Salman Akhtar - Sources of Suffering - Fear, Guilt, Greed, Deception, Betrayal, and Revenge-Karnac Books (2014)
Salman Akhtar - Sources of Suffering - Fear, Guilt, Greed, Deception, Betrayal, and Revenge-Karnac Books (2014)
Salman Akhtar - Sources of Suffering - Fear, Guilt, Greed, Deception, Betrayal, and Revenge-Karnac Books (2014)
SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Fear, Greed, Guilt, Deception,
Betrayal, and Revenge
Salman Akhtar
Chapter One has previously appeared in S. Akhtar (Ed.), Fear: A Dark Shadow
Across The Life Span (pp. 3–34). London: Karnac, 2014.
Portions of Chapter Three are taken from Salman Akhtar’s paper, “Guilt: an
introductory overview”, which appeared in S. Akhtar (Ed.), Guilt: Origins,
Manifestations, and Management (pp. 1–13). Lanham, MD: Jason Aronson, 2013.
Portions of Chapter Four are taken from Salman Akhtar’s paper, “Lies, liars,
and lying: an introductory overview”, which appeared in S. Akhtar and
H. Parens (Eds.), Lying, Cheating, and Carrying On: Developmental, Clinical, and
Sociocultural Aspects of Dishonesty and Deceit (pp. 1–15). Lanham, MD: Jason
Aronson, 2009.
All this material is reprinted here with the author’s and the corresponding
publishers’ explicit permission.
The right of Salman Akhtar to be identified as the author of this work has been
asserted in accordance with §§ 77 and 78 of the Copyright Design and Patents
Act 1988.
ISBN-13: 978-1-78220-069-7
www.karnacbooks.com
To
RAMA RAO GOGINENI & APRIL FALLON
in friendship
CONTENTS
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ix
INTRODUCTION xiii
CHAPTER ONE
Fear 3
CHAPTER TWO
Greed 35
CHAPTER THREE
Guilt 67
vii
viii CONTENTS
CHAPTER FOUR
Deception 97
CHAPTER FIVE
Betrayal 123
CHAPTER SIX
Revenge 143
REFERENCES 163
INDEX 185
ACKNOWL EDGEMENTS
Salman Akhtar
Philadelphia, PA
ix
ABOUT THE AUTHOR
Fear
F
ear is ubiquitous. All of us experience it at one time or another.
The sound of footsteps approaching us from behind in a dark
alley, an unexpected visit to the city morgue, eye contact with a
large alligator in the zoo, and a precipitous “fall” of a rollercoaster can
all give us goose bumps of terror. We shriek, scream, or simply become
paralysed with fear. We readily recognise its dark arrival in the pit of
our stomachs and feel its movement in our blood.
But do we understand the actual nature of fear? Do we know the
purpose it serves? Do we agree upon the circumstances under which
it is “normal” to be afraid? And, when does fear become abnormal or
morbid? Is fear to be avoided at all costs or can this bitter gourd of
emotion be transformed into a sweet mango of cultural delight? Ques-
tions like these suggest that fear is simple and self-evident only on the
surface. Examined carefully, it turns out to be a complex and nuanced
phenomenon.
Fear
Webster’s dictionary defines fear as “an unpleasant, often strong
emotion caused by anticipation or awareness of danger” (Mish, 1998,
3
4 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
p. 425). While the source of the threat is not identified, the tone makes
it clear that the danger referred to resides in external reality. Fear, in other
words, is a dysphoric reaction to an actual object (e.g., a wild animal,
a knife-wielding drunkard), event (e.g., an earthquake, a stampede),
or situation (e.g., watching a horror movie, losing control of a car on an
icy road) that is felt to be threatening. The extent of dysphoria in the face
of approaching danger varies and four levels of fear’s severity are iden-
tified in the English language: (a) apprehension, which refers to a mild
anticipation of a bad occurrence; (b) dread, which blends the convic-
tion that one is facing danger with a powerful reluctance to encounter
the scary object or situation; (c) panic, which denotes an overwhelming
sense of being scared, coupled with alarmed hyperactivity (e.g., pacing,
running away) and physiological arousal (e.g., increased heartbeat,
laboured breathing); and (d) terror, which signifies an extreme degree
of consternation, a feeling of doom, “catastrophic aloneness” (Grand,
2002), and psychomotor paralysis.
The fact that fear is ubiquitous in the animal kingdom suggests that
it is a “needed emotion”, that is, one that is important for the organ-
ism’s survival and functioning. For all living beings, including humans,
the emotion of fear serves as a protective device; it warns them that
some danger is approaching and they had better undertake measures
to avoid it. This could be in the form of actively combating the “enemy”
or rapidly escaping from it, meaning the well-known “fight-or-flight”
response to threats.
Some fears are widespread over the animal kingdom and seem
“hard-wired”. Others are the result of developmentally unfolding, epi-
genetic sequence of fantasies that are specific to human beings. Among
the former are fear of loud noises, sudden and jerky movements,
looking down from heights, and animals that have fangs, claws, sharp
teeth, and can jump or move at great speed (Abraham, 1913a; Akhtar &
Brown, 2005). Present from birth onwards and persistent throughout
life (even if in attenuated forms and at a preconscious level), these
fears give testimony to man’s essential kinship with animals since their
function is self-protective and oriented towards survival. Among the
latter are the developmentally derived fears of loss of love objects, loss
of love, and castration (Freud, 1926d); fear of death joins this list some-
what later during the course of psychic development. These “hard-
wired” and developmentally derived fears exist in both sexes though
there is some evidence (Horner, 1968; Miller, 1994; Symonds, 1985) that,
FEAR 5
Anxiety
Fear and anxiety share some characteristics. Both evoke a sense that
something bad is about to happen. Both are unpleasant and undesir-
able experiences. Both can serve as alarms and thus protect us from
danger. However, in other ways, the two experiences are different. Fear
is a response to external danger; anxiety to dangers emanating from the
internal world. As early as 1895, Freud noted the relationship between
“unpleasure” (not yet delineated as anxiety) to earlier painful experi-
ences. He wrote:
Thirty years later, Freud (1926d) published his major work on the prob-
lem of anxiety and restated this thesis. However, this time, he linked the
cathexis of previous traumata and their memories to the specific affect
of anxiety. He stated:
Phobia
By itself, fear is a rational response and therefore poses few problems.
When it gets fuelled by anxiety in a regressive blurring of external and
internal realities, difficulties of clinical proportions begin to arise. The
most well known among these conditions is phobia. A term derived the
Greek word phobos (meaning flight, dread, and panic), phobia stands
for “marked and persistent fear that is excessive or unreasonable,
cued by the presence or anticipation of a specific object or situation”
(DSM-IV-TR, 2000, p. 449). In effect, both anxiety (internal danger) and
fear (external danger) coexist within phobia, although in their pure forms,
anxiety and fear are quite different (see Table 1). Phobia is distinct from
FEAR 9
symptom usually develops at the onset of latency, that is, around six
to eight years of age. There is little tendency for its “generalisation”
and there is little tension in the absence of the phobic object.
• Social phobia: involves fear of public speaking, blushing, shak-
ing, writing, eating, drinking, vomiting, or becoming incontinent
in public. It occurs with equal frequency among men and women
and usually starts after puberty, with a peak of incidence in the late
teens.
• Miscellaneous specific phobias: start any time in life and persist fairly
consistently. The phobic situations vary from one case to another but
remain fairly specific for a given individual. The dreaded situations
include travel, heights, wind, thunderstorms, darkness, bridges, and
large bodies of water.
are “chosen” as fearful. Some of these authors have pointed to the fact
that most animal phobias involve harmless (spider, cockroach, maggot,
snake, and rat) rather than predatory animals (lions, tigers, sharks);
they postulate that animal phobias correlate more with contamination
and disgust rather than with fear. Together, these three aetiological
perspectives, namely modelling, vicarious learning, and observational
conditioning, along with consideration of potential hereditary determi-
nants of fear and phobias (Delprato, 1980), might explain why specific
animals have remained both “chosen” phobia objects and symbols in
mythology in almost every culture.
Returning to the psychoanalytic perspective on phobias, one notes
that the complexity of their dynamics is due to the fact that repression
alone becomes incapable of keeping the threat sufficiently removed
from awareness. As a result, displacement, symbolism, and regression
come into play. Displacement, the process by which an affect or attitude
is unconsciously transferred from one object to a more acceptable sub-
stitute, is then added to repression. Now, it is not the sexual situations
but the sexualised situations that are feared. The diffuse anxiety becomes
bound to a specific object/situation. This makes life easier, since the
specificity of the fear now makes matters manageable through the
active process of avoidance. The advantage offered by displacement is
that the original offensive idea/affect does not become conscious. Also,
by binding the hostile vector of ambivalence towards one’s father, for
instance, into a fear of horses, the displacement tends to resolve con-
flicts of ambivalence. Also, as Freud (1909b) pointed out, displacement
by itself renders avoidance easier.
The feared object/situation often represents an exquisitely unique
and symbolic crystallisation of all the important determinants of the
phobia, including the predominant impulse of threat against which
the phobia is a defence. Jones (1948) emphasised the role of symbolism
in phobia, noting that there is a certain affinity between the individual
and the icons he chooses to express his instrapsychic concerns. Lewin
(1952) likened the process determining the specific phobia to the dream
work, sharing the same overdetermination and other parallel phenom-
ena, including traces of early experiences. Although universally sym-
bolic meanings for various phobias may be suggested, these are not
invariably valid. It is therefore better not to approach the patient’s pho-
bia with preconceived ideas about its meaning. The true meaning of
any symbol to an individual patient can be determined only by listen-
ing to his/her associations.
FEAR 13
Phobic character
Introduced by Fenichel (1945), the designation “phobic character” is
reserved for individuals “whose reactive behavior limits itself to the
avoidance of situations originally wished-for” (p. 527). Those with
severe inhibitions of sexuality and aggressiveness also display a similar
picture of generalised apprehension and social withdrawal. Elaborat-
ing on Fenichel’s proposal, Mackinnon and Michels (1971) emphasised
that more common than ego-dystonic, monosymptomatic phobia is
the use of fearful avoidance as a character defence, adding that such
FEAR 15
Cowardice
A habitual reaction to threat and danger, cowardice—at least on the
surface—is a response to fear of actual harm. It involves a “crippling of
the will” (Menaker, 1979, p. 93); one succumbs to fear and withdraws
from the “combat”.4 Cowardice can be evident in physical, intellectual,
and moral realms. Physical cowardice involves an inordinate fear of
injury and the resulting restriction of exploratory and playful motor
activity; one avoids athletics, amusement park rides, and any possibil-
ity of physical altercation. Intellectual cowardice results in inhibition of
mental activity; one cannot think “outside the box” and gets scared if
new insights do pop up in the mind. Moral cowardice manifests as the
inability to uphold ethical standards and speak the truth under difficult
circumstances; one lies, suddenly seems to lack words, and adopts the
“silence of the complicit” (Akhtar, 2013a).
The coward reacts to confrontation with distress. In part, this is
due to “automatic anxiety” (Freud, 1926d), the spontaneous reaction
16 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
A cultural digression
Although fear is ubiquitous in human existence, it does have a deep
and complex relationship with culture. Their relationship is often dia-
lectical in nature. Fear can disturb a culture’s slumber and mobilise
adaptive and maladaptive responses. Cultural narratives can embellish
existing fears, create new ones, and offer rich iconography for both. All
this becomes evident in the realms of regional concerns, prejudice, poli-
tics, literature, and even entertainment. The following passages address
these matters in brief.
Some fears (e.g., looking down from a great height, fast-moving ani-
mals) seem so widely spread across the globe as to appear independ-
ent of cultural influences. Like “universal dreams” (Freud, 1900a),5 such
“universal fears” combine phylogenetic predisposition, evolutionary
advantages, and precipitates of early childhood experiences. Other fears
are idiosyncratic, limited to some people, and, at times, restricted to
regions and eras. Fear of ghosts and evil spirits, for instance, has largely
gone from modernised societies while persisting in less educated, less
industrialised, rural and sub-rural communities of the world. Fears of
earthquakes, floods, and tornadoes are generally restricted to areas with
vulnerability to such disasters. Similarly, animal phobias are regionally
anchored; it is hardly conceivable for one living in Saudi Arabia to be
afraid of polar bears.
The phenomenology of “culture-bound psychiatric syndromes”
(Guarnaccia & Rogler, 1999; Meth, 1974; Yap, 1969) is replete with
observations that support this line of thought. Not only animals that
populate a specific region are chosen as phobic objects by people living
there, they can also become the suitable containers of projections of the
attributes of bravery and cowardice. In colloquial English, for instance,
a coward is referred to as “chicken-hearted” or merely a “chicken”
and in Spanish, as gallina (hen). In Arabic, a brave man is called an
assag (lion) while in Urdu, such a person is called sher-dil (one with a
lion’s heart); in contrast, a coward is called buz-dil (one with a goat’s
heart). What all this demonstrates is that not only are the objects of
fear but even the metaphors of bravery and cowardice often regionally
determined.
Fear plays in important role in prejudice as well. The “unmentalized
xenophobia” (Akhtar, 2007c) that results in bland indifference towards
and avoidance of those different from oneself is merely the tip of the
18 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Under such circumstances, the analyst might feel afraid and rationally
worry about the safety of himself, others, or the patient. This might
22 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Clinical vignette: 1
Sarah Green, a forty-five-year-old librarian made an appointment
to see me upon her sister’s insistence. She appeared overwhelmed
with pain at the break-up of a romantic relationship. Having
lived alone most of her life, she found this belated attachment
profoundly significant. The man she was involved with was mar-
ried. He abruptly left her saying that he could no longer continue
cheating on his wife. She was destroyed. Heartbroken, she came to
see me.
We began the first hour of consultation in a customary history-
taking way. However, within twenty minutes of the session, she
announced that she had decided to blow her head off with a gun
which she had bought earlier that day. Alarmed by the earnestness
of her tone, I suggested that we take immediate steps to get the gun
removed from her apartment, obtain some collateral information
regarding the extent of her depression, and consider beginning our
work on an inpatient basis. The patient reacted sharply to my sug-
gestion and, refusing to let me contact her sister who could remove
the gun, got up to leave the office. At this point, I said to her, “Look,
everybody gets about ten candles’ worth of life and inside you
eight have already gone off. The wind is blowing hard and to pro-
tect the remaining two candles, you came here and put them in
my heart. Now, since you have enlisted me for this purpose, it is
my duty to keep these two candles protected from the wind. When
the storm settles, I will return them to you so that you can light the
other eight candles back with their help.” The patient broke down
in tears and after some thinking gave me the permission to contact
her sister who subsequently removed the gun from the patient’s
apartment and encouraged the patient to stay at her house for the
next few days.
Clinical vignette: 2
Bob Dolinski, a borderline young man in twice weekly psycho-
therapy, exploded with rage when I refused to comply with his
demand for painkillers. In a menacing tone, he threatened to
take my eyeballs out and crush them under his feet. Alarmed by
his emotional flooding and rapidly disintegrating reality-testing,
I firmly told him to stay put in his chair. I added that if he as much
as laid a finger on me I would terminate the treatment and never
see him again. I told him that he needed someone who could listen
to him peacefully, not someone who was afraid of him and that I
would be afraid of him if he acted even once on his impulse to hurt
me. Noticing that he was settling down, I added that the idea that
he could take my eyeballs out was both unrealistic and intriguing.
He could not do it; I would not let him. And, why did he think of
eyeballs in the first place? Could it have something to do with the
memory of his mother looking contemptuously at him? Interven-
tions along these lines calmed him down and soon the session was
progressing in a more mutually related manner.
Clinical vignette: 3
Rebecca Cohen, twenty-six-year-old daughter of a Holocaust sur-
vivor father, was in analysis with me. The course of early treat-
ment was filled with anxiety-laden fantasies about her father’s
experience in the Nazi concentration camp. Dreaded scenarios of
ethnic hatred and violence preoccupied Rebecca and this readily
spread to the transference. She feared and hated me, regarded me
as a Jew-hating Muslim or Arab, and suspected that I supported
anti-Israeli violence by Palestinians. Projections of her own trans-
generationally given post-traumatic Jew-Nazi split of the self were
constantly active in her relatedness with me. One day, I was hated
and viciously attacked. Next day, I was deeply feared.
