(Texts in German Philosophy) Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Von Schelling - On The History of Modern Philosophy-Cambridge University Press (1994)
(Texts in German Philosophy) Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Von Schelling - On The History of Modern Philosophy-Cambridge University Press (1994)
(Texts in German Philosophy) Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Von Schelling - On The History of Modern Philosophy-Cambridge University Press (1994)
von Schelling
On the History of
Modern Philosophy
https://archive.org/details/onhistoryofmoderOOOOsche
TEXTS IN GERMAN PHILOSOPHY
On the History of
Modern
Philosophy
by
Andrew Bowie
PROFESSOR OF EUROPEAN PHILOSOPHY
CAMBRIDGE
UNIVERSITY PRESS
PUBLISHED BYTHE PRESS SYNDICATE OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE
The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge CB2 1RP, United Kingdom
Typeset in Baskerville
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Translator’s Introduction 1
Reassessing Schelling 1
Mind and Nature 3
Identity and Difference 13
Schelling and Hegel 23
References 35
[Introduction] 41
Descartes 42
Comparison of Bacon and Descartes 61
Hegel 134
Supplement from an Older (Erlangen) Manuscript 161
vii
viii Contents
Index 193
Translator’s Preface
IX
X Translator's Preface
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
*
Translator’s Introduction
REASSESSING SCHELLING
1
2 Translator's Introduction
of philosophy. Towards the end of the 1830s Schelling did reduce the
role in his system given to the historical review of philosophy that
makes up the Lectures (see Fuhrmans’ introduction to Schelling
1972), but the Lectures can still be regarded as an integral part of the
late work. The real importance of the Lectures lies in their critique of
Hegel in the light of the later Schelling’s understanding of the history
of philosophy since Descartes. In this introduction I shall describe
Schelling’s perspective on the history of modern philosophy by out¬
lining certain aspects of his work as a whole, in order to suggest why
the later Schelling deserves our renewed attention.1
The recent revival of interest in German Idealism has been fuelled
by the widespread rejection of philosophies which entail a subject-
object duality and a notion of cognition which depends upon assum¬
ing a mind separate from the rest of the world. The suspicion that the
mechanistic, objectifying forms of explanation that came to dominate
natural science and philosophy in the second half of the nineteenth
century are seriously inadequate has led to a reconsideration of some
of the major philosophical positions of the early nineteenth century.
German Idealism has a somewhat paradoxical status in this respect.
On the one hand, it is seen as a form of totalising metaphysics that
merely conjured away, rather than overcoming, the modern problem
of the relationship between thought and being that was revealed by
Kant’s critique of previous metaphysics. On the other hand, German
Idealism is seen as that strand of modern philosophy which began to
develop a methodologically defensible way of overcoming the split be¬
tween consciousness and the world. This latter perspective offers
most for a reassessment of the work of Schelling.
The overlapping stages of Schelling’s philosophy began with his en¬
thusiasm, in the mid-1790s, for Fichte’s attempts to revise Kant’s tran¬
scendental philosophy, which had given the primary role to the
activity of consciousness in the constitution of the knowable world.
Along with this went the beginning of Schelling’s lifelong preoccupa¬
tion with Spinoza. Towards the end of the century Schelling devel¬
oped his Naturphilosophic, or philosophy of nature, which extended
Fichte’s notion of the activity of the subject into the idea of all of na¬
ture as “productivity”. The System of Transcendental Idealism of 1800
considered art to be the medium in which the activity of thought and
the productivity of nature could be understood as ultimately the
same. The “identity philosophy”, Schelling’s attempt at a complete
system which would demonstrate that “subject” and “object”, the
1 I have elsewhere given a much more detailed account of these issues, relating
them to contemporary concerns (see Bowie 1993). I refer those who want more
historical detail to Xavier Tilliette’s monumental Schelling. Line philosophic en devenir
(Tilliette 1970).
Mind and Nature 3
“ideal” and the “real”, are only different degrees or aspects of the
Same, concerned him in the early 1800s (and in many ways for the
rest of his life). During this period he broke with Fichte, whom he re¬
garded as failing to move beyond the sphere of self-consciousness to
that consciousness’s ground in a nature of which it is only one aspect.
In the 1809 On the Essence of Human Freedom (the last substantial text
published by Schelling in his lifetime), and in the 1811-15 Ages °ftfie
World, Schelling renounced the tendency towards a balanced polar re¬
lationship of the “ideal” (mind, subject) and the “real” (matter, object)
that had been present in much of his preceding work and became
concerned with understanding the ground of which the antagonistic
principles that constitute the world are the consequence. Schelling’s
late work attempted to establish what he termed a “positive philoso¬
phy”, of which the Lectures formed a part. The late philosophy began
to develop in the 1820s, and he continued to revise it for the rest of
his life. Positive philosophy sought to move beyond “negative philos¬
ophy”, exemplified in Hegel’s Logic, which explicated the forms of
pure thought that determine what things are. The goal of positive
philosophy was to come to terms both with the fact that things are and
with the contingencies of the historical emergence and development
of thinking. The ultimate aim of positive philosophy was to derive a
philosophically viable religion from a reinterpretation of the histori¬
cal development of Christianity. It was not least Schelling’s failure to
achieve this latter aim that led to many of the valid aspects of the later
philosophy being ignored.
The story generally told about the history of German Idealism is
that it was initiated by Fichte’s critique of Kant, carried on by Schell¬
ing’s criticisms of Fichte in his Naturphilosophie and identity system,
and brought to (an albeit temporary) end by Hegel’s development of
a complete system of philosophy, on the basis of the philosophical
articulation of the identity of subject and object. It is this story that
now needs correction if we are to do justice to Schelling. Although
Schelling aimed at many of the same goals as Hegel, his work is im¬
portant precisely because it shows that Hegel’s attempt to reach a fi¬
nal resolution in'philosophy could not succeed. The divided world
with which Schelling’s later work confronts us makes a major contri¬
bution to modern philosophy in ways which are only now beginning
to be explored.
The importance of Kant in this debate, and the main reason why he
was attacked by Jacobi, lay in his denial that we can say anything pos¬
itive about things in themselves. Kant argued that all knowledge is of
“intuitions”, which are organised by categories of the understanding.
This meant we have no right to claim that we can know any more than
the necessary connections of intuitions in the judgements of our un¬
derstanding. The problem with this, as Jacobi suggested, is that it
makes knowledge groundless. Kant, though, did not deny the existence
of what was beyond the world of phenomena, in that the world “in
itself” includes ourselves, who are free as noumena, even as we are
determined as phenomena. The question that concerned German
Idealism was how to understand the relationship of the phenomenal
and the noumenal worlds.
It was J. G. Fichte who suggested, in the Wissenschaftslehre of 1794
and subsequent texts, that our cognitive and our practical aspects
must have a common source if Kant’s philosophy is to provide what
Kant intended, a grounding of the possibility of knowledge and ethics
that did not have to rely on theological support. Fichte’s key move was
to radicalise Kant’s question as to how knowledge can explain itself.
He argued that consciousness could not be understood in the same
way as any aspect of the object world. The real question was how the
mind came to the act of reflection upon its own functioning at all. If
the mind were really a mechanism, it would be inexplicable why it
came to reflect upon itself, because there could be no reason for it to
do so. Nothing in a chain of cause and effect can explain why that
chain should come to the point of thinking about itself as itself. For
consciousness to reflect upon itself it must have a subject—object
structure, but that structure is not sufficient to explain consciousness,
because one needs a third aspect that establishes the identity of re-
flecter and reflected. This ground must have an uncaused, absolute
status, which Fichte attributes to the “I”.
Subjectivity for Fichte, then, is a self-acting spontaneity which can¬
not be explained via a prior cause, because that would contradict its
essential nature by putting it in a relationship of causal dependence.
The structure of the world is, as it was for Kant, a product of the I: it
does not, as had been thought in dogmatic metaphysics, depend upon
the essence of things in themselves. Fichte, though, gives an account
of the I which Kant could not and did not accept. Without such an
account Fichte considers Kant’s philosophy incomplete, in that its
most fundamental aspect, self-consciousness, is unexplained. For
Fichte, the I cannot be known as an object because it is itself the prior
condition of objectivity. Access to this condition depends, therefore,
upon an action of the I upon itself, in “intellectual intuition”, where
6 Translator’s Introduction
In Schelling’s view, knowledge itself is, as it was for Kant, the result
of the necessary linking of phenomena expressed in judgements.
What makes knowledge (and practical reason) possible, though, can¬
not itself be of the same conditioned status. This is one of the most
important contentions of German Idealism. Schelling maintains, in
line with Fichte, that the condition of knowledge, the “positing” of
the I, must have a different status from what it posits: “nothing can be
posited by itself as a thing, i.e. an absolute thing (unbedingtes Ding) is
a contradiction” (I/i p. 166). The argument depends upon a play on
one of the words for “absolute”, unbedingt. Things can be determinate
only in relation to other objects, but they also depend upon what pos¬
its them as something, the subject. The subject is therefore unbedingt,
unthinged, “absolute”. The requirement, taken over from Fichte, that
the prior condition of objectivity is the subject, separates Schelling
from Spinoza for most of his career. There is, though, a serious prob¬
lem in understanding the Absolute in terms of subjectivity. In the
Philosophical Letters Schelling reformulates the question he had asked
in On the I as follows: “How is it that I step at all out of the Absolute and
move towards something opposed (auf ein Entgegengesetztes)?” (I/i p. 294).
Stepping out of the Absolute involves what must be conceived of as
the undifferentiated One somehow ceasing to be One. This intro¬
duces relation into the Absolute, which seems to contradict its es¬
sence. The relations in scientific knowledge are understood in terms
of the principle of sufficient reason, which makes links, in the form of
statements of identity, between what appears opposed. Jacobi’s point
was that the “negative” dependence of particular things on other par¬
ticular things for their determinacy meant that there must be a pos¬
itive ground, which he termed “being”, that could not be understood
in the same way as those particular things were understood. Schell¬
ing’s friend at the Tubingen seminary, Friedrich Holderlin, realised
that such an argument revealed a major problem in Fichte’s idea that
the Absolute should be understood as an absolute I. For it to be an
absolute / it must entail consciousness. However, if the absolute I con¬
tained all reality, it could not have anything opposed to it as an object
and therefore could not be conscious. Consequently, Holderlin ar¬
gued, one has to understand the structure of the relationship of sub¬
ject to object in consciousness as grounded in “a whole of which
subject and object are the parts”, which he, in the manner of Jacobi,
termed “being” (see Bowie 1990 p. 68). This meant that any attempt
to explicate the Absolute in reflexive terms, as a cognitive relation¬
ship of subject to object, was doomed to failure. A development of this
argument became the core of Schelling’s objections to Hegel. Schell¬
ing’s problem was to reconcile this view with his conviction that Fichte
had shown the inherent fault in Spinozism, its failure to explain sub-
8 Translator’s Introduction
one can push as many transitory materials as one wants, which become finer
and finer, between mind and matter, but sometime the point must come
where mind and matter are One, or where the great leap that we so long
wished to avoid becomes inevitable (I/2 p. 53).
1 I have looked in some detail at the System elsewhere (Bowie 1990 and 1993), so I
restrict myself here to a brief outline intended to facilitate the understanding of
Schelling’s own account of it in the Lectures.
Mind and Nature 11
Truth arises when opposed errors neutralise each other. Absolute truth can¬
not be admitted; and this is the testimony for the freedom of thought and of
spirit. If absolute truth were found, then the business of spirit would be com¬
pleted, and it would have to cease to be, since it only exists in activity (Schlegel
>991 P- 93)-
cannot reach, because art cannot be determined in the way any par¬
ticular object of knowledge can be determined. As the “eternal organ
and document of philosophy”, art even takes on a role superior to
that of philosophy, in that philosophy tries to articulate the Absolute
but cannot positively say what the Absolute is in a final statement of
identity. Art does not say what the Absolute is, but via its endless po¬
tential for meaning art shows that which cannot be said.
The System of Transcendental Idealism ends with the famous invoca¬
tion proclaiming the need for a “new mythology”, a “mythology of
reason”, to lead the sciences and art back to their common source.
This invocation is beginning to look less silly than it did for much of
the time from the publication of the System until recently. The grow¬
ing conviction in certain areas of both analytical and European phi¬
losophy that representational, or correspondence theories, which
underlie scientistic views of truth, are failing to give an adequate ac¬
count of our relationship to internal and external nature is leading in
many places to the suspicion that both scientific and aesthetic reve¬
lations of truth are only ever different aspects of the same language-
embodied process. The main philosophical failing of the System, which
led Schelling to a revised position in the years following 1800, lies in
its account of the identity of mind and nature, which is couched, as we
saw, in terms of an absolute I. In the next phase of his work, Schelling
attempted to find a way of avoiding the problems to which this ap¬
proach to the question of identity gives rise.
you recognise its [the earth’s] true essence only in the link by which it eter¬
nally posits its unity as the multiplicity of its things and again posits this mul-
i6 Translator’s Introduction
tiplicity as its unity. You also do not imagine that, apart from this infinity of
things which are in it, there is another earth which is the unity of these
things, rather the same which is the multiplicity is also unity, and what the unity
is, is also the multiplicity, and this necessary and indissoluble One of unity
and multiplicity in it is what you call its existence. . . . Existence is the link of
a being (Wesen) as One, with itself as a multiplicity (I/7 p. 56).
Identity is the link of the two aspects of being, which, on the one
hand, is the universe, and, on the other, is the multiplicity which the
knowable universe also is.
Schelling’s conception of identity leads him to a prophetic anti-
Cartesian stance, which is later worked out in detail in the Lectures.
The Cartesian primacy of self-consciousness is clearly undermined by
the I’s dependence for its existence upon the prior ground of absolute
identity. Schelling insists that “The I think, I am, is, since Descartes,
the basic mistake of all knowledge; thinking is not my thinking, and
being is not my being, for everything is only of God or the totality”
(I/7 p. 148). Instead of the I, as the absolutely prior fact, “positing”
the not-I as its means of self-realisation, in the identity theory I am, as
Schelling puts it, “affirmed” as a predicate of being. In trying to make
my conscious I absolute, I realise that it can only be in relation to the
not-I, the rest of the world. This means, as we have already seen, that
the conscious I inherently involves a relation to an other and cannot
be absolute. In the empirical world everything is, as in Spinoza, de¬
pendent upon other things for its determinacy. If one wishes to know
absolutely what something is, including the I, one is led into an infi¬
nite regress via the chain of relations of anything particular to every¬
thing else. In the reflexive view, the realm of appearances therefore
seems separated in Kantian fashion from the “in-itself”, the Absolute.
Schelling, who is fully aware of Kant’s objections to claims about the
in-itself, insists, though, that “All regression into infinity is cut off’
(1/6 p. 165) in his conception. This can be so only if the world of ap¬
pearance and the Absolute are the same. The question is how they are
the same. The fact of this identity cannot be known in the way we
know specific facts about ourselves and the world.
It is the inherent incompleteness of knowledge which shows the ne¬
cessity of the Absolute: we would not regard knowledge as incomplete
if what renders our knowledge relative did not already inherently play
a role in thinking. The point - and here Hegel and Schelling concur -
is not to assume that recognition of this incompleteness leads to scep¬
ticism. Schelling argues against scepticism on the basis of the
structural irreducibility of the Absolute to the subject-object struc¬
ture of propositional knowledge. He can do so because the Absolute
is the ground which necessarily emerges in the face of the relativity of
Identity and Difference
»7
and the Absolute itself are the same, so that “the sameness of the sub¬
jective and the objective is made the same as itself, knows itself, and is
the subject and object of itself’ (1/6 p. 173). This is, of course, what
Hegel thought he achieved in his mature work, beginning with the
Phenomenology of Mind. In this view it is the constitutive negativity of
particular knowledge and particular beings that leads to the final re¬
alisation of the nature of that negativity, in absolute knowledge. In
this view the Absolute is the result of the self-cancellation of the finite.
It can therefore be presented in the form of the successive over¬
coming of finite determinations in a system whose end comprehends
its beginning. The beginning thereby achieves a determinacy which it
did not have at the outset by being grasped in the concept. Schelling,
though, had begun with a positive Absolute, being, which made re¬
flexive knowledge of it impossible, because reflexive knowledge re¬
quires being as its prior real, rather than just as its cognitive ground.
In the later philosophy Schelling works out a position which uses this
understanding of being against Hegel in a prophetic manner. For now
we need to consider another problem that ensues from beginning
with the Absolute, in order to understand what moves Schelling
towards the position of the late philosophy that is represented in
the Lectures.
Though Schelling’s version of identity theory is enlightening as a
way of escaping the traps of representational thinking and of trying to
get beyond the mind-body dichotomy, nothing that we have consid¬
ered so far can explain why it is that there is a finite, knowable world
at all. Schelling began to become aware of the gravity of this problem
for a philosophy that begins with the Absolute as early as 1804, in a
text entitled Philosophy and Religion:
the origin of the world of the senses can be thought of only as a complete
breaking off from absoluteness, by a leap. . . . The Absolute is all that is real:
finite things, on the other hand, are not real; their ground cannot lie in a
communication of reality to them or their substrate, which would have ema¬
nated from the Absolute, it can only lie in a move away, in a fall (Abfatl) from
the Absolute (1/6 p. 38).
Jacobi’s problem appears again here: “nothing finite can arise immedi¬
ately out of the Absolute and be deduced from it. Whence already in this law
the ground of the being of finite beings is expressed as an absolute
breaking off from the infinite” (1/6 p. 41). How, then, does philoso¬
phy come to terms with this break, given the fact of the finite world?
The dialectical answer is that the finite and the infinite are necessary
correlates of each other. Schelling here already begins to see the prob¬
lems of a dialectical position in ways which will be vital for his critique
Identity and Difference !9
rable correlate of what moves beyond it. This move beyond the
ground leads to a constant struggle against it. At the same time, what
emerges could not be as itself without the ground. In order for free¬
dom to realise itself, it must have the possibility of non-realisation,
which Schelling now understands as the possibility of evil.
Schelling’s change of vision is evident in the way that the ground, as
the unity which links all finite things, now leads us, as finite beings, to
a vision of the “deep, indestructible melancholy of all life” (I/7 p. 399),
not to the serene insight into the necessary place of things in the to¬
tality of the first identity philosophy. “God”, as what makes the world
intelligible, relates to the ground in such a way that the “real”, what
becomes material nature, is in God but “is not God seen absolutely, i.e.
insofar as He exists; for it is only the ground of His existence, it is
nature in God; an essence which is inseparable from God but different
from Him” (I/7 p. 358). The implications of such an argument for
theology are evidently quite startling: if God is not to be nature, He
actually requires nature in order for Him to be what is above it, which
is what makes Him divine.
Even seen non-theologically, the argument has important conse¬
quences. Schelling now develops the identity theory in terms of the
story of conflicting forces whose struggles constitute the “ages of the
world”. He argues that the world whose origins he seeks to under¬
stand must entail the same conflicting forces which still act, though
not necessarily in the same form, in this world, of which the mind is an
aspect: “In us there are two principles, an unconscious, dark principle
and a conscious principle” (I/7 p. 433); “What we call understanding,
if it is real, living, active understanding, is really nothing but regulated
madness. Understanding can manifest itself, show itself, only in its op¬
posite, thus in what lacks understanding” (I/7 p. 470). As we saw in
the System of Transcendental Idealism, the problem Schelling repeatedly
faces is that the centre of his philosophy cannot be understood con¬
ceptually, in terms of its difference from other existents, because it is
the very condition of any kind of difference. If matter is always al¬
ready what Schelling terms “real-ideal”, because otherwise the emer¬
gence of life and consciousness is inexplicable, one cannot give an
account of that emergence merely in terms of mechanical explana¬
tion. We must therefore always be aware that what is articulated in
philosophy is grounded in what itself cannot be articulated. The
philosophical development of this basic thought will be what most ob¬
viously separates Schelling from Hegel.
Schelling claims that “Poured from the source of things and the
same as the source, the human soul has a co-knowledge/con-science
(Mitwissenschaft) of creation" (WA I p. 4). The basis of this claim is that
Identity and Difference 21
man learns that his peaceful dwelling place is built on the hearth of a prime¬
val fire, he notices that even in the primal being itself something had to be
posited as past before the present time became possible, that this past re¬
mains hidden in the ground and that the same principle carries and holds us
in its ineffectiveness which would consume and destroy us in its effectiveness
{WA I p. 13).
This connection to the past is evident in the way the Ages of the World
conceives of freedom. One does not choose one’s character, Schelling
argues, but this does not mean we think people incapable of free ac¬
tion and concomitant moral responsibility. There is “a region in which
there is no ground/reason (Grund) at all but rather absolute freedom.
The “unground” (Ungrund) of eternity lies this close in every person,
and each is horrified by it if it is brought to his consciousness” {WA I
P- 93)- Our sense of the lack of reason for our own existence enables
us to understand what God does when He freely takes on nature.
There can be no reason for God’s taking on of nature, because that
would make God’s freedom have a ground, thereby rendering Him
dependent and determined. The fact that there is no reason why each
person is that particular person does not mean that one cannot as¬
sume responsibility for oneself, despite the contingency of one’s own
existence. “Freedom” seen in this way includes, of course, the free¬
dom to do evil: “When the abysses of the human heart open them¬
selves in evil and those terrible thoughts come forth which ought to
remain eternally buried in night and darkness; only then do we know
what possibilities lie in man and how his nature is for itself or when
left to itself (1/8 p. 268)”. The problem Schelling tries to deal with in
this way is essentially the problem of Philosophy and Religion. Why does
God take on the ground, given that he has no need of anything? Less
theologically: why is being manifest at all?
