Techno Utopianism
Techno Utopianism
Techno Utopianism
net/publication/323542821
CITATIONS READS
0 252
1 author:
Kevin Carson
16 PUBLICATIONS 44 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
Exodus: General Idea of the Revolution in the XXI Century View project
All content following this page was uploaded by Kevin Carson on 03 March 2018.
1 Nick Dyer-Witheford, Cyber-Marx: Cycles and Circuits of Struggle in High-Technology Capitalism (Urbana and Chicago:
University of Illinois Press, 1999). pp. 16-17
2 Ibid., pp. 17-18.
3 Ibid., p. 19.
4 Ibid., p. 19.
movement at the turn of the 20th century. Progressivism had its origins as the ideology of the
managerial and professional stratum which ran the new, large institutions (corporations, regulatory
agencies, universities, large municipal governments, public school systems and foundations) that
sprang up to dominate society in the late 19th century.
The first corporate managers came from an industrial engineering background. They saw the
corporation -- as well as other large organizations -- as something to be rationalized the same way
engineers on the factory floor rationalized the production process. According to Rakesh Khurana they
sought to apply the engineer's approach of standardizing and rationalizing tools, processes and systems
to rationalizing the organization.5
And as time passed and the kinds of organizations they headed came to be the hegemonic norm that
characterized the larger society, they came to view outside society as a whole as something to be
organized and managed by the same scientific principles that governed the large organization. Yehouda
Shenhav described, in Manufacturing Rationality: The Engineering Foundations of the Managerial
Revolution, the transfer of mechanical and industrial engineers' understanding of production processes
to the management of organizations, and of the managers' understanding of organizations to society as
a whole.6
Since the difference between the physical, social, and human realms was blurred by acts of
translation, society itself was conceptualized and treated as a technical system. As such, society and
organizations could, and should, be engineered as machines that are constantly being perfected.
Hence, the management of organizations (and society at large) was seen to fall within the province
of engineers. Social, cultural, and political issues... could be framed and analyzed as "systems" and
"subsystems" to be solved by technical means.7
Probably the most important feature of Progressivism, and its closest point of intersection with
liberal post-industrialism, was its focus on the application of disinterested expertise as transcending
politics and class conflict. Of course it's no coincidence this was the heyday of Taylorist "scientific
management," whose purpose was to suppress labor conflict on the shop floor by substituting the
manager's and engineer's expertise for the skilled worker's direction of the work process. And
according to Shenhav
[l]abor unrest and other political disagreements of the period were treated by mechanical engineers
as simply a particular case of machine uncertainty to be dealt with in much the same manner as they
had so successfully dealt with technical uncertainty. Whatever disrupted the smooth running of the
organizational machine was viewed and constructed as a problem of uncertainty. 8
Christopher Lasch argued that for the new managerial class
conflict itself, rather than injustice or inequality, was the evil to be eradicated. Accordingly, they
proposed to reform society... by means of social engineering on the part of disinterested experts who
could see the problem whole and who could see it essentially as a problem of resources... the proper
application and conservation of which were the work of enlightened administration. 9
Going back to Shenhav, "American management theory was presented as a scientific technique
5 Rakesh Khurana, From Higher Aims to Hired Hands: The Social Transformation of American Business Schools and the
Unfulfilled Promise of Management as a Profession (Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2007), p. 56.
6 Yehouda Shenhav, Manufacturing Rationality: The Engineering Foundations of the Managerial Revolution (Oxford and
New York: Oxford University Press, 1999).
7 Ibid., p. 74.
8 Ibid., p. 174.
9 Christopher Lasch, The New Radicalism in America (1889-1963): The Intellectual as a Social Type (New York: Vintage
Books, 1965 ), p. 162.
administered for the good of society as a whole without relation to politics."10 Taylor saw bureaucracy
as "a solution to ideological cleavages, as an engineering remedy to the war between the classes."11 At
the level of state policy, the Progressives' professionalized approach to politics was "perceived to be
objective and rational, above the give-and-take of political conflict." It reflected "a pragmatic culture in
which conflicts were diffused and ideological differences resolved."12 Both Progressives and industrial
engineers "were horrified at the possibility of 'class warfare'" and saw "efficiency" as a means to "social
harmony, making each workman's interest the same as that of his employers."13
The end of ideology and post-industrialism exemplified all these earlier qualities of Progressivism
in full measure. And so, equally, have all the various strands of capitalist techno-utopianism that have
emerged from the 1990s on.