FEAR 25
Clinical vignette: 4
As the treatment proceeded, Sarah Green (the patient mentioned
in clinical vignette 1) recounted details of her long-term suicidal
wishes and her constant sense, while growing up, that her mother
FEAR 27
hated her and wanted her dead. She also talked about the harsh
criticism her mother directed at her; she repeatedly called Sarah a
“monster” and an “evil one”. Not surprisingly, Sarah was terrified
of her mother and made few demands on her time and attention.
As these details unfolded, Sarah stole a revolver from her
sister’s house and started sleeping with it—fully loaded—in her
hand. I was terrified and yet felt prompted to stay away, this time,
from insisting that she get rid of the gun immediately. I had a vague
sense that the fear I was experiencing was the consequence of pro-
jective identification with her frightened child-self, as well as a
direct result of her revenge-seeking fantasies. In other words, due
to the effect of her projection, I had become “scared little Sarah”
while she had adopted the role of her terrifying mother. And, at
the same time, she had transformed herself from poor little Sarah
to intimidating Sarah and I, as the mother, had to be tormented for
what I had done to her as a child.
The very fact that I could conceptualise the enactment and put
what was, most likely, going on into mental words, told me that
there was something containable and, ultimately, interpretable
here. The risk (for her) was high and the fear (in me) palpable but
session after session, we talked about the potential underlying what
was taking place—feelings, somewhere deep in our hearts, that we
did not need to rupture the enactment by behavioural limit-setting,
that she needed me to bear the anxiety. We felt that all that was
happening was in the “pretend mode” (Fonagy & Target, 1997).
Then one afternoon, Sarah called me, saying that she was feeling
truly suicidal again. I had another patient in the waiting room and
asked her if she could assure me that she would not do anything
impulsive and self-destructive for the next hour. She promised and
we agreed that I would call her as soon as the patient I was about to
see left. However, when I called, the phone kept ringing and ringing
and Sarah did not pick it up. I was horrified, and thought that she
had killed herself. Trembling with fear and cursing myself for being
unduly heroic and adventuresome in my clinical work, I called her
sister, who immediately departed for Sarah’s apartment. The next
thirty minutes were the longest thirty minutes I have ever lived.
Then, I got a call from her sister that she had found Sarah fast asleep
and that everything was fine and under control. Sarah came on the
phone and profusely apologised for what had happened. I accepted
28 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
her apology but, feeling that a certain line had been crossed (and,
that from a containing mother, I was becoming an ignoring and
destructive mother), I insisted that the sister not only take the gun
away but immediately dispose of it in a manner that Sarah would
never be able to get her hands on it again. This intervention and its
subsequent discussion in the clinical setting paved the way for the
deepening of our therapeutic work.
Second is the fear of the analyst’s own impulses to act out. If the analyst
is under great personal stress (e.g., bereavement, divorce, serious ill-
ness), his fear of acting out with his patients, using his patients to
diminish his loneliness, and venting sexual or aggressive effects (even
if in a mild and aim-inhibited manner) is plausible and worthy of atten-
tion; consultation with a trusted colleague or return to some treatment
must be considered under such circumstances. However, there are other
times when the analyst is functioning optimally and yet develops a fear
of doing something odd or strange with his patient. This is the stuff
of countertransference and restraint coupled with self-reflection often
reveals the nature of transference that is putting such pressure on the
analyst. Here is a clinical example of such an occurrence.
Clinical vignette: 5
Melanie Wright, a boyish young woman had sought treatment
owing to feelings of anxiety and some marital tension. She had
panicked when her husband was laid off from his job and, even
though he was able to find gainful employment soon afterwards,
remained anxious; in fact, she feared that they would become des-
titute. She and her husband frequently argued over this fear of hers
and the friction between them was growing.
What struck me most when I first met her, however, was not
this undue anxiety but the fact that she—a young woman in her
mid-twenties—looked like a teenage boy. Making a mental note of
it, I proceeded with gathering some background history. It turned
out that her parents were divorced when she was six years old and
that she had been raised by a loving but industrious and busy pro-
fessional mother. Two other important facts were that the divorce
had been precipitated by her father’s announcement that he was
gay and that young Melanie had to grow up with a very difficult
FEAR 29
Concluding remarks
In this chapter, I have described fear, categorised its intensities, and
traced its developmental origins. I have delineated the similarities and
differences between fear and anxiety while showing how the two coex-
ist in the state of phobia. Following this, I have made a brief foray into
the cultural realm and attempted to demonstrate how the unpleasant
emotion of fear can be turned into the excitement of horror movies,
gothic literature, and thrill-seeking games, while, on the negative side
of things, forming a part of ethno-racial prejudice and political oppres-
sion. Returning to the clinical realm, I have discussed the presence of
fear in the transference-countertransference matrix and outlined the
strategies to deal with the resulting problems.
Before concluding, however, it seems only fair to make some com-
ments about psychic states that seem to be the opposite of fear. There
are three such conditions: (i) fearlessness, (ii) counterphobia, and
32 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Notes
1. An admittedly incomplete list includes ablutophobia (fear of wash-
ing), acrophobia (fear of heights), agoraphobia (fear of open spaces),
arachnophobia (fear of spiders), batrachophobia (fear of frogs), claustro-
phobia (fear of enclosed spaces), homophobia (fear of homosexuals),
Islamophobia (fear of Muslims), photophobia (fear of lights), and so
on. The list, frankly, can be endless; one internet site contains 530
entries!
2. This affected the later reconstructions of Little Hans’s childhood as well
(Joseph, 1990; Silverman, 1980), which gave more attention to his pre-
Oedipal development.
34 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Greed
I
t is to the gifted Greek storyteller of ancient times, Aesop (circa
620 BC), that we owe the eternally impressive tale of greed. Among
the numerous fables told by him is this story of the farmer who
found a goose that laid a golden egg each day. Initially jubilant at his
good fortune, the farmer soon felt unable to wait twenty-four hours for
the next egg to arrive. He imagined that the goose had hundreds of eggs
inside her but was stingy in doling out the wealth. The farmer grew
restless and wanted all the gold immediately. He cut the goose open but
found no gold inside it. All that happened was that the goose died and
the farmer lost the daily nugget of riches that was assured to him.
In this brief tale, Aesop elegantly addressed the coexistence of enor-
mous hunger, impatience, inconsolability, a defective sense of empa-
thy, and ingratitude towards one’s benefactors. It is this constellation of
descriptive and dynamic features that are subsumed under the rubric of
greed. Since greed—along with narcissism, paranoia, and discontent—
constitutes an important feature of severe personality disorders and has
an unmistakable impact upon their treatment, it is surprising that psy-
choanalytic literature has given inadequate attention to it.
My contribution here aims to fill this gap in our literature. In it,
I will discuss the nature of greed and highlight its phenomenological
35
36 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Descriptive aspects
Webster’s dictionary defines greed as “excessive and reprehensi-
ble acquisitiveness” (Mish, 1998, p. 511). The meaning of this phrase
seems self-evident. However, a careful look reveals its ambiguous,
even though textured, nature. The first qualifier (“excessive”) suggests
that acquisitiveness is to be termed greed only after it exceeds a certain
threshold but does not specify what that threshold is and how and by
whom it has been set up. The second qualifier (“reprehensible”) posits
that greed lacks dignity, is vulgar, perhaps even immoral, and some-
thing to be looked down upon but does not reveal why does greed
deserve such derision. Left in a phenomenological morass, we open our
eyes wider, search for more clues, and look deeper and farther. Now it
dawns upon us that what we call “greed” is actually a complex set of
affects, attitudes, and fantasies lumped together. For didactic ease and
to create epistemic order out of chaos, I divide the phenomena pertain-
ing to greed into three categories: (i) primary manifestation, (ii) second-
ary manifestations, and (iii) defensive distortions.
Primary manifestations
The best-recognised aspect of greed—to the extent that it is consid-
ered the crux of the matter—is an excessive and unrelenting desire to
acquire and possess goods. Its “excessive” nature is revealed by the fact
that the quantity of goods desired far surpasses actual need as well as
by its exaggerated quality when compared to the desires of others. Its
GREED 37
Money and food are, however, not the only realms in which greed
makes its appearance. Sex is another area where the operation of greed
38 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Secondary manifestations
Alongside the three “primary” features of greed (i.e., excessive desire,
inconsolability, entitlement) exist certain other manifestations. Promi-
nent among these are a constant sense of hurry, ingratitude, defects of
empathy, and corruption of superego functions. Hurrying, on which
there is a lamentable lack of psychoanalytic musing, is a frequent
accompaniment of greed, since to be able to wait means tolerating “less-
than-full” states of body and mind. Waiting for supplies also implies
taking turns, sharing with others, and believing in a less than magical
regeneration of goods. The greedy individual insists upon sustained
fullness and cannot tolerate temporal gaps in the appearance of sup-
plies; impatience is the twin sister of avarice.
Ingratitude is also a frequent accompaniment of greed. Called the
“marble-hearted fiend” by Shakespeare (King Lear, 1606, I, iv, p. 283),
ingratitude is, in essence, a refusal to acknowledge that one has received
goodness, love, and material supplies from others. No amount of indul-
gence appears enough to the one incapable of gratitude. Inwardly meas-
uring every favour against the “debt” owed to him due to childhood
deprivation, such an individual becomes incapable of enjoying what is
offered and remains thankless to his benefactors. He gobbles up what is
given, does not acknowledge others’ generosity, and keeps craving for
more (Akhtar, 2012; Bergler, 1945).
Constant yearning for supplies leads to pushing others aside and
losing contact with their needs and rights. Driven self-interest causes
blindness to others’ place in the market of libidinal supplies. This indif-
ference to fellow human beings is most likely the reason that greed
GREED 39
Defensive distortions
Greed can be rendered unconscious by defensive operations of the ego
due to moral condemnation from within and/or due to the need to
safeguard a lofty self-image. Four common defences deployed against
greed are repression, reaction formation, splitting, and projective
identification. By the use of repression, all temptations and longings
felt to be “greedy” are sent into psychic exile. However, since “[T]he
repressed exercises a continuous pressure in the direction of the con-
scious” (Freud, 1915d, p. 151), hints of greed continue to appear in
parapraxes and dreams. Moreover, the individual who has repressed
his own greed feels exquisitely uncomfortable at encountering the
attitude in others and might even equate their healthy appetites with
avarice. A not infrequent accompaniment is pretended contempt for
money in real life (Jones, 1913) and “moral narcissism” (Green, 1986),
that is, yearning to be pure, free of attachment, and above ordinary
human needs.4 Disenchantment with food to the extent of develop-
ing anorexia nervosa is often the consequence of such narcissism and
repressed greed (Davies, 2004).
Reaction formation against greed can give rise to “unrelenting gener-
osity” (Akhtar, 2013a), which involves excessive and incessant giving to
others. The individual feels helpless in the face of an inward command
to provide and be helpful; such giving exceeds realistic limits both of
what one has and what others need. It cloaks and defends against greed,
envy, and the need to control the object (Seelig & Rosof, 2001).
Another distortion occurs when self-representations tinged with
greed are held in abeyance via the mechanism of vertical splitting.
A “mirror complimentarity of the self” (Bach, 1977) then develops
whereby the individual consciously experiences and alternately acts
out the contradictory attitudes of being greedy and being not greedy.
He seems rational and well regulated in his appetites and then, to eve-
ryone’s surprise, suddenly turns greedy. Sequestered avarice of this sort
can also undergo projective identification and lead to the perception of
others being greedy. When this happens, desires and demands of others
are looked at with suspicion, even if those wishes are, in fact, realistic.
GREED 41
Developmental origins
The word “greed” appears only six times in the complete corpus of
Freud’s work (Guttman, Jones & Parrish, 1980). Five of these usages are
colloquial and of little theoretical significance. The sixth, though set in
the context of his ironic view of human nature, does reveal where he
thought greed originated in the course of psychic development. Freud
stated the following:
speak, greed can evolve into appetite. Appetite makes actual (and not
wished-for) experience for the first time a player in the developmental
process. The fact is that actual experience not only plays a role during
the formative years of childhood, when it contributes to the genesis of
greed, but also during adult life where it sustains greed and/or causes
its reactive flare-ups. This “actual experience” comes both from home
and from the society-at-large.
Sociocultural aspects
The topic of greed and culture is vast and can hardly be dealt with
comprehensively in this largely clinical essay. Nonetheless, it is impor-
tant to be addressed since neither do our children grow up in a cul-
tural void nor our patients remain unaffected by the societal currents
around them. In innumerable ways, sociocultural institutions and
practices interact with, and are affected by, the human propensity
towards greed. Such interplay is more marked in societies dominated
by capitalistic ideology and the free market economy. The monetary
ambition of producers of goods forcefully impacts on individual sub-
jectivity and seeks to turn the general population into mere “consum-
ers.5 The following scenarios highlight the interplay of capitalism and
human greed.
• Induction of false needs: Even though all human beings have the same
psychological needs (e.g., needs for safety, freedom, identity, affir-
mation, love, causality, temporal continuity, and generativity), those
living in capitalist economies are vulnerable to experiencing their
wishes also as needs (Akhtar, 1999a). For instance, food is a need
but the variety of pizza toppings offered can create a wish for them
which under the mesmerising juggernaut of advertising can be expe-
rienced as an urgent need. Respite from the daily humdrum of work
and turning to moments of leisure is certainly an emotional need but
the alluring luxuries of today’s resorts and retreats can delude one
into thinking that such accoutrements are truly needed for relaxation.
Induction of such “false needs” lies at the core of a consumer-driven
economy; the more one can make people buy things, the better off the
state of the nation, declares this mentality. Hypnotised by seductive
television commercials, the vulnerable person begins to feel needy
and, over time, turns greedy.
GREED 47
Two caveats must be entered here. The first pertains to whether some
nations are more greed-driven than others and whether the East and
the West differ in the extent and nature of greed. The second pertains to
our selective use of the word “greed” vis-à-vis certain pursuits in life.
Regarding the first matter, it should be noted that such generalisations
are prone to error and fail to take into account that all sorts of human
48 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
beings exist in all sorts of societies. At the same time, it is possible that
some cultures might be less money-driven than others. A comparison,
for instance, of the over $60,000 annual fees for medical school tuition
in the United States with Germany, where such education is free for the
students pointedly brings this point home. Another illustration comes
in the form of socialised medicine. Nations that provide universal access
to health care create an ambiance of safety and fuel material pursuits to
a lesser extent. Less greed is in the air people breathe in such lands.
The second matter, namely, our applying the term “greedy” to some
pursuits and not to others, also reveals some interesting points for consid-
eration. For instance, if an investment banker makes a lot of money and
has little sense of civic responsibility or if a real estate mogul keeps build-
ing one high rise tower after another, we are quick to call them greedy.
But if a fiction writer churns out novel after novel or if a psychoanalyst
publishes paper after paper, we do not look upon them as “greedy”. We
readily discern greed in overeating but are reluctant to see it in vora-
cious reading. Why? Is all this a knee-jerk response to our exposure
to corrupt and scandalous entrepreneurs like Bernie Madoff? Is this a
moral recoil from Gordon Gekko’s7 celebrated declaration that “greed
is good”? Or does it express an idealised preference for aim-inhibited
discharge of instincts on our part? Have we inherited this legacy from
Freud’s stoic ethics? If that is indeed so, are we not ignoring that some
creative activities are actually “pseudo-sublimatory” (Kernberg, 1975),
that is, done in the pursuit of glory, fame, and immortality? And, worse,
by harshly judging rich businessmen, are we not overlooking that their
work itself might be about making money (sublimation in the direction
of what we deride as instinctual) and require great devotion and intel-
lectual prowess? To be sure, no clear-cut solutions exist for such concep-
tual conundrums but we must acknowledge their existence. Humility
of this sort might preclude moralising and enhance curiosity. It might
even become a stepping stone for developing poignant empathy and
“respect” for what is or seems to be greed in others. This applies to
sociopolitical views as well as to clinical work with patients.