Wolfram Hogrebe (Hogrebe 1989) has suggested that the Ages of the
World should be understood as a theory of predication which develops
aspects of Schelling’s theory of identity. In this work being, as initially
One, is not manifest and has no reason to be manifest: Hogrebe terms
it “pronominal being” (ibid., p. 83). The problem is that the same be¬
ing must also be “predicative being” (ibid.), which “flows out, spreads,
gives itself” (1/8 pp. 210-11), since there is now a manifest world. The
contradiction is only apparent, Schelling claims: “the properly under¬
stood law of contradiction really only says that the same cannot be as
the same something and also the opposite thereof, but this does not
prevent the same, which is A, being able, as an other, to be not A” (1/8
22 Translator's Introduction
It seems universal that every creature which cannot contain itself or draw it¬
self together in its own fullness, draws itself together outside itself, whence,
e.g., the elevated miracle of the formation of the word in the mouth belongs,
which is a true creation of the full inside when it can no longer remain in
itself (WA I pp. 56-7).
This forming process happens both at the level of the material cos¬
mos and at the level of consciousness. The whole universe, as the link,
the Band, of the expansive ideal and the contractive real,
is very expressively termed the “word”, (a) because in it and with it all capacity
for differentiation begins; (b) because in it being-self and not-being-self. . .
are organically linked . . . the being which is dumb for itself is first raised to
comprehensibility by the ideal (I/7 pp. 442-3).
Schelling and Hegel
23
But the subject can never grasp itself as what it Is, for precisely in attracting
itself (t'm sich-Anziehen) it becomes an other, this is the basic contradiction, we
can say the misfortune in all being - for either it leaves itself, then it is as
nothing, or it attracts itself, then it is an other and not identical with itself1
(I/10 p. 101).
would require a perspective from which both the object and its reflec¬
tion in consciousness can be seen and be known as the same. Con¬
sciousness, though, can see only a reflection, which involves an
illusion, in that what is reflected does not appear as itself but as an
inverted image of itself. We can even make a further move by correct¬
ing this inversion in thought, by acknowledging that it is only an im¬
itation, but that still means we remain in thought and thus have failed
to show how thought is grounded in being, which requires a transcen¬
dence of thought.
This difficult argument comes down to the fact that I cannot know
the absolute subject, because there is no predicate that I can attribute
to it which would be able to say what it is: any such predicate, as we
saw, would contradict the subject’s freedom to “enclose itself in a form
and not to do so”. All I can say is that there must be that which car¬
ries the process of the differentiated world, that “goes through ev¬
erything and remains in nothing”. Thought itself can also go through
everything and remain in nothing by encompassing an infinity of dif¬
ferentiation and change in the knowable world whilst remaining it¬
self. In this way the apparent identity of thinking’s encompassing of
the development of the object world with the activity of the absolute
subject is a repetition, but only in thought, of what is the prior real
ground of thought. In consequence, the ground cannot be encom¬
passed by thought: “in man there is no objective bringing forth but
rather just ideal imitation (ideales Nachbilden) ... in him there is only
knowledge” (ibid. p. 27). There is no place from which the identity of
the “imitation” with what it imitates can be known, because knowl¬
edge depends on consciousness. Consciousness itself depends upon
the division in the Absolute that gives rise to a manifest world by split¬
ting subject and object.
The identity of thinking and being, which Schelling does not deny,
thus depends upon what cannot be reflexively identified within
thought, because thought must come after the division which gives
rise to consciousness. Being therefore cannot appear as itself, because
to do so it would itself have to be in a structure of reflection: it would
have to be reflected in an other, thinking. The problem with the no¬
tion of reflection is that it entails a logic which excludes precisely
what has to be established, the identity of thinking and being that al¬
lows being to know itself as an object of thinking. Being could know
itself as itself in thinking, via reflection in an other, only if it already
had a non-reflexive access to what it is. Without this access it would
have no way to identify itself as being with itself as thinking, because
it would not be able to say that its reflection is the same as itself. As
Fichte had realized, to see myself as myself in a mirror I must already
Schelling and Hegel
29
All we know are the results of what has been “been”, which does not
give us access to the final truth about what has brought this about. It
is this failure of reflection to ground itself that leads Schelling to the
notion of positive philosophy, which he conceives of as a theology that
does not fall prey to Spinozism. This brings us again to Jacobi’s prob¬
lem. The failure of reflection described in the Initia leads to a familiar
issue: the chain of conditioned conditions, even when viewed as the
activity of the “absolute subject”, does not account for the fact of the
world at all, unless one has a Spinozist conception of God, which is
what Schelling has opposed all along.
By the later 1820s Schelling had begun to radicalise his insights into
this problem into a verdict on the “common mistake of every philos¬
ophy that has existed up to now”, namely the “merely logical relation¬
ship of God to the world” in those philosophies (Schelling 1990
p. 57). In 1827-8 he applied this criticism to the conception of being
in Hegel’s Logic: “This being had to transform itself for no reason into
existence (Dasein) and the external world and then into the inner
world of the concept. The consequence was that the living substance,
as a result of the most abstract concepts, was left only in thought”
(ibid. p. 58). The crucial factor in the “merely logical relationship” is
that the priority of thought and being is reversed in the manner we
saw in the Initia. This reversal is what makes something into a nega¬
tive philosophy. Negative philosophy is exemplified in a system like
Hegel’s Logic. Such a system can be self-contained because it is con¬
stituted via the principle of reflection, in which each moment of
thought, as in the identity philosophy, is constituted negatively, by not
being the other elements. Schelling wants philosophy to come to
terms with the very existence of such a system, which cannot be done
from within the system and requires a positive philosophy. Schelling is
prepared, as we saw, to acknowledge the inner necessity of a system of
philosophy, such as the explanation of the dynamic stages of the de¬
velopment of nature in the Naturphilosophie, but he now demands an
answer to the question of why there is such a necessity at all. There is
no logical explanation of this within the system itself; it is a “fact”.
This fact has, then, to be considered as unconditioned, as “absolute”.
Schelling, reminding us of the importance of Fichte for his opposition
to Spinozism, calls the fact a free “deed”, in order to remove any sense
of its being like a determinate thing. In this way what leads to the
disclosed, living world cannot be explained in the same terms as what
it gives rise to. God is therefore the subject of positive philosophy,
whilst the world of determinate knowledge is articulated in negative
philosophy.
Schelling and Hegel 3i
For either the concept would have to go first, and being would have to be the
consequence of the concept, which would mean it was no longer absolute be¬
ing; or the concept is the consequence of being, then we must begin with be¬
ing without the concept (II/3 p. 164).
s I rely in this matter on the classic account of the failure of Hegel’s “logic of re¬
flection", Henrich 1971, which deals with this complex issue more fully than is
possible here; on its relation to Schelling, see Frank 1975 and Bowie 1990a, 1993.
34 Translator's Introduction
our self-consciousness is not at all the consciousness of that nature which has
passed through everything, it is precisely just our consciousness ... for the
consciousness of man is not = the consciousness of nature. . . . Far from man
and his activity making the world comprehensible, man himself is that which
is most incomprehensible (II/3 pp. 5-7).
REFERENCES
All translations are my own. The following abbreviations are used in the ci¬
tations in the Introduction and the translator’s notes: (I/10 p. 121) refers to
part, volume, and page in Schelling’s works (Schelling 1856—64). WA refers to
36 Translator's Introduction
his Die Weltalter (Ages of the World) (Schelling 1946). India refers to his India
Philosophiae Universae (Schelling 1969).
Beiser, Frederick C. The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte.
Cambridge, Mass., 1987.
Bowie, Andrew. “The Actuality of Schelling’s Hegel-Critique.” Bulletin of the
Hegel Society of Great Britain, double issue (21-2) 1990a.
Aesthetics and Subjectivity: From Kant to Nietzsche. Manchester, 1990.
“Revealing the Truth of Art”: Review essay on Manfred Frank, Einfiihrung
in die friihromantische Asthetik. Radical Philosophy 58 (1991), 20—4.
Schelling and Modern European Philosophy. London, 1993.
Fichte, J. G. Werke, Berlin, 1971.
Frank, Manfred. Der unendliche Mangel an Sein. Frankfurt, 1975.
Was 1st Neo-Strukturalismus? Frankfurt, 1984.
Erne Einfiihrung in Schellings Philosophic. Frankfurt, 1985.
Einfiihrung in die friihromantische Asthetik. Frankfurt, 1989.
Hartmann, Klaus, ed. Die ontologische Option. Berlin, 1976.
Hegel, G. W. F. Enzyklopadie der philosophischen Wissenschaften, ed. Friedhelm
Nicolin and Otto Poggeler. Hamburg, 1959.
Wissenschaft der Logik (pts. I—II). Vols. 5-6 in Werke, ed. E. Moldenhauer
and K. M. Michel. Frankfurt, 1969.
Phanomenologie des Geistes. Frankfurt, 1970.
Henrich, Dieter. Fichtes urspriingliche Einsicht. Frankfurt, 1967.
Hegel im Kontext. Frankfurt, 1971.
Selbstverhaltnisse. Stuttgart, 1982.
Hogrebe, Wolfram. Pradikation und Genesis. Metaphysik als Fundamentalheunstik
im Ausgang von Schellings “Die Weltalter”. Frankfurt, 1989.
Marquard, Odo. Transzendentaler Idealismus. Romantische Naturphilosophie. Psy¬
choanalyse. Cologne, 1987.
Novalis. Dasphilosophisch-theoretische Werk, ed. Hans-Joachim Mahl. Vol. 2. Mu¬
nich, 1978.
Sandkaulen-Bock, Birgit. Ausgang vom Unbedingten. Fiber den Anfang in der Phi¬
losophic Schellings. Gottingen, 1990.
Schelling, F. W. J. Sammtliche Werke, ed. K. F. A. Schelling. 2 parts, 14 vols.
Stuttgart, 1856—61.
Die Weltalter, ed. Manfred Schroter. Munich, 1946.
India Philosophiae Universae (1820-1), ed. Horst Fuhrmans. Bonn, 1969.
Grundlegung der positiven Philosophic (1832-3), ed. Horst Fuhrmans. Turin,
>972.
Philosophic der Offenbarung (1841-2). ed. Manfred Frank. Frankfurt,
> 977-
Spinoza, Benedict de. The Ethics, trans. R. H. M. Elwes. New York, 1955.
Theunissen, Michael. “Die Aufhebung des Idealismus in der Spatphilosophie
Schellings”. Philosophisches Jahrbuch 83 (1976).
References
37
Tilliette, Xavier. Schelling. Une philosophic, en devenir. 2 vols. Paris, 1970.
White, Alan. Absolute Knowledge: Hegel and the Problem of Metaphysics. Colum¬
bus, Ohio, 1983a.
Schelling: Introduction to the System of Freedom. New Haven, 1983b.
ON THE HISTORY OF
MODERN
PHILOSOPHY
Munich Lectures (ca. 1833-1834)
F. W. J. von Schelling
■
There are various reasons why, at least as an addition to an introduc¬
tion to philosophy itself, a look back to earlier systems can also be ad¬
visable. Science (Wissenschaft) is also a product of time and constantly
develops. Everyone who thinks he is in a position to advance science
a big or a small step forward will tend of his own accord to show his
relationship to what precedes him, in order thereby to make clear
from which point of development or standstill he is taking up science
and towards which subsequent goal he intends to advance it. He will
stimulate greater interest in his own researches if he shows how, from
stage to stage until now, the highest goal has not been achieved. The
beginner in philosophy in this way already gets to know, albeit only
historically, the issues in question and which of these have primarily
concerned the minds of the last centuries. Finally, if it is also neces¬
sary, in order to learn to value and judge the truth, to know error,
then such a presentation is the best and most gentle way to show the
beginner the error which is to be overcome. But the weight of all these
reasons increases if it is not just a question of a new method or of
changed views in particular matters, but of a change in the concept of
philosophy itself. In this case it will then be desirable if this concept,
independently of the truth which it initially has or has in itself, ap¬
pears at the same time as the natural historical result of earlier un¬
successful endeavours, no longer in its simple generality, but rather as
a necessary result of precisely this time.
4
Descartes
42
Descartes
43
(Seyn) in myself; for the same reason that I must doubt things, I would
have also to doubt myself. However, the doubt of Descartes in the re¬
ality of things really does not have the speculative significance which
we just gave it; the basis of his doubt is only empirical, as he says him¬
self, because he has often discovered that the senses deceived him, be¬
cause many a time he has convinced himself in a dream that this or
that was outside of him which afterwards turned out to be the oppo¬
site; indeed he adds that he has known people who felt pain in limbs
which they had had removed long ago - in this argument one recog¬
nises the former military man. Incidentally, it seemed reasonable to
reflect that such persons only felt pain in limbs which they once had,
and there is no example of anyone who felt pains in limbs which they
never had. Through this last experience, however, he thought himself
even particularly justified also to doubt the existence of his own body.
From here he then proceeds to cognitions which are not drawn
from the senses, which are therefore endowed with the character of
necessity and generality, namely mathematical truths, for whose du-
bitability he cites the strangest reason, which is not, as was that of the
ancient sceptics, taken from the inside of these objects and their pre¬
mises themselves, but from something external. Namely, so he ex¬
plains, although I am as convinced as I am convinced of my own life,
and cannot help for a moment knowing, that the three angles of a
triangle = two right angles, my soul has the opinion — I do not really
know whether taught to it or even implanted in it — that there is a
God, of whom I have heard that He can do everything and that I (the
doubter) am completely His creature, with all I am and know. Now He
could, he continues, also have made me be deceived even about those
things which otherwise appeared to me as the most clear. As if one
did not have far more cause to doubt such a doubt. Before one threw
up this last doubt, one would have to cite some interest or other which
the creator could have in deceiving me with necessary truths. The
true relationship in which philosophy finds itself at the beginning to
everything, and thus also to mathematical truths, is not to doubt
them (for how would philosophy anyway already come to make them
the object of its thinking?), but simply to leave them open until, in the
course of its investigation beginning absolutely from the beginning,
philosophy is led of its own accord to the premises upon which its
truth depends.
Having doubted in this not really very deep manner everything
which has come before his consciousness, Descartes asks whether he is
left with nothing at all which he could still doubt as well, for the rea¬
sons given earlier or for other reasons. Although he seemed now to
have doubted everything, he still had something left, namely himself
Descartes 45
1 A special peculiarity lies for us in the fact that this beginning of completely free
philosophy was, to all appearances, made in Bavaria, that, therefore, the founda¬
tion of modern philosophy was laid here. Descartes had, as he says himself in his
essay De Melhodo, which I take this opportunity to recommend to everyone as a
splendid exercise, come to Germany in order to see the beginning of the Thirty
Years’ War; he had been present under Maximilian I at the battle on the white
mountain and the capture of Prague, where, though, he primarily only made in¬
quiries about Tycho Brahe and his unpublished work. In 1619, when he returned
to the camp from Frankfurt, from the coronation of Ferdinand II, he had his win¬
ter quarters in a place on the Bavarian border, where he, as he says, found no one
with whom he would have liked to converse, and there he conceived (aged twenty-
three) the first ideas of his philosophy, which he, however, published much later.
In the same way as Descartes began to philosophise in Bavaria, he later found in
Princess Elisabeth, daughter of the unfortunate Elector of the Palatinate, Karl
Friedrich, the so-called Winter King, a great and devoted admirer, just as it was later
again a prince from the house of the Palatinate who became Spinoza’s protector.
46 On the History of Modern Philosophy
think all the more truly the less the subject interferes with it. There¬
fore, because that which is thinking and that which reflects on this
thinking and posits it as one with itself are two different things, or
because there is an objective thinking which is independent of me, it
follows that that which reflects might deceive itself about that sup¬
posed unity, or, by attributing the original thinking to itself, it might
be precisely this attribution about which it is deceived, and the “I
think” could have no more significance than expressions I also use,
such as “I digest”, ‘‘I make juices”, “I walk” or “I ride”; for it is not
really the thinking being that walks or rides. It thinks in me, thinking
goes on in me, is the pure fact, in the same way as I can say with equal
justification: “I dreamed”, and “It dreamed in me”. The certainty
which Descartes attributes to the Cogito ergo sum cannot be sustained
even by thinking; if there is a certainty, then it is blind and devoid of
thought. To this certainty Descartes then attaches everything else. His
principle is: Everything which is just as clearly and distinctly recog¬
nised as the “I am” must also be true. But, expressed more exactly,
this can only mean the same as: Everything that is connected to that
blind empirical certainty which I have of my own being, or which is
implicite posited with the “I am” or can be proven to belong to the
completeness of this idea (Vorstellung), I must assume as just as true as
the “I am” itself (it goes no further); it does not follow, namely, that it
is also like that objectively and independently of me. The truth of the
“I am” can be sustained just as well if I am only compelled to imagine
all those other things, e.g., my body and the things that apparently
influence it. Once I want to attach everything to the “I am”, I must
give up ever getting any further than to this necessity of the idea of
everything else; it can also, if I am the focus of all knowledge to my¬
self, be completely indifferent to me whether that which I am com¬
pelled to imagine is there independently of imagining it or not, since
it, to use Descartes’s own example, is completely indifferent to the
dreamer as long as he is dreaming.
Descartes, who was not even concerned to comprehend things but
only to know that they are (the least that one can know of things), be¬
came the cause, by his procedure, of the question whether anything
really corresponded to our ideas of external things being regarded for
a considerable time as the main question in philosophy. It would have
been easy for Descartes to proceed already to complete idealism, i.e.
to the system which maintains that things are not objectively outside
us, but only exist in our, albeit necessary, ideas. But he did not want
this; in order to avoid this necessary consequence, he took refuge in
another conception. Because ideas have no guarantee in themselves,
he needed a guarantor for the truth of his ideas of external things -
Descartes
49
ics, it was always in first place until Kant. It is important to note that
this argument was not recognised at all by the scholastics. For, al¬
though Anselm of Canterbury had already advanced a similar argu¬
ment, Thomas Aquinas most emphatically contradicted him. The so-
called ontological proof became primarily an object of the Kantian
critique, but neither Kant nor any of his successors hit upon the cor¬
rect point. The main objection to the Cartesian proof which was pri¬
marily raised by Kant depends upon the already-mentioned incorrect
idea that the argument is supposed to be as follows: I find in me the
idea of the perfect being, but existence is itself a perfection, therefore
existence is also of its own accord included in the idea of the perfect
being. Here, then, the minor proposition of the conclusion is denied.
It is said that existence is not a perfection. A triangle, e.g., does not
become any more perfect by existing, or, if this were the case, then I
should also have to be allowed to conclude that the perfect triangle
must exist. What does not exist, it is said, is neither perfect nor im¬
perfect. Existence only expresses the fact that the thing, i.e. that its
perfections, are. Therefore existence is not one of these perfections,
but it is that without which neither the thing nor its perfections are.
But I have already remarked that Descartes does not infer in this man¬
ner. Rather, his argument goes as follows: it would contradict the na¬
ture of the perfect being to exist just contingently (as, e.g., my own
existence is simply contingent, precarious and for this reason doubt¬
ful in itself), therefore the most perfect being can only exist necessar¬
ily. There would, I suggest, be no objection to this argument,
particularly if one agrees that the concept of necessary existing
should be understood to mean merely the opposite of contingent ex¬
isting. But the conclusion of Descartes is different. Let us repeat again
the whole syllogism. The perfect being cannot exist only contingently,
thus can only exist necessarily (major proposition); God is the perfect
being (minor proposition), therefore (he ought to conclude) He can
only exist necessarily, for this alone is inherent in the premises; in¬
stead of this, though, he concludes: therefore He necessarily exists,
and, it is true, thereby apparently brings out the fact that God exists,
and seems to have proven the existence of God. But it is something
completely different whether I say: God can only exist necessarily, or
whether I say: He necessarily exists. From the First (He can only exist
necessarily) only follows: therefore He exists necessarily (N.B., if He
exists, but it does not at all follow that He exists). In this, therefore, lies
the mistake of the Cartesian conclusion. We can also express this mis¬
take like this. In the major proposition (the perfect being can only ex¬
ist necessarily), it is only a question of the manner of existence (it is only
Descartes
51
stated that the perfect being could not exist in a contingent manner)-,
in the conclusion (in the conclusio), however, it is no longer a question
of the manner of existence (in this case the conclusion would be cor¬
rect) but of existence at all, therefore there is plus in conclusione quam
fuerat in praemissis [more in the conclusion than there was in the pre¬
misses], i.e. a logical law has been broken, or the conclusion has an
incorrect form. That this is the real mistake I can also prove by the fact
that Descartes himself directly infers in several places, or, for the time
being at least, infers only in the manner I have shown. In an essay with
the title “Rationes Dei existiam etc. probantes ordine geometrico dis-
positae”, the conclusion is as follows: Therefore it is true to say of God
that in Him existence is a necessary existence or (he adds) that He ex¬
ists. The latter, though, is something completely different from the
former and cannot be regarded as equivalent to it, as is suggested by
the “or”. (Descartes himself is well aware that in his concept of the
perfect being only the manner of existence is determined.) Thus he
says in the same account: in the concept of a limited, finite thing,
merely possible or contingent existence is contained; in the concept of
the perfect thing, therefore, is contained the concept of necessary and
perfect existence. At another point, in his fifth Meditation, he carries
out the conclusion as follows: I find in me the idea of God no differ¬
ently or in the same way as I find the idea of any geometrical figure
or of a number, nec, he immediately continues, nec minus dare et dis-
tincte intelligo, ad ejus naturam pertinere, ut semper existat [nor do I un¬
derstand any less clearly and distinctly that it belongs to His nature
that He always exists], (Take good note of this semper; here he does
not, then, say, ad ejus naturam pertinere, ut existat, but only ut semper ex¬
istat.) From that it merely follows that God, if He exists, only always
exists, but it does not follow that He exists. The true meaning of the
conclusion is always only: either God does not exist at all, or, if He ex¬
ists, then He always exists necessarily, i.e., not contingently. But it is
clear that His existence is not proven thereby.
With this critique of the Cartesian argument we admit, though,
that, if not the existence, then the necessary existence of God is
proven — and this concept is now really the one which has had the most
decisive effect for the whole subsequent period of philosophy.