Bell's post-industrialist thesis intersected, in the 1970s, with the rise of networked digital
communications and the personal computer revolution. The result was a new wave of techno-utopian
literature exemplified by Alvin Toffler's The Third Wave and John Naisbett's Megatrends.
Exponents of this model have used exuberantly optimistic, "revolutionary" or utopian rhetoric
about the nature of the social transformations that can be expected.
The undesirable features of industrial society -- meaningless work, huge impersonal organizations,
rigid routines and hierarchies, anonymous and alienating urban existences -- are seen dissolving. In
their place the information age holds out the hope of diversification, localism, flexibility, creativity,
and equality. Promises include the computer-aided recovery of craft skills and artisanal traditions...;
the revivication of domestic life in an electronic cottage; the participatory democracy of electronic
town halls; and a historically unprecedented diffusion of every sort of knowledge -- "all information
in all places at all times."14
The liberal capitalist variant of information age utopianism is distinguished -- like its Progressive
and post-industrial antecedents -- by its hand-waving away of class antagonism. The transition to Third
Wave information capitalism will be peaceful. It will be positive-sum and benefit everybody, rendering
the old class struggles irrelevant.15
But the class struggles remain very much real -- only under post-industrialism they center on the
ownership, not of land or physical capital, but of knowledge. Dyer-Witheford's reference above to
knowledge as a "wealth-creating resource" is central to the real nature of capitalist techno-utopianism.
"The generation of wealth increasingly depends on an 'information economy' in which the exchange
and manipulation of symbolic data matches exceeds, or subsumes the importance of material
processing."16
As Manuel Castells summed up the post-industrial thesis:
(1) The source of productivity and growth lies in the generation of knowledge, extended to all
realms of economic activity through information processing.
(2) Economic activity would shift from goods production to services delivery….
(3) The new economy would increase the importance of occupations with a high informational
and knowledge content in their activity. Managerial, professional, and technical occupations would
grow faster than any other occupational position and would constitute the core of the new social
10 Shenhav, p. 5.
11 Ibid., p. 8.
12 Ibid., p. 35.
13 Ibid., p. 96.
14 Dyer-Witheford, p. 25.
15 Ibid., pp. 26-27.
16 Ibid., p. 24.
structure.17
Toffler described it as a "new system of accelerated wealth creation" based on "the exchange of
data, information and knowledge." Land and labor are less important than the knowledge that can find
substitutes for them.18
The same principle resurfaces in one of the most recent iterations of post-industrialism, Paul
Romer's "New Growth Theory." The main source of growth is not simply adding inputs of material
resources or labor, which are finite, but developing better ideas -- which can be imitated without limit --
on how to use the same amount of resources and labor in more effective ways.19
The problem is that, absent coercion, the natural result of ephemeralization -- the use of knowledge
to reduce the material inputs required for production -- is deflation. The only way to transform this
improved efficiency into wealth -- money wealth -- is prevent competition from diffusing the benefits
and making things cheaper for everybody.
Knowledge can only be a wealth-creating resource -- or capital -- if it is owned. It can function as a
source of rents only if it is enclosed, if access to it is restricted, if tribute can be demanded for allowing
such access.
It's no coincidence that the most fervent enthusiasts of the "Information Superhighway" in the '90s,
were also strident advocates of draconian "intellectual property" laws and subsidies to the telecom
industry. Newt Gingrich's Progress and Freedom Foundation issued a pamphlet called "Cyberspace and
the American Dream: A Magna Carta for the Knowledge Age," whose agenda included proposals that
sounded remarkably like the Digital Millennium Copyright Act and Telecommunications Act.
And it's likewise no coincidence that Romer's model of growth relies heavily on "intellectual
property" for monetizing the increased productivity as rents to investors rather than allowing it to
deflate prices for consumers.
Romer: ...When we speak of institutions, economists mean more than just organizations. We
mean conventions, even rules, about how things are done. The understanding which most sharply
distinguishes science from the market has to do with property rights. In the market, the fundamental
institution is the notion of private ownership, that an individual owns a piece of land or a body of
water or a barrel of oil and that individual has almost unlimited scope to decide how that resource
should be used.
In science we have a very different ethic. When somebody discovers something like the
quadratic formula or the Pythagorean theorem, the convention in science is that he can't control that
idea. He has to give it away. He publishes it. What's rewarded in science is dissemination of ideas.
And the way we reward it is we give the most prestige and respect to those people who first publish
an idea.
reason: Yet there is a mechanism in the market called patents and copyright, for quasi-property
rights in ideas.
Romer: That's central to the theory. To the extent that you're using the market system to refine
and bring ideas into practical application, we have to create some kind of control over the idea. That
could be through patents. It could be through copyright. It might even be through secrecy.... 20
Although Romer classifies "intellectual property" as an "institution of the market," it is in fact no
17 Manuel Castells, The Rise of the Network Society (Blackwell Publishers, 1996), pp. 203-204.
18 Dyer-Witheford, p. 24.
19 Ronald Bailey, “Post-Scarcity Prophet: Economist Paul Romer on growth, technological change, and an unlimited
human future” Reason, December 2001 <http://reason.com/archives/2001/12/01/post-scarcity-prophet/>.
20 Ibid.
such thing (except perhaps insofar as it's an institution that enables people to charge money for
something on the "market," in the sense of the cash nexus, that would otherwise be naturally free). The
fact that he distinguishes IP, as an "institution of the market," from "institutions of science" like free
sharing of knowledge, is an admission that for him the "market" is not simply the realm of voluntary
interaction but the cash nexus as such. "Intellectual property" is an artificial creation of the state.
Romer -- again -- implicitly admits as much, arguing that the natural functioning of the market price-
setting mechanism, under which price tends towards marginal production cost, is inadequate to pay
back the original outlays for R&D.21 In fact he explicitly argues for the superiority of monopoly pricing
over market competition for some purposes.
There was an old, simplistic notion that monopoly was always bad. It was based on the realm of
objects -- if you only have objects and you see somebody whose cost is significantly lower than
their price, it would be a good idea to break up the monopoly and get competition to reign freely. So
in the realm of things, of physical objects, there is a theoretical justification for why you should
never tolerate monopoly. But in the realm of ideas, you have to have some degree of monopoly
power. There are some very important benefits from monopoly, and there are some potential costs as
well. What you have to do is weigh the costs against the benefits. 22
Romer's model is essentially Schumpeterian, in the sense that Schumpeter regarded the market
power of the monopoly corporation as "progressive" because it enabled it to charge a price above
marginal cost in order to subsidize innovation. Hence Romer's Schumpeterian schema precludes price-
taking behavior in a competitive market; rather, it presupposes some form of market power
(“monopolistic competition”) by which firms can set prices to cover average costs. Romer argues that
his model of economic growth based on innovation is incompatible with price-taking behavior. A firm
that invested significant sums in innovation, but sold only at marginal cost, could not survive as a
price-taker. It is necessary, therefore, that the benefits of innovation—even though non-rival by their
nature—be at least partially excludable through “intellectual property” law.23
And cognitive capitalism and Romer's "new growth theory" are implicit in all the models of
"progressive capitalism," "green capitalism" and the like that we hear from Bill Gates, Warren Buffet,
Bono and their ilk.
Dyer-Witheford goes on to survey the approaches to cybernetic technology on the part of assorted
Marxisms -- or at least schools of left-wing or socialistic analysis -- of the 20th century.
The "scientific socialists" or neo-orthodox Marxists celebrate the liberatory potential of technology,
and its role in both making capitalism unsustainable and providing the building blocks of a post-
capitalist society of abundance. Their failing, as he sees it, is a tendency towards technological
determinism which reduces the agency of the working class -- its central role in self-liberation -- to
almost nothing. Rather an almost inevitable transition is driven by the forces of production or social
relations of production.24
The second strand of Marxist thought on high technology is the pessimists or neo-Luddites, who
emphasize the nature of technology as a totalizing system of control. They include theorists of work-
21 Ibid.
22 Ibid.
23 Paul M. Romer, “Endogenous Technological Change” (December 1989). NBER Working Paper No. W3210.
24 Dyer-Witheford, pp. 43-47.
discipline like Braverman and Marglin, and David Noble's work on deskilling through automated CNC
machine tools.25 Similarly cultural theorists like Marcuse and media analysts Herbert Schiller view the
corporate control of communications as a totalitarian force that closes off possibilities of critique.26
The ruling class, by definition, always selects among the variety of technological alternatives for
one that best serves its interest; it follows that the ruling classes' need for control is built into whatever
technology is in use and there is exploitative by its very nature.27
This approach is useful, Dyer-Witheford argues, because it sees through the liberal capitalist
techno-utopian project's treatment of technology as class-neutral and positive-sum, and points to the
very real class agenda embodied in that project.28
But its shortcomings are far more significant. It makes the mistake of equating "capitalism's
intentions and its capacities," and "ignores the consequences of [workers'] counter-strategies and
resistances." In particular, it neglects "the possibility -- particularly apparent in the field of media and
communications technologies -- that capital's laboring subjects may find real use-values, perhaps even
subversive ones, for the new technologies."29
These latter possibilities are heightened, I would add, by the radical cheapening and ephemerality
of new production and communications technology, and the resulting collapse of entry barriers -- at
least those based on material conditions -- for production directly undertaken and controlled by
producers.
The strand on the Left which most resembles liberal capitalist "information society" theory -- post-
Fordism -- may include Marxists but is not necessarily Marxist as such. It shares a blurry border area
with liberal capitalist models. The post-Fordist ranks include Michael Piore and Charles Sabel, authors
of The Second Industrial Divide. Their flavor, Dyer-Witheford notes, is more Proudhonian than
Marxist: "fascinated by the prospects of escaping the alienation of modern capitalism by return to
small-scale, cooperative, artisanal production" -- a situation which will "allow the restoration to the
workplace of the judgment, learning, and variety lost to Taylorism."30
And the more optimistic post-Fordists share the negative qualities of liberal capitalist "information
society" enthusiasts, downplaying the extent to which post-Fordist industrial organization and
networked supply and distribution chains have been integrated into a corporate capitalist institutional
framework and subjected to the logic of labor exploitation and neoliberal austerity.31 Even post-Fordists
from a Marxist background tend to downplay the significance of class conflict and the contradictions of
late capitalism, instead framing the emergence of a post-capitalist society in largely peaceful and
evolutionary terms.32
After surveying all these thought systems, Dyer-Witheford goes on to discuss his own preferred
model for transition to a high-tech post-capitalist society: autonomist Marxism.
Autonomism stresses the working class's role as creative subject of revolutionary struggle, actively
laying the basis for a new society.
Far from being a passive object of capitalist designs, the worker is in fact the active subject of
production, the wellspring of the skills, innovation, and cooperation on which capital depends.
25 Ibid., pp. 48-49.
26 Ibid., p. 50.
27 Ibid., p. 52.
28 Ibid., p. 53.
29 Ibid., pp. 53-54.
30 Ibid., p. 56.
31 Ibid., pp. 57-59.
32 Ibid., p. 60.
Capital attempts to incorporate labor as a object, a component in its cycle of value extraction, so
much labor power. But this inclusion is always partial, never fully achieved. Laboring subjects
resist capital's reduction. Labor is for capital always a problematic "other" that must constantly be
controlled and subdued, and that, as persistently, circumvents or challenges this command. 33
Workers, autonomists argue, "are not just passive victims of technological change but active agents
who persistently contest capital's attempts at control." One of the most important forms this
contestation takes is workers use of "their 'invention power' -- the creative capacity on which capital
depends for its incessant innovation -- in order to reappropriate technology."34
Another theme of autonomism is the way in which workers' own social relationships have become
the main source of productive capital, as physical capital has declined in importance relative to human
capital and production has taken on a networked, horizontal character. And at the same time, the
boundaries between this increasingly social production process and the rest of life -- the spheres of
consumption, family life, lifelong learning and the reproduction of labor-power -- are becoming more
and more blurred.
The activities of people not just as workers but as students, consumers, shoppers and television
viewers are now directly integrated into the production process. During the era of the mass worker,
the consumption of commodities and the reproduction of labor had been organized as spheres of
activity adjunct to, yet distinct from, production. Now these borders fray.... Work, school, and
domesticity are re-formed into a single, integrated constellation. 35
And the growing centrality of network communications and information to all forms of production,
and the penetration of this networked culture into the entire cultural sphere, means that it becomes a
familiar part of the worker's life.
The "system of social machines" increasingly constitutes an everyday ambience of potentials to be
tapped and explored. The elaboration and alteration of this habitat become so pervasively socialized
that they can no longer be exclusively dictated by capital. 36
When workers' skills and social relationships become the main form of capital, the converse is
that--in contrast to the days when "capital" was expensive, absentee-owned physical capital that
workers were paid to come to a physical location and work--workers are in direct possession of a much
larger share of the prerequisites of production.
