Ideas Images and Truth
Ideas Images and Truth
Ideas Images and Truth
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
North American Philosophical Publications and University of Illinois Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to History of Philosophy Quarterly.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 128.174.141.166 on Tue, 05 Jan 2016 15:47:34 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
History of Philosophy Quarterly
Volume 6, Number 2, April 1989
The significance of Part II should be obvious. Apart from its own value
for a theory of knowledge, it is crucial for understanding Part I because
the existence of substance cannot be made clear until we first explain our
idea of substance. Part II is also essential for understanding Parts III-V
because the passions, their bondage and freedom, cannot be understood
until we are able to explain the activity and passivity of the mind.
161
This content downloaded from 128.174.141.166 on Tue, 05 Jan 2016 15:47:34 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
162 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
of an object, like a sphere, can be true even if the object does not exist
outside the mind. In order for a thought to be true, we must understand
its cause, another idea, and eventually God. The reason for this is that
everything is in God and nothing can exist outside God, and in order to
know a thing, we must know its cause. A true idea is part of the infinite
intellect ofGod. When one has a true idea, one knows that he has a true
idea, and one knows the difference between it and a false idea. There is
nothing about truth which takes us beyond a true idea.
A true idea is related to a false idea as being or completeness is related
to non-being or incompleteness. Falsity means two things for Spinoza. It
means partial or incomplete knowledge, such as an idea of the sun being
closer or farther away than it actually is or not being aware that each
action we perform has a cause. It also means affirming or denying some
thing, such as motion and rest of a circle. A false idea has its origin in
the imagination (ideas of images). Falsity arises when ideas of bodies
external to our own occur simultaneous with our body when it is affected
by external bodies. It does not arise from the power of the mind. Rather,
the mind is passive or acted upon when it has ideas of other objects.
Images are affects of bodies and occur when external bodies affect our
body, and we have ideas of images when we have ideas of such occurrences.
The mind has ideas of external bodies through ideas or affections of its
own body. Images are constituted by corporeal motions and fall under
the attribute of extension. Ideas of images fall under the attribute of
thought. Images contain no error, but ideas of images do.
An idea is not an image and cannot be expressed in words. Certain
things like a square-circle can be expressed in words but cannot be
expressed by the imagination or the understanding. We have no sensa
tions or images of such a thing. The distinction between the understanding
and the imagination is the distinction between true ideas and all other
ideas. A true idea does not involve remembering or forgetting. Substance,
infinity, indivisibility, and eternity can only be grasped through true
ideas. Ideas of images are ideas only of such things as individual bodies
and their parts.
The body is the object of the human mind. It is what the mind thinks
about. The idea of the body is composed of other ideas because it is a
complex idea. Some of the ideas ofwhich it is composed are adequate and
some are inadequate. The mind can only have ideas which involve the
existence of its body. This means that the mind's knowledge only extends
to those things which are contained in the idea of its body or which follow
from such an idea. The mind can perceive itself, its body, or external
bodies either adequately or inadequately. The mind only knows its own
body through ideas by which its body is affected. In other words, it knows
its body indirectly through ideas of external bodies affecting its own body.
So, the idea of an affection of the human body involves the nature of the
external body. The mind only knows external bodies indirectly also. It
knows them through ideas by which its body is affected. The mind also
This content downloaded from 128.174.141.166 on Tue, 05 Jan 2016 15:47:34 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
IDEAS, IMAGES, AND TRUTH 163
knows itself through ideas by which its body is affected. In this case the
mind only knows itself indirectly too. All this means is that the mind,
through the imagination, does not have clear and direct knowledge of
itself, its own body, and external bodies. It can only know them through
something else, hence inadequately.
An idea is considered adequate ifwithout relation to its object, it has
all the properties of a true idea. When God has the idea of other things
in addition to the idea of a particular mind, that mind perceives things
partially or inadequately. In a sense all our ideas are inadequate or
incomplete because we never have all the ideas that God has. We are
only part of an infinite being, some of whose thoughts constitute our
mind and some ofwhose thoughts do not. All God's ideas are adequate,
but only some of ours are. The mind though can have an adequate idea
of God. Each idea expresses in its own way and to its own extent the
nature of substance. So each idea in doing so involves the eternal and
infinite essence of God. How does this happen? The body has God for its
cause, and to know a thing is to know its cause. The mind has an idea
which expresses the essence of the body under a species of eternity. When
the mind knows itself, its body, and external bodies under a species of
eternity, it knows God and hence has an adequate idea.
Now that certain basic concepts are clear, I can pursue the various
interpretations that commentators have given of what constitutes the
object of the idea. Four different accounts in the literature are given of
the object of the idea. One is that Spinoza cannot account for an object
of thought at all. Another is that the object of thought is ambiguous or
has a double meaning. A third is that ideas represent their objects, or at
least some ideas do. Finally, there is the view that ideas do not represent.