What is it, then, about this necessary existence of God?
Even as we only recognise the following as the correct conclusion:
Therefore God exists necessarily, if He exists, we already state that the
concept of God and the concept of the necessarily existing being are
not simply identical concepts, namely in such a way that the one could
be exactly contained in the other, that God would not be any more
52 On the History of Modern Philosophy
than the being which just exists necessarily. If He were only this, then
the proposition that He exists would be self-evident. Above all, then,
the question is
it of all freedom. It is the concept against which thinking loses all its
freedom.
But now the question arises as to how God might be called the being
which is or exists necessarily (das nothwendig seyende oder existirende
Wesen). Descartes contents himself with the popular argument that
because non-necessary, i.e. contingent existence (as he defines the
concept), is an imperfection, God is the most perfect being {Wesen).
What he thinks when he thinks of the perfect being he does not say;
but one can see that he is thinking of that which is the essence {Wesen)
of all being {Seyn), which does not have a being outside itself, to which
its own being also relates as one being {Seyn), or, more simply, which
is not a being {Seyendes) which has another being or other beings
{Seyende) outside itself, but is being per se {das schlechthin Seyende),
which, therefore, can in its highest conception only be precisely
what we called being itself {das Seyende selbst), ipsum ens. If God is only
to be determined as being itself and that which is being itself as
that which cannot not be, as that for which it is impossible not to be,
then God is definitely and without all doubt that which exists neces¬
sarily {das nothwendig Existirende): this is now the highest sense in which
the real ontological argument is to be taken; the so-called proof of
Anselm comes down to this. But it is also now immediately clear
whence the mistrust against this so-called proof originates, and why
especially scholasticism rather preferred to refute it and refuse it than
to adopt it.
Here we come to the question of whether the concept of the nec¬
essarily existing being {Wesen) is identical with the concept of God.
We have just shown the necessarily existing to be at the same time
the blindly existing. Now there is, however, nothing more opposed to
the nature of God as it is thought of in common belief—and only
from this did Descartes, and thus up to now we also, adopt this con¬
cept - nothing is more opposed to the nature of God than blind being
{Seyn). For the first thing about the concept of that which exists
blindly {des blindlings Seyenden) is, of course, that it is devoid of free¬
dom in relation to its being {Seyn), it can neither negate {aufheben), nor
change, nor modify it. That which has no freedom in relation to its
own being has no freedom at all - is absolutely unfree. If, then, God
were the necessarily existing being {Wesen), He could only be defined
at the same time as that which was rigid, immovable, absolutely un¬
free, incapable of any free action, progression or going out of Him¬
self. Either we should have to stop at this blind being - we could not
take a step beyond what exists blindly at all - or if we wanted to
progress out of it, say to reach the world, this could only happen to
the extent to which we were able, say, to demonstrate an emanative
power in His blind being, by virtue of which other being {anderes
Descartes
55
Seyn), e.g., that of things, poured out of this blind being - I say poured
out, not emerged, for to that one could still attach the thought of a
creation — but creation is precisely thoroughly incompatible with a
blind being, which could at best be thought as an emanative cause,
and even this would present not inconsiderable difficulty. Here, then,
we come up against, to use a Kantian expression, an antinomy be¬
tween what follows from reason of necessity, and what we really want
if we want God. For so far God is obviously just an object of our wish¬
ing - we are not compelled by anything to use the expression God; be¬
ginning with the absolute concept of reason, with the concept of what
Is, we are only led to the concept of the necessarily existing being (We-
sen), but not to the concept of God. But even if we begin with the con¬
cept God, we have to say: God is the essence (Wesen) of all being (Seyn),
He is what Is in the absolute sense, to ON, however he was defined;
but if He is this, He is also that which exists necessarily and blindly.
But if He is that which exists blindly, then he is for just this reason not
God — not God in that sense which the common consciousness associ¬
ated with this word and concept. What can help here, or how can we
escape from the straits in which we find ourselves? It would be no
help at all if one just wished to deny that God is the necessarily ex¬
isting being. For the real original concept (Urbegriff), which we abso¬
lutely may not renounce if our thinking is not everywhere to lack a
firm point of departure, would thereby be removed.
God as such is, of course, not just the necessarily or blindly existing
being (Wesen), He admittedly is it, but as God He is at the same time
that which can negate (aufheben) this His own being which is depen¬
dent upon Him, can transform His necessary being into contingent
being, namely into a being posited by itself, so that it in fact always
fundamentally (im Grunde) (in the foundation) (der Grundlage nach)
persists, but effectively or in fact is converted into an other, or as fol¬
lows: necessary being does always lie at the foundation of that self-
posited being, but without the effective, the real being of God just
being this necessary being.
Life (Lebendigkeit) consists precisely in the freedom to negate its own
being as immediate, posited independently of itself, and to be able to
transform it into a being posited by itself. What is dead in nature, e.g.,
has no freedom to change its being; it is as it is - at no moment of its
existence is its being self-determined. The very concept of the neces¬
sary being (Seyenden) would, therefore, not lead to the living but to the
dead God. Generally, though, in the concept of God it is thought that
He can do what He wants, and since He has no other object of His
activity than His existence, then — I cannot say: it is, but in the con¬
cept of God it must be thought that He is free in relation to His ex¬
istence, not bound to it, that He can make it itself into a means, can
56 On the History of Modern Philosophy
sion might in its own way also be a spiritual principle, it would not nec¬
essarily need to be something extended itself, as, e.g., the principle of
warmth is not itself warm because it is the principle of warmth, al¬
though it makes the body warm, communicates warmth to it. Des¬
cartes knows nothing of a principle of extension, but only of the
extended thing, which for this reason is absolutely unspiritual. On the
other hand he speaks of himself as of a thing which thinks: “Je suis
une chose, qui pense” (Med. Ill p. 263). The thing which thinks and
the thing which is extended are, therefore, two things to him, which
mutually exclude each other and have nothing in common; the ex¬
tended thing is completely devoid of spirit, spirit-less; the spiritual, in
turn, is absolutely immaterial; what is extended is simple being to¬
gether and being apart, pure disintegration, which, to the extent to
which it appears nonetheless as held together, as in physical things, is
not held together by an internal and thus spiritual principle, but only
through external pressure and thrust. The extended thing consists of
parts which are absolutely external to each other, these parts them¬
selves lack an inner moving principle, thus also any inner source of
movement. All movement is based on thrust, i.e. it is purely mechan¬
ical. Just as there is no spirit in matter, so, according to Descartes,
there is, in turn, nothing in spirit which is related to matter; the being
which is in matter (das in der Materie Seyende) is not a being which is
only in a different manner, but something toto genere different, both are
beyond all contact, two completely disparate substances, between
which, for this reason, nothing in common is possible.
Two things which have absolutely nothing in common also cannot
have effects on each other. For Descartes’s philosophy it was, then, a
very difficult task to explain that undeniable interaction which obvi¬
ously takes place between the thinking and the extended being (We-
sen). If both have nothing to do with each other at all, how can body
and spirit do so much together and suffer so much together? As when
a physical pain is felt by the mind, or an impression just made on the
body transmits itself to the mind and creates in the thinking thing
which we call our soul an idea, or when, on the other hand, an exer¬
tion of the mind, a pain of our soul tires out the body or makes it ill,
or the thought of our mind, as, e.g., in speaking, forces merely phys¬
ical organs to serve it, or a will, a decision of our mind produces a
corresponding movement in the extended thing which we call our
body. Until the time of Descartes, the accepted older scholastic system
concerned with this was the system of so-called natural or immediate
iniluence (systema influxus physici), which was based, even if not in a
clearly conscious way then in an unconscious way, on the presuppo¬
sition of a certain homogeneity of the final substance, of the substance
Descartes
59
which lay at the foundation of both matter and mind and was there¬
fore common to both. Admittedly it was a crude idea, if one did not
wish to explain this just by a gradual becoming finer of the materials,
as in certain hypotheses of the physiologists, who, it is true, consid¬
ered a direct influence of the mind on what was called the crudely
physical to he impossible, but who thought that if one only interpo¬
lated finer materials between the mind and the crudely physical (they
used to talk of nerve juice, or, as they put it nowadays, in a supposedly
more refined way, nerve ether), then such an immediate transition
would eventually be possible.
Descartes removed at a stroke the difficulties which emerged for his
dualism through the obvious interaction between the thinking and
the extended thing by (1) denying animals a soul, declaring them to
be just highly artificial machines which only carry out all their ac¬
tions — even their actions which obviously resemble actions based on
reason - in the same way as a good clock tells the time. He also needed
to deny animals a soul because where there is thought there is a sub¬
stance which is completely different from matter, and therefore inde¬
structible and immortal.' (2) As far as man is concerned, he considers
him in terms of his body as also only a highly artificially arranged ma¬
chine, which, like a wound-up clock, carries out all natural actions
completely independently of the soul and only according to its own
mechanism; but as far as those movements which cannot be explained
as automatic, which correspond to certain movements or acts of will
of the mind, he is forced to assume that in every such case, if, e.g., a
desire or a wish arises in the mind, which the body should carry out,
God Himself should step in and produce the corresponding move¬
ment in the body - as if it should be more comprehensible how the
highest spirit (for it is not that God is identical with it (denn Gott ihm
nicht etwa Identitat [the sense is not clear])) should affect the purely
physical than how the human spirit should. And, in the same way, ev¬
ery time material things produce an impression on our body, the cre¬
ator steps in and produces the corresponding idea in the soul; the
soul would be inaccessible to all external or material impressions for
itself, only God acts as a go-between, so that my soul has an idea of
physical things. This is also, therefore, not an essential, but only an
1 This cause (immortality), for which Descartes had to deny animals a soul, is ex¬
plained by More in his letter to Descartes (Oeuvres, vol. 10, p. 190): “Having sup¬
posed that the body was incapable of thinking, you have concluded that
everywhere where there is thought there ought to be a substance really distinct
from the body and consequently immortal; whence it follows that, if animals
thought, they would have souls which would be immortal substances.” [Translator’s
note: The More quotation is given in French in Schelling’s text.]
6o On the History of Modern Philosophy
tainty). Admittedly Bacon did not get any further than the founda¬
tion, and did not get into the science itself. But the same is true of
Descartes; for he also really concludes with what, if one only were to
have begun with it, would have made really progressive science pos¬
sible, with the highest, with God. Both are at one in their opposition
to scholasticism, in the common striving for a real (reell) philosophy.
T hey only decisively part company in relation to the highest concept,
which Descartes wishes, by an a priori argument, to make independent
of all experience, thus also from his own starting point (the immediate
fact I think)-, he is thereby the originator of a priori, rational-a priori
philosophy, whilst Bacon still unquestionably wants the highest as
something empirical.
Spinoza, Leibniz, and Wolff
If one recalls the Cartesian system in its true constitution, then one
longs for a better, more beautiful, more reassuring form (Gestalt),
which is then at once to be found in Spinozism.*
SPINOZA
translator’s note: Headings for the philosophers’ names have been added, for clarity,
in this and other chapters.
64
Spinoza, Leibniz, and Wolff
65
ill. Individual real things are not at all the subject of being itself (des
Seyns selbst), although they are in being (seyend sind)\ they are in being
{sind seyend) only by participation in being (S<?yn), not by the fact that
they could not not be at all, for they rather cannot be, because their
being (Seyn) is attached to being in a particular way (das so Seyn). We
must, of course, ascend to that of which not just being in a particular
way, but of which being at all (das Seyn iiberhaupt) can be predicated,
cujus actus est existere [whose act is to exist], and only this is the general
or absolute subject of being (Seyn), which we also call being itself (das
Seyende selbst). One can attempt to hold onto it purely and abstractly,
where it is still the Prius of being; here it would then be being (das
Seyende) just in thought, which only has a being (Seyn) in thinking (in
this sense, unity of thinking and being — namely taken negatively, in
the sense that being is not outside thought, thus not transitive being,
but just immanent being); but, as was already said, it cannot be held
onto in this narrowness, it is not just in the logical sense, it is also in the
transitive sense that which cannot not be, and however early I may
arrive, before I have had time to think, so to speak - before all think¬
ing, it is to me, or I find it already, as being (das Seyende), because it, as
the subject of all being (alles Seyns), is precisely that which is according
to its nature, and is never to be thought as not being.
This, then, is the origin of the Spinozist concept, which, as the his¬
tory of philosophy shows, has been until the present time the point
around which everything moves, or rather the imprisonment of
thought, from which thought has sought to emancipate itself by the
succeeding systems without yet being able to do so. It is the concept by
virtue of which there is in God explicite - expressly - neither will nor
understanding, according to which He really is only that which
blindly exists - we can also say: that which exists in a subjectless way,
namely because He has gone over wholly and completely into being
(Seyn). In possibility there is still a freedom from being, thus also
against being. But in this case possibility is swallowed by being. Because
that First is that which can only be (and not also that which is able not
to be), it is for that reason that which only is (das nur Seyende), i.e.
being (das Seyende) which is by the exclusion of all non-being - by the
exclusion of all potentiality - of all freedom (for freedom is non-
being). Accordingly it is being (das Seyende) without potentiality, and,
in that sense, powerless being, because it absolutely does not have the
power of another being (Seyn) in itself. Spinoza calls God causa sui, but
in the more narrow sense that He Is through the sheer necessity of
His essence (Wesen), without being able to be held onto as being able
to be (as causa)-, the cause has completely merged into the effect, and
behaves only as substance, against which His thought can do nothing.
66 On the History of Modern Philosophy
sion and thought and thus divided the universe, so to speak, into two
worlds, into the world of thought and the world of extension, Spino¬
za’s inheritance from Descartes is quite clear here. For him (Spinoza)
God is admittedly no longer simply the occasional mediator between
one and the other, who remains external to both, but their lasting and
constant unity. For Descartes thinking is outside God, for Spinoza
God is Himself infinite thinking and is Himself infinite extension. But
even this unity should not be taken, as one might be tempted to take
it these days, in such a way that thinking affected extension, and in
such a way that the different extended things were different just be¬
cause thinking was expressed more in the one and less in the other.
Not in this way. For, besides their both following/rom the same sub¬
stance, they have nothing in common, they are as alien to each other
as they are to his predecessor [Descartes]. Only when their correspon¬
dence has been or is mediated in every single case by a particular actus
for Descartes is the correspondence for Spinoza there once and for all
via the identity of the substance. Spinoza’s true idea is, therefore, an
absolute unity of substance combined with absolute opposition (mu¬
tual exclusion) of the attributes. What is extended is as devoid of spirit
for him as for Descartes, and Spinoza’s view of nature, his physics, is
for this reason no less mechanical and lifeless than that of his prede¬
cessor. The unity between both attributes is only a formal and exter¬
nal one, not one which is posited in themselves and substantial and
immanent in that sense. The duality which he posits in unity does not
found a real pulse, a true life, for the opposed sides remain dead and
indifferent to each other. This is only the necessary consequence of
the fact that has already been remarked upon, that Spinoza arrives a
priori at the duality of attributes, not by beginning with the substance.
For him they are admittedly consequences, and, indeed, necessary
consequences, of the existence of the absolute substance, but he does
not grasp them as these consequences. He does say that they are, but
he does not explain them. He does not prove that necessity. He just
takes them up a posteriori from experience, because he is forced after
all to acknowledge that the world does not just consist of spirit or
thought, but in part also of matter or extended being (Wesen), and just
as little does it consist just of matter, but in part also of spirit or
thought. Indeed, had he been aware of the necessity which drove him
to that system, then this necessity would not have led him to duality at
all, and the fact that apart from what is extended he also posits what
thinks is really just a correction of his system by experience. For what
is extended is obviously the First, that alone which is truly primary, of
the two. Thinking only relates to what is extended and could not be at
all without it; the human mind, e.g., is a modification of infinite
Spinoza, Leibniz, and Wolff 6g
thought, which it calls the “concept”, but this active or living concept
is only the immediate concept of the human body, i.e. of the modifi¬
cation of infinite extension which exists wholly independently of the
mind but corresponds with it. But how does infinite substance come
to posit not only what is extended but also the concept of the same,
why does it not stop with what is extended, which precedes the con¬
cept of what is extended in terms of time even if not in terms of na¬
ture? To this question there is only one answer, or it can only be
explained in one way, namely by assuming that the infinite substance,
in positing what is extended, or positing itself as what is extended,
does not completely exhaust itself; only in this case does it have to
posit itself once more in a higher stage - in a higher potential, as it
has later been called; this higher stage cannot again be what is ex¬
tended but must rather be the concept of what is extended, or must
relate to what is extended as its concept; for the higher is always that
which grasps what precedes it or is lower than it, as, e.g., the mind
grasps the body, its prerequisite, but not vice versa, or the later time
always grasps an earlier time which has not grasped itself. But this
view is completely alien to Spinoza, and, even though he calls the soul
the concept of the body, he has no other basis for the existence of the
soul, or for positing infinite thought as well as what is extended, than
experience. The fact that he opposes thinking to what is extended can
only be attributed to the irresistible influence of reality, and is already
the seed of a higher system which is latent in his own, without him
grasping it himself. For this reason Spinoza is primarily stimulating
and to be recommended for study because everywhere in his system
the seeds of higher developments are sown. Spinoza, whose system, by
the way, is capable of higher development even as a system of mere
necessity and even within its limit (that God (1) does not posit things at
all and (2) already for this reason does not posit them outside Him¬
self), represents in the history of philosophy the whole hermeticism
(Verschlossenheit) of the Old Testament (he was himself Jewish). The
higher developments of a later time and their greater proportions are
still foreign to him, but they are prepared and hinted at in part; the
sealed bud can still unfold into the flower. One might say Spinoza’s
philosophy (even considered within its limit) is, like Hebrew, a script
without vowels, the vowels were only added and made explicit by a
later age.
The God of Spinoza is still lost in substantiality and thereby in im¬
mobility. For mobility ( = possibility) is only in the subject. The sub¬
stance of Spinoza is just object. Things follow from God, not through
a movement, a wanting in Himself, but in a quiet manner, as, in his
one simile, the nature of the right-angled triangle follows from the
7° On the History of Modern Philosophy
from the nature of God (aeterno modo), but such that one includes the
other. All things - both those which are now and those which used to
be or will be in the future - are posited in an eternal way by the na¬
ture of God, like the properties of a triangle.
How can eternal, and therefore simultaneous being-posited (Gesetzt-
seyn) fit together with that regress into infinity, i.e. how can that re¬
gress into infinity nevertheless be thought of at the same time as
absolutely present in the eyes of God? Spinoza answers this with a
mathematical simile. Think, he says, of two circles drawn from dif¬
ferent centres, one of which encloses the other, in this way the ine¬
qualities of the space between these two circles, or the changes which
a liquid or soft material would have to undergo in this space, will be
beyond number. And yet, he says, there is no external infinity in this
case. Just as here, with the simple idea of two circles with different
centres but which are not drawn concentrically, an infinite number of
inequalities or changes in a limited space is posited simultaneously
and actu, so an endless progression from one thing to another is pos¬
ited with the idea of God. One can, therefore, progress into infinity
with the being (Seyn) posited with God, without ever stepping out of
divine nature, but also without ever finding a true beginning of the
finite. Nothing finite is immediately explicable by God. (Spinoza re¬
garded the figure just described, of two circles placed within one an¬
other without being concentric, which are not, therefore, at any point
the same distance from each other, as a sort of symbol of his whole
philosophy, and it is, thus, engraved at the beginning of his Opus Post-
humum. The mathematician, he specifies, does not doubt for a mo¬
ment that the inequalities of the space between the two circles or the
number of changes which a pliable material moved in the space would
undergo are not determinable by any number, and are in this sense
infinite; he does not infer this from the size of the enclosed space. For
I can take again a randomly big or small part of this space and the
same infinity is always posited, which proves that this is an infinity
which is in the nature of the thing, and is posited with the thing, i.e.
with the idea. Thus an essential infinity is posited with the nature of
God, inside which I can progress into infinity, without ever stepping
outside divine nature).
But whence now do - not this or that thing, this or that affection,
but any affections at all of the divine substance come from? Spinoza
gives no answer to this, because he cannot give an answer. Determi¬
nation, limit, etc., can only be thought where there is reflection (Be-
sonnenheit), but the being (Seyn) of the substance is a being completely
devoid of reflection and limits, namely being which does even not
limit or reflect itself. Spinoza, then, posits determinations in the in-
72 On the History of Modern Philosophy
here about the possible meanings of it, but initially only in relation to
Spinoza. The commonest conception of Pantheism and, to the extent
to which one declares Spinozism to be Pantheism, also of Spinozism,
is the following: according to it, every single thing - every body, e.g. -
is only a modified God, therefore there are as many Gods as single
things; some more recent ideas declared in this blind attack against
Pantheism that it was the same as fetishism, which is contrary to every
received and well-known understanding of words. For it would occur
to nobody, e.g., who knows the differences of human ways of thinking
even just historically, to consider the fetishism of Negro peoples, who
choose an ostrich feather, a tooth, or a piece of wood as the object of
their prayers, to be the same as the Pantheism of an educated Indian.
Particularly in relation to Spinoza, everyone, even if he is inexperi¬
enced in philosophy (Wissenschaft), can be made to understand that, if
the being which is everything {das alles Seyende), as that which for just
that reason cannot be a particular or single being (Seyendes), is God -
that precisely for that reason God Himself could not be part of ev¬
erything which is particular or singular. But the concept can also be
grasped as follows: Although nothing singular can be called God, the
world, thought as unity or as universe, is the same as God, or, as is usu¬
ally said, not different from God. But by this universe is really only
understood the collectivity of finite things, so it is not true that
Spinoza does not distinguish them from God. For he teaches contin¬
ually from beginning to end that God is that which is grasped by itself,
which does not presuppose any other concept; the world, however, is
that which is only after God, and can only be grasped as a conse¬
quence of God (Substantia divina natura prior suis affectionibus [Divine
substance is by its nature prior to its affections]). This doctrine, which
maintains the absolute independence of God and the absolute depen¬
dence of things, posits a difference between the two, which is truly
differentia totius generis [a complete difference of kind], and, just as lit¬
tle as the single thing can be called God, can the world as well, as a
mere complex of single things, be called God according to Spinoza.
