passage from Sent. I, d. 8.2c
quoted above (cf. Fabro, Participation et causalité, 195-202). Perhaps he does not
invoke it because it uses ‘dynamic’ terms of ‘reception’ rather than merely terms of
static Participation.
68
Aquinas, Sent. 1, d. 8.5.1 sc; cf. also De sub. sep. 8, ll. 255-273.
69
SCG 1.43, n. 8 (Amplius. Ipsum).
70
See above, n. 53.
104 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
71
Thomas Dillon, The Real Distinction between Being and Essence in the Thought
of St. Thomas Aquinas, Notre Dame diss. (Notre Dame, 1977), 215, lists this as a
fifth argument beyond the standard four summarized by Sweeney; cf. also Roland-
Gosselin, Le “De ente,” 188: “proofs from the nature of created being;” Fabro, La
nozione metafisica, 214-15, 220-21. The argument was central in medieval and
renaissance Thomism; cf., for example, Norman Wells, “Capreolus on Essence and
Existence,” Modern Schoolman 38 (1960): 1-24.
72
Aquinas, SCG 2.52, n. 6 (Amplius. Substantia).
73
For other places where such causal reasoning is reflected, see above, nn. 28, 40,
and 49, as well as Step (2) in Section II.H below, and Steps (1.a) and (4.b) in
Section II.J; for causal reasoning in general, cf. above, n. 32. Aquinas’ “Effect to
Cause Argument” grows out of his reading of Avicennian arguments regarding the
possible versus necessary being—according to which arguments a caused thing is
only possible in itself and must receive esse from another in order to be; see
Sent. 1, d. 8.5.2c; Sent. 2, d. 1.1.5 ad sc 2; ST I.3.7 ad 1, but especially QDDV 8.8c,
ll. 121-126: “Omne autem quod aliquid non habet a se ipso sed ab altero, est ei
praeter essentiam suam; et per hunc modum probat Avicenna quod esse cuiuslibet
rei praeter primum ens est aliquid praeter essentiam ipsius quia omnia ab alio esse
habent; In Met. 4, lect. 2, n. 9 (556): “[Avicenna] dicebat, quia in qualibet re quae
habet esse ab alio, aliud est esse rei, et substantia sive essentia eius.” See especially
Avicenna, Liber de philosophia prima sive scientia divina, ed. S. Van Riet
(Louvain-Leiden, 1977-1980), vol. 2, 8.3, pp. 395.12-396.28; cf. 8.4, pp. 400.7-
402.47. Notice, though, that Avicenna’s reasoning here, if it can be taken as a
proof of the Real Distinction, proceeds from God to creatures. Fabro takes it as
David Twetten 105
crucial that Aquinas departs from Avicennian causal and ‘extrinsicist’ lines of
argumentation for the Real Distinction, such as mark Aquinas’ early works, in
favor of ‘static and intrinsicist’ lines through Participation; Fabro, Participation et
causalité, 216; cf. Mario Pangallo, L’essere come atto nel tomismo essenziale di
Cornelio Fabro (Roma, 1987), 34-37, 49-52. As Pangallo observes, however,
Aquinas’ shift is not as absolute as Fabro suggests; ibid. 36. Of course, the second
half of Fabro’s Participation et causalité develops in Aquinas’ mature thought a
causal line of reasoning subsequent to the Real Distinction that owes something to
Avicenna but is completely rethought in terms of intensive esse; cf. Fabro,
Participation et causalité, 341, 381-88, 431-41.
74
The brackets contain one way of completing the argument. For this step, cf.
Aristotle, Metaphysics Z.17, 1041a15-24. For a cause as that from which the esse
of another follows, see Thomas Aquinas, De principiis naturae 3, ll. 76-79, in
Opera omnia, vol. 43.
75
See above nn. 26, 48-49.
106 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
76
Compare the version of this argument in Giles of Rome, Theoremata V, 25.19-
26.5: were a creature its own unparticipated esse, it would be entirely simple.
77
I add Step (1) to show that the argument, although it uses ‘created form’, need
hinge only on there being something other than subsistent esse—whether or not
such a thing is seen as caused.
78
Aquinas, In De ebdom. 2, ll. 36-39, 55-113, 198-206; cf. also Step (3) in the
following Section.
David Twetten 107
K. Summary Observations
All nine of Aquinas’ arguments for the Real Distinction that we have
reviewed seem vulnerable to the Question-Begging Objection. Aquinas
seems never to have been aware of the objection. At the same time, his
Exposition of Boethius’ De hebdomadibus shows his awareness of the
83
See ST I.3.4 ad 2; QDDP 7.2 ad 1.
David Twetten 109
85
Cf. above, nn. 48-49, 66, 72-75.