Some other account must be given of the relation between the idea and
its object.
I think Joachim ismistaken. First, Spinoza does not intend to say that
This content downloaded from 128.174.141.166 on Tue, 05 Jan 2016 15:47:34 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
164 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
This content downloaded from 128.174.141.166 on Tue, 05 Jan 2016 15:47:34 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
IDEAS, IMAGES, AND TRUTH 165
anything, it only means being aware (having ideas) ofmy body or parts
ofmy body insofar as it is affected by external objects. I only know external
objects through modifications ofmy own body. What I experience ismy
own body. There is no representation in the traditional sense. There are
just affections or ideas.
A second view on the relation between an idea and its object is that
the object of an idea is ambiguous or has a double meaning. Martineau
says that Spinoza sometimes describes the object of an idea as an external
object and sometimes as a bodily affection.8 We know only particular
affections of our own body, and our ideas of other bodies are mixed with
these affections. Some of our affections are properties of our own body
and some are properties of external bodies. The affections of our own
body are inseparable from the affections of external bodies. We are left
with no clear account of the relation between other bodies and our own.
This also leads to a confused knowledge of our own mind because we get
the idea of our mind from the affections of the body.
Pollock states that the word "idea" denotes two kinds of relation.9 In
one case it is a concept; in the other a physiological process. When I think
of Peter, my consciousness is an idea of Peter. But also there is the idea,
not of Peter, but the corresponding state ofmy brain. The object of the
first idea is Peter. The object of the second ismy bodily organism, which
is correlated to the thinking mind. Pollock thinks that Spinoza mixes up
concepts of representation and correlation under the term "idea." With
correlation there is only one object of an idea. With representation there
are as many objects as there are ideas in the minds of individuals who
think about them.
Pollock does not understand the relation between the mind and the
This content downloaded from 128.174.141.166 on Tue, 05 Jan 2016 15:47:34 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
166 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
A third view tells us that all or some ideas represent. Hart takes the
position that all ideas represent.11 He says that the mind and its object
(the body) are identical, but this does not mean, as was pointed out, that
the mind and the object of knowledge are identical. All ideas refer, point
toward, or intend their objects of knowledge. The referent of the idea of
an image is another image. The referent of other ideas is an idea, not a
body.
Mark says that representation has to do only with those ideas which
are ideas of images.12 These ideas represent external objects (finite phys
ical bodies different from our own). Representation is confined to the first
kind of knowledge?imagination. Ideas are modifications of thought.
Images are modifications of extension. Ideas do not represent and are not
different for different people. Only ideas of images represent because they
are passive or acted upon. Other ideas are active.
The problem I have with these views which say that ideas represent
is the word "represent." The word "represent" or an explication of it is
not necessary for understanding Spinoza. For Spinoza the mind is the
same as the body. As the body undergoes changes so does the mind. An
idea is an affection or change in the bodily process. Some affections arise
because of the body's own power and others arise because the body is
acted upon. In either case the body is modified and some changes take
place which in us is a perception of our body or some other body through
our body. This modification is an idea which is caused by other ideas. At
any rate, we have an idea of something. All our ideas are of something.
The "of something" is not part of the idea orwhat the idea intends; rather
it is the idea itself. This is what is meant by saying that the idea and
what it is about (its object) are the same.13 An idea is one whole. There
This content downloaded from 128.174.141.166 on Tue, 05 Jan 2016 15:47:34 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
IDEAS, IMAGES, AND TRUTH 167
is no consciousness lurking behind it. There are only more ideas which
are integrated into one individual called a human mind.
Three positions have been taken on the second issue, the truth and
falsity of our ideas. One is that none of our ideas are true. A second is
that all of our ideas are true. A third is that one or only a few of our
ideas are true. I would like to examine these interpretations and argue
that none of them are really in line with Spinoza's thinking.
The first position, that no ideas of human beings are true and that
there is only one idea which agrees with its ideatum, is stated but not
necessarily held by Parkinson.16 That one idea is God's idea or the idea
of the whole. Ideas that human beings have are incomplete and falsity
is incompleteness. Ideas that are incomplete are only part ofGod's intellect
and hence are false. Only God has true ideas since he is the only one
with the idea of the whole. Human beings at best have only fragments
of the truth. According to this position, all human ideas are false because
falsity means incompleteness, and our ideas are partial or fragmentary.
But this position cannot be correct for Spinoza affirms in Book II P34,
P36, 38-43, 46-47 the truth and adequacy of some of our ideas.