Waska (2003a) notes that greed destroys insights gained in analysis. The
hunger for more coupled with intense oral aggression makes internali-
sation and retention of good objects (including the analyst) difficult.
Prognosis is far better, in my experience, for patients who are con-
sciously aware of their greed and can even muster a bit of self-reflective
humour about their malady.
Clinical vignette: 6
Phil Robertson, a highly successful businessman in his late thir-
ties, had sought analysis for being unable to establish a sustained
romantic relationship with a woman. He was tall, handsome,
wealthy, well mannered, and, generally speaking, a very likeable
person. As a result, he had no difficulty in finding women to date.
He was constantly “fixed” with women by his peers and relatives;
others sought him out spontaneously. The problem, though, was
that he could not tolerate them beyond three or four dates. Their
slightest “blemish” would lead him to become totally disenchanted,
even hateful. One had a coarse laughter. Another came to the date
wearing sandals. A third one did not know who Chaucer was. And,
a fourth one hated Boston (which Phil liked very much). And so
on. Soon each became history. Phil’s restless search for a “good”
woman (he was smart and avoided the word “perfect”) began to
appear endless.
Soon after starting analysis, Phil said, with wry laughter, “Doc,
I am the sort of guy who is never satisfied by ninety per cent of any-
thing.” Elaborating upon this, he said, “If you put all my favour-
ite food items on a boat in amounts that would last for a hundred
years and then have me sail away, I would still be worried about
the potential of scarcity. What if I wanted something and it was not
on the boat? What if it had fallen out of the boat? What will I then
do?” As this material unfolded, a childhood memory emerged. Phil
recalled that, on more than one occasion, when a dish was being
passed around during the family’s dinner, his mother reversed
the direction of the dish’s movement as it was about to reach him.
Consequently, he was unable to take that food item. The “screen
memory” (Freud, 1899a) nature of this account did not preclude
my empathy with his sense of chronic deprivation during child-
hood. Somehow, though, he had maintained a sense of humour,
GREED 51
too, about this pain. For instance, once he laughed and said, “Doc,
wouldn’t you say that life with a woman who has a big mole on her
back would be tough?”
Clinical vignette: 7
Amira Hashmi, a Pakistani-American student of clinical social
work, was bored with her studies and wanted to drop out of the
university. However, she had no alternative plan. Nothing excited
her. She felt depressed, adrift, and utterly anhedonic. Referred by a
fellow analyst, she came to see me having tried psychotherapy as
well as antidepressant medications to no avail.
A polite, soft-spoken woman of extraordinary intelligence and
keen empathy for her “clients”, Amira filled the sessions with what
Warren Poland has called “militant hopelessness” (cited in Jordan,
2002, p. 989). She cried endlessly, declared incessantly that her
treatment with me was bound to fail. “Nothing will change, I can
tell you. Ten years will pass and I will be suffering in the same way
and to the same extent.”
The omnipotence that underlay such a seemingly hopeless (but
darkly triumphant) rant was beyond her awareness. Calling herself
weak, mindless, lifeless, inept, and stupid, Amina nonetheless dis-
played great eloquence, impressive debating capacity, and stunning
certainty regarding her dire predictions. More strikingly, she would
beseech me to speak, comment, and comfort her, but would instan-
taneously turn anything I said as meaningless; she either told me
that I was flat-out wrong or repeated my interventions in an exag-
gerated and mocking manner. Nothing I could say or do brought
her any comfort. She told me so and yet she came to her sessions
with saintly devotion and asked me to speak with greater frequency
during sessions. She was intolerant of my silence and rejecting of
my words. I was an emptied out, defiled breast from which she
nonetheless demanded the milk of therapeutic optimism.
Powerful and accurate though this statement is, it does not take into
account that the patient is not alone in bringing the hues of greed into
the clinical situation. The analyst contributes to it, too. An excessively
austere style of intervening on the analyst’s part can stoke the fires of
GREED 53
Clinical vignette: 8
Pamela Kasinetz, an elderly woman of extreme wealth, sought
psychotherapy for depression and anxiety of recent origin. The
apparent trigger for this was the worsening relationship with her
husband of over three decades. With their children no longer at
home, the two had become quite alienated; he was engrossed in his
business and she with her social commitments and philanthropic
work. Matters became worse when Pamela ran into an “adorable”
seven- or eight-year-old Cambodian boy in a shopping mall and
“fell in love with him”. She took it upon herself to help him and his
financially strained family. The boy gradually became her constant
companion. Paying huge sums of money to his parents, Pamela
pretty much took over his life. She would pick him up from school,
bring him home, shower him with lavish gifts, and indulge all his
whims and desires; his friends also were welcome at her house and
were treated with similar indulgence. While numerous examples
can be given, one instance should suffice, where she spent in excess
of thirty thousand dollars over a weekend entertaining her little
“friend” and his four playmates. All this led to frequent arguments
between Pamela and her husband, who insisted on putting limits
54 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Clinical vignette: 9
In the process of writing her will, Kathleen Roberts, a wealthy
widow in her late seventies, became anxious and sought consul-
tation with me. Intellectually gifted, artistic, and good looking,
GREED 55
Clinical vignette: 10
Judith Conahan, a highly intelligent lawyer with narcissistic per-
sonality disorder, was in analysis with me. For the first year or
so, all she talked about was how she felt unloved by her husband
and, during her childhood, by her mother. She never made a com-
ment about me and in effect treated me with an indifference that
was quite like what she had received from her mother. Then, in
the eighteenth month of her analysis, I announced that I had to
take a few days off at rather short notice. The patient responded to
the news with immediate acceptance and the usual lack of associa-
tions. The next day, however, she began her session by telling me
that one of her clients had cancelled an appointment that morning.
During that hour, she went through her desk drawers and found
her home insurance policy. Judith went on to tell me that she got
quite upset upon reading parts of that policy. There were too many
loopholes, too little coverage! Discerning unmistakable allusions to
my impending absence (e.g., “cancelled appointment”, “too little
coverage”) in her associations, I said: “Perhaps, you find it easier to
talk about an insurance policy with loopholes than an analysis with
interruptions.” After a long pause, she responded in a pained voice:
GREED 57
“I can see how you arrived at what you said but it hurt my feelings
because I was really worried about the policy and it seems that you
are not paying attention to my concern about it.”
Clinical vignette: 11
Stephanie Brooks, an analysand with known psychosomatic sensi-
tivity to fresh paint, started to sneeze and cough badly during her
second session in my office in a brand new building. Knowing that
the hallway water fountains were not yet functional, she asked me
where she could get some water to drink. I told her that she could
step out and I would instruct my secretary, on the intercom, to give
her a paper cup, which she could take to the ladies’ room to get
some water. The patient went out and returned within a few min-
utes. She mumbled “Thanks” and resumed the chain of thought she
was pursuing earlier. I listened to the material carefully, wondering
if any overt or covert reference to my intervention would appear.
None did. During the next couple of sessions, I silently looked for
any reference to my intervention but did not find it.
Clinical vignette: 12
In the throes of a regressive transference, Jill Schwartz entered my
office enraged and waving a finger. Approaching the couch, she
said, “I have a lot on my mind today and I want to do all the talk-
ing. I don’t want you to speak even a single word!” A little taken
aback, I mumbled, “Okay.” Jill shouted, “I said, ‘not one word’ and
you have already fucked up this session!” Now sitting on my chair
behind her, I was rattled. “Did I do wrong by speaking at all?”
58 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
I asked myself. As she lay on the couch, angrily silent and stiff,
I started to think. Perhaps she is so inconsolable today, so intent
upon forcing me into the role of a depriving person, that she found
a way to see even the gratification of her desire as its frustration.
I was, however, not entirely satisfied with this explanation and
therefore decided to wait, and think further. It then occurred to me
that maybe she was rightly angered by my saying ‘Okay’. In my
agreeing to let her have omnipotent control over me, I had asserted
my will and thus paradoxically deprived her of the omnipotence
she seemed to need. I was about to make an interpretation along
these lines, when it occurred to me that by sharing this under-
standing, I would be repeating my mistake: making my autono-
mous psychic functioning too obvious. As a result, I decided to
only say, “I am sorry,” and left the remaining thought unspoken.
Jill relaxed and the tension in the room began to lessen. After ten
minutes of further silence, she said, “Well, this session has been
messed up. I had so many things to say.” After a further pause,
she said, “Among the various things on my mind …” and thus the
session gradually “started”. By the time we ended, things were
going pretty smoothly.
In both these cases, I chose not to explore and not to interpret what was
overtly an “attractive” piece of clinical material. In the first vignette,
I did not ask what, if any, fantasies the patient had about stepping out of
my office, getting a cup from the secretary, drinking water, and coming
back. In the second case, I did not ask the patient what the patient had
been thinking during the long silence before she resumed talking. Inter-
estingly, upon hearing the presentation of both vignettes, some analytic
colleagues expressed the opinion that I had missed important data by
my lack of investigation. While I am able to see their point and even
have some “old” empathy9 with such a perspective, I believe that not
analysing or letting go of some aspects of these sessions was preferable.
To do otherwise would unnecessarily “pathologise” iatrogenic events
and betray analytic greed.
Similar restraint is needed when faced with moments of “mutual
silence” (Akhtar, 2013b) during the clinical session. Such silences feel
peaceful. The analyst and the analysand are attuned to each other but
experience little need to speak (Elson, 2001). Take a look at the follow-
ing vignette.
GREED 59
Clinical vignette: 13
Marcy Schectman begins the last session of her nearly ten year long
analysis by saying that on her way to my office, she felt as if she
were coming to a funeral. She describes her experience of there
being an air of finality, solemnity, and loss to the afternoon. As I
remain silent, Marcy goes on to recount her experiences at a couple
of funerals she has attended. She sobs. I too feel sad, but do not say
anything. Gradually, her associations shift to her getting a doctor-
ate soon and then to graduation dinners, commencement ceremo-
nies, etc. She begins to be animated. Soon, however, she catches
herself and observes that this talk of happy endings (graduations)
is defensive against her sadness (funerals). Significantly, she adds
that while this might be the case, the two sides most likely repre-
sent the two sides of her feelings regarding parting from me for
good: “happy and sad, sad and happy”. I now say, “Yes, it does
seem like that,” and, after a momentary pause, add “but you know,
all well-timed funerals are graduations of a sort and all gradua-
tions contain funeral-like elements.” Marcy nods in agreement. She
remains silent and so do I for the next couple of minutes. The sense
of our being together in each other’s apartness is evident as the end
of the session approaches.
Here, like in the two preceding vignettes, it would have been greedy to
insist upon a verbal exploration of the patient’s silence, especially as it
occurred during the last few minutes of a long analysis. A better techni-
cal choice was to allow the non-verbal relatedness to remain intact, and
avoid succumbing to “interpretive greed”. Even outside the drama that
the very last session of an analysis presents, non-intrusive handling of
silences can form an extremely important “intervention” and a demon-
stration that the analyst has mastered his interpretive greed.
Clinical vignette: 14
Marilyn McDonough, a very attractive architect in her fifties,
had sought help following an emotional crisis with one of her
children. Once the acute matter was settled and the treatment
began to deepen, the centrality of her own mother’s death when
Marilyn was barely five years old came to the surface. A talented
60 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Clinical vignette: 15
Laura Klafter, a blond sixty-year-old widowed attorney, was in psy-
chotherapy with me for interpersonal difficulties that had plagued
her for a very long time. Estranged from her son, she felt bereft
62 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
What all these clinical examples show is that the analyst has to make
choices of not only what to address in a session but also of what to
leave untouched. Such titration of dosage, timing, and even the very
offer of interpretation is what makes analytic work forever challeng-
ing. Limentani’s (1989) quip that “Psychoanalysis is an art and for this
reason it needs discipline” (p. 260) is pertinent in this context. Needless
to say that the “art” consists of both interpreting and not interpreting.
Interpretive appetite is good, analytic greed is not.
Concluding remarks
In this chapter, I have delineated the phenomenological aspects of greed,
clarifying its manifestations into three categories: (i) primary, (ii) sec-
ondary, and (iii) defensively altered. Following this, I have elucidated
diverse perspectives on the ontogenetic origins of greed and included
the concepts of constitutionally innate greed, developmentally-
inevitable greed, and greed as an angry intensification of appetite. After
taking a brief foray into the sociocultural realm, I returned to the clini-
cal realm and discussed how conscious and unconscious greed operate
in the matrix of transference-countertransference relatedness.
Two areas remain to be addressed: variations in nature and inten-
sity of greed that are lifespan dependent and/or gender based. As far
as the impact of the unfolding epigenetic sequence of development is
concerned, only one thing is certain, that greed originates in infancy
and early childhood. What remains unclear is whether massive dep-
rivations during late childhood (e.g., death of a parent when the child
is six or seven) can “activate” or even “cause” greed for the first time.
GREED 63
Notes
1. For a detailed discussion of the need-wish distinction and its implica-
tions for psychoanalytic technique, see Akhtar (1999a).
2. Hoarding of things and animals appears to be a consequence of greed
on the surface. At its depth, though, hoarding is mostly a result of fear
of loss, inability to let go, and profound feelings of insecurity. Forever
needing the warmth of closeness to his objects, a hoarder is an ocnophile
(Balint, 1959) par excellence.
3. The term “pleonexic personality” was coined by Nikelly (1992) to
describe a character constellation dominated by pathological greed. In
his view, such preoccupation can be traced to fixation at the anal stage,
with money and faeces being symbolically connected. It may also be
attributed to loss of gratification.
4. Green (1986) distinguishes the resulting asceticism from masochism
on two grounds. First, the moral narcissist suffers from shame over his
needs, while the moral masochist suffers from guilt over his wishes.
Second, the moral narcissist seeks to impoverish his object relations in
order to restore his infantile megalomania of self sufficiency, while the
moral masochist retains a tormented but rich tie to his objects. An illus-
tration of moral narcissism comes from Gandhi (1940) who, in attempt-
ing to become passion-free, concluded: “I must reduce myself to zero”
(pp. 504-505).
5. This is clearly not true for many societies. To begin with, the sheer fact
of poverty keeps people “uninvolved” with money matters. And, on
top of it, the values of stoicism, asceticism, and spirituality uphold dis-
interest in monetary affairs. It is therefore not infrequent to find men
and women, especially of older age, with pretty much no contact with
money and little desire to purchase things. This can come as a huge sur-
prise to those living in capitalistic societies. No wonder the publication
of The Man Who Quit Money (Sundeen, 2012), an account of a Utah man
who has survived without spending a penny since 2000, in the United
States, was received with great scepticism and curiosity.
6. The provision of maternity leave for twelve weeks (with highly variable
salary support) in the United States compares poorly to the thirty-six
weeks in Norway and twenty weeks in Estonia, Poland, and Russia (all
with 100 per cent of the salary).
GREED 65
Guilt
I
“ am sorry” is perhaps the most versatile combination of three words
in the English language. Compared to its lexical rival, “I love you,”
the expression “I am sorry” is used far more often and in much more
varied contexts. It can carry the hues of emotions that vary from flimsy
courtesy through considerable remorse to soul-wrenching contrition. It
can therefore be spoken with comparable ease at spilling coffee on the
tablecloth, forgetting to turn the cell phone off during a play, hurting
a lover’s feelings, and hearing the news of someone’s passing away.
It can also be used by a child molester seeking a lesser punishment in
a court of law, a politician caught embezzling party funds, and even a
head of state expressing “regret” for policies that led to abuses of an
ethnic minority or for a weak response to a natural disaster.
All these instances involve the experience of guilt, be it real or pre-
tended, mild or severe, fleeting or sustained. The utterance of “I am
sorry” is always motivated by guilt. But what is guilt? What gives rise
to it? How does it affect us? And, why do some people feel so much
guilt, others so little? Certainly the emotion does not result solely from
committing “bad” (i.e., hurtful) acts. If that were the case, hardened
67
68 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Definition
According to Webster’s dictionary, the word “guilt” stands for: “1. The
fact of having committed a breach of conduct, especially violating law
and involving a penalty; 2a. The state of one who has committed an
offense, especially consciously, and, 2b. Feelings of culpability, espe-
cially from imagined offenses or from a sense of inadequacy” (Mish,
1998, p. 517). The scope of this definition is broad. It includes (i) an act
of breaking rules, (ii) the possibility that such act only took place in the
imagination, and (iii) the emotional state of the one who has commit-
ted the transgression. Additionally, by mentioning culpability from a
“sense of inadequacy”, the dictionary definition acknowledges that acts
of omission can also underlie feelings of guilt. This is pure and simple
English.
Now let us turn to five prominent psychoanalytic glossaries. Surpris-
ingly, two of these (Eidelberg, 1968; Laplanche & Pontalis, 1973) do not
have entries on “guilt”. The other three (Akhtar, 2009; Moore & Fine,
1990; Rycroft, 1968) do but end up with definitions of guilt that are of
variable quality. Rycroft (1968) regards it to be “the emotion which fol-
lows infringement of a moral injunction” (p. 59). He adds that guilt dif-
fers from anxiety insofar as
Moore and Fine (1990) offer the following passage by way of defining
guilt.
Refers, like shame to a group of affects, including fear of retribution
both from outside and within the self, feelings of remorse, contri-
tion, and penitence. Its core is a form of anxiety with the underly-
ing ideational content: “If I hurt somebody else, I shall be hurt in
turn.” In addition to this outer or inner retaliation for one’s sexual
or aggressive acts or wishes, one may hold the depressive connec-
tion that one has already hurt the other and is being punished for
it; therewith goes the hope that, by atonement through mental or
physical suffering, one can attain forgiveness, that is, regain love
and acceptance. (p. 83)
baby’s mind the conflicts between love and hate then arise, and the
fears of losing the loved one become active. These feelings of guilt
and distress now enter as a new element into the emotion of love
… Side-by-side with the destructive impulses in the unconscious
both of the child and of the adult, there exists a profound urge to
make sacrifices, in order to help and put right loved people who in
phantasy have been harmed or destroyed. (pp. 308, 311, italics in
the original)
that have already taken place. Seen this way, regret is even closer to
remorse since the latter is always about something in the (remote or
near) past. Commenting upon this, I have elsewhere noted that both
regret and remorse
… are about the past. Both are about one’s own actions. Both
can involve acts of commission or omission. Both lead to a wist-
ful rumination to somehow erase or undo the events of the past.
Both can, therefore, underlie the “if only … fantasy” (Akhtar, 1996).
This fantasy assumes that, in the absence of this or that “calam-
ity”, everything would have turned out all right. Both “regret”
and “remorse” can impoverish the ego and contribute to anhe-
donia, depression, and suicidal tendencies. Finally, both “regret”
and “remorse” can serve screen functions and both can be put
to secondary (e.g., sadomasochistic) uses. However, there is one
very important difference between the two emotions: “remorse”
involves feelings about how one’s actions have affected others,
while “regret” involves feelings about how one’s actions affected
oneself. In other words, “remorse” is more object related, “regret”
more narcissistic. (Akhtar, 2009, p. 244)
Origins of guilt
The search for the font origio of guilt leads us to two registers of expe-
rience and fantasy. One is made up of ubiquitous events and experi-
ences of childhood. The other is constituted by occurrences that might
be common enough but by no means are ubiquitous. The first category
leads to (i) annihilation guilt, (ii) epistemic guilt, and (iii) Oedipal guilt.
The second category leads to (i) separation guilt, (ii) induced guilt,
(iii) borrowed guilt, (iv) deposited guilt, and (v) survivor guilt. Need-
less to add that the latter four types of guilt, while originating from
idiosyncratic and serendipitous occurrences, can readily exploit the
ubiquitous roots of moral unease; in other words, the two broad catego-
ries of guilt (i.e., ubiquitous and serendipitous) can get condensed with
each other. Waelder’s (1936) “principle of multiple function” applies to
guilt as much as it does to any other psychic phenomenon.
Annihilation guilt
During childhood, our desires are simple, direct, and intolerant of
delay in their gratification. We want what we want; we despise realities
G U I LT 75
and people who come in the way of the fulfilment of our wishes. We
wish such “enemies” gone, vanished, even dead. We wish to annihilate
them. Given the limited circumference of our childhood interper-
sonal world, it is our parents and siblings who usually constitute such
“enemies”.2 They are the ones who seem to come in the way of the
immediate gratification of our wishes. No wonder we hate them from
time to time and, in the typical childhood mode of absolutism, wish
them dead. And, it is the persistence of these death wishes towards
others that becomes the bedrock of the human experience of guilt.
Unlike “annihilation anxiety” (for a formidable survey of literature on
this topic, see Hurvich, 2003), which is the distress felt due to the antici-
pated disintegration of the self, “annihilation guilt” is the distress felt at
the self-caused destruction of one’s love objects.
A particularly nuanced manifestation of such guilt is seen in those
brought up by parents who wish them dead, on a chronic basis, but
did not have the physical and moral courage to actually do the deed.
The child thus raised is unconsciously aware of the parental death
wishes (Ferenczi, 1929) and, if he or she is fortunate enough to achieve
a coherent sense of selfhood and agency, feels guilt at harbouring hate-
ful feelings towards the parents.
Epistemic guilt
An additional source of guilt is formed by our childhood curiosities
and their uninhibited expression. As children, we ask questions that
seem natural to us (e.g., “Why does grandpa smell of pee all the time?”,
“Wouldn’t Aunt Jenny die if she smokes?”) but make adults around
us uncomfortable. At other times, even mundane questions of ours
(e.g., “Dad, what time are we going out?”) are responded to by our
parents (especially if they are tired, hung over, sick, worried, etc.) with
annoyance and disapproval. In either case, we are silenced. But the
questions—and the wish to ask them aloud—remain alive within us.
And since we have internalised the adult injunctions, it makes us feel
bad. This is “epistemic guilt”.3
Curiously, development of such guilt is more marked in bright chil-
dren. Delineating the multifaceted contribution of superior intelligence
to neurosogenesis, Keiser (1969) wrote the following:
Repeatedly it was observed that the child felt guilty for being more
highly endowed than his parents or siblings. Areas of conflict
are often created because the avenues of expression that a child
76 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Oedipal guilt
When the “annihilation guilt” and “epistemic guilt” occur in the con-
text of early triadic relations within the family, the resulting phenome-
non is called “Oedipal guilt”. Here, the importance of Freud’s (1912–13,
1916d, 1917e, 1924b) observations is paramount. He emphasised that
“[P]arricide and incest with the mother are the two great human crimes”
G U I LT 77
(1916d, p. 333) and that the sense of guilt derived from the Oedipus
complex was a reaction to “the criminal intentions of killing the father
and having sexual relations with the mother” (ibid., p. 333). The gender
bias implicit in these pronouncements (i.e., matricide and incest with
the father being overlooked) was more or less corrected in some of his
other writings. For instance, Freud (1916–17) stated that:
As you see, I have only described the relation of a boy to his father
and mother. Things happen in just the same way with little girls,
with the necessary changes: an affectionate attachment to her
father, a need to get rid of her mother as superfluous and to take
her place, a coquetry which already employs the methods of later
womanhood—these offer a charming picture, especially in small
girls, which makes us forget the possible grave consequences
lying behind this infantile situation. We must not omit to add that
the parents themselves often exercise a determining influence on
the awakening of a child’s Oedipus attitude by themselves obey-
ing the pull of sexual attraction, and that where there are several
children, the father will give the plainest evidence of his greater
affection for his little daughter and the mother for her son. (“The
Introductory Lectures”, Vol. 16, p. 333, italics in the original)
Freud’s main point, however, remained that the erotically driven wishes
to woo the opposite sex parent and eliminate the same sex parent form
the essence of the Oedipus complex,4 and the persistence of such wishes
in the unconscious (despite their overt renunciation due to parental dis-
approval and, later, superego threat) forms a source of lifelong vulner-
ability to guilt. The greater the strength of such unconscious wishes, the
greater the amount of guilt. Success in life’s pursuits then gets equated
with Oedipal victory and mobilises guilt. Indeed, some individuals are
“wrecked by success” (Freud, 1916d, p. 316) and often engineer their
own failures. A few others become “criminal from a sense of guilt”
(ibid., p. 332), that is, they arrange to be punished by conscious mis-
deeds as an expiation for transgressive impulses in the unconscious.
Freud’s earlier (1912–13) proposal of an actual, even if “pre-historic”,
murder of the primal father having saddled man with ancestral “bad-
ness” had a similar Oedipal ring to it.
Regardless of its specific colouration and context, Oedipal guilt
invariably results in a compromised love life. Rescue fantasies towards
78 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
the “suffering mother” (in the primal scene) lead men to repeatedly
seek needy women as their love objects (Freud, 1910h), a scenario that
often ends up in frustration once the “rescue” operation is over. In
women, Oedipal guilt frequently leads to frigidity, inability to achieve
orgasm or bursting into tears at the moment of orgasm, and a com-
pulsion to get involved with abusive and betraying partners. Prostitu-
tion fantasies often colour sexuality (in both men and women) when
Oedipal guilt plays a prominent role in psychic life.
Separation guilt
The feelings of “wrongdoing” that narcissistic and needy parents incul-
cate in their children when the latter begin to take steps towards psychic
autonomy and independence is termed “separation guilt” by Modell
(1965). Here the child’s ego advances are age-specific and maturationally
appropriate but are rendered doubt-ridden and “bad” by the parental
response to them. Pine’s (1997) useful distinction between “separation
anxiety” and “separateness anxiety”5 is, however, important to keep
in mind; the former refers to the mobilisation of anxiety due to actual
separation from love objects, the latter refers to the anxiety that results
from experiencing oneself as an autonomous source of agency, thought,
feeling, morality, and action. In light of this, it is better to call the bad
feeling aroused by parental rejection of the growing child’s autonomy
as “separateness guilt”. Regardless of which label one uses, this sort of
guilt is seen more often in children raised by self-centred, sickly, lonely,
and otherwise needy parents.
One situation which can contribute to such guilt with particular
ferocity is that of immigration. Children of immigrant parents often
experience an “acculturation gap” (Prathikanti, 1997) between their
parents and themselves. This has the potential of causing role reversal
between them. As a result, children can be placed in a position where
they have to “translate” (literally or metaphorically) the ways of the
culture-at-large for their parents. This may range from innocuous
advice on how to operate a VCR or a computer to the more serious
interventions of advocacy in medical and legal settings that are beyond
the full comprehension of immigrant parents; clearly, this is more likely
to occur if the older generation is less educated, non-optimally accul-
turated, and not proficient in English. Lan Cao (1997), a Vietnamese
American writer, described such role reversal in poignant terms:
G U I LT 79
The consequences of such role reversal are that the child comes to
know the family’s financial, medical, and legal secrets somewhat
prematurely. This can burden his ego. More importantly, the parental
dependence makes the child’s developmentally appropriate movement
toward separation and autonomy guilt-ridden.
Induced guilt
A related phenomenon is “induced guilt”. This refers to the feeling of
“badness” that arises in a child when the parents vociferously announce
the suffering they have undergone in raising him. For instance, mothers
who repeatedly tell their child about the difficulties in her pregnancy
and labour (“You know, when you were born, I bled so much that I
nearly died”) end up burdening him with profound guilt (Asch, 1976).
Similarly, immigrant parents who parade their culturally dislocated
lives as a sacrifice for their offspring (“We came to this country so that
you can have a better life”) cause the latter to suffer enormous amounts
of guilt (Akhtar, 2011a). Espiritu (2009) notes that “We did it for the
children” is a common refrain among Filipino immigrants. However,
this might also apply to many other groups, including those from India,
Pakistan, Mexico, and African and Central American countries. The
refrain has a more nefarious twin: “We stayed in this country because
of you guys.” This conveys to the child that the parents are suffering
on a daily basis and are tolerating it only for the sake of their children.
Such declarations on the parents’ part can saddle their offspring with
much guilt.
Children of Holocaust survivors are also vulnerable to induc-
tion of guilt by their parents. Having undergone extreme suffering,
the latter often fail to recognise their children’s age-specific doubts
80 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Borrowed guilt
A counterpart to parentally induced guilt is what, for the lack of a bet-
ter term, might be called “borrowed guilt”. This consists of a growing
child taking the blame for parental mistreatment upon himself and
exonerating them altogether. Such development, designated “moral
defence” by Fairbairn (1940) has two origins: (i) the child’s ego-centric
perception which precludes an awareness of independent motivation
on the parents’ part, and (ii) the child’s attempt to preserve some hope
of things getting better. In other words, if the child allows himself to feel
that his parents are “bad”, then the situation becomes unbearable since
he has no other place to go and no one to seek love from. But, if he feels
that it is he who is “bad”, then, by behaving better, he can hope that his
parents might treat him kindly and stop abusing him.
Deposited guilt
This type of guilt results from the child’s succumbing to the “projec-
tive identification” (Kernberg, 1975; Klein, 1935) of their parents’ guilt.
In other words, parents feel guilty about something and cannot bear
G U I LT 81
While true, this statement does not mean that “deposited guilt” is
restricted to the children of immigrants. Parents who are carrying a
heavy load of guilt due to any reason (e.g., corruption at work, cheat-
ing in their marriage) can shift the burden of their remorse and make
their children feel guilty. The latter then develop a proclivity for
masochism in a phenomenon that is best termed “self-punishment
by proxy”.
82 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Survivor guilt
This type of guilt is seen among individuals who suffer from lifelong
anguish over their escaping the fatal blow that fell upon their friends
and family members. Niederland (1968), who originally described such
guilt in the context of Holocaust survivors, states:
entity unto itself. The guilt Western tourists experience while visiting
the poor nations of Africa and Asia is the type that Modell has deline-
ated. It is based upon the awareness of being more fortunate than oth-
ers; to be sure, unconscious childhood wishes of robbing one’s siblings
(of mother’s love) and feelings of contempt towards the less fortunate
also play a role in the genesis of such guilt.
Having elucidated the various origins of guilt, we can move on to the
consequences of guilt. The question, “What causes guilt?” has a coun-
terpoint in “What does guilt cause?”
Projection of blame
Guilt is often warded off by attributing blame to others. By irritable nit-
picking, the guilty individual shifts the burden of contrition to someone
else. Finding faults in others relieves him of self-criticism. Paranoia thus
becomes a useful defence against depressive anxieties. In his elucida-
tion of the relationship between guilt and hate, Jones (1929) made the
following astute observation.
Hatred for someone implies that the other person, through his cru-
elty or unkindness, is the cause of one’s sufferings, that the latter
are not self-imposed or in any way one’s own fault. All the respon-
sibility for the misery produced by unconscious guilt is thus dis-
placed on to the other, supposedly cruel person, who is therefore
heartily hated. The mechanism is, of course, very familiar in the
84 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Libidinisation of suffering
This is perhaps the most common manifestation of guilt in clinical prac-
tice. Guilt gives rise to a need for punishment and to masochism which
satisfies this need. Since this is a realm of great clinical importance, it
might not be bad to look into the “need for punishment” and “maso-
chism” concepts a bit more carefully.
Sigmund Freud’s ideas about what he called the “need for punish-
ment” evolved in four steps: (i) In “Notes upon a Case of Obsessional
Neurosis” (1909d), he noted that the self-reproaches of the obsessional
neurotic were forms of self-punishment; (ii) In “Some Character Types
Met with in Psycho-Analytic Work” (1916d), he described a character
type called “criminal from a sense of guilt”; this constellation involved
committing outrageous and socially unacceptable, even criminal, acts
86 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Technical implications
Freud’s (1912e) injunction that the psychoanalytic attitude involves “not
directing one’s notice to anything in particular” (p. 111) has been tem-
pered by later technical innovations which speak not only of sharply
focused attention (Brenner, 2000; Gray, 1994) but also of therapeutic
“strategy” (Levy, 1987) that dictates measured and deliberate tracks of
interventions. The comments I am about to make upon working issues
of guilt and remorse in the clinical situation are in this latter spirit.
However, to my mind, the “free-floating responsiveness” (Sandler &
Sandler, 1998) and strategic confrontations and clarifications are not
opposed to each other. Good psychoanalytic work fluctuates between
these two polarities. It is quiet and lambent at one moment and forceful
and direct at another.
Having stated that, I propose that technical handling of guilt and
remorse involves a multi-pronged strategy which takes the following
six factors into account: (i) interpretation of the defences against the
awareness of guilt, (ii) interpretation of the defences against the aware-
ness of the masochistic pleasure drawn from guilt, (iii) interpretation
of the unconscious sadistic aspects of chronic self-blaming, especially
in the context of transference, (iv) reconstruction of the sources of guilt,
(v) interpretation of defensive functions of guilt (e.g., against lack of
omnipotence in those who have lost parents as children), and (vi) help
with bearing some guilt and finding productive ways of dealing with it.
A brief explication of each of these follows.
[…] must convey to the patient not only the direction he wants
the patient to move in, but also confidence that the movement is
inherent in the patient, which means that what the uncured patient
wants is indeed a representation, however distorted, of what the
cured patient will get. (Friedman, 1969, p. 150)
Concluding remarks
In this chapter, I have described the subjective experience of guilt and
distinguished it from the related phenomena of shame, remorse, and
regret. I have traced the origins of guilt to infantile and childhood
aggressive and hostile impulses, both outside and within the Oedipal
context. I have tried to show that Klein’s work is more pertinent to
pre-Oedipal remorse and the consequent drive of reparation while
Freud’s work is more pertinent to Oedipal guilt and the consequent
need for punishment. In addition, I have noted that seeds of lifelong
guilt can be sown by parental proclamations of suffering and sacri-
fice on behalf of their children, by parental depositing of their own
unresolved guilt into the children’s psyche, by parental intolerance of
their children’s developmentally appropriate strivings for autonomy,
and by accidents of nature and random occurrences that leave the
individual in a more fortunate position than his loved ones. Finally,
I have delineated three pathological outcomes (projection, externali-
sation, and libidinisation) and one healthy (apology and reparation)
outcome of guilt.
Despite casting a wide net, I have not been able to address two
important issues, namely, the impact of gender and of culture upon
the experience of guilt. Both variables demand attention but the
burgeoning literature on these topics defies a quick summary here.
Suffice it to say that (i) it is conceivable that some cultures (e.g., Japan)
are more driven by shame (Kitayama, 1997) and others by guilt,
(ii) the earlier report of a high rate of suicide in Germany, Austria,
Japan, and Switzerland and the low rate of suicide in Holland, Italy,
Brazil, and Spain (Weiss, 1974), as well as the more recent assertion
(Nock, Borges & Ono, 2012) that rates are highest in Eastern Europe
and lowest in Latin American countries make one wonder about the
culturally determined vulnerability to guilt and self-punishment,9
and (iii) in a sharp rebuttal to Freud’s (1923b, 1925j) denigration of
women’s morality, recent studies (e.g., Bernstein, 1983; Gilligan, 1982)
have found differences in the nature, not in the strength, of the female
superego when compared to its male counterpart. The relevance of
such culture-based and gender-specific insights to the understanding
of guilt in its clinical and non-clinical dimensions is indeed great and
needs to be pursued further.
94 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Notes
1. This traditional viewpoint is called into question by the concepts
of “deposited” and “induced” guilt; these are discussed later in this
chapter. Moreover, the long-held position that the capacity for genuine
guilt is a post-Oedipal development has been called into question by
the epigenetic scenarios postulated by Klein (1937, 1940) and Winnicott
(1954, 1956b). These theorists place the origin of guilt in the child’s early
dyadic relationship with mother, though their use of the term “guilt”
differs in important ways from that of Freud’s (1912–13, 1916d, 1924a).
This difference is taken up in the later parts of this chapter.
2. Freud (1916–17) notes that while murderous impulses are a regular com-
ponent of the childhood Oedipal experience, such wishes are even more
strongly felt and verbalised in the context of the sibling relationship.
3. The biblical tale of Adam and Eve is an illustration par excellence of such
“epistemic guilt”.
4. Clearly, the opposite is the case in the context of homosexuality; for
literature pertaining to this matter, see Akhtar, Comprehensive Dictionary
of Psychoanalysis (2009, pp. 131–132).
5. Pine emphasises that all anxiety at separation is not “separation anx-
iety”. For instance, a patient who feels anxious upon learning of his
analyst’s vacation may be responding to a drive upsurge consequent
upon the removal of an externalised superego. Or, he may be respond-
ing to an anticipated disorganisation of the self. The former anxiety,
while precipitated by separation, is not true “separation anxiety”, since
the separation in question is from a well-differentiated object. True
“separation anxiety” involves a relationship with an undifferentiated
other and is therefore an “anxiety over the sense of separateness” (1997,
p. 230). This is better termed “separateness anxiety”.
6. Such anti-Islamic xenophobia led to the emergence of the “good
Muslim, bad Muslim” dichotomy in the public mind. Mamdani’s (2004)
penetrating analysis of this issue details the unfortunate consequences
and politico-economic antecedents of this development.
7. The fact that all the cases from which Freud drew the idea of “feminine”
masochism were males betrays a certain rigid preconception of
theorising.
8. Sexual abuse literature pays special attention to this issue, with some
family therapists (e.g., Madanes, 1990) requiring the perpetrator to
actually, even ritualistically, apologise to the victim in front of other
family members.
9. Clearly, more than guilty self-punishment contributes to suicide and
the rates cited here might not be entirely reliable since the reporting
patterns of suicide vary from country to country.
PART II
SUFFERING INFLICTED
CHAPTER FOUR
Deception
W
hile overtly destructive acts derived from rage and hatred
draw sharp clinical and public attention, far more damage is
done to human relations by the quieter evils of lying, cheat-
ing, and deceit. In myriad forms that range from pretentious decorum
at official events to pseudo-cordiality among political adversaries, from
socially convenient bending of truth to outright lying for monetary
gain, and from laborious inflation of the self to deliberate fraud for
seducing others, deception corrodes trust that is the glue of attachment
and interpersonal bonds. Regardless of its form, deception arises from
trauma and causes suffering to self and others. A common denominator
in various types of deception (e.g., mendacity, forgery, betrayal) is the
existence of a lie.
It is this central feature that I will address in this contribution. I will
begin with elucidating the formal characteristics of lies and the motiva-
tions that propel individuals to distort the truth. In the passages that
follow, I will take up the developmental achievements necessary for
the capacity for lying to emerge. Then I will make a brief sociocultural
foray into the worlds of art and entertainment, politics, propaganda,
advertising, forgery, and counterfeit. Following this digression, I will
return to the clinical realm and address the implications of lying for
97
98 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
• Everyone lies.
• Anyone who claims to be forever truthful is telling a lie.
• It is undesirable to be truthful under all circumstances.
• Lying is essential for smooth social dialogue and interpersonal
politeness.
• Different forms and varying extents of lying are integral to many
socially useful lines of work.
• Lying can at times save lives.
• Since all sorts of grey areas exist between what constitutes a lie and
what constitutes a truth, it is not always easy to separate the two.
• The inherent “truth bias” (Feldman, 2009) of human beings makes
them prone to believe what they are told and compromises their
capacity to discern lies.
• Even in forensic settings where distinguishing between truth and lies
is of paramount importance, there is no foolproof method to detect
deception (Watson, 2009).
• Lies come in many shapes and forms even though they share certain
common features.
• Not telling the truth. Remaining silent while being asked to respond
to a question, the answer to which one actually knows, constitutes
a lie.
• Replacing the facts one knows to be true by false and misleading
information.
• Telling the truth but not the “whole truth” and, by such withholding
of parts of relevant information, altering the inference to be drawn
from one’s report.
• Telling the truth but embellishing it in a way that results in a carica-
ture and thus puts its veracity in question. The mechanism of “denial
by exaggeration” (Fenichel, 1945) belongs in this category.
• Flatly and forcefully questioning and even repudiating an estab-
lished truth. The phenomenon of “gaslighting” (Barton & Whitehead,
1969) where one individual seeks to drive someone crazy by stirring
up doubts about the latter’s perception is an example of this type of
lying. Instances of “soul murder” (Shengold, 1989) where a child’s
perception is ruthlessly erased by a cruel and abusive parent, and
the denial of Holocaust, are other examples from individual and
collective arenas, respectively, of this very type of lie.
• Acknowledging the truth about a certain matter but retrospectively
imputing motives to it that were not in operation earlier. The ego
operation of “sliding of meanings” (Horowitz, 1975) seen in narcis-
sistic personalities is an example par excellence of such a strategy.
What all this demonstrates is that lies come in many forms.1 From bald-
faced assertions of falsehood to subtle distortions or reality, lies elude
simplistic nosological traps. To discern them, one is not only required
to pay close attention to what is being said and why but also to what
is not being said, what is being exaggerated, what is being minimised,
and what is being painted with a revisionist brush. One also has to take
into consideration the intrapsychic and interpersonal context in which
a lie is being constructed and conveyed; lying invariably involves a
self-object scenario, however deeply buried under narcissistic grounds
that might be. And this brings up the consideration of the motivational
dynamics behind lying.
100 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Two other issues need mention. The first pertains to the collapse of
motivation and consequence in lying (e.g., shame leading to lying and
this resulting in a deceived other party). Sometimes, this conflation is
obvious. At other times, there occur consequences that were not moti-
vationally sought (e.g., shame leading to lying resulting in an awful
feeling of guilt at having misled someone). In other words, the conse-
quences of lying are both the desired one and the undesired ones and
both types of consequences might involve the self and other. A paral-
lel concern is the psychology of one who is lied to. While unconscious
collusion might exist between him and the liar, the individual who is
fooled brings his own dynamics to the situation. He might be unduly
gullible and believe all that is told to him though not without feeling
deceived and hurt later on. Curiously, some paranoid personalities—
while contemptuous of others’ naivety—are themselves remarkably,
though latently, gullible (Stanton, 1978).
102 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
and enjoys others’ indulgent attention towards his play. Fischer (2009)
concludes that achievement of an Oedipal organisation is the
Blum (2009) concurs that the development, during the second year of
life, of symbolic, cognitive, and linguistic capacities for pretence and
play and for anticipation of consequences foreshadows the appearance
of intentional lying. According to him, children begin to lie around three
years of age and do so largely to avoid blame. The list of motivations to
lie grows as development proceeds further.
and their explicit hypocrisy and dishonesty that lays the groundwork
for lying. At times, however, the parents appear quite moral, even
moralistic, and yet the child turns out to be habitually deceitful. More
often than not, such parents have unconsciously encouraged the child’s
delinquency and have vicariously enjoyed it. This transgenerational
duplicity leads to what Johnson and Szurek (1952) have termed “super-
ego lacunae” in the offspring.
Addititional to these psychoanalytic ideas are empirical studies
of lying children. An important one pertains to the “peeking game”
research (Talwar & Lee, 2002) whereby a child is given a chance to com-
mit a transgression (e.g., by looking at a forbidden object) and then fib
about his action. Three year olds can do so but they lack “semantic leak-
age control”, that is, maintaining consistency of verbal statements and
not letting the fact out that they have peeked. By the age of about six
or seven, some 50 per cent of children can maintain feigned ignorance.
Edelsohn (2009), who has recently reviewed research studies on chil-
dren’s lying from elementary school through adolescence, concludes
that while young children lie to avoid punishment and buttress self-
esteem, adolescents lie for protecting their privacy and enhancing their
autonomy and individuation. Both honesty and lying are learned in the
home and reflect not only the child’s cognitive and moral development
but also the texture of the child’s relationship with his or her parents.
Predominance of love between the two parties strengthens the capacity
for honesty. Predominance of hate tilts the balance towards lying.
formations is along similar lines. He noted that the ego is pulled, often
to a painful extent, in opposite directions by the demands of the id and
external reality, and at times
… it will be possible for the ego to avoid a rupture in any direc-
tion by deforming itself, by submitting to encroachments on its
own unity and even perhaps by effecting a cleavage or division
of itself. In this way the inconsistencies, eccentricities, and follies
of men would appear in a similar light to their sexual perversions.
(pp. 152–153)
While the discovery of the resulting secret lives is fodder for newspa-
per headlines (especially when it involves celebrities and model citi-
zens), the psychiatric clinics encounter a different type of syndrome
associated with lying. This involves the spectrum of factitious disor-
der and malingering. Also known as Munchausen syndrome (Asher,
1951),6 factitious disorder involves feigning physical or mental illness.
Patients with this disorder simulate, induce, and exaggerate all sorts of
symptoms, often to the extent of ingesting unsafe materials and insert-
ing unsafe objects in their bodies. They might produce fake evidence
of having bled and false documents of suffering this or that malady.
They frequently seek hospitalisation and their goal is to be emotion-
ally taken care of. While deceptive in the literal sense of the word, the
behaviour of these individuals differs from malingering in an important
way. In malingering, distress is feigned for material gain (e.g., monetary
compensation, avoidance of work-related duties) whereas in factitious
disorder, illnesses are faked in order to receive emotional care and
attention (Sadock & Sadock, 2007). The boundaries between factitious
disorder, malingering, and “genuine” hypochondriacal conviction
are, however, not always easy to draw. The heightened susceptibility
to auto-hypnotic suggestion might be so great that the individual suc-
ceeds in suppressing all knowledge of his or her desire to adopt a sick
role (Davis & Weiss, 1974).
The New York Times prides itself on its role as “the paper of record”,
printing corrections to stories sometimes decades after the fact to
maintain its reputation of accuracy. Hence the sensation when it
was revealed that Jayson Blair, a Times reporter, had fabricated
or plagiarised material for dozens of national news stories. He’d
offered reporting from places he had never been, he’d given quotes
from people he’d never interviewed or met, he’d misstated facts,
and he’d made up details. USA Today reported Jack Kelley was
a finalist for the Pulitzer Prize before it revealed, in 2004, that he
had invented material, including portions of the story that had
earned him a Pulitzer nomination. In a front-page article, USA
Today admitted that “Kelley fabricated substantial portions of at
least eight major stories, lifted nearly two dozen quotes or other
material from competing publications, lied in speeches he gave for
the newspaper, and conspired to mislead those investigating his
work.” (pp. 197–198)
108 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
The fact that we respond to such revelations with dismay does not
prevent us from marvelling at cold-hearted bluffs in a game of poker
(Moore, 2009) and from enjoying depictions of scammers, impostors,
and con artists on the big screen. Indeed, there has been a long genre
of such movies that includes hits like The Music Man (1962), The Sting
(1973), Dirty Rotten Scoundrels (1988), The Grifters (1990), House of Cards
(1993), Ocean’s Eleven (2001), and Catch Me If You Can (2002). Splitting-
off their avowedly moral selves, the audience vicariously identifies with
the slick protagonist’s finesse while, at a still deeper level, partaking of
the masochistic pleasure of the one who is duped.9
Stakes are raised when we encounter con artists in the real world.
Running Ponzi schemes (e.g., the notorious Bernie Madoff) or glad-
handing “liar loans” (Zibel, 2008)—home mortgages approved without
checking the borrower’s income or assets—they can lead us to financial
ruin. Or they might sell us art and antiquities that turn out to be fake.