86
Étienne Gilson, Elements of Christian Philosophy (Garden City, N.Y., 1960),
130. See ibid. 128: “[N]o one has ever been able to demonstrate the conclusion
that, in a caused substance, existence is a distinct element, other than essence, and
its act.” Cf. also Étienne Gilson, The Christian Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas,
tr. L. Shook (New York, 1956), 82.
87
Gilson, Elements of Christian Philosophy, 130-35.
88
Fabro, Participation et causalité, 75, 79-81; Cornelio Fabro, “Notes pour la
fondation métaphysique de l’etre,” in Fabro, Tomismo e pensiero moderno, 291-
317, at 292, 312, 314, reprinted from Revue thomiste 2 (1966): 214-37; cf. Luis
Romera, Pensar el ser: Análisis del conocimiento del “Actus Essendi” según C.
Fabro (Bern, 1994), 99-100. Notice the evolution in Fabro’s thought and
expression on this issue. In his 1939 article on the Real Distinction, he defends
both what he calls the ‘logico-metaphysical argument’ of the First Stage of De ente
4, and the two ‘metaphysical arguments’ of the Second and Third Stage; Fabro,
“Un itinéraire,” 94-97. In the 1950 revision of La nozione metafisica, 217-22, 243-
44, Fabro still distinguishes Aquinas’ two logical arguments (De ente 4, First
Stage, and the “Genus Argument”) from two early metaphysical arguments (De
ente 4, Second and Third Stages), though the logical arguments must not be taken
to stand on their own (ibid. 219); but Fabro favors Aquinas’ third and subsequently
David Twetten 111
dialectical analysis89 that starts from the intensive act of being, which is
also identifiable with God.90 The first source of this properly Thomistic
Both Gilson and Fabro end by denying that the Real Distinction can be
known through proof. But their approach to the Real Distinction leaves it
open, again, to the objection that the distinction is a theological or
Neoplatonic accretion, unjustifiable on philosophical grounds. As both
Gilson and Fabro would admit, the Real Distinction is not per se known:
from the understanding alone of essence, substance, or form, on the one
hand, and of ‘to be’, on the other, it is not obvious that in reality outside
the mind, ‘form’ is other than ‘to be’. To say otherwise will raise the
Question-Begging Objection. The Real Distinction, I conclude, needs to be
defended by argument but cannot be deduced from prior principles without
assuming ‘to be’ as an ontological component, without assuming ‘esse’ in
the Thomist sense. In this situation, it appears that one must resort to
indirect argumentation such as through effects or through a reductio ad
absurdum. Are there any impossible consequences for one who would
affirm Aristotelian principles but reject really distinct esse? I submit that
where he explicitly does not appeal to God at the moment of the ‘foundation’, but
only subsequently in completing the causal account; Fabro, “Notes pour la
fondation métaphysique de l’etre,” 291-93, 309-14.
91
Fabro, Participation et causalité, 15, 51, 169, 198, 207-208, 216-19, 229, 537. It
does not contradict Fabro’s position to add that the ‘first moment’ of Thomist
metaphysics is the Aristotelian concept of act; for, the ultimate foundation of the
newly emergent esse ut actus versus the potency of essence is the Platonic notion
of Participation; Fabro, Introduzione a san Tommaso, 85, 91. Giacon criticizes
Fabro’s acceptance of a biblical origin and of a “God to Creatures” approach in his
account of the Real Distinction; Carlo Giacon, “S. Tommaso e l’esistenza come
atto: Maritain, Gilson, Fabro,” in Giacon, Itinerario tomistico (Rome, 1983), 137-
65, at 162-63. Late Fabro seems to have changed his position, insisting that
Aquinas differs from previous Christian thought in that the evidence of the event
of creation for him is founded on esse as act, rather than vice versa; Fabro,
“Intorno al fondamento dell’essere,” in Graceful Reason: Essays in Ancient and
Medieval Philosophy Presented to Joseph Owens, C.Ss.R., ed. L. Gerson (Toronto,
1983), 229-37, at 237. In any event, Fabro’s account of the Real Distinction turns
on his establishing that there is an esse as act containing all things intensively at a
transcendental level, whereas essences at the predicamental level have this act only
by Participation. The intensivity of esse is what makes it possible to establish the
Real Distinction, whereas all other accounts take esse in a ‘logical’ or ‘formal’
sense as containing merely the minimal base of what makes something to be
(existence). So thin a notion of esse makes the Real Distinction vulnerable to
objections such as those of Descoqs or the Question-Begging Objection.