To crown it all, Spinoza also says: only Substantia infinita in se consid-
erata et sepositis suis affectionibus [infinite substance considered in itself
and separate from its affections] is God. It only remains to say that
according to Spinoza the world is indeed not God, but conversely God
is the world, or is world in general, i.e. with His being (Seyn) a totality
of determinations of His being is posited. But it does not follow from
this that everything - is God, as one expresses it by the word Panthe¬
ism, but instead that God is everything. But here every system will find
it immensely difficult to show how and in what sense God should not
be everything, i.e. how one could absolutely exclude God from any-
74 On the History of Modern Philosophy
LEIBNIZ
stands by material only what is composite, then for Spinoza what is ex¬
tended, or the substance seen in relation to this attribute, is just as
spiritual as the idea is even to Leibniz. Matter which is divisible or put
together from parts arises just as much from a false and incorrect re¬
flection for Spinoza as it does from a simply confused idea for Leib¬
niz. Leibniz also does not absolutely deny that matter is divisible (as
appearance). Leibniz also considers those units which he calls monads
as the last, though spiritual, elements of everything material. One
monad looked at for itself is absolutely incorporeal, pure power of
thought (Vorstellkraft) (for being power of thought is, according to
him, the essence of all being (Wesen alles Seyenden). Only what thinks
(vorstellt) Is); but several monads together form a whole which consists
of relatively subordinate and relatively dominant monads, above
which, finally, One dominating monad rises. Whoever saw this whole
as God sees it, i.e. only as a whole consisting of spiritual powers which
are connected and mutually presuppose each other, would perceive
no bodily extension. But the individual earthly being (Weltwesen),
man, e.g., does not stand in that perspectival centre, where things ap¬
pear to him in this way, but outside of it, and through this kind of
displacement of the monads in relation to each other a confused idea
arises, and the mere appearance, the mere phenomenon of this con¬
fused idea is bodily extension, which has no more reality in itself than,
e.g., the rainbow. What Spinoza has come into being in this way by a
simply abstract way of thinking, by abstraction from the substance
which is in itself indivisible — the apparent image of divisible mate¬
rial - comes into being for Leibniz by a confused idea. Every physical
thing is in itself only a totality of spiritual powers, if we could think it
as adequately as God can, then we would only see spirit in it. Only the
confused idea creates the appearance of physicality. I do not wish to
investigate which of these two explanations is more plausible. I only
mention it here with the intention of showing that if one understands
by monad the simply spiritual, then the true substance of matter is sim¬
ple and indivisible for Spinoza as well. In this, then, Leibniz is no ad¬
vance on Spinoza; on the other hand, there is between them the big
difference that Spinoza has a real contradiction (Gegensatz) in the two
attributes, which he admittedly does not develop, but which could be
developed. Where there is contradiction there is life. Leibniz, on the
other hand, is an absolute Unitarian, if I may put it that way. He
knows nothing but spirit, for him nothing is unspiritual, opposed to
spirit. The differences which occur in him are really just quantitative
differences - there are more complete and less complete monads; the
one for him is lost in unconsciousness, the other conscious; but he can
explain neither whence this difference really comes, for it is not un-
Spinoza, Leibniz, and Wolff
77
of it, namely that it was not content always to talk of things only in
abstracto, without any consideration of their differences and grada¬
tions. Leibniz was the first to call the world of bodies which are inor¬
ganic and generally termed “dead” a sleeping monad-world; the soul
of plants and animals was for him the monad that was just dreaming,
only the reasonable soul was the waking monad. Although he only ex¬
pressed this gradation metaphorically, it should not be overlooked
that he did so; it was the first beginning of looking at the One essence
of nature in the necessary sequence of steps of its coming-to-itself,
and can, as such, be regarded as the first seed of later, more living
development. This side is still the most beautiful and best of Leibniz’s
doctrine; the doctrine is mainly presented from this side in the well-
known Thesibus, which Leibniz wrote about his system for the famous
Prince Eugene of Savoy, which are for that reason known under the
name of Theses in gratiam principis Eugenii; these prove at the same
time that the great commanders and princes of that time were more
concerned with philosophy than one can say they are these days — yet
Eugene as well was not a German.
Otherwise, in relation to Spinoza, Leibniz, as I stated, only worked
to drive out the speculative sense of this system from the thoughts of
his own time and the time that followed. His relationship to Spinoza,
whom he, it should be said, mentions rarely and only in passing, was,
however, not so much the one of an opponent as that of an interpreter
who cleverly interprets and tries to mediate. The Theodicy is mainly
written in this sense; throughout, without often naming him, it pre¬
supposes Spinoza but tries more to distract from him, to avoid him,
than go towards him. This work is supposed to contain a justification
of God for letting badness and evil into the world. But even the po¬
sition given to the question of the origin of badness and evil in the
world — viz. a justification of God is being demanded in this respect —
this position already presupposes a free relationship of God to the
world. For if the world is just a necessary consequence of the nature of
God, then there can, in things and in the world considered truthfully,
i.e. in the manner in which they follow from the nature of God, be
neither anything truly evil nor anything truly bad. Leibniz was, then,
already compelled by the question, which he, by the way, had not put
to himself but had been given as a task by an elevated personage (it
was Sophie, wife of the Elector of Brunswick, whose successors still
occupy the throne of Great Britain today, who had invited him to do
it, and in whom he had a great patron, as Descartes had earlier in the
already-mentioned Princess Elisabeth; everyone knows what science
and art owed to the house of the Palatinate; Karl Friedrich gave
Spinoza a professorship in Heidelberg); he was, then, already com-
Spinoza, Leibniz, and Wolff 81
Pel led by the task to give God a different relationship to the world
and to things than the one Spinoza had and he himself had given in
his monadological principles. He imagines God, then, as deliberating
with himself before all time (1) whether, given the necessary limita¬
tions to which a world different from Him would have to be sub¬
jected, it was better to create such a world or to refrain from doing so
completely; (2) which of the various possible orders of things, given
those unavoidable limitations, whose necessary consequences (he as¬
sumes) must be both physical evil and moral badness - which order of
things, then, presupposing those limitations, would still be the best of
all the possible ones; as a consequence of these deliberations he then
has God make the decision to create the present world which accord¬
ingly is not absolutely the best but still the best under those conditions;
whence the name optimism that was given to the Leibnizian idea.
Accordingly, Leibniz would have asserted (1) an origin of the world in
time and (2) a time before the world, not at all just a logical but a real
and historical origin of the same. However, many people wished to
doubt the honesty of Leibniz’s account as soon as, or at least soon af¬
ter, the appearance of the Theodicy, and a man, who was admittedly not
very credible on account of his vanity, even claimed to have received
a written communication from Leibniz himself which showed that
Leibniz himself regarded his whole theory in the Theodicy was just a
lusus ingenii [game of ingenuity]. If I were to express an opinion about
this, I would be inclined rather to assume that Leibniz regarded his
Monadology as just a lusus ingenii which he simply opposed to the ideas
of other philosophers of the time or of earlier times, and that he
meant the Theodicy seriously. Leibniz was on the one hand much too
experienced, and on the other too much a man of genius, to be able
himself to consider his doctrine of monads as more than just a tem¬
porary idea. But whatever opinion one adopts about this is less im¬
portant than the fact that even if the Theodicy is properly understood
it still cannot appear as really contradicting the Spinozist system, but
only as a moderating and accommodating interpretation of it. Leibniz
deduces the evil in the world from the necessary limitations in cre¬
ation. But this means to claim the same as Spinoza does: “The power
which shows itself in evil is, seen positively, the same as that which
works in good; it is admittedly comparatively more imperfect (less
positive) than that in good, but regarded in itself, or not in compar¬
ison, it is itself something positive and also a perfection. What we call
evil in it is only the lesser degree of the positive, which only appears
as a defect for our comparison, and in nature or in the totality is not
a defect, as this minus also belongs to the perfection of the whole.”
This is the true opinion of Spinoza, which is also completely consis-
82 On the History of Modern Philosophy
tent with his system. According to Leibniz there is likewise only a plus
of limitation and a minus of the positive in evil. This minus of the
positive in the one belongs, though, just as necessarily to the possibly
best world as the plus of the positive in the other, indeed, as in nature
a preponderance of the positive on the one side has a same prepon¬
derance of the negative on the other side as a necessary consequence,
so it is also in the moral world.
Leibniz defends God for admitting evil mainly by distinguishing the
divine will from the divine understanding (Verstand). God, he says, can
do nothing against the understanding, it is the understanding which
means that created things are limited at all, and are limited to differ¬
ent degrees; this limitation (and with it the possibility of evil) is, there¬
fore, independent of the will of God, God did not want these
limitations, He only wanted what is good. Leibniz, then, knows of no
other means of justifying God, as he thinks he must, for admitting evil
than by positing evil in limitation, i.e. in something which is only a
defect or a privation. And yet something more than simple limitation
must belong to evil; for of all created things only the one which is pre¬
cisely most perfect, i.e. the one which is least limited, is capable of evil,
not to mention that, according to the dogmatic conception, which
Leibniz defends in every way, the devil is not the most limited but
rather the most unlimited element of creation. Leibniz’s explanation
might be able to explain simply spiteful or common evil, but not evil
in its great manifestations, as it manifests itself in world history united
with the greatest energy and excellence — not just of spiritual but even
of moral powers. If one also takes into account that, according to Leib¬
niz’s doctrine, uncompromising evil also necessarily contributes to the
perfection of the world and, as such, is necessarily itself something
perfect, then one cannot see here where the difference is supposed to
be. One might say: but Leibniz sheds a soothing light over the whole
thing by his giving precedence to a free decision in God, which, by the
way, is left completely unfounded by him. But does not this decision
as well belong finally to the nature of God, could He deny Himself it?
Obviously not. The decision was, then, a necessary one in view of God
Himself. Leibniz only seeks to moderate this necessity by thinking of
it as a moral one. But if the moral necessity of choosing the good, and,
in certain conditions, the best, belongs to the nature, to the essence (We-
sen) of God, as Leibniz maintains, then this is only an attempt to me¬
diate and make comprehensible the necessity with which, as Spinoza
says, everything flows from the divine essence, not, though, an at¬
tempt to remove that necessity. In order to disperse this falsely sooth¬
ing glow, which the idea of a necessity founded only in the ethical
nature of God spreads over the system of necessity as a whole, one
Spinoza, Leibniz, and Wolff 83
WOLFF
Leibniz’s main endeavour seems to have been to pacify again the rev¬
olutionary element which had come into philosophy via Descartes
and to assert against the objective rationalism of Spinoza, which was
indeed premature because it sought to put an end to the free scien¬
tific dialectic too soon - to assert once more against this ossifying ra¬
tionalism the freedom of a dialectic which was by no means exhausted
or at an end. He could not avoid opposing to the objective rationalism
of Spinoza a philosophy which was merely rationalistic (rasonnirend)
and a basis for subjective rationality (Vernunftigkeit), from which
naturally resulted, particularly after Christian Wolff [ 1679-1754], of
tedious memory, had appropriated the Leibnizian ideas, that rational¬
ism which remained dominant for so long, particularly in religion.
The first theological rationalists were Wolffians to a man, who had
emerged in the state in which Wolffian philosophy was for a long
time, so to speak, the privileged philosophy. Leibniz steered back to¬
wards old metaphysics and became thereby, it must be said, the indi¬
rect author, or even the indirect cause, of the form which orthodox
metaphysics had taken before Kant. But Kant was to become for this
modern metaphysics what Descartes was for the old metaphysics. The
general character of scholastic metaphysics, to which the modern ver¬
sion remained as a whole true, depends (1) on the presupposition of
certain general concepts, which are assumed to be given immediately
along with the understanding itself. Leibniz had made a great effort
to defend the priority, the independence of thejse concept^ from sen¬
suous perception and experience, and thereby to.defend the necessity
and generality inherent in them, and to shield them against the op¬
ponents of innate concepts. Along with these general' concepts one
then presupposed (2) certain objects as given in experience. To these
objects belonged not just those which today are the only ones to be
called “objects of experience” because experience is limited just to
that of the senses. To these objects belonged just as much the soul, the
world, and God, whose existence one generally presupposed as given,
and which one only strove to elevate to the status of rational cogni¬
tion. This happened by simply applying concepts which were already
at hand to the objects. Such concepts were essence, being, substance,
cause, or abstract predicates, such as simplicity, finitude, infinity, etc.,
and it was only a question of bringing the presupposed concepts into
Spinoza, Leibniz, and Wolff 85
thought orie was allowed to be more free, and the opinion heard so
often, even from theologians, that it did not matter to reason and
made basically no difference whether one assumed that God had cre¬
ated from eternity, or not, derives precisely from that Leibniz—Wolf¬
fian rationalism.
A great fault of this metaphysics is that it posited so-called formal
logic outside itself and left it behind. Kant was later reproached for de¬
riving the principle of deduction for his listing of the categories or
concepts of the understanding from the table of logical judgements,
as well as for deriving the principle of deduction for the “ideas of
reason” (as he calls them) from the conclusions. But the correct per¬
ception is at least present in the fact that the formal-logical differ¬
entiation of thought, judgement and inference, and the material
differentiation of the metaphysical concepts flow from one and the
same source. Kant proved, for another reason we can note here, to
have understood things correctly in this procedure (of deducing the
table of categories without more ado from the table of judgements,
which is presupposed as known). For had he wanted to deduce these
supposed forms of the human spirit genetically, he would have had to
go beyond them and precisely thereby acknowledge them as insepa¬
rable from man, as absolutely inherent in him.
In accordance with its particular content, this metaphysics split it¬
self up, by the way, into a succession of several individual sciences.
The first was ontology, which got its name from the fact that it was sup¬
posed to contain the initial and most general determinations of being
(des Seyenden), the basic and original concepts, which had to hold sway
in all subsequent proofs. It was concerned, then, with essence and be¬
ing (Wesen und Seyn) in general, with the possible, the contingent, and
the necessary, with the various concepts of cause, of multiplicity and
unity, finiteness and infinity, etc. But one can justifiably conclude this
list with an x, because this ontology as little secured the completeness
of its content as it secured a real system, a resulting-from-each-other
of these concepts, as is evident from the fact that it is not easy to en¬
counter the same order or sequence of concepts in different presen¬
tations of the ontology. Basically this definition was only a collection
of definitions with which one imitated the geometrical method, which
also gives definitions ahead of its demonstrations; it would be more
correct to regard this ontology as just an explanatory dictionary of
the various expressions and concepts which occur in philosophy,
which was given ahead of what follows in order to aid understanding.
In this science the presupposition was general that one could possess
those concepts independently of the objects, and possess them for
themselves, which is why it was preferred to call them concepts a pri-
Spinoza, Leibniz, and Wolff 87
on, so that the whole subsequent era understood under concepts and
cognitions a priori those which arise before and separately from the
objects, as if for the true science which begins at the beginning the
objects would not have to be just as a priori as the concepts.
The second science was sometimes rational psychology, sometimes ra¬
tional cosmology. In the former (1) the absolute simplicity of the soul
was primarily to be proven - a concept which relied completely on
the atomistic view of matter - basically it was only proven that the
soul was not composite, in the sense that one thought of matter as
composite. But what if matter itself is not composite in this manner, so
that it was not at all a valid inference that: matter is divisible, there¬
fore it is composed of parts? From simplicity (2) the absolute inde-
structability of the soul was supposed to be proven. However, one
soon started to mistrust the conclusiveness of this proof; perhaps one
also felt the bareness and abstractness of the concept of immortality,
which is the least one can say about the continuation of the soul after
death, for instance; in short, all proofs were permitted, including, by
the way, empirical ones, such, e.g., as the proof taken from the per¬
fectibility of the human spirit, but one had then to rely again on the
help of the doctrine of God, which was, though, only dealt with after
this. In rational cosmology the creation of the world was then dealt
with, which one presupposed from the tradition; in this the question
of whether God had created from eternity or only at a certain time
was particularly discussed, in addition the infinity or finitude of the
world in terms of space, the mechanism of nature and whether it
could be interrupted or not, e.g. by miracles, a few general laws, the
law of economy (lex parsimoniae), of constancy, etc., as well as the gen¬
eral laws of movement were dealt with.
The last science and the pinnacle of all was, finally, the so-called
rational theology, in which, however (since it was only a question of ex¬
istence), three successive proofs - the ontological, the cosmological
and the physio-theological - were found necessary. This succession of
proofs already showed that none of these proofs was regarded as suf¬
ficient in itself. I have already said what I think about the first of
these, the ontological argument, in relation to Descartes, and I there¬
fore only need briefly to repeat its content in the form which it later
assumed. Everything which is only one being (Seyendes), which, there¬
fore, only takes part in being (Seyn), can also be considered in abstrac¬
tion from this being (Seyn), without this being (Seyn) — be considered
naked, as it were, as that which has just drawn being to itself (sich das
Seyn bloss angezogen), has just put it on (sich mit ihm iiberkleidet hat). Now
to the extent to which everything which is just one being (Seyendes)
can be considered as something to which being (Seyn) happens (ad-
88 On the History of Modern Philosophy
whilst it was impossible if one just began with the concept to arrive at
existence in the concluding proposition.
The cosmological argument, examined more closely, is based on the
foundation used already by Aristotle, that a progression from causes
to causes in a row, where a last cause is never encountered, that such
a regressus in infinitum [infinite regress] would not really explain any-
thing. For the next cause which I assume is not really a cause, but, be¬
cause it presupposes another cause, only an effect, and the same with
the following cause. I only move, therefore, from effects to effects,
and the regressus in infinitum is really only an ever continued negation
of the cause. Either, then, I must never explain, or I must assume a
cause which itself does not presuppose another cause, which is abso¬
lute. This last cause can, admittedly, only be found in that which
purely is (das rein Seyende), for that which is not purely and absolutely
cause also cannot be that which purely is. In this way one really could
believe that the existence of God was proven, and the Thomist school
of the scholastics indeed lay the greatest emphasis on this argument.
For the purpose of this argument one had, however, to imagine a so-
called chain of causes. I admit that this has never been clear to me. For
if one does not, for example, wish to limit oneself just to living beings,
where one can go back from the son to the father, from the latter to
his father, etc., into the indeterminate, then I do not see how one can
demonstrate it in the rest of nature, because research into nature im¬
mediately comes up against limits in all directions that it cannot go
beyond; e.g., if it thinks it can explain magnetic or electrical phenom¬
ena by a magnetic or electrical fluid, then it cannot go any further
back with this matter, it must immediately accept it as something
which originally is, or was originally created. If one just relates this
chain to movements in nature, then the substance to which movement
is only attached as an accident remains unexplained: if one takes
things as the elements of this row, then we see, instead of such a chain
in nature in general, rather a system of general mutual determination.
If, for instance, one wanted to say that this particular substance, e.g.,
this metal = A could not exist in nature if that other metal = B did
not exist, thus metal A is dependent for its existence on metal B, then
we immediately see that metal B could just as much not exist if there
were no metal A, i.e. we see that the determination is a mutual one,
not a one-sided one. Perhaps one can allow such a mutual obligation
of bodies to each other, or allow the fact that in case one of them
could disappear from the row of things, all the others would have to
disappear - one can, I suggest, perhaps allow this for inorganic na¬
ture; it could not be asserted for organic beings at least, as experience
shows that members admittedly have already disappeared from the
90 On the History of Modern Philosophy
does not want such a cause, does not want a cause inherent in the
things themselves, it wants God as a cause which remains outside
things and outside matter. The kind of cause which is different from
the material can, though, e.g., will the organic form of the material,
but cannot produce it, for the form which it produced could in every
case only be imposed externally onto the matter, but not be the inner
form which has grown together with it, which we must gain knowl¬
edge of in organic nature.
So the simple presupposition of an intelligible cause in general is
not sufficient to explain the purposiveness of nature. On the other
hand, the concept which we wish to realise in God is not exhausted in
the concept of an intelligent, intelligible cause. God would also be an
intelligible cause as just the architect of the world.
But the understanding alone is not sufficient to produce a world in
terms of material as well. The understanding is only applied in every
production, but from this it is clear that it is not the really producing
force. What absolutely distinguishes God is His being the power to
produce material; if this cannot be demonstrated or made comprehen¬
sible in Him, then God is still not posited as God. The concept of a
simply intelligible (like that of a free, moral, i.e. generous) nature does
not contain anything which is really distinct with regard to God. For
man is also an intelligible nature, he is even, at least to a certain ex¬
tent, receptive to wisdom, just as to power, foresight and other ethical
qualities. Whence an addition was always found necessary in the ap¬
plication of these qualities to God; God is not called wise, but all-wise,
not powerful, but all-powerful, not generous, but all-generous (all-
giitig). By this addition the fact that God is not limited in the exercise
of these qualities by any material was to be expressed, and thus the fact
that He Himself is the cause which brings forth material — the creator,
and from this it is clear that the really distinct concept of God is not
to be absolute intelligence, but to be creator. With this third argument
as well, then, the concept of God as such was not achieved.
However, after it was thought that the existence of the true God had
now been proven, one went on to the doctrine of the attributes of God.