Joachim and Mark take the second and opposite position that every
idea we have is true. Joachim says that according to Spinoza every idea
is its ideatum and every idea is true.17 The criterion of truth is within
the idea itself. An idea is not made true by being brought into agreement
with an object. Its truth belongs to it internally. Mark says that truth
and idea mean the same thing.18 Truth is a property which inheres in
the idea. It does not connect the idea with the object. It leaves the object
This content downloaded from 128.174.141.166 on Tue, 05 Jan 2016 15:47:34 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
168 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
Joachim and Mark also take the third position. They hold that although
other ideas can be true to some extent, only the idea ofGod that human
beings have is ultimately or absolutely true. Joachim says that this idea
is true because "it is inwardly coherent. . . ."19Mark
real, complete, says
". . .no idea, except the idea ofGod, corresponds to reality in every respect,
so every idea, except the idea of God, must fail to correspond to reality
in some respect."20 The distinction between truths which are absolute and
those which are not can perhaps be clarified by Curley's distinction
between truths which are absolutely necessary and truths which are
relatively necessary which is based on Leibniz's distinction between neces
sary truths and contingent truths.21 The former are those whose denial
is self-contradictory or whose reason for existence is contained in their
nature (substance). The latter are those whose denial does not involve a
contradiction or whose reason for existence lies outside their nature
(modes). Joachim also holds that there are degrees of truth in finite
minds.22 An idea is true to the degree that it is in its own mind what it
is in God's mind or to the extent that God's idea is in the thought of a
finite mind.
If it is the case that only our idea of God is absolutely true and other
ideas are only true to some extent, then either all our other ideas are
false or falsity when it occurs makes up the lack of the truth of our ideas.
Spinoza rejects the first disjunction because he admits that many of our
ideas are true or can be true. He says that falsity consists in partiality,
in not having other ideas in addition to the ones we have. So in order to
know that an idea is false or partial we must be able to compare itwith
an idea that is true or complete. For example, our basis for the view in
thinking that the sun is very close to us lies in the fact that our bodies
are affected by a large, bright object. But there are other, more scientific
ways, that we can explain our distance from the sun. There are different
levels of awareness of an object. We are only part of a complete whole,
and what we affirm sometimes extends beyond or falls short of what is
involved in the idea. God or a complete intelligence is incapable of doing
this, but we are not.
It must be the case that we have true ideas and falsity makes up the
lack of truth of our other ideas. We can have a true idea of substance,
and we can have a true idea of things other than substance. We can have
a true idea of the distance between the earth and the sun, and we can
have a true idea of the causes of our action. Spinoza asserts that the mind
is an idea (EIIP11), a complex idea composed ofmany other ideas (EIIP15)
This content downloaded from 128.174.141.166 on Tue, 05 Jan 2016 15:47:34 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
IDEAS, IMAGES, AND TRUTH 169
and that truth is nothing more than an idea or kind of idea (TEI, par.
36). The mind does contain true ideas (EIIP34, 45). Spinoza often speaks
in terms of the plurality of true ideas. Also he argues that since all God's
ideas are true (EIIP32); the human mind is part ofGod's mind (EIIP11C);
man's idea of God is part of God's idea of himself (EVP36); the human
mind has an adequate knowledge ofGod (EIIP47); we can conclude that
we do have true ideas and that truth means the same as these ideas.
NOTES
1. Harold Joachim, A Study of theEthics of Spinoza (New York: Russell & Russell, 1964,
2. Ibid., p. 141.
3. Ibid.
4. H. Barker, "Notes on the Second Part of Spinoza's Ethics (II)," Mind, vol. 47 (1938),
8. James Martineau, A Study of Spinoza (Freeport, New York: Books for Libraries Press,
1971, reprint of 1895), pp. 140-42.
9. Frederick Pollock, Spinoza (London: C. Kegan Paul, 1880), pp. 131-34.
10. Alan Hart, Spinoza's Ethics, Part I and II (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1983), pp. 96-99.
11. Ibid. Most of Chapter 2 is devoted to an appraisal of the papers ofMark, Radner and
Brandom.
12. Thomas Carson Mark, "Truth and Adequacy in Spinozistic Ideas," in Spinoza: New
Perspectives, ed. by Robert Shahan and J. Biro (Norman: University of Oklahoma, 1978),
p. 16, and Spinoza's Theory of Truth (New York: Columbia University, 1972), pp. 23-26.
13. This is what I think Wallace Matson is saying in his "Spinoza's Theory ofMind," in
Spinoza: Essays in Interpretation, ed. by Eugene Freeman and Maurice Mandelbaum (La
14. See my paper, "The Mind's Body: The Body's Self-Awareness,"Z)?aZogz?e, vol. 23 (1984),
pp. 619-633.
15. Errol Harris, Salvation from Despair (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973), pp. 80-82
and "Body-Mind Relation in Spinoza's Philosophy," in Spinoza's Metaphysics, ed. by James
Wilbur (Amsterdam: Van Gorcum, 1976) pp. 14-15.
Chap. 6.
This content downloaded from 128.174.141.166 on Tue, 05 Jan 2016 15:47:34 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
170 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
pp. 89-92.
22. Joachim, op. cit., p. 151.
This content downloaded from 128.174.141.166 on Tue, 05 Jan 2016 15:47:34 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions