2020 UOxford Hum Rts Hub J236
2020 UOxford Hum Rts Hub J236
2020 UOxford Hum Rts Hub J236
Citations:
Provided by:
Available Through: National Law University Odisha
-- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and
Conditions of the license agreement available at
https://heinonline.org/HOL/License
-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.
-- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your license, please use:
Copyright Information
Should the Indian Supreme
Court Scrap the Marital Rape
Exemption?
Bryan Dennis Gabito Tiojanco*
Judges always have at the ready some doctrinal basin to wash their hands
of moral complicity. Incanting dura lex sedlex (the law is hard, but it is the
law) is an age-old judicial ritual. Any combination of the traditional case
and controversy or standing requirements also allows a court to avoid an
overheated issue.' In the Philippines, where I am from, the political
question doctrine is the Supreme Court's preferred washbasin.
Where do Indian judges ceremonially dip their hands when they play
Pontius Pilate? What often follows after they raise their cleansed hands
before the public? Like neon signs these questions kept flashing brightly
before me as I read Agnidipto Tarafder and Adrija Ghosh's well-argued
article. The answers to them will be crucial if the goal is to persuade the
Indian Supreme Court to scrap a longstanding law. Personally, these
answers will also determine if I would agree with this goal.
In India, the law emphatically considers non-consensual sex between
a husband and his adult wife as "not rape".3 Most of us will find this rule
reprehensible.' To liberals, a marital rape exemption is morally wrong,
'National University of Singapore Faculty of Law, Centre for Asian Legal Studies,
postdoctoral fellow; [email protected]
Alexander Bickel, The LeastDangerousBranch: The Supreme Courtat the Bar of
Politics (2" ed, YUP 1986) Chapter 4.
'Bryan Dennis Gabito Tiojanco, 'Why Let SC play Pontius Pilate?' (PhilippineDaily
Inquirer, 29 November 2016) <https://opinion.inquirer.net/99605/let-sc-play-pontius-
pilate> accessed 8 January 2020.
' S375, Exception 2, The Indian Penal Code 1860; Independent Thought v. Union of
India (2017) 10 SCC 800 [73] declaring the marital rape exemption unconstitutional with
respect to girls between fifteen to eighteen years of age. The husband can still be proceeded
against for cruelty, hurt, wrongful restraint, use of criminal force, or sexual harassment;
s498A The Indian Penal Code 1860; see Gautam Bhatia, 'Addendum: The Impact of the
S.2(q) Judgment upon the Marital Rape Exception' (IndianConstitutionalLaw and
Philosophy, 12 October 2016)
<https://indconlawphil.wordpress.com/2016/10/12/addendum-the-impact-of-the-s-2q-
judgment-upon-the-marital-rape-exception/> accessed 6 February 2020.
'There may be disagreements on this point. Some may believe, for example, that non-
consensual sex between husband and wife is not rape because saying "I do" is shorthand for
"Marital Rape Exemption?"
since any sort of sex without the consent of one of the parties should be
punishable as rape, regardless of their marital status.' Thus, for liberal
judges the exemption could raise what Yale Law Professor Robert Cover
called a "moral-formal dilemma":6 should they apply the legal rule and
acquit a proven rapist, or should they apply the moral rule and place the
criminal behind bars?
One way out of the moral-formal dilemma is legal formalism, which
claims that 'there is always a right answer to every legal question, and that
it is the responsibility of the judge to find and apply this answer without
resorting to moral considerations of any sort." By asserting that there is but
one way to apply the rule, the judge avoids moral responsibility for
acquitting a criminal. The notion that a judge is a mere mechanical
conveyer of rules who has no choice in the matter pushes considerations
of justice and morality out of mind. In fact, this notion makes these
considerations improper when interpreting law.
Tarafder and Ghosh close this escape route to formalism by arguing
that a judge can in fact choose to invalidate the marital rape exemption on
the legal ground that it violates the Constitution of India 1950. First, since
the purpose of rape law is to punish non-consensual sex, classification
based on marital status is both unreasonable and arbitrary and hence
violates the Constitution's guarantees of equality and non-discrimination.