Strangely enough; for you would think that the complex of these at¬
tributes would constitute the concept of God, but one would have had
to have assured oneself of the concept before thinking of the proof of
existence. But now it was easy to distinguish two kinds of attribute
among the so-called attributes of God which could be found in the
tradition and in common belief. Some of these attributes presented
themselves as those without which God could not be God, so they
could be called the simply negative ones. Such attributes are, e.g., eter¬
nity, infinity, being of its own accord (a se Esse). A being (Wesen) which
92 On the History of Modern Philosophy
was not eternal, which was not of itself could not be God, but it is not
yet God for this reason alone; these seem, then, to be attributes of
God in and before Himself, i.e., as it were, before His Godhood, at¬
tributes which He, so to speak, needs, in order to be God, so that He is
God (a priori attributes). But as the blind substance of Spinoza is just
as eternal, just as infinite and of itself, then it is clear from this that
these attributes are not attributes of God as such. Others of these at¬
tributes presented themselves, on the other hand, as those through
which God really was God, or which God has according to His God-
hood (= positive). To these now belonged all those attributes which
include freedom, intelligence, will and Providence, or a real relation¬
ship [?] (eine aktuelle Relation). These two classes of attributes, though,
just stood side by side, without how they relate to each other being ex¬
amined (no transition from those of the first to those of the second
kind). The positive, or, as they were also termed, the moral attributes
were then used to try to refute Spinozism; however, one felt less se¬
cure against this system by these refutations than by the fact that God
was transferred to the end of metaphysics, where one thought that the
independent existence of things, the freedom of human actions, and
all those other things closest to the human heart were already pro¬
tected against infinity, omnipotence (which only seemed to leave an
absolute impotence for everything which exists outside God), as well
as against the omniscience of God (which seemed incompatible with
the freedom of human actions). One consoled oneself with it without
pondering that in reality God is not after things but before them.
I thought it was necessary for various reasons to present the former
metaphysics somewhat more extensively here. For (1) it was, after all,
really the only one which was valid, publicly tolerated and accepted:
neither the philosophy of Descartes, nor that of Spinoza, nor even
what was really speculative about Leibniz’s philosophy was ever taken
up in the schools; (2) it is still important to know what a dialectic which
is merely subjective and which thus remains outside the object is capable
of, and, as a preliminary exercise for higher philosophy, this meta¬
physics was still presented to good effect even in universities. For al¬
though we can only consider it to be a merely rationalistic,
subjectively-rational philosophy, it does allow precisely for that rea¬
son at the same time a certain freedom of thought and use of the un¬
derstanding which would be all the more charitable in its effect
because this way of philosophising is the only one which is suitable to
and comfortable for the great majority; for if the majority concerns
itself at all with philosophy, it does not like distancing itself from its
own point of view, but rather, being very satisfied with the education
it happens to have achieved, and being little inclined to admit that the
Spinoza, Leibniz, and Wolff
93
KANT
This was the state in which philosophy found itself when Immanuel
Kant unexpectedly appeared as its restorer and gave back to it its sci¬
entific seriousness, and at the same time its lost dignity.
Before I move on to Kant himself, I want to begin with a general
observation, which applies to more or less all human deeds: namely
that their real importance, i.e. that their true effects are generally oth¬
ers than those which were intended or which relate to the means by
which they were produced. The effect of Kant was indeed excep¬
tional. One cannot be pleased that, fifty years after the appearance of
Kant, after we are admittedly at a different point, but one to which we
would never have got without him, Kant’s contribution is diminished
by those who contribute nothing to going beyond Kant. The same can
be said of Fichte. It does not take much to pass a dismissive judge¬
ment about both, but it would take a lot only to raise philosophy again
to the point to which it had been raised by Kant and Fichte. The
judgement of history will be that a greater outer and inner battle for
the highest possessions of the human spirit was never fought; at no
time has the endeavour of the scientific spirit led to deeper experi¬
ences and experiences more rich in results than since Kant.1 But this
' With Kant’s appearance the previous course of philosophy suddenly changes, it is
as if a current which has been held back and dammed up for a long time had fi¬
nally found an opening, which it immediately works continually on widening, un¬
til it comes to the complete break-through, and it can flow freely and without
hindrance. If this stream does not keep a regular course straightaway, if it escapes
without barriers to each side and floods fields and meadows, then this is all right;
petty and narrow spirits may afterwards chide the river and praise the little stream
which they have diverted from it in order to drive their mill, the judgement of
history will be different. . . . Since Kant’s real influence began in philosophy (for
he remained unnoticed for a long time, and the first success by which his influence
announced itself was only a swarm of merely literal copiers and largely thoughtless
exegetes), but since his real influence began it is not various systems, but One sys¬
tem which forces its way through all the successive appearances to the last point of
94
Kant, Fichte, System of Transcendental Idealism
95
effect was not really produced by what Kant directly wanted. Whilst he
thought that he had brought all knowledge of the supersensuous to
an end for all time by his critique, he really only caused negative and
positive in philosophy to have to separate, but precisely because of
this the positive, now emerging in its complete independence, was
able to oppose itself, as positive, to the merely negative philosophy as
the second side of philosophy as a whole. Kant began this process of
separation and the resultant process of transfiguration of philosophy
into the positive. Kant’s critique contributed to this all the more be¬
cause it was in no way hostile towards the positive. Whilst he demol¬
ishes the whole edifice of that metaphysics, he always makes his view
clear that in the last analysis one must want what it wanted, and that
its content would in fact finally be the true metaphysics, if it were only
possible.
I now move on to the presentation of Kant himself with the asser¬
tion that Kant’s critique was initially directed against the metaphysics
accepted in the schools, but that from another side and, as it were,
unintentionally, it also again became a defence of precisely this
metaphysics.
Empiricism had, starting in England mainly with John Locke, re¬
volted against metaphysics at that time, denying the existence of all
concepts independent of experience, and out of this empiricism the
doctrine of the famous philosopher and historian David Hume had
its transfiguration; as the plant which begins to grow does not know what point it
will arrive at but still has a sure feeling of that point, and this feeling is what drives
it, is what we call the drive in it. Thus even if in this whole succession nobody had
a clear concept of the goal, everyone felt that it was necessary to reach some final
point, and precisely this feeling, this drive, which came into philosophy with Kant,
distinguished this epoch from all earlier ones - for, e.g., in Leibniz’s system there
was no such drive, the power which had awakened it consumed itself in the dead,
deaf and sterile endeavours of that pre-Kantian metaphysics; what, on the other
hand, in relation to the movement begun by Kant, brought those who stood out¬
side it, who looked at it from the outside, to mock and scorn it, namely the swift
change of its systems, was itself precisely the proof that finally the living point in
philosophy had been hit upon, which, like the seed of a being which has once been
fertilised, or like the basic thought of a great tragedy, does not allow any peace
until the complete development has been achieved - philosophy was gripped by a
necessary and, so to speak, involuntary process; what appeared to them to be a
rapid succession of systems was really only the swift succession of the moments of
development and continuating of One system. In such a succession, the individual
is not to be considered according to what is just idiosyncratic or peculiar about
him; this individual side is only the tribute he pays to his time, just the skin and
husk, which is left behind in the subsequent development, or even only a remain¬
der of the earth and the ground from which he has grown which has stuck to him.
We must, then, see Kant this way as well. (From another Munich manuscript.)
[Translator's note: The footnote text was added by Schelling’s son.]
g6 On the History of Modern Philosophy
is just an external succession, from the other, the propter hoc, why
should we not be able to do this in every case? I do not, however, even
wish to insist upon this reflection, as I would really like to ask whether
the great apparatus of the Kantian critique was actually necessary to
refute the Humean doubt. It is strange enough that this refutation
was found to be so difficult, as no one until now has noticed the very
simple fact that it can even be refuted just by experience. Hume ex¬
plains the principle of causality by a habituation; but for every habit¬
uation a certain amount of time is necessary; Hume must, therefore,
allow not only the individual but the whole human race a certain
amount of time during which it always has seen, following the par¬
ticular phenomenon A, the other phenomenon B, and thus has fi¬
nally got used to seeing this succession as necessary (for this is inherent
in the law of causality). But precisely this fact, which Hume tacitly pre¬
supposes, and thus thinks he is able to presuppose, cannot be presup¬
posed. For I am convinced that none of us would be willing to admit a
time when the human race did not judge according to the law of
cause and effect, and Hume himself, if we could present him with the
question as to whether he could think human beings at any point in
time of their existence without this concept and without the applica¬
tion of the same, would hesitate with his yes to this question; he
would feel that the human being from whom he had withdrawn the
judgement of cause and effect could no longer appear to us as a hu¬
man being. We can, then, be completely certain that on the very first
day of his existence the first human being judges according to this
principle, because it belongs to human nature to judge in this man¬
ner, as the snake in Paradise, which, by the way, according to the Mo¬
saic story, immediately whispers sceptical remarks against the divine
interdict to the first human being, is not giving him lessons on the law
of causality, but presupposes that he will understand it if it says: “If
you ea‘t the fmit, your eyes will be opened”, or “On the day that you
eat of this ffuit, you will be like God”; which means the same as: “The
fruit or the eating of the fruit will be the cause of your eyes being
opened, the effect of this eating will be that you become equal to
God'’. There exists in Arabic a novel or a story with the title Philoso¬
phies Autodidactus, in which a child is invented which is abandoned by
its mother immediately after birth on an island in the Indian Ocean,
and which only gradually arrives at all philosophical concepts and
knowledge by applying its inherent or innate understanding. But we
do not need such fiction to refute Hume; for the child in the cradle,
which has not yet had an opportunity to get used to a particular
sequence of phenomena and to whom it is even less the case that
anyone has talked about cause and effect, the child in the cradle,
On the History of Modern Philosophy
if it hears a noise, turns to the area whence the noise comes, with no
other intention than to see the cause of this noise, which it, therefore,
presupposes.
Judging according to the law of causality is, then, imposed upon us,
not just independently of our will, but even of our thinking, by a ne¬
cessity which precedes it; but we call something which is independent
of our will and our thinking a real principle. It is therefore proven by
experience itself that it is a real principle which, as it were, compels us
like universal gravity—just as this determines the body to move to¬
wards the centre, so are we compelled to judge according to the law of
cause and effect, as we are compelled to think according to the law
of contradiction.
But if we now move on to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, then the
general foundation of it is the thought: before one wishes to know
something, it is necessary to submit our capacity for knowing itself to
an examination. Just as a careful builder carefully ponders his re¬
sources before he erects a house, to see whether they are sufficient for
both the firm foundation and the successful execution of the build¬
ing, the philosopher must, before thinking of erecting a building of
metaphysics, first be sure of the materials for it, whether he can ob¬
tain them, and, since these materials are drawn from a spiritual
source in this case, this source must itself first be examined, in order
to be certain whether it really contains or offers sufficient material for
the intended building. Before one can hope to have knowledge — par¬
ticularly of supersensuous objects — we must first examine whether
we also have the capacity to know them.
At first sight this thought is extremely plausible.' Looked at more
closely, it is revealed that it is here a question of a knowing of know¬
ing, and that this knowing of knowing itself is, in turn, precisely a
knowing. Accordingly it would first require an investigation of the
possibility of such a knowledge of knowing, and in this way one could
keep on asking into infinity.
At least Kant, given that he sets about his work so critically, will
have assured himself of a central principle and a reliable method for
his investigation of the capacity for cognition. Unfortunately this is
not the case. He does not start with a general investigation of the na¬
ture of knowing, but instead goes straight on to the listing of the in¬
dividual sources of knowledge or of the individual cognitive faculties,
which he does not, however, deduce scientifically, but rather takes
1 This thought was particularly plausible for that time, because one was already ac¬
customed by empirical psychology to assume a multiplicity of capacities in the
spirit or the soul. (From another manuscript.) [Translator’s note: The footnote text
was added by Schelling’s son.]
Kant, Fichte, System of Transcendental Idealism
99
that time has even less independence from our ideas than space, that
it is more subjective than even the latter.
Along with all this Kant also has, though, besides time and space,
which are just forms of our intuition and thinking, the basis of our
intuitions which is in itself space- and timeless, that Unknown, which
he designates with x (the sign of the unknown quantity in mathemat¬
ics), and which he, strangely enough, calls the “thing in itself” (really
it would be the “thing in and before itself”, i.e. before it becomes a
thing, for it only becomes a thing in our thinking). But what this thing
which is posited outside all space and all time, which, to the extent to
which it is outside of space is something mental, because outside all
time is something eternal, what this Unknown might be, if it is not
God, for example, is hard to say. But Kant is far from determining it
as God, for he calls the idealism of Berkeley, which explains the whole
world of the senses as a pretence created by a divine influence on our
powers of imagination - Kant calls this idealism, which can at least be
thought, fanciful. This it may be, but the fanciful itself, if at least there
is to be something to be thought via it, is philosophically better than
that which ends in a complete non-thought, or an un-thought like
Kant’s theory of sensuous intuition, which ends with two ungrasp-
ables, namely with the incomprehensible arrangement of what thinks
in us, which is forced to think what in itself is outside all space and all
time in space and time, and with that equally incomprehensible
outside-us and the necessity or the interest it has in affecting us and
giving rise in us to the idea of a world of the senses.
But Kant now moves on from the world of sensuousness to the sec¬
ond faculty which knows or determines knowledge in us — the under¬
standing. He remarks that what is sensuously perceived is not
necessarily just in space and time for us, that we, once it has been
known — once it elevates itself to being an object of judgement for us -
that we are immediately just as compelled to ascribe certain determi¬
nations of the understanding to it, e.g., to determine it as substance or
as accident, as cause or effect, as One or many, etc. All these
determinations are now no longer just forms of intuition, they are de¬
terminations of thought, concepts — concepts of the pure understand¬
ing. And yet it is our opinion that these concepts are in the objects of
thought themselves, that our judgement that this or that is substance or
is cause is not just subjective but an objectively valid one, and things can
be as little thought without these concepts as, e.g., they can be intu¬
ited without space. Nonetheless — because those determinations are
concepts, which can only be thought in an understanding, then - one
would think, they prove the presence of an understanding in the things
Kant, Fichte, System of Transcendental Idealism 101
objects are for him just ideas of reason, which, as he says, cannot be
found in any experience.1 But in the generality and indeterminacy
with which this is asserted, it is still in no way established that God is
not or could not be an object of experience. Admittedly not of that
1 I would like, with regard to these inherent ideas of reason, which, according to
Kant, are also independent of all experience, just to say the following here. It is
incomprehensible how Kant can call these a priori concepts as well. In relation to
the categories, this is comprehensible — they are a priori relative to the object; for
they are not themselves the object. But soul, world, God — these are themselves
objects; for how can objects be known otherwise than if they are there, i.e. a pos¬
teriori. Besides, the soul, e.g., is object of its own immediate experience; the con¬
cept of the world, however, at least as it occurs in Kant, is nothing but the last,
summarising concept of all individual existences. That complete separation from
experience which Kant assumes in these ideas would therefore, for instance, only
be applicable to the idea of God. But if God is explained as the object of a pure
idea of reason, i.e. as something which can only be thought and determined by my
reason, then this leads to the idea of the merely general being (Wesenf, for every
determination which is added beyond this would in Kant’s eyes already itself be an
empirical one. If one (to add this about Kant’s doctrine of the a priori concepts) — if
one had to distinguish a Prius and a Posterius in sensuous representation, then the
true Prius in it would be what Kant calls “thing in itself”; those concepts of the
understanding which it shows itself as affected by in my thinking are, according to
Kant himself, precisely that by which it first becomes object of my thinking, thus
is able to be experienced by me; the true Posterius is, then, not, as he assumes, that
element which remains after the concepts of the understanding have been re¬
moved, for rather, if I take these away then this is the being Seyende which is un¬
thinkable, before and outside the representation, it is thus the absolute Prius of the
representation, but the true Posterius is precisely this Unknown (which he himself
compares with the x of mathematics), this x + the determinations of the under¬
standing - this common child is the true Posterius; the determinations of the un¬
derstanding, as those which make that x into merely the Posterius, could to this
extent only have a relative priority, or would only be regarded as what mediates
between the true Prius, the thing in itself, and the representation, i.e. the Posterius.
If the question is whether philosophy itself and as a whole is an a priori or an a
posteriori science, then Kant (to say this as well here) did not really make up his
mind. For if it had, for instance, been his opinion that philosophy consisted in the
Critique of Pure Reason which he established, then it is clear that he obtained the
content of this critique just from observation and experience, and correspond¬
ingly declared philosophy itself in the last instance to be a science of experience.
Kant fights against empiricism only as far as he, in opposition to Locke and above
all to David Hume, demonstrates an a priori element for the understanding in the
empirical representations themselves - but how he himself arrives or arrived at
this assertion he basically does not explain, or does so only tacitly by only begin¬
ning with experience in the founding of this assertion, namely the experience of
the observed generality and necessity of those concepts. The question we are con¬
cerned with here could only arise after Kant, namely only after one had ascended
to the idea of a system which derived, in One continuous development, everything
from a first beginning. (From a Munich manuscript of 1827.) [Translator’s note: The
footnote text was added by Schelling’s son.]
Kant, Fichte, System of Transcendental Idealism 105
(1) Kant had a beneficial effect just by the fact that he really set to
work once more in a methodical and serious manner, and thereby put
an end to that philosophical anarchy which preceded him — I do not
mean by this the external anarchy that at that time there was no rul¬
ing head in philosophy, but rather the inner anarchy — the complete
lack of principles (it is known that apxq, whence avapxia derives,
means “principle”), that he therefore put an end to this complete lack
of principles in philosophy; (2) that, if he did not answer, indeed did
not even raise those deeper questions which related primarily to the
intelligible basis of all knowable being (Seyn), he did at least unavoid¬
ably provoke them; in particular, though, as already stated, that he
maintained the universality and necessity in human knowledge
against a destructive scepticism and sensualism. But the real historical
effect of Kant —what it was that made him determining for subse¬
quent German philosophy — is not to be sought in all this. This effect
was caused rather by the fact that he directed philosophy towards the sub¬
jective, a direction which it had completely lost since Spinoza; for what
is peculiar in Spinoza is precisely the substance which is just object, is
subject-less, which has completely destroyed itself as subject. It is true
that a certain timidity, which Kant could not overcome and which was
further increased because his philosophy was immediately met by ev¬
ery possible spiteful description, had led him to exchange passages in
the first edition of the Critique of Pure Reason, in which he had even
almost declared himself to be an idealist, for others in the later edi¬
tions in which he apparently refuted idealism. But the way to idealism
was nevertheless opened, the thing in itself was something too inde-'
terminate, indeed too right (for everything that makes the object into
a thing, into something real, only came from the subject) for it to per¬
sist, and thus the next step was undoubtedly the one whereby the sub¬
ject, the I, alone remained. This step took place via Fichte, who
proclaimed frankly: the I, namely the I of every single individual (eines
jeden Ich), is the only substance.
FICHTE
' If we take another general look back from here at the movement of philosophy, it
had in Descartes the empirical subject as immediately certain, to which other me¬
diate certainties were then to be connected by just subjective conceptual necessity
or necessity of thought. Spinoza forcibly broke through this barrier by jumping
from the empirical subject immediately to the absolute object, which destroys ev¬
erything subjective — the absolutely infinite, against which the philosophising sub¬
ject had no freedom, this absolutely infinite was also the absolutely immobile;
every attempt at movement only fell to the philosophising subject; as such, seen
formally, Spinozism had to appear as just subjectively dialectical, but every such
attempt ended with the negation of all movement and with hanging on to simple
being (Seyn). Dogmatism revolted against this compulsion, and, as such, admittedly
stood higher than Spinozism. It sought to restore the freedom of the philosophis¬
ing subject against the object and to assert, not by again making the empirical sub¬
ject into the point of departure, but by presupposing in the understanding certain
given, universal, transcendental concepts, via which all being (Seyn), thus includ¬
ing the being of the Absolute, would be determined. As these concepts were, on
the one hand, concepts of the pure understanding, on the other hand, however,
they had objective significance and supposedly the power themselves to determine
the Absolute, then it was as if a mediator had been found by this, whereby both the
Absolute and the philosophising subject could exist; there was, if this was success¬
ful, a free relationship between the philosophising subject and its object. But this
hope was destroyed and thwarted by Kant, by his declaring precisely those pure
and general concepts to be concepts of a merely subjective understanding, and by
io8 On the History of Modern Philosophy
the I and for the I. Fichte had thereby extended the independence or
autonomy which Kant attributed to the human self for its moral self-
determination to theoretical autonomy, or he had justified the same
autonomy to the human I for its ideas of the external world as well.