In both these regards, Dyer-Witheford's analysis is rooted in Antonio Negri's Grundrisse-based
approach to Marx, a treatment of class antagonism framed around the working class as revolutionary
subject and constitutive element of communist society, and its historic role of abolishing "work" as a
conceptual category as it now exists. The mainstream line of Marxist analysis by the Old Left saw
Capital as the crowning achievement of Marx's theoretical system, and after the publication of the
Grundrisse tended to treat the former as having distilled everything of importance in the latter. Negri,
on the other hand, sees Capital as only a partial completion of the larger project outlined in the
Grundrisse. The chapter on labor in Volume One of Capital did not at all cover the ground envisioned
by Marx in the projected book on wage labor; he dealt with it only in part, in "reduced and objective
terms" in that chapter, whereas the analysis in the Grundrisse that was never incorporated into a
separate volume on labor, was intended to link "Marx's critique of the wage and his revolutionary
definition of communism and communist subjectivity."37
33 Ibid., p. 65.
34 Ibid., pp. 70-71.
35 Ibid., pp. 80-81.
36 Ibid., p. 84.
37 Antonio Negri, "Marx Beyond Marx: Working Notes on the Grundrisse (1979)," in Antonio Negri, Revolution Retrieved:
The objectivisation of categories in Capital blocks the action of revolutionary subjectivity. Is it not
possible... that the Grundrisse, on the other hand, is a text supportive of revolutionary subjectivity?
Is it not the case that it succeeds in rebuilding something that the Marxist tradition has all too often
broken and split apart -- ie the unity between the constitutive process and the strategic project of
working-class subjectivity?38
...In the Grundrisse, labour appears as immediately abstract labour.... Labour becomes abstract
inasmuch as it is immediately intelligible only in terms of the social relations of production. Thus
labour can only be defined in terms of the relations of exchange and the capitalist structure of
production. The only concept of labour that we find in Marx is that of wage labour, of labour that is
socially necessary for the reproduction of capital. Work, as Marx describes it, is not something to be
reformed, reinstated, liberated, or sublimated; it exists only as a concept and a reality to be
abolished.39
4) The open-ended dynamism of Marx's "system" is directed wholly towards identifying the
relationship between crisis and the emergence of revolutionary subjectivity.... In this regard, the
Grundrisse is perhaps the most important -- maybe the only -- Marxian text on the question of
transition, and it is curious to note that among the thousand and one positions published on the
question of transition, this fact goes completely unregarded.
5) Marx's definition of communism in the Grundrisse... is an extremely radical definition. The
fundamental element here is the nexus between communism and class composition.... The nexus
between class composition and power, like that between class composition and transition, is
articulated on the real material nature of forms of behaviour, of needs, of structure, and of self-
valorisation.40
Translated into plain language, that means analysis of the working class in terms of "revolutionary
subjectivity" and its role in the transition means looking at the actual working class as it exists right
now, how it exercises agency through its actual practices, forms of organization and activity, and how
those practices and organizational forms prefigure (or form the nucleus of) the future communist
society it will create.
Getting back to Dyer-Witheford's own analysis of revolutionary subjectivity, it follows from all this
that the main form of revolution ceases to be seizing the factories, and instead becomes -- to use the
term of perhaps the most notable autonomists, Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri -- "exodus." It is
feasible to undertake an ever larger share of production of life's necessities in the social sphere, in self-
provisioning in the informal economy, through commons-based peer production, or through
cooperative labor by workers using affordable high-tech tools in their own homes and shops. And the
social relationships which capital has enclosed as a source of profit are vulnerable to being repurposed
in the form of counter-institutions. Because the "social factory" is immaterial and permeates every
aspect of life, there is no need to physically seize it.
Likewise, as Dyer-Witheford paraphrases Negri, "the new communicative capacities and
technological competencies manifesting in the contemporary work force..."
exist in "virtual" form among the contingent and unemployed labor force. They are not so much the
products of a particular training or specific work environment but rather the premises and
prerequisites of everyday life in a highly integrated technoscientific system permeated by machines
Writings on Marx, Keynes, Capitalist Crisis and New Social Subjects, 1967-1983. Volume 1 of the Red Notes Italian
Archive. Introductory Notes by John Merrington (London: Red Notes, 1988), p. 166.