David Twetten 113
The first point that needs to be made, which I cannot defend at length here,
is that Aristotle himself maintains a conceptual distinction between mere
‘to be’ and ‘that which is’.92 Thus, Aquinas, insofar as he begins his
discussions of the Real Distinction by first establishing a conceptual
distinction, as in the Exposition of the De hebdomadibus, follows Aristotle
even more than he follows Boethius or Avicenna. It is often observed that
Aristotle identifies essence or to ti ēn einai with being or to einai, as in the
formula to kuklōi einai (the being of a circle), used for the essence of a
92
One may find strong defenses of the position—and not merely to favor
Aquinas—that there is no hint of an existential notion of ‘to be’ in Aristotle, that
‘to be’ always means ‘to be so and so’, as in the statement of the principle of non-
contradiction; see Joseph Owens, “An Aristotelian Text Related to the Distinction
of Being and Essence,” Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical
Association 21 (1946): 165-72, at 164; see also G. E. L. Owen, “Aristotle on the
Snares of Ontology,” in New Essays on Plato and Aristotle (New York, 1965), 69-
95; Alfonso Gomez Lobo, “The So-Called Question of Existence in Aristotle, An.
Post. 2.1-2,” Review of Metaphysics 34 (1980): 71-90. Still, many today ascribe to
Aristotle propositions that affirm existence; see Milton Munitz, Existence and
Logic (New York, 1974), 59-62; David Demoss and Daniel Devereux, “Essence,
Existence, and Nominal Definition in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics II 8-10,”
Phronesis 33 (1988): 133-54; Thomas D’Andrea, “Essence and Existence in
Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics,” in Saints and Scholars, 15-21; Owen Goldin,
Explaining an Eclipse: Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics 2.1-10 (Ann Arbor, MI,
1996), 52-71; Jaakko Hintikka, “On Aristotle’s Notion of Existence,” Review of
Metaphysics 52 (1999): 779-805, at 785-90; David Charles, Aristotle on Meaning
and Essence (Oxford, 2000), chs. 2-3; and David Charles, “Some Comments on
Prof. Enrico Berti’s ‘Being and Essence in Contemporary Interpretations of
Aristotle’,” in Individuals, Essence and Identity: Themes of Analytic Metaphysics,
ed. A. Bottani, et al. (Dordrecht, 2002), 109-26. Linguistic studies reveal an
existential sense for einai in classical Greek and in Aristotle, although Aristotle
does not articulate a concept of existence or distinguish it carefully from other
senses of einai; A. C. Graham, “‘Being’ in Linguistics and Philosophy: A
Preliminary Inquiry,” Foundations of Language 1 (1965): 223-31, at 223-24, and
Charles Kahn, “The Greek Verb ‘To Be’ and the Concept of Being,” Foundations
of Language 2 (1966): 245-65, at 247-48, 265.
114 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
93
Aristotle, Metaphysics Z.10, 1036a1-19; for to ti ēn einai, see H.3, 1043b1-4.
94
See especially Aquinas, Sent. 1, d. 33.1.1 ad 1: “Sed sciendum, quod esse dicitur
dupliciter. Uno modo dicitur esse ipsa quidditas vel natura rei, sicut dicitur quod
definitio est oratio significans quid est esse; definitio enim quidditatem rei
significat. Alio modo dicitur esse ipse actus essentiae; sicut vivere, quod est esse
viventibus, est animae actus; non actus secundus, qui est operatio, sed actus
primus. Tertio modo dicitur esse quod significat veritatem compositionis in
propositionibus, secundum quod est dicitur copula: et secundum hoc est in
intellectu componente et dividente quantum ad sui complementum; sed fundatur in
esse rei, quod est actus essentiae. . . .”
95
For Owens, the question ‘whether something is’ in Posterior Analytics 2 in fact
asks about a thing’s generic or quasi-generic character: Joseph Owens, The
Doctrine of Being in the Aristotelian Metaphysics: A Study in the Greek
Background of Mediaeval Thought, 3rd ed. (Toronto, 1978), 289-94; or about its
logical possibility: Joseph Owens, “The Accidental and Essential Character of
Being in the Doctrine of St. Thomas Aquinas,” in Owens, St. Thomas Aquinas on
the Existence of God, 52-96, at 59. The work of Graham, Hintikka, Kahn, and
Suzanne Mansion helps elucidate the difficulty to which Owens points, even while
it admits an existential sense to einai in the Posterior Analytics. For Graham,
“‘Being’ in Linguistics,” 224-25, einai in the existential sense in Posterior
Analytics 2 is a great exception in the corpus, and Aristotle must signal its use by
adding haplōs (2.1-2, 89b33; 90a5, 10-12, 33; De Sophisticis Elenchis 5, 166b37-
167a7); elsewhere in Posterior Analytics 2, einai may include existence but cannot
merely be translated by ‘exists’ since it also may imply a predicate, whether a
thing’s essence or properties (2.7, 92b20-25). Similarly, Hintikka, “On Aristotle’s
Notion,” 785-87, ascribes to Aristotle the valid inference from ‘Homer is human’
to ‘Homer is’ in a jointly existential and essential sense—a fused Aristotelian sense
supported by Riek Van Bennekom, Journal of the History of Philosophy 24
(1986): 1-18, but opposed by Russell Dancy, “Aristotle and Existence” in The
Logic of Being: Historical Studies, ed. S. Knuuttila and J. Hintikka (Dordrecht,
1986), 49-80, at 59, 64-67; cf. also Richard Ketchum, “Being and Existence in
Greek Ontology,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 80 (1998): 321-32.