That proposition “Everything is only via the I and for the I ’ admit¬
tedly initially flatters human self-esteem and appears to give to the
inner person the last independence from everything external. But
looked at more closely it has something thrasonical and boastful, as
long as it is not shown how, in what manner, all that we have to ac¬
knowledge as existing is via the I and for the I. It could not be the
opinion of this subjective idealism itself that the I posited things out¬
side itself freely and of its own volition; for there is far too much that
the I would want to be completely different if external being (Seyn)
depended on it. The absolute idealist cannot avoid thinking of the I as
dependent in relation to its ideas (Vorstellungen) if the external world -
even if it is not dependent on a thing in itself, as Kant called it, or on
a cause outside itself, it is at least dependent on an inner necessity, and
if Fichte attributes a production of those ideas to the I, then this must
at least be a production which is blind and not grounded in the will
but rather in the nature of the I. Fichte showed himself unconcerned
his denying every possible transition from them, denying every possible break¬
through into the objective. There was no alternative here, if one did not wish to
move once again into the absolute object which destroys everything free in the
subject, than to move to the opposite - to the all-destroying subject, which was
now no longer the empirical subject of Descartes, but only the absolute subject, the
transcendental /. Already for Kant, the transcendental unity of apperception,
which was nothing other than transcendental egoity (Ichheit), was the only last
principle or creator of the only knowledge which he admitted as real, knowledge
through experience, Fichte raised this I from the partially obscuring surround¬
ings it had in Kant, and put it absolutely as the sole principle at the highest point
of philosophy, and thereby became the creator of transcendental idealism. Since
this I was not the empirical I, then for Fichte the / am, which he made into the
highest principle of philosophy, could also not be in an empirical fact — Fichte de¬
clared it to be an action (Thalhandlung [literally “deed-action”]), and showed how
the I could in no way exist independently of this action as a dead, immobile thing,
but only in this act of self-positing, in which he recognised not just a temporal, and
also not just a transitory beginning which had begun the movement at some time,
but the beginning which was always equally eternal - thus that, wherever and
whenever one wanted to begin, this act of self-positing always had to be the be¬
ginning. Fichte’s idealism thus is the complete opposite of Spinozism or is an in¬
verted Spinozism, because it opposes to Spinoza’s absolute object, which destroys
everything subjective, the subject in its absoluteness, opposes the deed to the
merely immobile being (Seyn) of Spinoza; the I is for Fichte, not, as it is for Des¬
cartes, just something assumed for the purposes of philosophising, but the real,
the true beginning, the absolute Prius of everything. (From an older (Erlangen)
manuscript.) [Translator's note: The footnote text was added by Schelling’s son ]
Kant, Fichte, System of Transcendental Idealism tog
nore it), and it could not get involved with itself without thereby lim¬
iting itself, without inhibiting its activity, which in itself strives into
infinity, without making itself, which was formerly pure freedom and
as nothing, into something for itself, thus into something limited. The
barrier which Fichte had fall outside the I fell in this manner in the I
itself, and the process became a completely immanent one, in which
the I was only concerned with itself, with its own contradiction, which
was posited in itself, concerned with being simultaneously subject and
object, finite and infinite. For the I had admittedly, by becoming an
object to itself, found itself, but not as the simple 1 it had been before,
but instead as a double 1, as subject and object at the same time - it was
now for itself, but had thereby precisely stopped being in itself; this con¬
tingency which was posited in it had to be overcome, the moments of
this successive overcoming were proven to be identical with the mo¬
ments of nature, and this process was continued from step to step,
from moment to moment, until the point where the I broke out again
from limitation into freedom and only now really had itself, or was for
itself as it was in itself — as pure freedom. With this the theoretical phi¬
losophy was closed and the practical philosophy began. I had here at¬
tempted historical development in philosophy for the first time — the
whole of philosophy for me was the history of self-consciousness,
which I formally divided into epochs, e.g., first epoch from the orig¬
inal sensation (of the limitation posited by the self-objectification of
the I) until productive intuition. But the instrument was too limited
to be able to perform the whole melody on it. The principle of pro¬
gression or the method rests on the differentiation of the I which is
developing or is concerned with the production of self-consciousness
from the I which is reflecting on this, which, so to speak, is watching
it, is thus philosophising. By this moment a determination was pos¬
ited in the objective 1, but this determination was posited in it only for
the watcher, not for it itself. Progress therefore always consisted in the
fact that what had been posited in the 1 in the preceding moment just
for the philosophiser was posited objectively in the succeeding mo¬
ment for the I itself — for the I itself in the philosophiser, and that in
this way the objective I itself was finally brought to the standpoint of
the philosophising I, or that the objective I became completely the
same as the philosophising, thus subjective I; the moment at which
this sameness begins, at which, then, exactly the same was posited in
the objective I as in the subjective I, was the closing moment of phi¬
losophy, which had thereby definitely assured itself at the same time
of its end. Between the objective I and the philosophising I there was
roughly the same relationship as between the pupil and the master in
the Socratic dialogues. In the objective I more was always posited in a
Kant, Fichte, System of Transcendental Idealism 113
developed way than it itself knew; the activity of the subjective, of the
philosophising I now consisted in helping the objective I itself to
knowledge and consciousness of what is posited in it, and of finally
bringing it in this way to complete knowledge of itself. This process, in
which what is posited just subjectively in the preceding moment al-
ways joins the object in the next, has done sterling service in the sub¬
sequent greater development as well.
The beginnings of the presentation of idealism can be found in the
various essays which have been reprinted in the first part of my philo¬
sophical writings. If any of you wish to do me the honour of judging
the path of my philosophical development, and particularly if you
wish to get to know the real heuristic principle, the principle of dis¬
covery which led me, you must go back as far as that.
The Philosophy of Nature
(Naturphilosophie)
"4
The Philosophy of Nature (Naturphilosophie) 115
by being as before, but that which has inhibited itself with being, it
itself feels this being as foreign (zugezogenes) and thus as contingent.
Note here that correspondingly the first beginning is expressly
thought of as a contingent beginning. The first being (Seyende), this
primum existens, as I have called it, is, therefore, at the same time the
first contingency (original coincidence) (Urzufall). This whole con¬
struction therefore begins with the emergence of the first contin¬
gency — which is not identical with itself — it begins with a dissonance,
and must begin this way. For previously - before the drawing to itself
(Zuziehung) of being (Seyn), in its being in and before itself, the subject
was also infinite, but only in as much as it still had finitude before
itself, but for that reason it is not yet posited there as infinite; to posit
itself as infinite it must have cleansed itself from this possibility of also
being the finite. Thus finitude itself becomes a means for it to posit
itself as infinite (i.e. as freedom from being (Freiheit vom Seyn)), for no
other concept is connected here with the word “infinite”. Only
through real opposition could it be raised into its true essence, could
it reach itself as infinite.
I would like to explain the last point again in another, though
wholly equivalent formulation.
The subject which is at first a subject which is pure and not present
to itself - in wishing to have itself, in becoming object to itself - is
tainted with contingency (contingency is the opposite of essence). But
it cannot in this way negate itself as essence, for it is not just essence in
general, but in an infinite manner. That contingency only becomes the
reason for it to posit itself as essence which it previously was not by
retreating into its essence. In and before itself it was essence (= free¬
dom from being), but not as essence, for it still had that, if I may say
it, fatal (verhangnisvoll) act of attracting itself (des sich-selbst-Anziehens)
before it; it was still standing at that slope from which it cannot hold
itself back. For either it remains still (remains as it is, thus pure sub¬
ject), then there is no life and it is itself as nothing, or it wants itself,
then it becomes an other, something not the same as itself {sich selbst
Ungleiches) sui dissimile. It admittedly wants itself as such, but precisely
this is impossible in an immediate way; in the very wanting itself (im
Wollen selbst) it already becomes an other and distorts itself, but it sur¬
renders itself into this (es ergibt sich darein) because it is only denied
positing itself immediately as essence; that finite or inhibited being
(Seyn) - the only one which is immediately possible - presents itself as
the same as itself only as the mediation of its being as infinite, as es¬
sence (Als Vermittlung seines als unendlich-, ah Wesen Seyns); as such it
can want that being, although it is not what it really wants. This finite
being leads it to posit itself on a second stage or potential (Potenz) -
The Philosophy of Nature (Naturphilosophie) 117
light belong to the real world, but looked at for itself, or also in com¬
parison with matter, it is in its manner or its potential just as much
something Ideal as human thinking is something Ideal in its potential.
From the determinations so far it has turned out that the first mo¬
ments of the infinite self-positing, or, as the life of the subject consists
in this self-positing, that the first moments of this life are moments of
nature. From this it follows, then, that this philosophy is in nature with
its first steps, or it begins from nature — naturally not in order to re¬
main in it, but in order subsequently, via an ever progressing height¬
ening, to transcend it, to move beyond it, and to raise itself up to
spirit, into the really spiritual world. This philosophy could then be
called Naturphilosophie at the beginning, but Naturphilosophie was only
the first part or the foundation of the whole. Nature was itself only
one side of the universe or of the absolute totality in which the abso¬
lute subject is first completely realised; nature is the relatively ideal
world. The world of spirit was the other side. Philosophy had to de¬
scend into the depths of nature in order to raise itself from there to
the heights of spirit. The other side of the system was, therefore, the
philosophy of spirit. If the whole system was called Naturphilosophie
for that reason, then this was only a denominatio a potiori [designation
in terms of what is preferable], or really a priori, thus a designation of
what came first in the system, but which was, as such, rather what was
subordinate in it. It was basically difficult to find a name for this sys¬
tem, precisely because it contained annulled within itself the oppositions
of all earlier systems; it could in fact be called neither materialism nor
spiritualism, neither realism nor idealism. One might have called it
real-idealism, to the extent that in it idealism itself had a realism as its
basis and was developed from a realism. Only once, in the preface,
thus in the exoteric part of my first presentation of this system,* I had
called it the “identity system”, precisely in order to indicate that nei¬
ther a one-sided Real nor a one-sided Ideal was being asserted here,
but that instead only One last subject was being thought in what peo¬
ple were accustomed to call, following Fichte, the Real, and the Ideal.
But even this designation was badly interpreted and used by those
who never penetrated to the interior of the system to infer, or to make
the uneducated part of the public believe, that in this system all dif¬
ferences, namely every difference of matter and spirit, of good and
evil, even of truth and falsity, were annulled, that according to this
system it was, in the everyday sense, all the same. I will now, by the
way, continue the presentation of the system.
We now have, then, the two first potentials, matter on the one hand
as expression of the first being-inhibited with or by itself of the pre-
viously pure and free subject, and light as expression of the subject
posited as free and uninhibited, which for just this reason can no
longer be the whole or the absolute subject, precisely because it is the
subject which is already posited as such. For the absolute subject is still
purely infinite, thus also not yet posited as such. Now it is to be shown
how the development progressed further from this point. Here the
real principle of progression or the method is first discussed, which de¬
pended on the presupposition that whatever at a preceding stage was
still posited subjectively, at a subsequent stage itself becomes objec¬
tive -joins the object, so that in this way at the end the most complete
object arises, but finally so that the last subject arises, which alone
stands still, which cannot become objective any more (because all
forms are there), thus which is really the highest subject posited as
such, for what appears in the course of the development as the sub¬
ject is, as it were, subject only for a moment, but in a subsequent mo¬
ment we already find it as belonging to the object, itself posited
objectively again. The subject has the necessary tendency to the ob¬
jective; this tendency exhausts itself.
You can easily see that this method is not just an external one, only
applied from outside to the objects, that it was an inner, immanent
one which inheres in the object itself. Not the philosophising subject -
instead the object itself (the absolute subject) moved itself in accor¬
dance with a law inherent in it, according to which that which at an
earlier stage is subject becomes object at a subsequent stage. Thus
now - at the present moment - light, i.e. the relatively Ideal, stands
opposed to nature, to matter, as subject is opposed to the object. But
this Ideal must now itself also join the object - become objective, so
that in this way the whole, the complete object should arise. In this
first Ideal there is hidden already again a higher one which lies fur¬
ther back, which does not emerge and become distinguishable until
the former has itself become real. But it cannot become real or ob¬
jective without precisely thereby taking part in the being (Scyn) of
matter (which has taken all the space of the objective), i.e. not without
depriving matter of its previous being-itself, not without producing a
Third of which matter and light are both themselves only accidents or
attributes. What was previously (in the preceding moment) still each
a being-itself - matter and light - these two are supposed, in a subse¬
quent moment, to be merely the common attributes of something
higher, of a Third, both are supposed to be subordinated to a still
higher potential. But matter cannot, if I may say so, put up with this
deprivation of its being-itself without resistance. Thereby a process is
posited, then, in which, as I already hinted in advance, matter is taken
as merely the foundation of a higher being, or is transformed into it.
This moment was called the dynamic process, which again has its own
122 On the History of Modern Philosophy
itself, but only by virtue of this stage, i.e. to the extent that it has those
moments before itself, to the extent that it has already cleansed itself
of these moments which were in it, the absolute subject or the subject
regarded in itself, as possibilities, to the extent that it has excluded
them outside itself, thus at the same time from itself it is as pure knowl¬
edge, not in itself, but only via its potential, as A4, but as this it pre¬
supposes itself in the earlier potentials. For precisely this reason it
stands in a necessary and indispensable relationship to those preced¬
ing moments, but in an immediate relationship to that alone in which
there is the completion and end of the preceding being (Seyn), thus to
humankind (for the following moment must always hold onto the pre¬
ceding moment as its immediate basis) - it is, therefore, pure knowl¬
edge, which admittedly relates to the whole of nature, but has its
immediate relationship to humankind, and as such is human knowl¬
edge. With this a new sequence of moments arises which cannot avoid
being parallel to the sequence of moments which we have already rec¬
ognised in nature. But the difference is that here everything happens
only in the Ideal, which there is in the Real.
The first stage here will also be the objective or the finite, the sec¬
ond the subject posited as such or the infinite, the third - the unity of
both; but as in nature the Real and the Ideal, matter and light, are
both objective or real, here (in the spiritual world which is now begin¬
ning) Real and Ideal, despite their opposition, will both only be Ideal.
The subject which we have determined as elevated above the whole of
nature is immediately only pure knowledge, and is as such infinite
and in complete freedom; as such it stands again at the same point as
the first subject which was posited in its pure freedom and infinitude,
but it stands in an immediate relationship to something finite and
limited, to the human being, and since it cannot avoid becoming the
immediate soul thereof, it is also compelled to take part in all deter¬
minations, relations and limitations of the same, and in this way, by
entering all forms of finitude, it is compelled to make itself finite, and
although it itself always remains ideal, nevertheless to involve itself
(ideally) with the ruling necessity in the territory of being or of the
Real. From this relationship between knowledge which is infinite in
itself and something finite to which it relates, the whole system of nec¬
essary ideas (Vorstellungen) and of concepts according to which the ob¬
jective world determines itself to human consciousness was deduced;
the really cognitive or theoretical side of human consciousness was
developed here; the whole, albeit corrected, content of the Kantian
critique of reason, or what in this critique was the content of the
whole theoretical philosophy, was taken up here, but as the content of
just one moment, into the whole system. But the basis of a new in-
126 On the History of Modern Philosophy
higher than human freedom; duty itself could not command him,
once it has decided, to be quiet about the consequences, of his action
if he could not be aware that his action admittedly depends upon him¬
self, upon his freedom, but that the consequences or what develops
from this action for his whole species depend upon something else
and something higher, which implements and asserts a higher lawful¬
ness through the most free, indeed most lawless way of behaving of
the individual.
Without this presupposition a human being would never be in¬
spired by a courage which is wholly unconcerned about the conse¬
quences of its action to do what duty commands; without this
presupposition a person could never dare to undertake an action with
great consequences, even if it were dictated to him by the most sacred
duty. Here, then, a necessity is demanded for history itself which still
persists and asserts itself even against moral freedom, which, there¬
fore, cannot be blind necessity (above which freedom certainly is ele¬
vated), which rather only mediates freedom with necessity because it
does not itself (like human freedom) come into conflict with necessity,
and remains not just relatively but absolutely free in relation to neces¬
sity, which always remains Providence, thus at all times and in relation
to everything remains subject - pure, free, disinterested and therefore
truly infinite subject. Here, then, philosophy came to that last subject
which was victorious over everything, which itself no longer becomes
objective, but instead always remains subject, and which man can no
longer recognise, as he could in knowledge, as himself, but instead as
above himself and for precisely that reason as above everything, to
which finally everything is subordinated and which now, not as at the
first beginning, just is spirit and Providence, but also declares itself to
be Providence, and shows at the end what already was at the begin¬
ning. The last task could now only be to show the relationship of this
subject, whose nature is inaccessible and which lives as if in an inac¬
cessible light - because it cannot become an object - to human con¬
sciousness; for it had to have some relationship or other to this consciousness.
But as it has already been said that it itself could at no time and via no
further progression become an object, but rather remains as ruling
over everything, then no further relationship to human consciousness
can be thought than that of simple manifestation. For as it itself no
longer becomes, or can become, an object, one can only say that it
manifests itself. The question is, then, whether such manifestations
or, to use a Leibnizian expression which might be used more appro¬
priately here, whether such fulgurations of the Highest which is ele¬
vated above everything can be demonstrated in human consciousness,
appearances in which the human self behaves as tool or organ of the
128 On the History of Modern Philosophy
Highest; for that which just manifests itself does not act (wirkt) di¬
rectly, but rather only acts through an other. (Thus in the whole line
of progression.) Now we must remember that the highest subject is
admittedly in itself only One, but in relation to the two sides of the
universe which now stands completed before us it can be thought in
three forms; for it is, precisely because it is the Highest, and because
everything is beneath it, just as much the Last, that which finally brings
forth nature, the real world, as it is Lord of the spiritual, of the ideal
world, and again is that which mediates both and grasps both as one
beneath itself. As that which brings forth, it will now manifest itself in
man by a bringing forth, by real production; it will show itself (1) as
that which has the power over material, over matter to overcome it
and compel it to be the expression of spirit, indeed of the highest
ideas themselves — fine art just as fine art goes this far, but (2) in Po¬
etry (Poesie), which is presupposed by fine art and to which the former
itself only relates as a tool, in Poetry it will manifest itself as spirit itself
which has the power to bring forth or create the material as well.
The highest truth and excellence of the plastic work of art does not
just consist in the correspondence with the created being or the
model of the created being, but rather in the fact that the spirit of
nature itself appears to have brought it forth; in it an activity is re¬
vealed, therefore, which is itself not of the kind which is created but
rather in which one thinks one is seeing the creator. In the highest
work, Poetry united with art — in the highest work of Poetic art (Dicht-
kunst), tragedy, there appears, in the storms of passions which blindly
rage against each other, where for the actors themselves the voice of
reason goes silent, and despotism and lawlessness, entangling each
other ever more deeply, finally transform themselves into a hideous
necessity — in the midst of all these movements there appears the
spirit of the Poet as the quiet light which alone still shines, as the sub¬
ject which alone is not submerged, itself unmoving in the most violent
movement, as wise Providence which can yet lead the greatest con¬
tradictions finally to a satisfactory conclusion.
Here, the Highest manifests itself as the genius of art. If art is the
most objective side of human activity, then religion is the subjective
side of it, to the extent that the latter does not, unlike the former,
move towards positing a being (Seyn), but rather, in relation to that
highest subject, towards positing all beings as not being (alles Seyende
als nicht seyend). Here, then, the highest subject reveals itself precisely
as that in relation to which everything sinks into nothingness; it re¬
veals itself as such in the enthusiasm of those ethical-religious heroes
through which humankind itself appears as glorified and divine.
There is a third human activity which unites in itself the objectivity
(1das Objektive) of art and the subjectivity (das Subjektive) (or the subor-
The Philosophy of Nature (Naturphilosophie) 129
change effected by Kant, from which point the spirit it had awakened
successively had to take hold of all the sciences and the whole of
learning. Herder as well deserves to be mentioned among the genii
who prepared this new spiritual movement, in part without knowing
it or willing it.
How did it happen, then, that in the form in which it at first exer¬
cised an almost universal power of attraction, this philosophy never¬
theless saw itself inhibited in its effect not long afterwards, revealed a
repelling pole which was less noticed at the beginning? It was not the
largely senseless and unjust attacks that it was exposed to from many
sides, to which belonged, e.g., the trivial, the ordinary view that it was
Spinozism, Pantheism - it was not these attacks that could really in¬
hibit it; it was rather a misunderstanding in which it found itself in
relation to itself by showing itself as something, or (one could rather
say) by letting itself be seen as something that it was not, which, ac¬
cording to the original thought, it was not supposed to be.
To explain this I must go back somewhat further.
The point at which every philosophy will find itself either in agree¬
ment or in conflict with common human consciousness lies in the man¬
ner in which it explains the Highest, explains God. What position did
God have in the philosophy just presented? Initially the position of a
mere result, of the highest and last thought which brings everything to
a conclusion — completely in accordance with the position which He
also had in previous metaphysics, and which Kant as well, for whom
God was just the necessary thought for the formal conclusion of hu¬
man knowledge, had left to Him. In the system just presented, God
was that subject which finally came to rest victoriously above every¬
thing, as subject which can no longer sink down into being an object;
it was this subject which had gone through the whole of nature,
through the whole of history, through the sequence of all the mo¬
ments of which it seemed only the last result, and this going-through
was thought of as a real movement (not as a progression in thought
alone), it was even thought of as a real process. Now I can indeed
think of God as the end and just the result of my thinking, as He was
in the old metaphysics, but I cannot think of Him as result of an ob¬
jective process; furthermore, this God which was assumed as result
could, if He is God, not have something outside Himself (praeter se), He
could at the most have Himself as presupposition; but in that presen¬
tation He really does have the earlier moments of the development as
His presupposition. From this - from the last moment, it follows that
this God must after all be determined at the end as He also was al¬
ready at the beginning, therefore that the subject which goes through
the whole process is already God at the beginning and during the pro-
The Philosophy of Nature (Naturphilosophie)
133
cess, before it is also posited in the result as God - that in this sense
God is admittedly everything, that the subject going through nature is
also God, only not as God — thus God only outside His divinity or in
His externalisation (Entausserung) or in His otherness (Anderheit), as
an other of Himself as which He only is at the end. But again, if this
is assumed, then the following difficulties reveal themselves. God is
obviously in part involved in a process, and in order precisely to be at
least as God, is subjected to a Becoming, which offends the received
concepts too much ever to be able to rely on general consent. But phi¬
losophy is only philosophy in order to sustain universal understand¬
ing, conviction and thus also universal agreement, and everyone who
sets up a philosophical doctrine makes this claim. One can admittedly
say: “God exposes Himself to this Becoming precisely in order to
posit Himself as such”, and one really must say this. But as soon as this
is said, one can also see that one must immediately either assume a
time when God was not as such (but this again contradicts general re¬
ligious consciousness), or one denies that there ever was such a time,
i.e. that movement, that happening is explained as an eternal happen¬
ing. But an eternal happening is no happening at all. Consequently
the whole idea of that process and of that movement is itself illusory,
nothing has really happened, everything happened only in thoughts
and this whole movement was only a movement of thinking. That phi¬
losophy should have grasped this; it put itself beyond all contradiction
thereby, but precisely because of this it also gave up its claim to ob¬
jectivity, i.e. it had to confess to being a science in which there is no
question of existence, of that which really exists, and thus also not at all
of knowledge in this sense, but only of the relationships which the ob¬
jects take on in mere thinking, and since existence is always the Posi¬
tive, namely that which is posited, affirmed, asserted, then it had to
confess to being a purely negative philosophy, but precisely thereby had
to leave space free outside itself for the philosophy which relates to
existence, i.e. for the positive philosophy; it had not to present itself as
the absolute philosophy, as the philosophy which leaves nothing out¬
side itself. It took some time before philosophy became clear to itself
about this, for all progressions in philosophy only happen slowly.