38 Ibid., pp. 162-163.
39 Ibid., p. 165.
40 Ibid., p. 166.
and media.41
In Negri's own words, "the raw material on which the very high level of productivity is based -- the
only raw material... which is suitable for an intellectual and inventive labour force -- is science
communication and the communication of knowledge." To extract profit from the cooperative
relationships between workers, capital "must... appropriate communication. It must expropriate the
community and superimpose itself on the autonomous capability of manufacturing knowledge..."
The socialized worker's labour is more productive than that of the mass worker. It is endowed with a
very high level of productive potential because it is capable of setting in motion the productive
potentiality of the whole of society.... At all levels and in all contexts, community has increasingly
become the foundation of the productivity of labour.... Today capitalist expropriation no longer takes
place through wages alone. Given the conditions we have described, expropriation no longer simply
consists in the expropriation of the producer, but, in the most immediate sense, in the expropriation
of the producers' community.... Advanced capitalism directly expropriates labouring cooperation.
Capital has penetrated the entire society by means of technological and political instruments... to
anticipate, organize and subsume each of the forms of labouring cooperation which are established
in society in order to generate a higher level of productivity. Capital has insinuated itself
everywhere, and everywhere attempts to acquire the power to coordinate, commandeer and
recuperate value. But the raw material on which the very high level of productivity of the socialized
worker is based... is science, communication and the communication of knowledge. Capital must,
therefore, appropriate communication.42
But in doing this, capital must diffuse the informational tools of production into workers' hands.
And the skills and social relationships capital profits off of become an inseparable part of the worker's
mind and personality. Unlike the case of the physical factory, where management could search workers'
lunchboxes for tools and parts on the way out the door, employers cannot force workers to upload their
knowledge and skill, or their social relationships, to a company mainframe when they clock out.
By informating production, capital seems to augment its powers of control. But it simultaneously
stimulates capacities that threaten to escape its command and overspill into rivulets irrelevant to, or
even subversive of, profit.43
In many areas of production, the communication and information processing tools used in the
workplace are becoming virtually indistinguishable from those used in the social sphere. Wikis and
blogs, and social media like Twitter, developed primarily for use outside the workplace, have been
seized on by champions of the "Wikified Firm" or "Enterprise 2.0" as tools for coordinating production
within the workplace. At the same time, open-sourced desktop or browser-based utilities are frequently
more productive and usable than the proprietary "productivity software" forced on workers in the
workplace. As Tom Coates put it, "the gap between what can be accomplished at home and what can be
accomplished in a work environment has narrowed dramatically over the last ten to fifteen years."44
Since Marx's day, his simple schema of the circuit of capital (production and circulation) has
expanded to encompass virtually all of society, including both the reproduction of nature and the
reproduction of labor-power -- the "social factory."45 And, Dyer-Witheford notes, the map of the circuit
of capital, in addition to being something capital seeks to control through automation and cybernetics,
41 Dyer-Witheford p. 84.
42 Antonio Negri, "Expropriation in Mature Capitalism," in The Politics of Subversion: A Manifesto for the Twenty-First
Century. Translated by James Newell (Cambridge, UK: Polity Press, 1989), pp. 115-116.
43 Dyer-Witheford, p. 85.
44 Tom Coates, "(Weblogs and) The Mass Amateurisation of (Nearly) Everything..." Plasticbag.org, September 3, 2003
<http://www.plasticbag.org/archives/2003/09/weblogs_and_the_mass_amateurisation_of_nearly_everything>
45 Dyer-Witheford, pp. 91-92.
is also a map of capital's vulnerabilities.