Contrary to the suggestion of Posterior Analytics 2.1-2, then, Aristotle offers
no existential syllogisms—which are impossible since being is not a genus; yet
existence can form part of the middle term; Jaakko Hintikka and Ilpo Halonen,
“Aristotelian Explanations,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 31
(2000): 125-36, at 132. For Kahn, “The Greek Verb ‘To Be’,” 248-49, 263-65,
although einai has an existential sense, there is no universal concept of existence,
such as would allow it to be a subject of predication, either in classical Greek or in
David Twetten 115
states: “The whatness of a human [ti estin anthrōpos] is other than that a
human is [to einai anthrōpon]. . . . ‘To be’ [to einai] is not the substance of
anything, since ‘a being’ [to on] is not a genus.”96
But why, once again, must even Aristotle himself hold that ‘to be’ is
distinct from whatness not only conceptually but also ‘in the nature of
things’, as Thomas would say?97 We can ask this question without begging
it precisely because of the conceptual distinction between what and
whether x is. We may ask, Can the principles of form and matter alone
(and their efficient and final causes) ‘account for actually to be’, that is,
explain what it is about x that constitutes x’s actually being at all, in
addition to explaining what x is? Do form and matter and the causes of
becoming alone account for why x’s actually being, x’s ‘actually to be,’
differs from x’s non-being or only potentially being? Notice that this is not
Aristotle’s question. Aristotle asked only, What brings it about such that x
comes to be or ceases to be? whereas the question now is, What is it about
x that ‘accounts for its actually to be’ while it is?
not substance, then two reasons why form is not esse. I adopt his reasons
regarding matter, and I adopt his format, while modifying it to generate the
trichotomy required. The Question-Begging Objection must be met
ontologically by showing through a reductio ad absurdum that neither
matter alone, nor form alone, nor matter and form together can ‘account
for actually to be’. Once again, I assume that matter and form are
principles of the real, and I argue as follows.
(1) If Aristotle does not need really distinct ‘actually to be’, then
form and matter alone ‘account for actually to be’ (assuming that
‘actually to be’ does not merely name an extrinsic relation).
(2) But, first, matter alone as matter cannot account for ‘actually to
be’.
a. For, matter alone is pure potency; but what is in potency
as such is not yet.98
b. Also, matter alone does not explain why things come to
be, since pure potency, which is not yet, cannot as such
act.
c. Also, we do not say that matter alone is, but that the
composite is; if matter alone in the genus of substance
were to be, then all form would be accidental.99
(3) Second, form alone as form cannot account for ‘actually to be’.
a. For, although form is actuality, form as form in material
things ‘is not’.
i. For, otherwise, the form of material things
would not need matter to be.
ii. Also, just as for Aristotle form does not come
to be, but only the composite, so form as such
in material things does not have ‘actually to
be’,100 but only the composite.101
98
Cf. SCG 1.16, n. 7 (Item. Videmus).
99
SCG 2.54, nn. 2-3. See also below, nn. 122-123.
100
See below, nn. 122, 124. That the composite alone, unlike matter or form by
themselves, is “separate not only in formula (logos), but also absolutely speaking
(hapls),” see Aristotle, Metaphysics H.1, 1042a29-31; that the composite
properly acts, not the soul or intellect, see De anima 1.4, 408b13-15; 3.8, 432a1-3.
David Twetten 117
101
I reverse the argument found in Aquinas; see below n. 122, in addition to
Aquinas, QDDP 6.3c.
102
See below, nn. 112, 113.
103
Aristotle, Metaphysics H.2, 1042b9-11; H.6, 1045a14-33, b16-24; De anima
2.1, 412a7-11.
104
This actualization simply results from form as form; see below, nn. 117-120.
Cf. Aristotle, Metaphysics H.6, 1045a14-33, b16-24.
118 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
105
Cf. the reduction of Siger of Brabant, Quaestiones in Metaphysicam, ed. W.
Dunphy (Louvain-la-Neuve, 1981), Introduction, q. 7 (Munich reportatio), 45.114-
20: esse is either form, matter, the composite, or an accident. Of course, the
Aristotelian would hold that ‘actually to be’ is form alone in the case of the
separate first substances or prime movers—which are not under consideration here.