One look at the exorbitant prices successful forgeries in the realm of art
can fetch reveals that monetary benefit is a major motivation of lying
here. The list of those who thrive in this business is indeed long. Two
outstanding art forgers who made enormous money by their decep-
tive craft are Hans van Meegeren (1889–1947), the Dutch art dealer who
painted many fake Vermeers, and Tom Keating (1917–1984), the British
con artist who forged more than 2,000 paintings by more than 100 art-
ists in his lifetime. The fact, however, is that the money made by these
two master forgers constitutes a minuscule proportion of that made by
art forgers all over the world. And art is not the only arena where fake
products offer lucrative financial rewards. Collectors of autographs,
rare manuscripts, old photographs, letters, and even stamps and coins
know very well how widely inauthentic objects circulate in the bazaars
of their passion. They can readily recount all sorts of tales involving
someone being swindled by a forger who got away with a huge sum
of money.
However, monetary profit is not the only motive for creating a for-
gery. Emotional factors also seem to play a role here. Prominent among
these are the following:
the “sadism behind their narcissistic charm and charisma” (p. 61).
Deceiving others promises to undo the chronic feelings of inferiority
and impotence the forger often carries within himself.
• Trading in fake products invariably involves a rebellion against
ordinary morality. It involves breaking the law as well. Making and
selling counterfeit objects can thus give vent to emotional conflicts
with authority figures. The irreverence and bravado of an impostor
is a slap in the face of the established order. The ever-present risk of
being caught adds to the thrill of defiance.
• Fakery also fulfils strivings for magical powers. To produce a dol-
lar bill in one’s basement, for instance, gratifies our childish wishes
for becoming “rich” pronto. To paint a Cezanne or a Picasso over a
few days in downtown Cleveland is to reverse time, change location,
and acquire creative genius at will. Just like that, with a snap of the
fingers.
peace offering of the Trojan horse by ancient Greeks, the Dreyfus affair
of late nineteenth-century France, the massive anti-Semitic propa-
ganda by Nazis during the 1930s, the ideological witch-hunts of the
1950s McCarthy era in the United States are but a few examples of how
wicked shenanigans pervade domestic and international politics. Nota-
ble in this context is Alterman’s (2004) thorough account of lies told by
the US presidents to Congress, the media, and the public at large. It is
a painful saga of how moral values and the honourable covenant to
uphold the truth at the highest level of a democratic government can be
sacrificed at the altar of political convenience. While Bill Clinton’s bald-
faced denial (“I did not have sex with that woman, Miss Lewinsky”)
has its titillating impact, far more serious consequences have followed
Lyndon Johnson’s deceptive assurances regarding the second Tonkin
Gulf incident, Richard Nixon’s Watergate cover-up, Ronald Reagan’s
lies regarding the Iran-Contra deal, George Bush Senior’s false prom-
ises (“Read my lips: no more taxes”), and the younger Bush’s fabricated
reasons to attack Iraq. Indeed hundreds of thousands of people have
been killed due to the last mentioned deceit, to say nothing of its dev-
astating impact upon the American economy and the nation’s prestige
in the eyes of the world.
turned paranoid. Both had “basic suspicions” (p. 190) instead of basic
trust and both felt “cut off from their depths” (p. 191). Like Lafarge,
O’Shaughnessy observed the impostor’s tendency towards idealisa-
tion: “This lie about lying is at the center of the deterioration of his
character” (p. 193). O’Shaughnessy delineated a characteristic “triad of
a deficient primal object, a strong destructive instinct in the patient, and
a general perverse overlay” (p. 193) and concluded that
If the fundamental level of the lie can be understood, that a liar
lies in identification with the lying object, and, at the same time,
if the patient’s hostile lying, his different perspective in regard to
truth and also his perverse excitement at using the lie to communi-
cate with his analyst can be analysed in all their concreteness, I am
sure at least of this: a genuine analytic process can be set in train.
(p. 194)
keeping certain thoughts and feelings secret from parents. Later, the
ego begins to keep the same (and similar psychic phenomena) hidden
from the superego and even from portions of the ego itself. The pro-
vision of strict confidentiality and the adherence to non-participation
in the patient’s life outside analysis prepare the ground for growing
trust in the clinical situation. With moment-to-moment interpretation
of transference-based fears of criticism, some softening of superego
occurs and the possibility of revealing secrets appears on the hori-
zon. The process of defence analysis, in the hands of an abstinent and
technically neutral analyst, encourages the patient to reveal the con-
scious secrets to the analyst and, later on, the unconscious secrets to
his own ego and superego. In effect, in the psychoanalytic treatment
of neuroses, the exact reversal of what happened during childhood
occurs.
Regardless of its being incisive or painstakingly slow, the emphasis
upon the interpretive approach must not overshadow the importance
of the analysts “holding” (Winnicott, 1960) functions and of his capac-
ity to discern unconscious hope (that the environment will tolerate the
burden of deceit and yet continue to provide care) in the patient’s cheat-
ing and outrageousness (Winnicott, 1956a).11 Only with such a judicious
and tactful admixture of holding and interpretive approaches and that
too on a sustained and long-term basis can a liar be truly helped.
Concluding remarks
In this wide-ranging survey, I have delineated the formal characteristics
of lies, phenomenological subtypes of lies, and psychodynamic motiva-
tions to distort the known truth. Utilising the scene of art forgery as a
didactic scaffold, I have elucidated the dialectical configurations that
intricately bind the liar and his victim. Such a “two-person” explana-
tory approach has, however, not stood in my way to recognise the truly
“one-person” contributions to the phenomenon of lying. My emphasis
has overall been on the multiply determined, multi-functional, object-
related, and ubiquitous nature of lying. At the same time, I have empha-
sised that a concerted effort to be honest and seek psychic truth—to the
extent any such striving can be fully successful—is a fundamental aspect
of mental health and of intensive psychotherapy and psychoanalysis.12
With this in mind, I have made brief comments on patients who misin-
form their therapists during the initial evaluation, the development of
DECEPTION 117
do so. The lion says that he was telling the truth when he promised but
the procrastination on the woodsman’s part to release him caused delay
and this, in turn, made him hungry. He says that now he cannot help
himself and has to eat the woodsman. Just as this discussion is going
on, a jackal happens to pass by. He stops and asks the arguing duo as to
what is going on. Upon being told the story, first by the woodsman and
then by the lion, with their obvious mismatch, the jackal turns pensive.
He thinks for a while and then says that he does not believe either of
them. In fact, he calls both the woodsman and the lion liars. He says
that he cannot believe that such a large and majestic animal like the
lion could ever fit in that small iron cage. He mocks the woodsman and
the lion for fabricating such an incredulous tale. Annoyed at this, the
lion promptly decides to prove the jackal wrong and re-enters the cage.
With lightning speed, the jackal locks the cage door and thus saves the
woodsman’s life.
As one encounters a fable of such richness, many questions present
themselves.
• Was the lion telling the truth when he said to the woodsman that he
would not attack him?
• Was the lion lying when he said that his hunger had grown because
of the woodman’s procrastination?
• Was the woodsman pathologically gullible (due perhaps to some
unconscious masochism) in trusting the lion to begin with?
• Was the jackal truthful when he accused the lion and the woodsman
of being liars?
• Was the lion pathologically gullible (due to his unconscious guilt at
cheating the woodsman) to believe the jackal and re-enter the cage?
• Was the woodsman aware of the jackal’s lying and in remaining silent
about it, was he not lying himself?
there is no such thing as objective truth. Indeed, there is. The fact that
you are reading these words (regardless of your agreeing or disagreeing
with them) is one such truth and to deny it would be a lie.
Notes
1. Any discussion of lies contains within itself implicit assumptions about
truth. If it were not so and truth did not exist (or, was not known), how
could anything be considered a lie? In other words, to know a lie is to
know the truth behind its veil. This theorem might not fit well with the
contemporary hermeneutic turn to psychoanalysis which lays empha-
sis upon co-constructed data, intersubjectivity, and “narrative truth”
(Spence, 1982). Sass and Woolfolk (1988) have provided a thorough
assessment of this tension and Hanly (1990, 1992) has elucidated the
criteria (e.g., coherence, correspondence) for establishing “truth” in
psychoanalysis.
2. Chasseguet-Smirgel’s (1984) concept of regressive anal homogenisation
in the perverse character and Grunberger’s (1989) metapsychological
discourse on the false notion of “purity” are especially pertinent in this
context.
3. In the preoccupation with delineating different types of lies, it should
not be overlooked that an inability to lie, when circumstances demand
such a posture, might also reflect psychopathology. Such “compulsive
honesty” (Rajnish Mago, personal communication, August 19, 2008) is
often accompanied by self-glorification, moralistic exaltation of truth
for its own sake, and a sadomasochistic bent to interpersonal relation-
ships. In more severe cases, such driven desire to be “honest” is cou-
pled with a split-off sector of personality that may be quite corrupt and
perverse.
4. There is some evidence, however, that higher primates can “lie” to
avoid blame and gain advantage over others (Byrne & Whiten, 1992;
Fouts, 1997; Maynard-Smith & Szathmáry, 1999). Stone (2009) has
recently provided a review of the evolutionary literature on the subject
of lying.
5. Freud (1895) used the term “overdetermination” to denote the fact
that psychic phenomena are caused by multiple factors operating in
unison. Thus, forces of constitution and trauma, scenarios of past and
present, and pressures by different psychic agencies converge into the
final common pathway leading to a given phenomenon. Freud’s later
study of dreams (1900a) and parapraxes (1916–17) gave strong support
to this idea. Still later, his delineation of a tripartite psychic structure
(1923b) led to the conclusion that neurotic symptoms were not simply
120 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
they have character flaws and vulnerabilities. They are hardly immune
to the temptations of lying. Sigmund Freud’s signing “Dr Sigm Freud
u Frau” (German for Dr Sigmund Freud and wife) when he checked
into a hotel in Maloja, Switzerland on August 13, 1898, accompanied
by his sister-in-law Minna Bernays (Blumenthal, 2006) is a recently
unearthed piece of psychoanalytic history that supports this asser-
tion. Other prominent examples are Wilhelm Stekel’s fabricating
clinical material for presentations at early gatherings at Freud’s house
(Bos & Groenendijk, 2006), Masud Khan’s merrily declaring himself to
be a “prince” (Akhtar, 2007b; Hopkins, 2006), and Heinz Kohut’s (1979)
report on the “two analyses of Mr Z” which in fact was an “appalling
deception” (Giovacchini, 2000, p. 78) since Mr Z was most likely Kohut
himself and there had been no second analysis (see also Strozier, 2004).
CHAPTER FIVE
Betrayal
T
he English word “betrayal” is derived from the old French traïr
and the Latin tradere, both referring to “traitor”. Indeed, the
Webster’s dictionary meaning of “betrayal” includes “to deliver
to an enemy by treachery” (Mish, 1998, p. 109). Among other explica-
tions are “to lead astray, to fail or desert especially in time of need, to
reveal unintentionally, [and] to disclose in violation of confidence”
(ibid, p. 109). These phrases indicate that: (a) betrayal involves breaking
someone’s trust in one’s reliability and availability, and (b) betrayal can
be deliberate or unintentional. A third feature, though not explicit, can
also be discerned. This involves the fact that (c) betrayal causes hurt.
The Hindi word for betrayal, vishwas-ghaat (literally, wounded trust)
captures the essence of this phenomenon.
Moving from the confines of the dictionary, I propose two other
facets of betrayal: (d) the phenomenon comes in active and passive
forms (i.e., betraying others and feeling betrayed), and (e) the affects
connected with these forms are conscious or unconscious sadistic glee
and sharp “mental pain” (Akhtar, 2000; Freud, 1926d; Weiss, 1934),
respectively.1 Yet another facet is that (f) betraying and being betrayed
are not as aetiologically, dynamically, and phenomenologically apart
as they initially appear. The drive to betray others and the need to be
123
124 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
actions are often subtle and out of their conscious awareness. Their
betrayals of others occur despite their good wishes and, at times, are
a source of surprise and disappointment to themselves.
c. Sadistic triumph over envied others: Individuals who betray
others with conscious sadistic glee usually display “malignant
narcissism” (Kernberg, 1984), that is, a combination of pathological
self-absorption, cruelty, and antisocial behaviour. They have
experienced severe betrayal trauma during childhood and often
view themselves as the most unfairly treated among the family’s
children. They envy other siblings and harbour intense envy and
hatred over their privileged status. Their betrayals are enactments of
their destructive impulses towards their siblings, though, at its base,
their hostility is directed at their parents. Superego functioning is
often compromised and an element of viciousness lurks underneath
their overt seductiveness. The following case illustrates this sort of
compulsion to betray others.
Clinical vignette: 16
Tall, big-boned, and bold in his gestures, sixty-year-old Paul Ruby
sought psychotherapy reluctantly and pursued it in staccato
fashion. He did accept my recommendation of twice-weekly ses-
sions but took frequent and long leaves during the course of work
which lasted nearly seven years. Paul had been forced to seek help
by his daughter after his divorce when he had begun drinking
excessively and missing work-related appointments. A prosecut-
ing attorney of considerable repute, Paul had been a consummate
womaniser and his divorce was precipitated by an affair which fiz-
zled out once he was on his own. He could not tolerate his girl-
friend’s demands for deeper relatedness.
Over the course of time, I learned about two other affairs and
a long series of one-night stands. Paul seemed embarrassed about
some of these, while reporting others with a sense of triumph.
Betrayal figured in all of them and curiously, the more conscious it
was, the more it seemed to energise him. And, mind you, I am not
referring to the betrayal of his wife—that was taken for granted.
The betrayals in question were those of the various women he
seduced. While the theme appeared again and again in the account
of his life, two episodes struck him—and me—as paradigmatic of
126 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
his driven need to betray, though from different vantage points and
with different psychic consequences.
The first of these was “the story of Ellen McGuire” (he named
his various escapades like chapters of a novel),3 a stunningly
beautiful woman whom Paul had known since their childhood.
She came from a more sophisticated and elite family than Paul’s,
though they had grown up in the same affluent suburb of Pitts-
burgh as children. As a child and later as a teenager, Paul had been
intimidated by her snobbish manner, her fine looks, and her elegant
clothes. Then, decades later when he had become quite success-
ful as a lawyer and had made a lot of money, Paul unexpectedly
ran into Ellen who, in his words, “had not amounted to much”.
She was still beautiful, though. Paul “worked on her” for over a
year, befriending her, showering her with gifts, and helping her
obtain a decent-enough job. Soon, they became lovers. Paul had
no shortage of money by this time. He rented a fine apartment and
handed her the keys. A site of their amorous interludes, soon it
became Ellen’s place. Then after he had “fucked her and fucked her
real hard and real good” many, many times, one day Paul arrived
at the apartment and announced that he had terminated the lease
and she had to vacate the place within a week. To a horrified Ellen,
he now recanted with glee how this had been his plan all along and
how this was his only way to overcome how intimidating he had
found her during their childhood and adolescent years. What is
more chilling here is that Paul was hardly regretful in telling me all
this. On the contrary, he regarded his victory over Ellen as a sign of
courage, determination, and manliness. Her pain at his profound
betrayal was peripheral in his version of the story.
In contrast, Paul felt much shame and even a twinge of remorse
in recounting “the story of the Yemeni woman”. I could see that
his betrayal of her had a less calculating and more “accidental”
(i.e., more unconsciously driven) quality about it. Paul had much
difficulty recounting what happened between them. Haltingly, he
gave the following account. He had gone to London presumably
for a business trip but actually to meet a woman whom he had
been courting off and on for a while. With characteristic flair, he
rented a high-end apartment for a week with tip-top amenities—
concierge, chauffeur, cleaning service, and so on. The very first
B E T R AYA L 127
being beaten, being sexually abused, and so on) becomes the central
feature of some masochistic individuals. The answer to how it happens
is the following: the masochist possesses a remarkable, though latent,
gullibility. He believes everything he is told and overlooks facts that
contradict his rosy expectations. Isaacs, Alexander, and Haggard (1963)
have eloquently described the genesis of such naiveté.
When a parent misuses the faith and the developing trust of a
child, a disillusionment occurs which is a great blow to the psyche.
If the child has a strong enough ego, he will integrate the fact as a
determinant of limitations and restrictions on the trustworthiness
of parents and others. If he has a somewhat weaker ego, the disap-
pointment may connote a loss of the illusion of ideal parents and
thereby mean a resulting bereavement, loneliness, and depression.