Second, the exemption is based on an unjustified gender stereotype and
thus violates the Constitution's anti-stereotyping principle. Third, the
exemption denies married women their fundamental rights to a dignified
existence, bodily integrity, and sexual autonomy. Fourth, the constitutional
right to free expression includes a woman's right to refuse sex, including
to her husband. Fifth, the exemption is an official endorsement of the
subjugation of wives by their husbands, which violates the constitutional
guarantee against both public and private exploitation of the oppressed.
an irrevocable "You can always have sex with me anytime". Others may believe that
criminalizing marital rape will unduly undernine family unity and integrity. If so, the task
here is not to change these differing views; rather it is to ask whether the moral intuition
that marital rape should be rape can be reconciled with the state of the law.
SJed Rubenfeld, 'The Riddle of Rape-by-Deception and the Myth of Sexual Autonomy'
(2013)122 Yale Law Journal 1372 I do not wish to tackle the issue of "rape-by-deception"
in this essay. I use the word "consent" in its ordinary sense, to sidestep Rubenfeld's
argument that 'sex-by-deception is sex without consent, because a consent obtained by
deception, as courts have long and repeatedly held outside of rape law, is 'no consent' at all'
ibid 1376.
6Robert Cover, Jusdce Accused:Antslavery and the JudicialProcess(YUP 1975) 199.
237
2020 Universityof Oxford Human Rights HubJournal Vol 3(2)
' See Gautam Bhatia, 'The Constitutionality of the Marital Rape Exception' (Indian
ConsatuionalLawand Philosophy, 16 January 2014)
<https://indconlawpbil.wordpress.com/2014/01/16/the-constitutionality-of-the-marital-rape-
exceptiou/> accessed 6 February 2020.
° Cover (n 6) 119-23.
" 5 US 137 (1803).
" Act No 3815 (1930) (emphasis in the original).
238
"Marital Rape Exemption?"
239
2020 Universityof Oxford Human Rights HubJournal Vol 3(2)
charges because they found it difficult to convince victims that marital rape
was a crime, and some New York courts continued to rely on the
exemption in dismissing marital sexual assault cases." Part of the blame
can be placed on the US Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit, which
'caused confusion among lower courts and scholars' by refusing to rule on
the exemption's constitutionality when it affirmed the conviction in
Liberta.' But the New York legislature's failure to amend the State's penal
code by expressly criminalizing marital rape also deprived Liberta of a
'publicly visible' change in legislative policy which, rape law reformers then
argued, could 'influence public attitudes toward criminal acts' and 'ensures
that a judge cannot rely on the current statutory language to dismiss a
case." In the Philippines, Congress made such a publicly visible change in
legislative policy in The Anti-Rape Law of 1997' by 'recognizing the reality
of marital rape and criminalizing its perpetration'.'
Herein lies the crux of my dilemma. Cover notes that it is
'commonplace for a result to be justified' by a court 'on the basis of the
direction in which the law is moving.' If a judge thinks that their unjust
decision is 'only a temporary phenomenon', in light of 'a perceptible
movement of a particular legal issue toward conformity with libertarian
values', then they could sleep well with the thought that nudging the
legislature towards amending the law was the more democratic route to
take." He called this the 'professional role' justification:' a court should
refuse to scrap the marital rape exemption because that would in effect
criminalize a legal act, and it is for a legislature, not a court, to determine
which acts deserve imprisonment and for how long.' The Indian Supreme
Court should instead-i la Marbury-declare itself constrained by the
exemption to acquit the accused while urging the Indian Parliament to
promptly criminalize marital rape. By trusting the legislative process, the
Indian Supreme Court can wash its hands clean by giving reasons while
withholding relief (much like what a Philippine judge does by submitting a
penal law reform report). 'Yes; the marital rape exemption is
reprehensible for the following reasons,' the Court will say. 'We cannot
remove the exemption ourselves, but these reasons should get the
Parliament swiftly started on amending the Indian Penal Code.'
" Cassandra DeLaMothe, 'LibertaRevisited: A Call to Repeal the Marital Exemption for
All Sex Offenses in New York's Penal Law' (1996) 23 Fordham Urban Law Journal 857.
Sibid 870.
Sibid 883.
Repeal Act No 8358 (1997).
People vJuma wan GR No 187495, 21 April 2014.
Cover (n 6) 201.
" ibid 202-03.
Sibid 215.
° For a doctrinal answer to this objection see Bhatia (n 3).
240
"Marital Rape Exemption?"