106
Notice the similarity between this approach and Aristotle’s reduction of ousia to
form, not matter or the composite; Aristotle, Metaphysics Z.3, 1029a7-33.
107
Cf. Aquinas’ view that the soul is what makes the body to be a body, and that
matter ‘is’ only because substantial form makes it actually be; Aquinas, ST I.76.4c,
ad 1; I.76.6c; De ente 2, ll. 135-150. See also Christopher Hughes, “Matter and
Actuality in Aquinas,” in Thomas Aquinas: Contemporary Philosophical
Perspectives, ed. B. Davies (Oxford-New York, 2002), 61-76.
108
It may be thought that this is Aquinas’ position, as the following points
suggests. (1) Through form, which is the act of matter, matter is made a being in
act and ‘this something’; Aquinas, De ente 2, ll. 31-35; ST I.29.2 ad 5; I.66.1c.
David Twetten 119
to the actuality of form alone,109 or, if ‘actually to be’ does not merely
name a thing’s relation to an external cause, the argument reaches its
conclusion: ‘actually to be’ is accounted for only by an actuality that is
really distinct from both form and matter.
Can form alone, then, in the third place, account for ‘actually to be’? If so,
the Aristotelian finds that form has been substantified or partially
Platonized as what ‘is’ on its own, and that a central Aristotelian tenet has
been denied: that form ceases to be upon the destruction of the
composite.110 For if form alone accounts for ‘actually to be’, why should
the form of material things, any less than the form of the immaterial prime
movers, ever cease to be?111 As Aquinas himself argues, any form of a
(2) Thus, form gives esse to matter, which receives it; Sent. 3, d. 1.1.1 ad 3.
(3) Similarly, the soul gives living to the body, that is, ‘to be’ for what is alive;
QDSC 1 sc 4, ll. 231-237; 3c, ll. 405-412; 11 ad 14; ll. 421-428. (4) Hence, the
only ‘to be’ that matter or the body has is through form; De ente 4, ll. 41-50.
(5) Form also gives ‘to be’ to the body; QDSC 3c, ll. 408-409; 6 ad sc 6, ll. 430-
431. (6) Thus the soul makes—formally, not efficiently—the substance to be, the
body to be, and the animated body to be; Thomas Aquinas, Sentencia libri De
anima 2.1, lect. 1, ll. 265-288, in Opera omnia, vol. 45.1; Quodl. 1.4.1 ad 2, ll.
111-118. (7) The ‘to be’ that the body has is the same as the soul’s ‘to be’; Sent. 1,
d. 15.5.3c. (8) By being given substantial ‘to be’ from the soul, the composite is
generated, and the body is constituted in the genus of substance; Sent. 4, d. 44.1.1
qc 1 ad 4; ST I.76.4c. Nonetheless, in other places it is clear that for Aquinas the
‘to be’ given by form, although only one for form and matter, is really distinct
from both form and matter; see De ente 4, ll. 185-192. ‘To be’ is a per se
consequent of form, the result of form, just as is a property; see also below, nn.
116, 119, 121. Form as form gives matter its ‘esse specificum’; see below, n. 120.
Notice also soul’s relation to divine esse in human nature hypostatically united to
the divine; ST III.17.2c.
109
This view can be found among Aquinas scholars. For Hans Meyer, Thomas von
Aquin, 133, on Aristotelian principles form is so close to esse that a Real
Distinction is impossible; furthermore, even Thomas and Albert hold that form is
actus essendi.
110
See, for example, Aristotle, Metaphysics H.3, 1043b19-21.
111
For a defense of the view that all form is everlasting, although not without
actualizing the thinnest slice of matter, see James Ross, “Together with the Body
That I Love,” Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 75
(2001): 1-20. I owe this argument to the suggestion of Lawrence Dewan. Hints of
such reasoning can be found in Dillon, The Real Distinction, 183; Fabro, “Notes
pour la fondation métaphysique de l’etre,” 293; Giles of Rome, Theoremata XII,
68.2-8; 75.23-77.13.