Which meant, by the way, that that period of time was considerably
lengthened, was an episode which opposed this last development, and
about which at least what is necessary should also be mentioned.
Hegel
The philosophy which has just been presented, which could rely on
universal assent if it presented itself as a science of thought or of rea¬
son and presented God, whom it reached at the end, as the merely
logical result of its earlier mediations, acquired, by assuming the ap¬
pearance of the opposite, a completely false reputation which even
contradicted its original thought (hence the changeable and very var¬
ious judgements that were expressed about it were quite natural).
Now one might hope that this philosophy really would withdraw to
within this boundary, would declare itself as negative, merely as log¬
ical philosophy when Hegel established precisely as the first demand
on philosophy that it should withdraw into pure thinking, and that it
should have as sole immediate object the pure concept. Hegel cannot
be denied the credit for having seen the merely logical nature of the
philosophy which he intended to work on and promised to bring to its
complete form. If he had stuck to that and if he had carried out this
thought by strictly, decisively renouncing everything positive, then he
would have brought about the decisive transition to the positive phi¬
losophy, for the Negative, the negative pole can never be there in
pure form without immediately calling for the positive pole. But that
withdrawal to pure thought, to the pure concept, was, as one can find
stated on the very first pages of Hegel’s Logic, linked to the claim that
the concept was everything and left nothing outside itself. Hegel’s own
words are the following: “The method is only the movement of the
concept itself, but in the sense that the concept is everything and its
movement is the universal absolute activity. The method is, therefore,
the infinite power of knowing” (here, according to this, after it was up
to then just a question of thinking and of the concept, suddenly the
claim to cognition {Erkennen) comes in. But cognition is the Positive
and only has being (das Seyende), reality (das Wirkliche), as its object,
whereas thinking just has the possible, and thus also only has what
can be known {das Erkennbare) and not what is known {das Erkannte)
34
Hegel
*35
as its object) — “the method is, therefore, the infinite power of know¬
ing to which no object, to the extent to which it presents itself as ex¬
ternal, distant from reason and independent of reason, can put up
any resistance”.
1 he proposition: “1 he movement of the concept is the universal
absolute activity” leaves nothing left for God other than the move¬
ment of the concept, i.e. than for Himself to be only the concept. The
concept does not have the meaning here of just the concept (Hegel
protests most vigorously against this), but instead the meaning of the
thing itself {Sache selbst), and in the same way as the Zoroastrians say
that the true creator is time, one admittedly cannot reproach Hegel
with holding the opinion that God is just a concept; his opinion is
rather: the true creator is the concept; with the concept one has the
creator and needs no other outside this creator.
What Hegel primarily sought to avoid was precisely that God, as, of
course, it could not be otherwise within a logical philosophy, should
be posited only in the concept. For him God was not both just a con¬
cept and the concept God; for him the concept had the meaning that
it was God. His opinion is: God is nothing but the concept which step
by step becomes the self-conscious Idea {Idee), as self-conscious Idea
releases itself into nature, and, returning from nature into itself, be¬
comes absolute spirit.
Hegel is so little inclined to recognise his philosophy as the merely
negative philosophy that he asserts instead that it is the philosophy
which leaves absolutely nothing outside itself; his philosophy at¬
tributes to itself the most objective meaning and, in particular, a
wholly complete knowledge (Erkenntnis) of God and of divine things -
the knowledge which Kant denied to philosophy is supposedly
achieved by his philosophy. Indeed he even goes so far as to attribute
a knowledge of Christian dogmas to his philosophy; in this respect his
presentation of the doctrine of the Trinity is the most informative,
which is briefly as follows. God the Father, before the Creation, is the
purely logical concept which loses its way in the pure categories of be¬
ing (Seyn). But this God must reveal Himself, because His essence con¬
sists in a necessary process; this revelation or externalisation of
Himself is the world, and God is the Son. But God must also negate
(aufheben) this externalisation as well (which is a stepping outside of
the merely logical - Hegel so little recognised the merely logical char¬
acter of the whole of this philosophy that he declared he was stepping
outside it with the Naturphilosophie) - God must also negate this ex¬
ternalisation, this negation of his merely logical being {Seyn) as well,
and return to Himself, which happens through the human spirit in
136 On the History of Modern Philosophy
wanted to establish the same system overall and in the main question
(in der Hauptsache). Here, though, he is faced with determining that
which is most objective as the negation of everything subjective, as
pure being, i.e. (how else can one understand it?) as being in which
there is nothing subjective (nichts von einem Subjekt). For the fact that
he does, by the way, attribute a movement, a transition into another
concept to this pure being, indeed attributes to it an inner restlessness
which drives it on to further determinations, does not prove that he
nevertheless thinks a subject in pure being, it only proves something
or other of which it can only be said that is not not, or is not nothing
at all, but in no way proves that it already is something — if this were
his thought, the progression would have to be completely different.
The fact that he nevertheless attributes an immanent movement to
pure being means no more, then, than that the thought which begins
with pure being feels it is impossible for it to stop at this most abstract
and most empty thing of all, which Hegel himself declares is pure be¬
ing. The compulsion to move on from this has its basis only in the fact
that thought is already used to a more concrete being, a being more
full of content, and thus cannot be satisfied with that meagre diet of
pure being in which only content in the abstract but no determinate
content is thought; in the last analysis, then, what does not allow him
to remain with that empty abstraction is only the fact that there really
is a more rich being which is more full of content, and the fact that the
thinking spirit itself is already such a being, thus the fact that it is not
a necessity which lies in the concept itself, but rather a necessity which
lies in the philosopher and which is imposed upon him by his mem¬
ory. Thus it is really always only the thought which first seeks to with¬
draw to the most minimal content possible, but then seeks again
successively to fulfil itself, seeks to get to a content, and finally to the
complete content of the world and of consciousness - admittedly, as
Hegel professes, not in a random, but rather in a necessary progres¬
sion; but what always tacitly leads this progression is always the termi¬
nus ad quem, the real world, at which science finally is to arrive; but at
any time it is only what we have understood of it that we call the real
world, and Hegel’s own philosophy shows how many sides of this real
world he has not grasped; thus contingency (Zufall) cannot be excluded
from the progression, namely what is contingent about the more nar¬
row or broader individual views of the world of the philosophising
subject. Thus there is a double deception in this supposedly necessary
movement: (1) by the thought being substituted for by the concept, and
by the latter being conceived of as something which moves itself, when
the concept for its own part would lie completely immobile if it were
not the concept of a thinking subject, i.e. if it were not thought
Hegel
*39
the present point of view - still nothing”. But in the same way as in
the beginning, the non-being of the thing of which it is the beginning
is only the not yet real (wirklich) being of the thing, though not its com¬
plete non-being, but certainly also its being, admittedly not its being
in an indeterminate manner, as Hegel puts it, but its possible, its po¬
tential being, then the proposition: “Pure being is still (noch) nothing”
would just mean: “It is not yet (noch nicht) real being”. But precisely
thereby it would become itself determinate and no longer being in
general, but rather determinate being, namely being in potentid. How¬
ever, with that interpolated yet, something to come which has yet to be
is already promised, and with the help of this yet Hegel gets to becom¬
ing, of which he says in a very indeterminate manner that it is the
unity or unification of nothing and being - (one ought rather to say
that it is the transition from nothing, from not yet being, to real be¬
ing, so that, in becoming, nothing and being are not united but in¬
stead nothing is left behind. However, Hegel loves this inexact way of
expressing himself; but that way the most trivial things can be given
the appearance of something extraordinary).
One cannot really contradict these propositions, or declare them to
be false; for they are, rather, propositions that give one nothing. It is
as if one wanted to carry water in cupped hands, which also gives one
nothing. The work of just holding onto something which cannot be
held onto because it is not anything here replaces philosophising. One
can say the same thing about all of Hegel’s philosophy. One ought re¬
ally not to talk about it at all, because it is characteristic of it that in
many cases it consists of just such incomplete thoughts which cannot
even be held onto for long enough for a judgement about them to be
possible. However, Hegel does not arrive in the manner indicated at
some kind of determinate becoming, but rather only at the concept of
becoming in general, whereby again nothing is given. But this becom¬
ing immediately divides itself up for him into moments, so that he
moves over in this way to the category of quantity, and thus in general
to the Kantian table of categories.
The moments which have been presented thus far: pure being,
nothing, becoming are now the beginnings of the Logic, which Hegel
declares to be the purely speculative philosophy, specifying that here
the Idea is for the time being still enclosed in thought, or that the
Absolute is still enclosed in its eternity (the Idea and the Absolute are,
according to this, treated as synonymous, in the same way as thought,
because it is wholly atemporal, is regarded as identical with eternity).
Because it has to present the pure divine idea as it is before all time or
to the extent to which it is still just in thought, the Logic is in this sense
subjective science, the Idea is still just posited as Idea, and not also as
142 On the History of Modern Philosophy
which it had had in the Wolffian philosophy for example, where the
various categories were set up and dealt with in a more or less just
coincidental, more or less indifferent, juxtaposition and succession.
He sought to bring about this elevation by applying a method which
was invented for a completely different purpose, for real potentials, to
mere concepts, into which he in vain sought to breathe a life, an inner
compulsion to progression. One can see that there is nothing original
in this; the method would never have been invented for this purpose.
It is something which is only applied artificially and forcibly in this
case. But going back to this ontology at all was a retrograde step.
In Hegel’s Logic one finds every concept which just happened to be
accessible and available at his time taken up as a moment of the ab¬
solute Idea at a specific point. Linked to this is the pretension to com¬
plete systematisation, i.e. the claim that all concepts have been
included and that outside the circle of those that have been included
no other concept is possible. But what if concepts can be shown which
that system knows nothing about, or which it was only able to take up
into itself in a completely different sense from their real sense? In¬
stead of an impartial system which takes up everything with the same
fairness, we will have only a partial system before us that has only
taken up concepts of this kind, or has only taken up the ones it has
done in the sense in which they are compatible with the system once
the system has been presupposed. In the places where the system
comes to the concepts which are higher and thus more familiar to
people, to moral and religious concepts, at least, he has long since
been reproached with completely arbitrary manipulation of these
concepts.
One might like to ask where earlier philosophy had a location or a
place for concepts as concepts. One might think it has even been
claimed that this philosophy has no place for logic, for universal cat¬
egories, for concepts as such. It admittedly did not have a place for
concepts which still have the real (das Reale) outside themselves, for it
was, as was said, with its first steps in nature; but it progressed in na¬
ture to the point where the subject (the I), which has gone through
the whole of nature, has now come to itself, now possesses itself, ad¬
mittedly no longer finds the earlier moments themselves which have
been left behind in nature, but instead the concepts of these mo¬
ments, and it finds them as concepts with which consciousness can
now do as it pleases and apply in every direction, as it would with
something it owns which is completely independent of things. In this
way Hegel could at least be aware of the place in the system where the
world of concepts, in all its multiplicity and systematically complete
analysis, enters into the whole; he could even see the forms of what is
Hegel
l45
* Translator’s note: These are discussed in chapter 3 of “The Subjective Logic of the
Doctrine of the Concept” in Hegel’s Science of Logic.
146 On the History of Modern Philosophy
not assessed the system itself. And whoever in particular only takes to
the field against individual points of this Logic may not be wrong, and
may show much astuteness and correct insight in doing so, but in re¬
lation to the whole nothing is won thereby. I myself believe that one
could easily produce this so-called real logic in ten different ways. Yet
I do not for this reason underestimate the value of many uncom¬
monly clever, particularly methodological remarks which are to be
found in Hegel’s Logic. But Hegel threw himself into the methodolog¬
ical discussion in such a way that he thereby completely forgot the
questions which lay outside it.
I now turn to the system as such and will also, in doing so, not leave
unanswered the criticisms of the preceding system made by Hegel.
Although the concept cannot be the sole content of thought, what
Hegel asserts might at least remain true; that logic, in the metaphys¬
ical sense which he gives it, must be the real basts of all philosophy.
What Hegel so often emphasises might for this reason be true after
all: that everything that is is in the Idea or in the logical concept, and
that as a consequence the Idea is the truth of everything, into which
at the same time everything goes as into its beginning and into its
end. As far as this constantly repeated conception is concerned, it
might be admitted that everything is in the logical Idea, and indeed in
such a way that it could not be outside it, because what is senseless re¬
ally cannot ever exist anywhere. But in this way what is logical also
presents itself as the merely negative aspect of existence, as that with¬
out which nothing could exist, from which, however, it by no means
follows that everything only exists via what is logical. Everything can
be in the logical Idea without anything being explained thereby, as, for
example, everything in the sensuous world is grasped in number and
measure, which does not therefore mean that geometry or arithmetic
explain the sensuous world. The whole world lies, so to speak, in the
nets of the understanding or of reason, but the question is how exactly
it got into those nets, since there is obviously something other and
something more than mere reason in the world, indeed there is some¬
thing which strives beyond these barriers.
The main intention of the Hegelian Logic, and the one on which it
primarily prides itself, is that it should take on in its last result the
meaning of speculative theology, i.e. that it should be a real (eigentlich)
construction of the Idea of God, and that, accordingly, this Idea
or the Absolute should not just be a presupposition in it, as it was in
the immediately preceding system, but rather essentially a result. A
double reproach is made to earlier philosophy thereby: (1) it has the
Absolute merely as an unfounded presupposition instead of as a
founded result; (2) it thereby has a presupposition at all, whilst the
148 On the History of Modern Philosophy
that the truly first definition of the Absolute is “The Absolute is pure
being”, I might say: “The truly first definition of the Absolute is that
it is subject”. Only to the extent to which this subject must at the same
time also be thought in the possibility of its becoming object (=
subject deprived of itself) ((= entselbstetes Subjekt)), did I also call it the
absolute indifference of subject and object, in the same way as I later,
because it is already being thought in the actus, called it living, eter¬
nally moving and non-negatable identity of the subjective and the ob¬
jective. In the earlier system the Absolute is, then, not in any other
way a presupposition and only a presupposition in the way that in He¬
gel’s system pure being is a presupposition, about which he also does in
fact say: it is the first concept of the Absolute. But the Absolute is ad¬
mittedly not just a beginning or a mere presupposition, it is just as
much also a conclusion and in this sense a result - namely the Abso¬
lute in its completion. But the Absolute determined in this way, the
Absolute to the extent to which it now already has all moments of be¬
ing beneath and relatively outside itself, and as spirit which can no
longer descend into being, into becoming, i.e. as spirit which is and
remains — this Absolute is just as much end or result for the earlier sys¬
tem. The difference between the Hegelian and the earlier system as
far as the Absolute is concerned is only this. The earlier system does
not have a double becoming, a logical one and a real one, but, starting
out from the abstract subject, from the subject in its abstraction, it is
in nature with the first step, and it does not afterwards need a further
explanation of the transition from the logical into the real. Hegel, on
the other hand, declares his Logic to be that science in which the di¬
vine Idea logically completes itself, i.e. in mere thinking, before all re¬
ality, nature and time; here, then, he already has the completed
divine Idea as a logical result, but he wants immediately afterwards to
have it again (namely after it has gone through nature and the spir¬
itual world) as a real result. In this way Hegel admittedly has some¬
thing over the earlier system, namely, as was said, the double
becoming. But if the Logic is the science in which the divine Idea
completes itself merely in thinking, then one would have to expect that
philosophy would not be closed, or if it were to progress further the
progress could only be in a wholly different science, in which it is no
longer just a question of the Idea, as it is in the first science. For He¬
gel, however, the Logic is only a part of philosophy, the Idea has log¬
ically completed itself, and now the same Idea is supposed to
complete itself in reality. For it is the Idea which makes the transition
into nature. Before I talk about this transition, I want to mention an¬
other criticism of the identity system which has been made on the
part of Hegel. Namely, the reproach just touched upon (in the pre-
150 On the History of Modern Philosophy
'Journal of Speculative Physics, vol. 2, no. 2. [Translator’s note: 1/4 pp. 105ft.)
* “On the True Concept of Naturphilosophie”, Journal of Speculative Physics, vol. 2, no.
1, 1801. This treatise might also show that the author was aware of his method, as
well as of the contradiction which is posited in the first concept and is compelled
to progress-an awareness which some would have liked to deny that he pos¬
sessed. [Translator’s note: The citation is to 1/4 pp. 79ft.)
Hegel
l5'
1 Because the identity philosophy concerned itself with the pure what of things,
without saying anything about real existence, it could only in this sense call itself
absolute Idealism, as opposed to merely relative Idealism, which denies the existence
of external things (for the latter still always keeps a relationship to existence). The
science of reason is absolute Idealism to the extent that it does not take up the
question of existence at all.
152 On the History of Modern Philosophy
I note that in that (first) Presentation of the Identity System the term
“the Absolute” did not occur at all, just as little as did “intellectual in¬
tuition”; the term could not occur in it, because the Presentation was not
brought to a conclusion. For that philosophy called the Absolute only
the potential which remained with itself, which existed, and was acquit¬
ted of all progression and further becoming-other. This was the Last,
was pure result. That philosophy did not call that which went through
the whole “the Absolute” but instead called it “absolute identity”, pre¬
cisely in order to remove every thought of a substrate, of a substance.
It becomes a substance, a being (zum Seyenden wird), precisely only at
the last moment, for the whole movement only intended to have be¬
ing (das Seyende) (that which is) as being (als das Seyende), which was
impossible at the beginning, which for that very reason was called in¬
difference. Before that it is not something of which I have a concept,
but is itself only the concept of all being (alles Seyenden) as something
which is to come. It is that which never was, which, as soon as it is
thought, disappears and Is only ever in what is to come, but is only in
a certain manner there as well, thus Is only really in the end. There,
then, it also first assumes the name of being (des Seyenden) as well as
that of the Absolute. The (first) Presentation had for that reason very
deliberately used nothing but abstract expressions such as “absolute
indifference”, “absolute identity”, only in later presentations did one
also allow oneself, perhaps out of a sort of condescension to those who
absolutely demanded a substrate, to use the expression “the Abso¬
lute” right at the beginning.
But in rejecting intellectual intuition in the sense in which Hegel
wants to attribute it to me, it does not follow that it did not have an¬
other sense for me, and that I do now still hold onto it in this sense.
1 hat which is absolutely mobile, of which I just spoke, which is con¬
tinually an other, which cannot be held onto for a moment, which is
only really thought in the last moment (take good note of this expres¬
sion!) — how does this relate to thought? Obviously not even as a real
object of thought; for by “object” one understands something which
keeps still, which stands still, which remains. It is not really an object,
but rather the mere material of thought throughout the whole sci¬
ence; for real thought expresses itself precisely only in the continual
determination and formation of this which is in itself indeterminate,
of this which is never the same as itself, which always becomes an
other. This first basis, this true prima materia of all thought, cannot,
therefore, be what is really thought, not be what is thought in the
sense that the single formation is. When thought is concerned with
the determination of this matter, it does not think about this substrate
(Unterlage) itself, but rather only of the determination of the concept
Hegel
*53
Encyclopedia §191, 1st ed. (§244, 2nd ed.). [Translator’s note: Schelling’s quotation
from the Encyclopedia is inaccurate. The passage in question goes as follows: “But
the absolute/rm/om of the Idea is that it does not just pass over into life, nor that it
makes life appear in itself as finite cognition, but, rather, that in the absolute truth
of itself it resolves Ireely to release the moment of its particularity or of the first de¬
termination and being-other, the immediate Idea as its reflection, as nature, from it¬
self' (Hegel, 1959 p. 197).]
Hegel
*55
mem) - the Idea in the infinite freedom, in the “truth of itself, resolves
to release itself as nature, or in the form of being-other, from itself”.
This expression “release” - the Idea releases nature - is one of the
strangest, most ambiguous and thus also timid expressions behind
which this philosophy retreats at difficult points. Jacob Bohme says:
divine freedom vomits itself into nature. Hegel says: divine freedom
releases nature. What is one to think in this notion of releasing? This
much is clear: the biggest compliment one can pay this notion is to
call it “theosophical”. Besides, anyone who was still able to doubt that
the Idea at the end of the Logic was meant as the really existing Idea
would now have to convince themselves of this fact; for that which is
supposed freely to decide must be something which really exists,
something that is just a concept cannot decide. It is a very awkward
point at which Hegel’s philosophy has arrived here, which was not
foreseen at the beginning of the Logic, a nasty broad ditch, the dem¬
onstration of which (it was mentioned in a few words for the first time
in the Preface to Cousin) has admittedly had much bad blood, but has
not had any at all useful and not merely deceptive information what¬
soever as a consequence.*
Now one can, it is true, not understand at all what should motivate
nature, after it has elevated itself to being the highest subject, and has
completely eaten up being (Seyn), to make itself subjectless again after
all, to reduce itself to mere being (Seyn) and to let itself disintegrate
into the bad externality of space and time. However, the Idea has now
thrown itself into nature, not in order to remain in matter, but rather
in order, through matter, to become spirit again, initially to become
human spirit. But the human spirit is only the scene on which spirit in
general again works off, by its own activity, alone, the subjectivity
which it has taken on in human spirit, and makes itself in this way into
absolute spirit, which finally takes up all moments of the movement
into itself as its own, and is God.
Here as well we will best capture the peculiarity of the system if we
see what relationship it gives itself to the immediately preceding phi¬
losophy in view of this Last and Highest. The preceding philosophy is
reproached with the fact that in it God is supposed to have been de¬
termined not as spirit but only as substance. By Christianity and by
the catechism everyone is admittedly instructed not only to think of
God as spirit but to wish and mean Him as spirit; in this way nobody
will be able to claim that they have discovered that God is spirit. It
cannot be meant in this way either. I do not in fact wish to enter into
' §472.
* P 43, 1832 edition. [Translator’s note: Hegel 1969, vol. 1, p. 70.]