SI Cover (n 6) 236.
" Rachel Barkow, 'Separation of Powers and the Criminal Law' (2006) 58 Stanford Law
Review 989, 1017.
' US vHudson & Goodwin 11 US 32, 32-34 (1812); Gary Rowe, 'The Sound of Silence:
US vHudson & Goodwin, The Jeffersonian Ascendancy, and the Abolition of Federal
Common Law Crimes' (1992) 101 Yale Law Journal 919, 920-21 arguing that Hudson
&
Goodwin 'departed from what was arguably the original understanding of those who framed
the Constitution and penned the Judiciary Act of 1789'.
' Barkow (n 32) 1017.
'John Hart Ely, D emocracy andDistrust:A Theory ofJudicialReview (HUP 1981).
' Venus Lique, 'The Anti-Rape Law and The Changing Times: Nature, Issues and
Incidents' 43 (1999) Ateneo Law Joumal 141, 174-75 (1998) arguing that the wholesale
removal of the marital rape exemption in the Philippines 'will prejudice the family' and
thus 'runs counter to the principles of the Constitution where the State vows to protect the
sanctity of the family.'
' Rep Act No 8353, sec. 2 (1997).
"Philippine Commission on Women, 'Amending the Anti-Rape Law-Women's Priority
Legislative Agenda for the 18' Congress'
<https://www.pcw.gov.ph/sites/default/files/documents/laws/wpla/2019/October/webmaster/
PCW%20WPLA%20PB%20%23%2001-%20Amending%20the%20Anti-
Rape%20Lawv%20AEB.pdf> accessed 2 April 2020.
241
2020 Universityof Oxford Human Rights HubJournal Vol 3(2)
The big "if" of this professional role justification is that the legislature
will soon enough do its part. No documented case on marital rape ever
reached the Philippine Supreme Court before the exemption for it was
repealed.' It is likely, however, that Congress would have swiftly heeded a
penal law reform report from it to repeal the marital rape exemption. First,
The Anti-Rape Law of 1997 was enacted promptly after the Senate in 1996
began inquiring into how the country must implement The Platform for
Action of the 1995 Beijing Conference on Women.) Second, Congress
swiftly enacted the Anti-Violence Against Women and Their Children Act
of 2004, which allows abused women to invoke battered woman syndrome
as a defense from legal liability," a few months after the Supreme Court
promulgated a decision saying that 'While our hearts empathize with
recurrently battered persons, we can only work within the limits of law...
Neither can we amend the Revised Penal Code. Only Congress, in its
wisdom, may do so.' Third, Congress has been responsive to public
demands for greater gender justice, enacting such landmark laws as the
Safe Spaces Act 2019 (which punishes 'any unwanted and uninvited sexual
actions or remarks against any person regardless of the motive')" and the
Magna Carta for Women 2009 (which mandates governmental agencies
to 'give priority to the defense and protection of women against gender-
based offenses and help women attain justice and healing')."
Tarafder and Ghosh seem to suggest that the Indian Supreme Court
cannot similarly trust the Indian Parliament to do its part when they note
that the Criminal Law (Amendment) Act 2013 had rejected the
recommendation of the Justice Verma Committee in 2012 to remove the
exemption. This though is not enough. Historically, the professional role
justification closes down only when judges are forced to confront the claim
that the unlikeliness of legislative change 'justified re-examination of the
role assumptions', and that given this unlikeliness '[t]he normal appeal to
a professional role would no longer be sufficient, for it was just that role
that had been put at issue.'" In short, if the goal is to persuade the Indian
Supreme Court to scrap the marital rape exemption, then it first needs to
be boxed into the moral-formal dilemma. Doing this requires closing off
the main escape route still open to it. This, in turn, requires a re-
examination of the professional role of a Supreme Court in a constitutional
242
"Marital Rape Exemption?"
" Bryan Dennis G Tiojanco and Leandro Angelo Y Aguirre, 'The Scope, Justifications
and Limitations of Extra-decisional Judicial Activism and Governance in the Philippines'
(2009) 84 The Philippine Law Journal 73. The argument was that extra-decisional judicial
activism and governance (as we called it) was a necessary corrective to a dysfunctional
democratic process and had basis not only in the Constitution's text and structure, but also
in the country's political culture and history.
243