120 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
composite that ‘is’ on its own right will be everlasting;112 only if form ‘is’,
not through itself, but through the distinct ‘to be’ of the composite, can it
cease to be.113
112
Aquinas, Quodl. 10.3.2 ad 3, ll. 146-151: “[A]nima [intellectualis] esse suum
communicat corpori, quod quidem ita acquiritur anime in corpore ut secundum
ipsum subsistere possit, quod non est de aliis formis; et sic ipsum esse anime fit
esse compositi, et tamen manet, composito destructo.” Thomas Aquinas, De
unitate intellectus 1, ll. 644-653, in Opera omnia, vol. 43: “Forma igitur que habet
operationem secundum aliquam sui potentiam uel uirtutem absque
communicatione sue materie, ipsa est que habet esse, nec est per esse compositi
tantum sicut alie forme, sed magis compositum est per esse eius. . . . non autem
oportet quod destruatur ad destructionem compositi illa forma per cuius esse
compositum est, et non ipsa per esse compositi.” Cf. also the relation of form and
‘to be’ in the following. ST I.50.5c: “si ipsa forma subsistat in suo esse, sicut est in
angelis, ut dictum est, non potest amittere esse.” QDDA 14c, ll. 179-183: “Si igitur
sit aliqua forma que sit habens esse, necesse est illam formam incorruptibilem
esse: non enim separatur esse ab aliquo habente esse nisi per hoc quod separatur
forma ab eo. Vnde si id quod habet esse sit ipsa forma, impossibile est quod esse
separetur ab eo.” Notice the objection that if form is the source of ‘to be’, then
subsistent form cannot be caused; QDDP 6.6 ob 4. Given the Real Distinction,
Aquinas easily handles the objection without denying that form is a source of ‘to
be’.
113
Sent. 2, d. 19.1.1 ad 2: “Si vero forma non habeat esse absolutum in quo
subsistat, sed sit per esse compositi, tunc ex quo compositum desinit esse, oportet
quod forma etiam esse amittat, et per accidens corrumpatur.” Sent. 4, d. 49.2.3 ad
6: “Sed forma quae non est per se subsistens . . . non habet esse nisi inquantum est
actus talis subjecti.” SCG 2.91, n. 5 (Item. Si): “Formae autem quae sunt in
materiis, sunt actus imperfecti: quia non habent esse completum. Sunt igitur
aliquae formae quae sunt actus completi per se subsistentes, et speciem completam
habentes.” QDDA 14c, ll. 169-179: “Manifestum est autem quod esse per se
consequitur formam: unumquodque enim habet esse secundum propriam formam.
Vnde esse a forma nullo modo separari potest. Corrumpuntur igitur composita ex
materia et forma per hoc quod amittunt formam ad quam consequitur esse; ipsa
autem forma per se corrumpi non potest; set per accidens, corrupto composito,
corrumpitur in quantum deficit esse compositi quod est per formam, si forma sit
talis que non sit habens esse, set sit solum quo compositum est.” De unitate
intellectus 1, ll. 630-650: “Forme igitur que nullam operationem habent sine
communicatione sue materie, ipse non operantur, sed compositum est quod
operatur per formam; unde huiusmodi forme ipse quidem proprie loquendo non
sunt, sed eis aliquid est. . . . Et similis ratio est de formis substantialibus que
nullam operationem habent absque communicatione materie, hoc excepto quod
huiusmodi forme sunt principium essendi substantialiter. . . . Et ideo destructo
composito destruitur illa forma que est per esse compositi.”
David Twetten 121
cause of the ‘to be’ of the whole, ‘shaping’ what is. It is the formal cause
of ‘to be in the sense of essence or of what x is’,118 but it is not what as
such ‘accounts for actually to be’. As Aquinas puts it in an underused
passage, form as form is not non-being but is act; yet, compared to ‘esse in
act’, form is a non-being, which ‘is’ only by participating in esse.119 Form
tells us not whether x is, but what the being of x is, what kind of ‘to be’ x
has.120 Form is that through which a thing has the ‘actually to be’ that it
has. Yet, for Aquinas, ‘actually to be’ is the actuality, not of matter, but of
the whole substance, a consequence of form, the very act of separate form
or of the form-matter composite so that it ‘is’, just as living is the act of
the soul.121 Thus, insists Thomas, just as neither matter alone nor form
alone comes to be, as Aristotle showed,122 so neither matter alone123 nor
118
Aristotle, Metaphysics Z.17, 1041a27-32, b12-31; H.2, 1043a2-12.
119
Aquinas, De sub. sep. 8, ll. 236-244: “Si igitur per hoc quod dico ‘non ens’
removeatur solum esse in actu, ipsa forma secundum se considerata est non ens,
sed esse participans. Si autem ‘non ens’ removeat non solum ipsum esse in actu
sed etiam actum seu formam per quam aliquid participat esse, sic materia est non
ens; forma vero subsistens non est non ens, sed est actus qui est forma
participativus ultimi actus, qui est esse.”
120
De unitate intellectus 1, ll. 493-495: “[A]nima per se ipsam est actus corporis
dans corpori esse specificum.” Sent. 1, d. 49.1.1 qc 1 ad 6: “[L]icet homo ex anima
et corpore consistat, tamen esse specificum habet ex anima, non ex corpore, quia
forma cujuslibet rei est principium esse ejus specifici.” See also Sent. 4, d. 36.4 ad
3; d. 44.2.2 qc 1c; d. 44.2.3 qc 1c; In De an. 2.1, lect. 1, ll. 285-288; QDDA 9c, ll.