In such circumstances—anger over the loss of the illusion, and guilt
over the anger—the distrust may be repressed and leave the child
unprepared to discriminate between trustworthy and untrust-
worthy persons. He has thereby become gullible, for he can only
indiscriminately trust. Gullibility has to do with a persistent need
to be deceived. The fact of being repeatedly deceived may serve
additionally as a reassurance that the parents are actually no less
trustworthy than anyone else. (p. 464)
Clinical vignette: 17
A diminutive and bespectacled middle-aged internist with a boy’s
face, Joel Lobner arrived at my office because he was considering
divorce and wanted to be “really sure” about the correctness of
B E T R AYA L 131
a result, furious. Being helpless to “get even” with his adult offenders,
the child discharges the aggression upon himself. But, in order to main-
tain a semblance of omnipotence, he libidinises it and learns to extract
pleasure from displeasure. Some inborn tendency made the occurrence
of a pleasure-in-displeasure pattern possible.6 These events later evolve
into adult patterns of psychic masochism. Bergler delineated a three-
step process as being paradigmatic in this context: (a) the masochist
unconsciously incites disappointment and humiliation by his behav-
iour and equally unconsciously derives pleasure from it, (b) he replaces
the knowledge of his own provocation and reacts to the insult with
righteous indignation, and (c) after such “pseudo-aggression” creates
further defeats, he indulges in conscious self-pity. Unconsciously, he
enjoys the masochistic pleasure.
In elaborating upon Bergler’s ideas, Cooper (ibid.) noted that the
capacity to defensively alter the meaning of painful experiences of
childhood is largely for maintaining an illusory self-control. He states
that:
Where the experience of early narcissistic humiliation is exces-
sive for external or internal reasons, these mechanisms of repair
miscarry. The object is perceived as excessively cruel and refusing;
the self is perceived as incapable of genuine self-assertion in the
pursuit of gratification; the gratification obtained from disappoint-
ment takes precedence over genuine but unavailable and unfa-
miliar libidinal, assertive, or ego-functional satisfactions. Being
disappointed or refused becomes the preferred mode of narcissistic
assertion to the extent that narcissistic and masochistic distortions
dominate the character. (p. 128, italics in the original)
Cooper emphasised that the pleasure sought in such cases is not genital-
sexual; it is pre-Oedipal and pertains to self-esteem and self-coherence.
The coexistence of narcissism and masochism is central to Cooper’s
conceptualising. He declared that
Treatment considerations
Before elucidating the nuances and strategies of technique, two cave-
ats must be entered. First, the suggestions I am making regarding the
treatment of the betraying and betrayed patients are not to replace the
customary work of empathic affirmation, transference interpretation,
reconstruction, and countertransference vigilance,7 Nor are these sug-
gestions meant to interfere with the “trio of guideposts” (Pine, 1997,
p. 13) of abstinence, neutrality, and anonymity that are a cornerstone
of our approach. What follows are not rules to be respected in work-
ing with all such patients. Indeed, the more psychologically sophisti-
cated and “analysable” the patient, the less attention needs to be paid
to these guidelines. Second, even though I make separate suggestions
for treating narcissistic-betraying patients and for treating masochistic-
betrayed patients, the fact remains that hybrid forms of such psy-
chopathology are common and shifting attention to narcissistic and
masochistic aspects of the patient’s functioning might be essential; this
would call for the use of both types of technical interventions in one
and the same patient.
Having entered these two caveats, we can move on to a considera-
tion of treating narcissistic-betraying patients. The following sequence
of interventions, though appearing overly schematic when put in writ-
ing, applies here. After ample psychic space has been provided for the
analysand to present his version of events and a therapeutic alliance has
evolved, the analyst needs to confront the patient with (a) the driven
quality of his seducing and betraying others, (b) the contradiction
between his seeking love and security while not providing those very
experiences to people he is involved with, (c) the denial of his hostile and
destructive aims towards others who are puppets in an inner theatre of
vindictiveness, and (d) the active jettisoning of moments when empa-
thy towards a victim is experienced and of similar affective-cognitive
B E T R AYA L 137
and happiness seems to be just around the corner;8 (d) help the patient
see how and how often he dismisses or minimises the presence of reli-
able people in his life, that is, people (including the analyst) who do not
betray him; (e) unmask and interpret the patient’s envy of the analyst’s
reliability (Kernberg, 1992) and, in a paradoxical turn of perspective, of
their own reliability in keeping the analytic appointments; and (f) man-
age, control, and learn from the countertransference feelings of exasper-
ation and hostility as well as defences against these burdensome affects
(Asch, 1988; Maltsberger & Buie, 1974).
A note of caution is needed here.9 In focusing upon the betrayer’s
sadism and the betrayed’s masochism, one ought not to overlook that
the former is continually depriving himself of genuine love and affec-
tion (i.e., he is being masochistic) and that the latter in harping about
his suffering is displaying his moral superiority and a condescending
attitude towards others (i.e., he is being sadistic). Remembering Freud’s
(1905a) declaration that sadism and masochism invariably coexist helps
the analyst retain a complex and multifaceted perspective on patients’
associations and transferences.
Concluding remarks
In this contribution, I have delineated some phenomenological and
metapsychological aspects of betrayal. Utilising two case reports, I have
attempted to show the lived and transference experience of betraying
others and of feeling betrayed by others.10 I have emphasised that these
narcissistic and masochistic scenarios often coexist even if one is more
overt and the other covert in a given case. Following the discussion of
these cases, I have outlined some guidelines for the treatment of betray-
ing narcissistic and betrayed masochistic patients, while reminding the
reader that the suggestions I have made are neither essential nor appli-
cable in all cases. Moreover, they are not intended to replace our usual
ways of conducting analytic treatment.
While I have cast a wide net, a few questions remain unanswered.
First, since both the betraying and the betrayed types seem to have
suffered severe betrayal trauma in their childhood, what accounts for
their phenotypical difference? In other words, why do some victims of
childhood betrayal become narcissistic betrayers and others masochis-
tic seekers of betrayal? Such “choice of neurosis” (Freud, 1913c) is most
likely dependent upon some difference in constitutional endowment
with the more inherently aggressive child “opting” for the narcissistic
B E T R AYA L 139
route and the inherently less aggressive (or less outwardly aggressive)
child succumbing to masochism. Perhaps the age and the degree of ego
maturity when the childhood betrayal occurred and the qualitative dif-
ference in helplessness it produced (e.g., by broken promises vs. actual
death of a parent) also play a role here. Putting all these possibilities
together gives rise to the following speculations. Betrayed children
who were constitutionally less aggressive, traumatised earlier, repeat-
edly, and had no recourse but to cling to their betrayers while grow-
ing up, most likely turn out to be masochists. Betrayed children who
were constitutionally more aggressive, traumatised somewhat later,
less frequently, and had recourse to caregivers other than their betray-
ers most likely turn out to be narcissists. However, more data and more
thought are needed about these issues for one to be certain about these
hypotheses.
Another area that needs further exploration is why some narcis-
sistic and some masochistic patients improve with analytic treatment
whereas others do not. While patient-based variables (e.g., honesty,
psychological mindedness, absence of substance abuse, work-related
sources of efficacy and pleasure) contribute much to the prognosis,
quality of the “fit” between the patient and analyst might also matter;
this less than optimally explored realm merits more investigation. And
so does the potential impact of gender and culture upon which pole
of the betrayer-betrayed scenario will predominate in the final psycho-
pathological picture in those exposed to the trauma of severe betrayal
during childhood.
While answers to such questions are awaited, one thing remains
clear. Betrayal is both a specific form of trauma and a constituent of
all psychic trauma. Sexual abuse, physical maltreatment, profound
neglect, mockery, and bullying all include an element of betrayal. All
involve breaking someone’s trust and putting someone’s faith and hope
in question. As a result, the dynamic and technical observations con-
tained in this chapter might apply—in small or large measure—to all
traumatised individuals while maintaining their specificity for those
who have been betrayed and hurt by their caregivers.
Notes
1. Having unintentionally betrayed others, however, leads to remorse,
and realising that one has been unintentionally betrayed diminishes
mental pain.
140 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
2. The word “betrayal” appears only eighteen times in the entire corpus of
Freud’s writings (Guttman, Jones & Parrish, 1980, pp. 272–273). Five of
these usages are colloquial and carry little scientific significance. Nine
pertain to “psychic self-betrayal” via slips of the tongue (Freud, 1901b),
clumsy testimony during a court trial (Freud, 1906c), or bodily fidgeti-
ness in a failed attempt to suppress a secret (Freud, 1905e). The remain-
ing four usages are in the context of compulsive rituals (e.g., keeping
scraps of paper) to control a fear of betrayal (Freud, 1896b), the mass
paranoia of a nation defeated in war defensively evolving a collective
“delusion of betrayal” (Freud, 1950a), and the masochistic tendency of
certain individuals who find themselves repeatedly betrayed by friends
(Freud, 1920g).
3. Besides his calling these relationships “stories”, Paul always referred to
various women by both their first and last names. I have encountered
this phenomenon in another narcissistic patient and believe that it is an
unwitting fetishistic ploy to turn women into caricatures.
4. While the term “masochism” has been used in many ways (see Maleson,
1984, for a comprehensive review), Brenner’s (1959) definition remains
authoritative. Masochism, for him, is “the seeking of unpleasure, by
which is meant physical or mental pain, discomfort or wretchedness,
for the sake of sexual pleasure, with the qualification that either the
seeking or the pleasure or both may often be unconscious rather than
conscious” (p. 197).
5. Limentani coined this term for an individual who harbours a powerful
wish to be a woman and has deep envy of everything female. He also
has a secret fantasy of possessing a vagina. Intelligent, charming, and
friendly, the “vagina man” reads voraciously, looks at things intently,
and insatiably seeks the company of others, especially women. He is
feminine but his femininity is hidden behind his attentiveness towards
women. Owing to this attentiveness, his sexual performance is better
than average. According to Limentani, such a person has been raised by
a mother who was somewhat masculine, while also treating her child as
her phallus. The “vagina man” constellation results from an identifica-
tion with such a mother. It serves as a defence against homosexuality.
Moreover, the fantasy of belonging to the other sex helps avoid the fear
of castration.
6. The binding of the death instinct by the libido lays down the ground
for such “primary masochism” (Freud, 1924c). While many psychoana-
lysts have reservations about such a formulation, poets have subscribed
to this view wholeheartedly. A recent illustration is evident in the line
Ghum ke sehnay mein bhi qudrat ne mazaa rakhha hai (literally, “Nature has
B E T R AYA L 141
created the potential of deriving pleasure from pain”) by the Urdu poet,
Nasir Kazmi (1972).
7. Our clinical work is a peculiar amalgam of a warm relationship which
we approach with “evenly suspended attention” (Freud, 1912e, p. 111)
and “without memory or desire” (Bion, 1967b, p. 272), and a theory-
driven deliberateness, hierarchy of interpretation (Loewenstein, 1951),
and “strategy” (Levy, 1987) of technique. We respond to the analysand’s
material with an admixture of “free-floating responsiveness” (Sandler &
Sandler, 1998) and selectively paying “attention now to defence, now
to what is defended against, depending upon which is apparent in a
patient’s communications” (Brenner, 2000, p. 548). My proposal of
certain guidelines for treating betrayed and betraying patients reflects
the spirit of focused attention and strategic interpretation in psycho-
analytic technique.
8. This, of course, is the essence of what Freud (1923b) termed “negative
therapeutic reaction”. He held that unconscious guilt over the wished-
for childhood Oedipal transgressions of incest and murder were
responsible for such a reaction. Subsequent analysts have, however,
added additional dynamics including anxiety over separation from
mother (Asch, 1976; Grunert, 1979), envy of the therapist’s ability to
soothe and help (Kernberg, 1984), and identification with a masochistic
parent (Akhtar, 2009).
9. This discussion of betraying and being betrayed has remained patient-
focused. It has not addressed betrayals of the patient by the analyst.
While their gross forms (e.g., sexual boundary violations) are well-
known and written about (Casement, 2006; Celenza, 2006; Gabbard &
Lester, 1995), more subtle betrayals by the analyst often go unrecog-
nised or are subsumed—by the analyst—under the rubric of “technical
errors” (see Charles, 1997, for a meaningful discussion of this matter).
10. Although the two cases described here involve men betraying women
or feeling betrayed by women, this does not mean that women cannot
do and feel the same. Moreover, betrayal can also occur in the “non-
erotic” realms of money, academic collaboration, national security, etc.
CHAPTER SIX
Revenge
T
he history of human civilisation is replete with examples of
man’s destructiveness towards man. Some of these outbursts
are impulsive, passionate, and transient. Others are calculated,
deliberate, and long-standing. Some involve individuals. Others
involve masses. Some occur only in fantasy and, under fortunate cir-
cumstances, are turned into defiant poetry, biting fiction, and provoc-
ative theatre. Others slit throats, ruin families, and cause bloodshed.
Regardless of their extent, all destructive actions somehow or other
become justified in the mind of the perpetrator. One’s violence is given
a patina of reasonableness through all sorts of rationales and rationali-
sations regardless of whether it involves the plebian tit-for-tat of chil-
dren or the awesome “messianic sadism” (Akhtar, 2007c) of paranoid
fundamentalists. Matters of the former variety fall under the purview of
parents, elementary school teachers, and benevolent clergy. Matters of
the latter variety belong to interdisciplinary think tanks that can inform
sociopolitical praxis.
These two extremes are not encountered in the clinical situation.
What one does witness there are “mid-level” destructive aims and
fantasies directed at old and new objects as well as their recreations
in the transference. Any therapist who has worked with narcissistic,
143
144 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Phenomenological aspects
The English word “revenge” is derived from the Old French vengier,
meaning “to avenge”. Its dictionary definition includes phrases such
as (i) to avenge by retaliating in kind or degree; (ii) to inflict injury in
return for an insult, and (iii) an opportunity for getting satisfaction
(Webster’s, 1987, p. 1009). An unmistakable implication is that revenge
has ideational, emotional, and behavioural aspects. In the ideational
sphere, revenge is accompanied by a fantasy (conscious or uncon-
scious) of having been grievously harmed by someone and of finding
relief from inflicting damage upon the perpetrator. In the emotional
sphere, revenge is accompanied by feelings of “mental pain” (Akhtar,
2000; Freud, 1926d; Ramzy & Wallerstein, 1958; Weiss, 1934), bitterness,
rage, and defensive exaltation; the vengeful person is often euphoric.
In the behavioural sphere, common manifestations of revenge include
verbal and physical assaults of varying degrees, ranging from sarcasm,
denigration, and hurling obscenities to slapping, hitting, punching,
throwing things at someone, knifing, maiming, shooting, and killing.
However, gross actions of such a sort do not exhaust the behavioural
manifestations of revenge. The phenomena associated with it are com-
plex in many ways.
First: Acts of revenge are not always directed at the individual or
organisation that is viewed as having caused harm. Often the rage ema-
nating from feeling hurt is aimed at objects that symbolically stand for
the injuring party or are weak and vulnerable, hence suitable for being
attacked. Nearly 100 years ago, Rank (1913) pointed out that neurotic
REVENGE 145
acts of revenge are often directed against the “wrong” people. Revenge
fantasies in terrorist acts especially depict how victims of the destructive
impulse are not truly the targets of it (Akhtar, 2003); innocent civilians
are killed and maimed not for rage directed at them but because they are
dispensable pawns in a violent game of chess with their governments.