H The First edition of the Logic of 1812 (p. 9) stated: “Thus spirit will also externalise
itself with freedom at the end of the development of pure knowledge, and release
itself into the form of an immediate consciousness, as consciousness of a being
which stands opposite it as an other”.
i58 On the History of Modern Philosophy
A general saying of Hegel’s is: man should be taken beyond mere rep¬
resentation (Vorstellung) by philosophy. If one understands by “repre¬
sentation” that in us which relates to the present (vorhanden) object as
present, then no one will disagree with this saying. For philosophy
should accept nothing as present — and should not, for example, reflect
only on the given. But if this “taking beyond” is meant absolutely,
then the saying is only a petitio principii, because it is presupposed as
self-evident that the higher relationships through which the world be¬
comes comprehensible cannot also be introduced into representation
and made plausible to it, but instead that they are above all represen¬
tation, or, conversely, that whatever is assumed about these relation¬
ships within the sphere of representation must in itself and already
because it is within the sphere of representation be contrary to rea¬
son. Admittedly, if one has first presupposed that those higher rela¬
tionships must be above all representation (a presupposition which
most people are encumbered with when they come to philosophy),
then one must oneself in fact seek an unnatural philosophy. But the
highest triumph of science would be precisely to lead down into the
realm of representation that which can only be known by raising one¬
self above representation, which is therefore for itself not accessible to
mere representation, but rather only to pure thinking. Thus the Co-
pernican world system could not be established without driving the
world beyond mere representation and without offending mere rep¬
resentation, and it was initially a system which was highly unpopular
and which contradicted all representations. But the same system,
when it is fully developed and even the representation of the move¬
ment of the sun around the earth is made comprehensible by it, rec¬
onciles mere representation with itself and becomes as clear to
representation as the opposite representatiori was, and on the con¬
trary the latter now appears to representation as confused and un¬
clear. This philosophy boasts of presupposing nothing, but this is not
the case: if one looks at its ground, at that which it does not say, but
quietly presupposes, and which is for this reason difficult to recog¬
nise, then one finds as this last basis, which has its effects throughout,
* Translator’s note: Schelling moved to Erlangen in 1820 and began lecturing there
in 1821. It is not clear how many semesters he actually lectured in Erlangen, but
it is clear that ideas on the history of modern philosophy which found their way
into the Lectures were already being developed in this period: hence the son’s ad¬
dition of this passage. See my discussion of the Erlangen Initia Philosophiae Uni-
versae in the Introduction, and the more extensive discussion in Bowie 1993,
chapter 6, pp. 130-40.
162 On the History of Modern Philosophy
the maxims of the most comfortable rationalism, which are valid for
it as self-evident foundations that supposedly nobody has ever
doubted or could doubt. Precisely what Kant assumes as only proven
for dogmatism, Hegel assumes as absolutely and universally proven.
But whoever wants to raise himself above all natural concepts with the
excuse that they are merely finite determinations of the understand¬
ing even deprives himself thereby of all organs of comprehensibility,
for only in these forms can everything become comprehensible to us.
The mistake which Kant showed up in the application of these forms
of understanding lies in the fact that it was a mere application of con¬
cepts to objects which were already presupposed independently of the
concepts — and these objects were really objects, i.e. things opposed to
the understanding; the mistake lies also in the fact that the concepts
and the objects did not arise together, which meant that a mere phi¬
losophy of reflection had to arise and all living creation of science was
made impossible. But there is a great difference between the rejection
of a mistaken application of these concepts and a complete exclusion of
them, whereby all comprehensible debate is made impossible at the
same time. Whence the conspicuous narrow-chestedness of this phi¬
losophy, which means that it cannot speak openly and express itself
and it is as though breath and voice have been taken from it, so that
it can only murmur incomprehensible words. People complain about
the incomprehensibility of this philosophy and seem to seek the rea¬
son for this in a failing on the part of the individual, whereby one is,
for example, being unfair to Hegel, who, when he comes out of his
confinement or Speaks of matters which are closer to life, certainly
knows how to express himself very decisively, very comprehensibly, in¬
deed very wittily. The incomprehensibility lies in the thing itself (in
der Sache selbstp, what is above all understanding can never become
comprehensible; if it were supposed to become comprehensible it
would first have to change its nature. It is a very bad objection to a
philosopher to say that he is incomprehensible. Incomprehensibility
is a relative concept, and what the oft-praised Caius or Titius does not
understand is not therefore incomprehensible. Philosophy also has, it
must be said, certain things that by their very nature will always re¬
main incomprehensible to many people. But it is something quite dif¬
ferent if the incomprehensibility lies in the thing itself. It often
happens that thinkers, who set out to solve mechanical tasks with a lot
of practice and skill but without real capacity for invention, who, e.g.,
set out to invent a machine for spinning flax — succeed in making one,
but the mechanism is so difficult and overly complex or the wheels
grate so much that one prefers to go back to the old method of spin¬
ning flax by hand. It can be like this in philosophy too. The pain of
Hegel 163
ignorance about the first, about the greatest matters is great and can
become unbearable for every person who feels and is not.mindless or
narrowly self-sufficient. But if the torment of an unnatural system is
greater than the burden of ignorance, then one prefers still to carry
the latter. One has the right to assume that the task of philosophy as
well, if it can be solved at all, must finally be unlocked in a few great
and simple moves, and that it should not be the case that, in the great¬
est human task of all places, the invention which one acknowledges in
all lesser tasks should have no validity.
Jacobi and Theosophy
JACOBI
164
Jacobi and Theosophy
65
the arms of the most empty rationalism, not that rationalism which
had achieved such an advanced development in philosophy and
which boasted that reason recognised itself in it, but rather into
the arms of that meagre, merely subjective rationalism in which the
main content of what was generally called Enlightenment really con¬
sists, whereby he fell out of the company of Spinoza, Leibniz and
other great spirits of an earlier time, ending on the same line
as, and in the company of the most abject philosophical mediocrity.
His remarks about Christ and Christianity in his later writings are
completely in agreement with the views of the most rabid theological
rationalism.
By this final result of his philosophy Jacobi became very unlike two
men who had had great influence on his education, and whom it
would be wrong to overlook in this historical development.
One of these men is Pascal. Whoever is still seeking, whoever de¬
mands a measure of how comprehensible and understandable a truly
historical philosophy must become, should read Pascal’s Pensees. Who¬
ever has not already irretrievably lost all sense of what is natural and
healthy via the unnaturalness of some other philosophy will come via
an attentive reading of Pascal’s thoughts to think of the idea of a his¬
torical system, at least in a general way.
The other of these men is Johann Georg Hamann [1730-1788],
whose now collected writings, which were previously scattered like
sibylline pages and were not easy to obtain, are without any question
the most important enrichment the literature of recent times has re¬
ceived; I do not say this with the direct intention of recommending
the writings to you; one requires extensive erudition to understand
their numerous allusions, deeper experience to grasp them in their
full significance; they are not reading matter for youths, but rather
for men, writings which a man should never put down, which he
should constantly regard as the touchstone of his own understand¬
ing - Hamann, whom Jacobi judged to be a true Jtav [universe] of
consistency and inconsistency (Gereimtheit und Ungerevntheit), light and
darkness, spiritualism and materialism.
Hamann did not have a system and did not establish one either; but
anyone who was aware of a whole which combined in one understand¬
ing all the various and disparate sayings, the consistent and the ap¬
parently inconsistent, the most free and, on the other hand, the
crassly orthodox statements of Hamann, that person would have the
right, in so far as any person may think he understands something, to
say to himself that he had achieved some insight. Philosophy really is a
deep science, a work of great experience; people without spiritual ex¬
perience, mere mechanics, cannot judge here, although they are free
Jacobi and Theosophy 169
damage to the really scientific education of our youth. One could al¬
most recognise in this determination given to reason only a misun¬
derstanding of the philosophy of the time, or an attempt to secure
itself against this philosophy by this adaptation to it. What was incon¬
sistent about it was that this God of an immediate knowledge of rea¬
son was not the universal substance but was supposed really to be the
personal God with all fullness of spiritual and moral qualities with
which common belief is used to think of Him. An immediate relation¬
ship to a personal being (Wesen) can, though, also only be a personal
one: I must deal with Him, be in a truly empirical relationship with
Him; but such an empirical relationship is just as excluded from rea¬
son as everything personal is excluded from it; it is supposed precisely
to be that which is impersonal. What reason immediately knows must
be just as free as itself of all empirical, and thus of all personal deter¬
minations. If God is already posited and known immediately with rea¬
son, then there is, of course, no need for mediating knowledge, i.e.
for a science, neither in order to get to the concept of God nor to con¬
vince oneself of His existence. There is no question that it was pre¬
cisely because of this exclusion of every personal relation to reason
that Jacobi had in his earlier writings and in his better period always
put “reason” which excludes everything empirical beneath “under¬
standing”. The fact that he had completely moved away from his first
wish and his initial goal is proven by the fact that in the complete edi¬
tion of his works which he arranged towards the end of his life, in all
the places where he had earlier put “reason” and had suggested its
negative character, he informs his readers that, instead of “reason”,
“understanding” should be read and instead of “understanding”,
“reason” should be read — in order thereby, as it were, to eradicate all
traces of his earlier better aspirations. For the fact that the under¬
standing, as he had earlier recognised, deserves first place in philos¬
ophy, reason the second, is clear precisely from the demand that
everything should be made comprehensible to reason, from which it
follows as a matter of course that reason is not that which originally
comprehends, that there is much that it originally does not compre¬
hend. If one does not wish to call that which makes clear to reason
everything which goes beyond its own immediate content, if one does
not wish to call this “understanding”, what, then, does one wish to call
it? God is known precisely only with the understanding, indeed only
the most highly developed understanding which has arrived at the
goal of thinking knows God. Reason only knows what is immediate,
that which cannot be; reason, is like the woman in the house, reliant
upon the substance, the otjoia, it must hold onto this in order that
prosperity and order should remain in the house, it is precisely that
Jacobi and Theosophy iyi
those delicate threads which swim in the air in late summer, incapable
both of reaching heaven and of touching the earth through their
own weight. Such an Indian summer of ideas is especially only to be
found in Jacobi’s thoughts, which are, incidentally, wittily and deli¬
cately expressed.
The end of the Jacobian philosophy is, then, universal non¬
knowledge. If Jacobi maintains that philosophy cannot grant precisely
what is most eagerly desired of it, namely an explanation of what lies
beyond the border of common experience, then he is in complete
agreement and harmony with rationalism, only differing by the fact
that he refers, in relation to everything which ought really to be the
highest prize of philosophy, to non-philosophy, to non-knowledge —
to feeling, to a certain vague idea, or else, particularly in his earlier
writings, to belief, for which he later substituted (because for a com¬
pletely rationalistic age belief is somewhat offensive) immediate
knowledge by reason, which, however, proved just as little able as feel¬
ing to be formed into science (contradiction) [i.e. the term “imme¬
diate knowledge by reason” excludes the possibility of theoretical
articulation]. The advice to refer people to belief in relation to every¬
thing really and truly positive was, by the way, not peculiar to Jaco¬
bian philosophy, it was always the usual thing to do: for the lack of
content of normal philosophy in relation to the rich content of Rev¬
elation always had to be evident. Since it is here a question of the re¬
lationship between knowledge and belief, I want to give my view
about this. One must make the following distinctions. (1) Those who
are indifferent to philosophy, or are even interested in philosophy’s
appearing deficient, cite precisely the fact that belief, by which,
though, they understand historical, Christian belief, contains what
philosophy does not contain and is incapable of containing. Knowl¬
edge and belief, or philosophy and belief, thereby remain outside each
other, like two separate areas, and one is quite able to grasp this op¬
position and can even see how it had to arise since the emancipation
of philosophy by Descartes. For from that point onwards philosophy
left the content of positive religion outside itself. (Descartes protests
in all his works that he does not wish to assert anything which is op¬
posed to the doctrine of the Church; on the other hand his aim is to get
the material of his philosophy completely by his own means. But since
philosophy - already accustomed since scholasticism only to presup¬
pose the positive content - now made itself completely independent
of it, it had naturally to move into the negative.) But it is (2) less com¬
prehensible if this difference between belief and knowledge is moved
into knowledge, into philosophy itself, so that both knowledge and be¬
lief are supposed to be philosophical, so that a philosophical knowl-
Jacobi and Theosophy !75
losophy of feeling, for example, can also be called mystical and has
been called it often enough; except that it is totally lacking in the sub¬
stantial content of really speculative mysticism. The same truth can,
then, be mystical to one person which is scientific to the other, and
vice versa. For to the person who expresses the truth on the basis of
a merely subjective feeling (Empfindung) or a supposed revelation, it is
mystical; to the person who derives the truth from the depths of sci¬
ence and hence alone truly understands it, it is scientific.
The true mark of mysticism is the hatred of clear knowledge (Ein-
sicht) - of understanding, which has received such a welcome predom¬
inance in our time - of science in general. But as not just mystics but
even many people who shout about and against mysticism are just as
much enemies of science as any mystic, then one would really have to
call them mystics themselves, if one did not prefer to declare them re¬
ally to be the true obscurantists.
On National Differences in Philosophy
186
On National Differences in Philosophy 187
off somebody is who stops at Kant than someone who stops even ear¬
lier at Locke and Condillac. For Locke wrote an Essay on Human Un¬
derstanding, Kant a Critique of Pure Reason, which is much more
methodical, but also a great deal not just more ponderous, but, as far
as the main question is concerned, more incomprehensible. Locke
maintains that not only all human ideas (Vorstellungen), but also all our
concepts, not even excepting the scientific concepts, are indirectly de¬
rived from experience. Kant admittedly allows us certain concepts
which are independent of experience; but since they are after all only
capable of application to objects of experience we do not become more
independent of experience via them - the result for us is the same;
for the particular way into the supersensuous which Kant found in his
moral philosophy could in a certain way still be tolerated by empiri¬
cism as well. For just as Kant, as it were, makes the absolutely impe¬
rious moral law in us into the witness of the existence of God, Locke
also does not omit to demonstrate guarantees of this existence in our
consciousness. But there is the big difference between them that Kant
nevertheless makes God the object of an Idea of reason in the theo¬
retical philosophy. This is, though, the Jtpcbxov i|>ei>6oa of modern
philosophy; it is incomprehensible how, if no personality exists, how¬
ever insignificant it may be, which does not demand something more
and something more real than reason if it is to be known, precisely the
highest and most perfect personality should announce itself to us by
means of nothing other than the Idea of reason. Rationalism was
therefore proclaimed by Kant in philosophy (previously people were
not so clear about this, particularly with regard to the Idea of God).
Kant admittedly refused and forbade any theoretical use of this Idea,
but it was all very well his refusing; if God is an Idea of reason, then
reason cannot be prevented from realising this Idea as such; naturally
this can only happen in a mere system of reason as well - and this,
nothing else, was undertaken by later philosophy. Empiricism, by al¬
ways only deducing the existence of God, like the existence of another
personality, from empirical, experiential traces, features, footprints
or characteristics, thereby founds that agreeable free relationship to
God which rationalism negates, and since one must admit that if even
today, as was the case in the later times of the Greek and Roman de¬
cline when the question was only between Stoicism and Epicureanism,
the Epicurean system is a refuge, precisely because of what appears
absurd in it, the so-called clinamen atomorum [inclination of atoms], via
which it introduces coincidence as, so to speak, the highest principle,
since even today, I say, the Epicurean system would have to be seized
upon and sought after, despite or rather because of this inconsistency,
as a refuge of freedom of every free and freedom-loving spirit, in
igo On the History of Modern Philosophy
preference to the Stoic system, then, if we had the choice between em¬
piricism and the all-oppressing necessity of thought of a rationalism
which had been driven to the highest point, no free spirit would be
able to object to deciding in favour of empiricism.
Empiricism itself, then, allows a higher way of looking at things, or
can be grasped from a higher perspective than the received, or, at
least since Kant, the usual concept grasps it, which expels everything
intelligible not only beyond the concepts of the understanding, but
originally and first of all beyond all experience. Hence the now usual
explanation that empiricism denies everything supernatural, but this
is not the case. Because it is empiricism, it does not necessarily for
that reason deny the supernatural, neither does it assume the legal
and moral laws and the content of religion as something merely con¬
tingent, namely in the sense that it reduces everything to mere feel¬
ings, which themselves would only be the product of education and
habit, as David Hume admittedly did, who, by the way, asserted the
same thing in relation to the sort of necessity with which we link cause
and effect in our thoughts. There is even a higher and lower concept
of empiricism. For if the highest goal, which philosophy can, by gen¬
eral consent even of those who up to now think differently, certainly
reach, is precisely to grasp the world as freely produced and created,
then philosophy, with regard to the main thing it can achieve, or pre¬
cisely by reaching its highest goal, would be a science of experience; I
do not mean in the formal sense, but I do mean in the material sense,
that what is highest for it would itself be something experiential in
nature. If up to now, then, that national difference with regard to
philosophy really exists, then this rift initially only shows that the phi¬
losophy in which humankind could recognise itself, the truly univer¬
sal philosophy, does not yet exist. The truly universal philosophy
cannot possibly be the property of a single nation, and as long as any
philosophy does not go beyond the borders of a single people one can
be safe in assuming that it is not yet the true philosophy, even if it is
perhaps on the way to it.
It is admittedly miserable pusillanimity and narrow-mindedness if
philosophy, e.g. in France, claims nothing for itself but the slender
and narrow area of petty, psychologically named observations and
analyses from the whole wide and great realm of experience. In
France itself the indigenous philosophy, or, as it has recently been
termed, “ideology”, lacks any real respect, is more politely tolerated
and politely treated than acknowledged. If a few younger men in
France have succeeded in arousing a certain enthusiasm for philoso¬
phy, it was mainly only in so far as they opposed the external morality
of Kant to the thoughtless frivolity of their nation and thought they
On National Differences in Philosophy lgi
had found in it the means, initially in the moral sphere, for a regen¬
eration of their people. The true promoters of philosophy in France
and England are their great natural scientists, and it is not to the dis¬
credit of the English if philosophy for them mainly, indeed almost ex¬
clusively, means physics. German ideas seem to gain entry to France
mainly in the realm of the natural sciences. Whoever, e.g., reads many
recent French investigations of the anatomy of the brain will be sur¬
prised to find a new language, a new kind of expression which until
very recently people in Germany thought they could insult by using
the epithet “poetic”, a new, thoroughly German sort of conception;
even Cuvier shows in his latest writings on geology and the natural
history of the prehistoric world that in relation to these great phe¬
nomena German ideas about the natural history of the earth and
even German expressions have had a great influence on him.* And,
as one can deduce from various factors, German science might mainly
gain entry to France and England in the realm of history and of re¬
search into the ancient world. It would be wrong, really wrong, then,
to want to call back those other nations from the doctrine of empir¬
icism which they pursue to such great advantage in other areas; for
them this would indeed be a retrograde movement. It is not up to
them, it is up to us Germans, who, since the existence of Naturphilos-
ophie, have emerged from the sad alternative of a metaphysics which
floats in the air, lacking any foundation (that they rightly make fun
of) and an infertile, arid psychology - it is up to us, I say, to develop
the system, which we may hope to grasp and to reach, the positive
system whose principle, precisely because of its absolute positivity
cannot itself be knowable a priori any more, but only a posteriori, to the
point where it will flow together with that empiricism which has been
expanded and purified to the same extent.
Absolute, 4, 7, 10, 13, 15, 16-18, 24, 26, German Idealism, 2, 3—5, 7
28, 32, 141, 147-50, 151, 152, God, 19-21, 30, 61, 73, 103—4, 129,
>53- >54. i56- '58. 160 132-3, 160, 169, 171-2, 175-6
absolute identity, 17, 152 cosmological proof of, 87, 89-90
Anselm of Canterbury, 54 as creator, 66, 85, 87, 91, 103, 157
Aristotle, 89, 90 doctrine of attributes of, 91—2
art (and Poetry), 11—12, 128—9, 131 and freedom, 54, 55-6, 65—7, 74, 80,
82, 85, 103, 159
Bacon, F., 61—3 and nature, 20-1, 159-60
Baumgarten, A., 103 ontological proof of, 31-2, 33, 34,
Berkeley G., 100 49-56. 87-9
Bohme, J., 22, 155, 181, 183-4 as personality, 74, 105, 165, 170, 171,
189
Cuvier, G., 191 physico-theological proof of, 90-1
Goethe, J. W. von, 131—2
Descartes, R., 16, 31, 42-63, 107, 174 ground, 19-20, 21, 102, 158
and Bacon, 61—3
Hamann.J. G., 22, 168-9
and Cogito ergo sum, 31, 42-8
Hegel, G. W. F., 7, 13, 16, 19, 20, 23-25,
and dualism, 56-60, 67-8, 79
88,134-63
and ontological proof of God, 49—56
on “concept”, 134-5, 136, 138,
142-6, 147-8
empirical psychology, 93, 98, 188 on God, 135-6, 146, 147, 155-6
empiricism (experience), 61—3, 95-8, Logic, 3, 25, 30, 32-3, 134-5, '4'.
104—5, *64—5, 166, 179, 188-90, 144, 146-7, 155, 157
»9i and Logic (his conception of, for phi¬
evil, 81-3, 126 losophy), 141-2, 143, 145,
146-9, 153-4
Fichte, J. G., 3, 5, 6, 7, 8, 13—14, 15, Phenomenology of Mind, 18, 24
28-9, 30, 33, 106-11, 136 and transition from Logic to nature,
on intellectual intuition, 5, 150—1 •49. '53-5. '57-8. 159
final cause, 90, 156, 158 Heidegger, M., 35
Frank, M., 26, 29 Henrich, D., 24
freedom, 10, 20, 21, 26-7, 28, 29, 30, Herder, J. G., 132
66, 75, 115—16, 118, 124, 125, history, 3, 10, 11, 34, 41, 42, 61, 65, 82,
126-7, >54-5. »77 83-4,94, 112, 117-18, 126-7,
!93
194 Index
While the new digital cover differs from the original, the
text content is identical to that of previous printings.
* :