293-295; QDSC 2c, ll. 264-272; 4c, ll. 178-190.
121
See, for example, Sent. 1, d. 23.1.1c: “[C]um esse consequitur compositionem
materiae et formae, quamvis forma sit principium esse, non tamen denominatur
aliquod ens a forma sed a toto. . .” Quodl. 9.2.2c, ll. 41-43, 58-63: “Alio modo esse
dicitur actus entis in quantum est ens, id est quo denominatur aliquid ens actu in
rerum natura. . . . Esse ergo proprie et uere non attribuitur nisi rei per se
subsistenti. Huic autem attribuitur esse duplex. Unum scilicet esse resultans ex hiis
ex quibus eius unitas integratur, quod est proprium esse suppositi substanciale.”
Super Boetium De trinitate 5.3c, ll. 102-105: “[Ipsum esse rei] quidem resultat ex
congregatione principiorum rei in compositis, uel ipsam simplicem naturam rei
concomitatur, ut in substantiis simplicibus.” See also SCG 2.55, n. 3 (Amplius.
Quod); ST I.50.5c.
122
Aristotle, Metaphysics Z.8, 1033a24-b26; Z.9, 1034b8-16. Aquinas, ST I.65.4c:
“Sed sicut probat Aristoteles in VII Metaphys., id quod proprie fit, est compositum,
formae autem corruptibilium rerum habent ut aliquando sint, aliquando non sint,
absque hoc quod ipsae generentur aut corrumpantur, sed compositis generatis aut
corruptis, quia etiam formae non habent esse, sed composita habent esse per eas,
sic enim alicui competit fieri, sicut et esse.” SCG 3.69, n. 21 (Rationes autem):
“Cum enim ad hoc aliquid fiat ut sit, sicut forma non dicitur ens quasi ipsa habeat
esse, sed quia per eam compositum est; ita nec forma proprie fit, sed incipit esse
David Twetten 123
form alone within the composite actually is.124 The composite alone ‘is’,
not its principles, by an act distinct from either matter or form, by an act
consequent upon form, and therefore by an act distinct also from the form-
matter composite itself.
per hoc quod compositum sit reductum de potentia in actum, qui est forma.” See
also ST I.110.2c; QDDP 3.8c; Thomas Aquinas, Quaestio disputata de caritate 12
ad 20, in Quaestiones disputatae, vol. 2; Thomas Aquinas, De operationibus
occultis naturae, ll. 142-147, in Opera omnia, vol. 43; In Met. 7.8, lect. 7 (1033b7-
8), n. 7 (1423).
123
Sent. 3, d. 6.2.2 ad 1: “[F]orma facit esse; non ita quod illud esse sit materiae
aut formae, sed subsistentis;” Sent. 1, d. 8.5.2c; d. 8.5.3, exp.; De ente 2, ll. 51-66;
In Met. 7.3, lect. 2, n. 23 (1292).
124
In addition to the texts of Aquinas cited in n. 122, see De ente 2, ll. 51-66;
Quodl. 9.2.2c, ll. 51-59; De unitate intellectus 1, ll. 633-634.
125
Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet 10.7, ll. 145-159, in Henry of Ghent, Opera omnia
(Leuven, 1979-), vol. 14; Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet 1.9, ll. 89-92, in Opera
omnia, vol. 5.
126
Francisco Suárez, Disputationes metaphysicae 31.6.17-18, in Francisco Suárez,
Opera omnia (Paris, 1856-1877), vol. 26.
124 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
Aquinas cites many times in his own name the Avicennian formula that ‘a
being’ is the first concept that falls into the mind.127 Admittedly, the
temporally first concept, which is also the most universal,128 contains
confusedly all other things within it, unlike the philosopher’s systematic
formula ‘a being qua a being’. Nonetheless, Aquinas is committed to the
fact that what first falls into the mind (ens) signifies and names something
through its esse in the primary sense, through its ‘actually to be’, namely,
through its ‘to be’ in the sense of ‘that by which it is versus is not’, ‘that
by which it actually is versus only potentially is’.129 Present at the
beginning of intellectual life, just as at the beginning of philosophy, is the
127
E.g., Aquinas, ST I.5.1c.
128
ST I.85.3.
129
For the meaning of ens see In Peryerm. 1.3 (16b20-26), lect. 5, ll. 355-376. For
the primary sense of esse, see ibid. ll. 394-405.