Second: Redirection of vengeful affects and behaviours can
involve the self. Thus the chronic self-effacement, self-deprivation,
self-denigration, self-mutilation, and self-destructiveness of severely
masochistic patients contain a powerful, though unconscious, element
of revenge. Freud (1917e, 1921c) had long ago discerned this element in
the symptomatology of depression. He stated that
Third: Even direct acts of revenge take many forms. Some of them
are active (e.g., sarcasm, physical violence), while others are passive
(e.g., gaze aversion, refusal to eat). Some involve aggression while
others deploy sexuality as a medium. Behaviours that have been
linked with an underlying theme of revenge are as varied as frigid-
ity, euphemistically referred as “revenge on the man” (Fenichel, 1945,
p. 174), incestuous acting-out (Gordon, 1955), pathological stealing
(Castelnuevo-Tedesco, 1974), primal scene reversals (Arlow, 1980),
shop-lifting (Ornstein, Gropper & Bogner, 1983), serial killing (Stone,
1989), and sexual betrayal (Akhtar, 2013a). At times, an individual’s
sexual object choice can also express his or her rebellion and revenge
against the cultural strictures of the family (Freud, 1920g). Neurotic
fears of being bitten by animals too can contain elements of revenge
being taken against oneself for one’s original hostility towards parents
(Freud, 1926d).
Finally, there exists a relationship between the level of character
organisation and the nature of revenge fantasy. At the “higher level
of character organization” (Kernberg, 1970), where identity is well-
consolidated and defences centre upon repression, revenge fantasies—if
they even exist—involve Oedipal issues. Childhood exposure to
parental sexuality fuels such fantasies and their subtle and disguised
seepage into actual behaviour. At the “intermediate” and “lower” levels
of character organisation (ibid.), characterised by identity diffusion and
the preponderance of splitting mechanisms, matters appear more stark.
Revenge, in this context, is usually overt, cold-blooded, and accompa-
nied by conscious sadistic pleasure. Rosenfeld’s (1971) description of
narcissistic personalities who idealise their destructive capacity and
Kernberg’s (1984) delineation of the syndrome of malignant narcissism
which combines grandiosity, paranoid traits, and antisocial tendencies
are highly pertinent here. Fantasies and actions of violent revenge are
common among such individuals and are founded upon severe child-
hood frustrations and actual trauma; their vindictiveness constitutes
the reversal of betrayal and abuse by their parents.
Psychodynamics
Freud’s first comment upon revenge was in the context of trauma
which, he believed, became more pathogenic when suffered in silence.
Taking revenge holds the possibility of getting over the injury, though
REVENGE 147
speaking about what has happened also helps. Here are Freud’s own
words on this matter.
Freud later evoked the idea of revenge in his elucidation of the dynam-
ics of Little Hans (1909b) and the Wolf Man (1918b). He regarded
their fears of being bitten and devoured by animals (in reality and in
dreams, respectively) as a boomerang effect of their own hostile fanta-
sies towards their parents, especially in the context of the latter’s sexual
lives. In Inhibitions, Symptoms and Anxiety, written nearly two decades
later, Freud reiterated this idea.
The case of the “Wolf Man” and the somewhat less complicated one
of “Little Hans” raise a number of further considerations … There
can be no doubt that the instinctual impulse which was repressed
in both phobias was a hostile one against the father. One might say
that that impulse had been repressed by the process of being trans-
formed into its opposite. Instead of aggressiveness on the part of
the subject towards his father, there appeared aggressiveness (in
the shape of revenge) on the part of his father towards the subject.
Since this aggressiveness is in any case rooted in the sadistic phase
of the libido, only a certain amount of degradation is needed to
reduce it to the oral stage. This stage, while only hinted at in “Little
Hans’s” fear of being bitten, was blatantly exhibited in the “Wolf
Man’s” terror of being devoured. (1926d, p. 106)
He does not forgive his mother for having granted the favour of
sexual intercourse not to himself but to his father, and he regards
it as an act of unfaithfulness. If these impulses do not quickly pass,
there is no outlet for them other than to run their course in phan-
tasies which have as their subject his mother’s sexual activities
under the most diverse circumstances; and the consequent tension
leads particularly readily to his finding relief in masturbation. As a
result of the constant combined operation of the two driving forces,
[sexual] drive and thirst for revenge, phantasies of his mother’s
unfaithfulness are by far the most preferred. (1910h, p. 171)
Freud repeated these ideas in Group Psychology and the Analysis of the
Ego (1921c, p. 109), though conceding, in Civilization and Its Discontents
(1930a, p. 130), that the severity of self-reproaches and the underly-
ing revenge motif is only partly due to experiential factors (either via
narcissistic injury in the Oedipal phase or via loss of an ambivalently-
held but needed object); inborn constitutional factors also contribute to
the ferocity of the superego and to the overall propensity for rage and
revenge in one’s character.
REVENGE 149
large did) towards the latter view. Even those contributors (e.g., Arlow,
1980; Socarides, 1966) who employed the vocabulary of drives did
so in the context of childhood trauma. Most others (e.g., Boris, 1986;
Castelnuovo-Tedesco, 1974; Daniels, 1969; Horney, 1948; Kohut, 1972;
Steiner, 1996) emphatically favoured the deprivation and/or humilia-
tion hypothesis of the origin of vindictiveness.
In a remarkable paper titled “The Value of Vindictiveness”, Horney
(1948) noted that while rational outrage at a frustrating event settles
soon after it is vented, vindictiveness, in neurotic characters, can become
a way of life. Its aims then are to humiliate, to exploit, and to frustrate
others. Its means can be varied and include the induction of guilt and
inferiority in others, ingratitude, indifference, and active assaults upon
others’ valued traits and capacities. Horney described three forms of
vindictiveness, namely, (i) openly aggressive vindictiveness that is
associated with a certain kind of pride in what is construed as one’s
honesty and straightforwardness; (ii) self-effacing vindictiveness which
operates covertly and exploits others’ inclinations towards fairness and
justice; vindictiveness of this sort evokes the puzzling impression of
being done at the person’s expense; and (iii) detached vindictiveness
that expresses hostility towards others “by not listening, by disregard-
ing their needs, by forgetting their wishes, by making them feel as
disturbing intruders, by withholding praise or affection, and by with-
drawing psychically or socially” (p. 4). Horney emphasised that vindic-
tiveness, while destructive in intent, serves some positive functions as
well. These include its protective power against real and/or imagined
hostility from others, its defensive aim against self-destructiveness, and
its promise to restore injured pride. The need for vindictive triumph,
in Horney’s formulation, arose from many sources, the prime variable
being a pressure to reverse the thoughtlessness or openly cruel humili-
ations experienced at the hands of others. The feeling of vitality and
even thrill provided by acts of revenge also counters the inner sense of
inferiority and shame.
Searles (1956) also underscored the defensive functions of revenge.
He noted that vindictiveness can serve as a defence against repressed
emotions, especially those of loss, separation, and mourning. Accord-
ing to him, the vindictive person is unable to let go of his attachment to
the object that is indifferent to his desire; seeking revenge against that
object maintains the hope of affecting a change in its attitude.
Socarides (1966) noted that the conscious aim of vengeance is ret-
ribution and punishment while the unconscious aim is to cover up
REVENGE 151
An attempt at synthesis
What becomes clear from this review is that many diverse phenomena
are subsumed under the term “revenge”. It appears in the vastly dif-
ferent contexts of repressed, disguised, and symbolically represented
154 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Technical implications
The theme of revenge appears frequently in the course of intensive
treatments. Individuals who seek psychoanalysis or long-term psy-
choanalytic psychotherapy often have significant childhood trauma
156 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Concluding remarks
In this chapter, I have provided a wide-ranging survey of the phe-
nomenological, dynamic, literary, and clinical aspects of revenge. My
scope has been broad and our theoretical stance multifaceted. Through-
out my discourse, I have paid attention to all “four psychologies of
psychoanalysis” (Pine, 1988): drive, ego, object relations, and self.
160 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
(1851), and the Count of Monte Cristo (1844) from Dumas’s eponymous
novel mobilise much sympathy and admiration in readers around the
globe. And the same is true of the avenging movie characters, rang-
ing from Clint Eastwood’s Dirty Harry series of the 1970s to the Angry
Young Man movies of Bollywood cinema (Akhtar & Choksi, 2005). The
audience simply laps it all up. It seems as if these books and celluloid
dramas afford an abreactive conduit for ubiquitous fantasies of get-
ting even and settling the score. Revenge seems to be “hot” and well
accepted in all cultures.
At the same time, children are discouraged from “tit-for-tat” think-
ing. Vindictiveness is frowned upon. Revenge-seeking is deemed
immature and the ideal of forgiveness is upheld by religious and noble
men (see the lives of Gandhi, Martin Luther King, Jr., and Nelson
Mandela). Parallel to the mesmerising tales of revenge, there exist
moving and poignant narratives of forgiveness especially in the tradi-
tions of Christianity.
Putting such diverse perspectives together leads one to conclude that
society holds ambivalent attitudes about revenge. Consciously, it strives
towards responding to injury by forgiving the enemy. Unconsciously, it
seeks to redress the trauma by taking revenge. Vicarious enjoyment of
“well-justified” revenge in the safety of fiction and movies then becomes
a compromise formation for this conflict of our culture. Some tension
between the correctness of forgiving and seeking revenge nonetheless
remains. Moss (1986) declares the two as competing attempts at recon-
ciliation with the traumatising figures of the Oedipus complex. While
the System Conscious might tilt in favour of one or the other strategy,
both persist unaltered in the System Unconscious. There, they are rep-
resented as self-object pairs involved in the two respective scenarios of
revenge and forgiveness. According to Moss, this fiction of symmetry
“lies at the base of the civilization-wide proclivity toward the pursuit of
revenge and forgiveness as strategies to obliterate the effects of trauma”
(p. 209). The implication is clear: the wish to settle a score never entirely
leaves the human heart.3 And this might not be bad. Elsewhere, I have
observed that
Some revenge is actually good for the victim. It puts the victim’s
hitherto passive ego in an active position. This imparts a sense of
mastery and enhances self-esteem. Revenge (in reality or fantasy),
allowing the victim to taste the pleasure of sadism, also changes the
162 SOURCES OF SUFFERING
Notes
1. Laura Blumenfeld’s (2002) book, Revenge, reports her encounter with
the Palestinian militant who had shot and wounded her father, a New
York rabbi. One of her goals was to see if she could make her father
human in the gunman’s eyes, since terrorism is not so much about
killing people as about dehumanising them to make a political point.
In effect, she sought to “punish” the terrorist by showing his victim’s
humanity. Her unusual form of revenge led to the Palestinian man’s
apologising to her father and her father’s forgiving him.
2. The deterrence function of revenge is what leads evolutionary theorists
(Barash & Lipton, 2011; Pinker, 2011) to regard revenge as a part of our
evolved human nature. “The necessity of revenge and punishment,
from such vantage point, is necessary for the emergence and suste-
nance of cooperation. It prevents the cooperator from being exploited”
(J. Anderson Thomson, Jr., personal communication, June 8, 2013).
3. The idea that the wish for revenge might be ubiquitous does not sit well
with everyone. The rejecting response to the movie, Inglorious Basterds
(2009, directed by Quintin Tarantino), by many Jewish people, is a case
in point. The movie depicted the fictional scenario of Jewish violence
against the Nazis and thus challenged the apparent absence of revenge
fantasies among Jews. In contrast, the movie, Django Unchained (2012),
showing a freed black slave taking revenge against his white tormen-
tors, was received with relative equanimity by the African American
community. The socio-historical reasons that might contribute to this
differential response remain unclear.
REFERENCES
163
164 REFERENCES
Blum, H. (2009). Where does the truth lie? In: S. Akhtar & S. Parens (Eds.),
Lying, Cheating, and Carrying On: Developmental, Clinical, and Sociocul-
tural Aspects of Dishonesty and Deceit (pp. 59–67). Lanham, MD: Jason
Aronson.
Blumenfeld, L. (2002). Revenge: A Story of Hope. New York: Simon &
Schuster.
Blumenthal, R. (2006). Hotel log hints at illicit desire that Dr Freud did not
repress. New York Times, p. A-1, December 24.
Bollas, C. (1999). The Mystery of Things. London: Routledge.
Bolognini, S. (2011). Secret Passages: The Theory and Technique of Interpsychic
Relations. G. Atkinson (Trans.). London: Karnac.
Boris, H. N. (1986). The “other” breast—greed, envy, spite and revenge.
Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 22: 45–59.
Bos, J., & Groenendijk, L. (2006). The Self-Marginalization of Wilhelm Stekel:
Freudian Circles Inside and Out. New York: Springer.
Brenman, E. (1985). Cruelty and narrow-mindedness. International Journal of
Psychoanalysis, 66: 273–281.
Brenner, C. (1959). The masochistic character: genesis and treatment.
Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association, 7: 197–226.
Brenner, C. (1976). Psychoanalytic Technique and Psychic Conflict. New York:
International Universities Press.
Brenner, C. (2000). Brief communication: evenly hovering attention. Psycho-
analytic Quarterly, 69: 545–549.
Brenner, I. (2004). Psychic Trauma: Dynamics, Symptoms, and Treatment.
Northvale, NJ: Jason Aronson.
Brontë, E. (1847). Wuthering Heights. New York: Random House, 2009.
Byrne, R. W., & Whiten, A. (1992). Cognitive evolution in primates:
evidence from tactical deception. Man, 27: 609–627.
Campbell, J., & Pile, S. (2011). Space travels of the Wolfman: phobia and its
worlds. Psychoanalysis and History, 13: 69–88.
Cao, L. (1997). Monkey Bridge. New York: Penguin.
Casement, P. (1991). Learning from the Patient. New York: Guilford.
Casement, P. (2006). Sexual Boundary Violations: Therapeutic, Supervisory, and
Academic Contexts. Lanham, MD: Jason Aronson.
Castelnuevo-Tedesco, P. (1974). Stealing, revenge, and the Monte Cristo
complex. International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 55: 169–181.
Catch Me if You Can (2002). Directed by S. Spielberg, Dreamworks
production.
Celenza, A. (2006). Sexual Boundary Violations: Therapeutic, Supervisory, and
Academic Contexts. Lanham, MD: Jason Aronson.
Chadwick, M. (1929). Notes upon the fear of death. International Journal of
Psychoanalysis, 9: 321–334.
168 REFERENCES
185
186 INDEX
Posada-Villa, J. 63 Roth, P. 44
Potenza, M. N. 63 Rounsaville, B. J. 63
Prathikanti, S. 78 Rudnytsky, P. 18
primary greed 45 Rycroft, C. 68–69
primary masochism 86
Procci, W. 91, 145 sadism 52, 86, 92, 109, 117, 138, 145,
process of defence analysis 116 148, 161
projective identification 24–25, 27, messianic 143
40, 80 primitive 155
psychiatric syndromes, pertinent unconscious 91
104–106 sadistic
Psycho 20 assaults 159
psychopathic transference 112–113, fantasies 82
117 glee 123, 125
psychopathic-paranoid transference lying 101
113 narcissistic- 16
psychopathic-unreal transference 113 oral- 42
Puppet Masters 20 phase of the libido 147
pleasure 146
Rachman, R. 11 self-blaming 89
Ramzy, I. 144 triumph 125
Rangell, L. 10 Sadock, B. J. 106
Rank, O. 144 Sadock, V. A. 106
Reich, T. 114 Sampson, N. A. 63
Reich, W. 87 Sandler, A. -M. 10, 31, 89, 141
revenge 143–162 Sandler, J. 31, 89, 141
antisocial tendency 149 Sass, L. A. 119
attempt at synthesis 153–155 Schafer, R. 137
defined 144 Schreiber, L. R. 63
demonic 154 Scott, K. M. 63
history 144 Searles, H. F. 150
phenomenological aspects secondary greed 45
144–146 Seedat, S. 63
psychodynamics 146–153 Seelig, B. 40
spectrum of 155 self-preservative lying 101
technical implications 155–159 Selzer, M. 112
Robertson, I. H. 63 Selzer, M. A. 115
Rogler, L. H. 17 sense of inadequacy 68
Rohrlich, J. B. 39 separation anxiety 74, 78, 94
Rosen, I. 88 separation guilt 78–89
Rosenfeld, H. 16, 129, 146 Shakespeare, W. 38, 154
Rosof, L. 40 Shames, L. 39
192 INDEX
universal fears 17
USA Today 107