David Twetten 125
This question does not presuppose the Real Distinction, does not
presuppose an ‘actually to be’ that is really distinct from form, does not
assume ‘esse in the Thomist sense’. The knowledge of ‘human’ and
‘animal’ precedes the knowledge of ‘rational’. Once the concept of
‘rational’ is achieved, one asks, is rationality really distinct from
humanity? Aquinas will answer, no, without giving up on the fact that
there is something in reality corresponding to both, that each has a
foundation in reality.132 Similarly, to ask whether ‘actually to be’ is really
distinct from form is to remain open to the possible answer: no, although
each has a foundation in reality. To ask this question does not beg it. I
have argued that Aquinas’ nine kinds of argument for the Real Distinction
fail to remain open to the answer ‘no’ by assuming without proof ‘actually
to be’ as an ontological component that is the act of form, that is, by
assuming Thomist esse. To this extent I have admitted both the thrust of
the Question-Begging Objection and that it has landed a blow. But it
would be unwarranted for the objector to exclude all talk of ‘actually to
be’. To assume that ‘actually to be’ has some foundation in reality does
not beg the question by assuming Thomist esse. It would be odder to deny
this foundation because of posterior difficulties than it would be to deny
that there is a real foundation for ‘humanity’ because of difficulties with
‘rationality’. Rationality is a highly doubted and dubious concept; the
radical empiricist and scientific realist alike even reject humanity. Form
(and essence) is far more subject to doubt than rationality; but if form is
130
Sent. 1, d. 24.1.3 ad 2; In Met. 4.2, lect. 3, n. 2 (566); 10.3, lect. 4, n. 15 (1998).
For the foundation of the principle of non-contradiction, the first judgment, on ens,
see In Met 4.3, lect. 6, n. 10 (605).
131
QDDV 10.12 ad 3. For the multiple senses of ens, see In Met. 5.7, lect. 9.
132
Sent. 1, d. 19.5.1c; QDDV 21.1c, ll. 94-110.
126 Really Distinguishing Essence from Esse
At the same time, the ultimacy or primacy of ‘actually to be’ indicates the
difficulty faced by the project of ‘proving’ the Real Distinction. The
project rests on a first principle, and first principles cannot be proved, but
have to be defended dialectically. To this extent Gilson and Fabro are
correct to question the very project of a proof of the Real Distinction.
‘Actually to be’ and that things actually are must be defended dialectically
as ontologically and epistemically primary. In drawing attention to
‘actually to be’ as such, the Scriptural notion of creation ex nihilo, I would
argue, has only helped highlight principles that were already obvious.
On the other hand, Aquinas scholarship has been correct to emphasize the
essential and central role of the “God to Creatures” approach in Aquinas.
Once form has been really distinguished from ‘actually to be’ in material
composites, Aquinas’ conclusion that God is ‘actually to be’ itself can take
on an ontological significance. As a result, once the Real Distinction is
established for material things, the “God to Creatures Argument” can
establish cogently that for all things except one (whether possible or
actual), including for all immaterial beings except one, ‘actually to be’ is
really distinct from essence. The universal scope of the “God to Creatures
Argument,” not the evidentness of its starting point, is the reason that
Aquinas frequently employs it.
IV. Résumé
The project of arguing for the Real Distinction begins only after essence
and form have been accepted to account for what is. Is form or are form
and matter together the same in reality as ‘actually to be’? The majority of
Aquinas’ nine kinds of arguments for the Real Distinction are cogent
except insofar as they fail to address precisely this question. Form is so
close to ‘actually to be’ that Aquinas fails to worry sufficiently about
detaching one from another.
I conclude that the real distinction between being and substance, although
not drawn by Aristotle, is a natural development required by his
philosophical principles weighed against reality. The actuality of form
cannot be identified in reality with ‘actually to be’. Form does not of itself
bring ‘actually to be’ to corruptible things. This is not the role of formal
causality. Otherwise, the forms of material things should ‘be’ forever. To
protect against this consequence, ‘actually to be’ must be seen as really
distinct from form. If things do have Aristotelian essence, it must be really
distinct from their ‘to be’.133
133
I am very grateful to Stephen Baldner, Jeffrey Brower, Lawrence Dewan, Owen
Goldin, Sebastián Kaufmann, Gyula Klima, Cyrille Michon, Stephen Pimentel,
Thomas Prendergast, Brian Shanley, Thomas Sullivan, Richard Taylor, Roland
Teske, Gregory Traylor, John Wippel, Yu Wong, and Michael Wreen for help and
suggestions at various stages in the composition of this paper. . I would also like to
thank the Catholic University of America Press for permission to publish online a
substantially similar paper to that forthcoming in Wisdom’s Apprentice: Thomistic
Essays in Honor of Lawrence Dewan, O.P., ed. Peter A. Kwasniewski
(Washington, D. C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 2007). A full
description of the book on the CUA Press website may be found at
http://cuapress.cua.edu/BOOKS/ viewbook.cfm?Book=KWIA