...[T]he cartography of capital's circuit maps not just its strength but also its weaknesses. In plotting
the nodes and links necessary to capital's flow, it also charts the points where those continuities can
be ruptured. At every moment we will see how people oppose capital's technological discipline by
refusal or reappropriation; how these struggles multiply throughout capital's orbit; how conflicts at
one point precipitate crises in another; and how activists are using the very machines with which
capital integrates its operations to connect their diverse rebellions. In particular, ...the development
of new means of communication vital for the smooth flow of capital's circuit -- ...especially
computer networks -- also creates the opportunity for otherwise isolated and dispersed points of
insurgency to connect and combine with one another. The circuit of high-technology capital thus
also provides the pathways for the circulation of struggles.46
...In virtual capitalism, the immediate point of production cannot be considered the "privileged"
site of struggle. Rather, the whole of society becomes a wired workplace -- but also a potential site
for the interruption of capital's integrated circuit. 47
Dyer-Witheford wrote in the early days of a trend towards networked struggles and comprehensive
campaigns (his most notable example was the Justice for Janitors campaign in Silicon Valley), based in
the entire social factory rather than in a particular workplace.48
...workers' organizations have entered into experimental coalitions with other social movements also
in collision with corporate order, such as welfare, antipoverty, students, consumer, and
environmental groups. The result has been new oppositional combinations. Thus striking telephone
workers join seniors, minorities, and consumer groups to beat back rate hikes, or unionizing drives
in the ghettos of the fast food and clothing industries intertwine with campaigns against racism and
the persecution of immigrants.... [Such alliances] expand the boundaries of official "labor" politics,
so that the agency of countermobilization against capital begins to become, not so much the trade
union, defined as a purely workplace organization, but rather the "labor/community alliance," with a
broader, social sphere of demands and interests. 49
Although it was written after the completion of Cyber Marx, the Empire trilogy, coauthored by
Negri and Michael Hardt, was a masterpiece of the autonomist tradition. And in particular the concept
of "Exodus," developed in the last book of the trilogy (Commonwealth) was a direct outgrowth of the
ideas in Negri's earlier work as well as Dyer-Witheford's.
…the trend toward the hegemony or prevalence of immaterial production in the processes of
capitalist valorization…. Images, information, knowledge, affects, codes, and social relationships…
are coming to outweigh material commodities or the material aspects of commodities in the
capitalist valorization process. This means, of course, not that the production of material goods… is
disappearing or even declining in quantity but rather that their value is increasingly dependent on
and subordinated to immaterial factors and goods…. What is common to these different forms of
labor… is best expressed by their biopolitical character…. Living beings as fixed capital are at the
center of this transformation, and the production of forms of life is becoming the basis of added
value. This is a process in which putting to work human faculties, competences, and knowledges –
those acquired on the job but, more important, those accumulated outside work interacting with
automated and computerized productive systems – is directly productive of value. One distinctive
feature of the work of head and heart, then, is that paradoxically the object of production is really a
50 Antonio Negri and Michael Hardt, Commonwealth (Cambridge: Belknap Press, 2009), pp. 132-133.
51 Ibid., p. 137.
52 "Toni Negri: from the refusal of labor to the seizure of power," ROAR Magazine, January 18, 2015
<https://roarmag.org/essays/negri-interview-multitude-metropolis/>.
53 Negri and Hardt, Commonwealth, pp. 152-153.
struggles like Seattle, the Arab Spring and Occupy tend to reproduce themselves from one geographical
location to another. Note that the following extended passage was written after the Seattle movement,
but before the Arab Spring:
Traditionally... the geographical expansion of movements takes the form of an international cycle of
struggles in which revolts spread from one local context to another like a contagious disease through
the communication of common practices and desires....
A new international cycle finally emerged around the issues of globalization in the late 1990s. The
coming-out party of the new cycle of struggles were the protests at the WTO summit in Seattle in
1999.... Suddenly the riots against IMF austerity programs in one country, protests against a World
Bank project in another, and demonstrations against NAFTA in a third were all revealed to be elements
of a common cycle of struggles... We should emphasize, once again, that what the forces mobilized in
this new global cycle have is not just a common enemy—whether it be called neoliberalism, U.S. hege-
mony, or global Empire—but also common practices, languages, conduct, habits, forms of life, and de-
sires for a better future. The cycle, in other words, is not only reactive but also active and creative....
The global mobilization of the common in this new cycle of struggle does not negate or even over-
shadow the local nature or singularity of each struggle. The communication with other struggles, in
fact, reinforces the power and augments the wealth of each single one. Consider, for example, the revolt
that broke out in Argentina on the nineteenth and twentieth of December 2001 in the midst of economic
crisis and has continued in different forms, with successes and failures, ever since....The response of the
Argentine population was immediate and creative: industrial workers refused to let their factories close
and took over managing the factories themselves, networks of neighborhood and city assemblies were
formed to manage political debates and decisions, new forms of money were invented to allow for au-
tonomous exchange, and the piqueteros, the movements of employed..., experimented with new forms
of protest in their conflicts with police and other authorities. All of this is clearly specific to the national
situation, but it is also... common to all those who suffer and struggle against the exploitation and hier-
archy of the global system. The revolt of Argentina was born with the common heritage of the global
cycle of struggle at its back....
The global cycle of struggles develops in the form of distributed network. Each local struggle func-
tions as a node that communicates with all the other nodes without any hub or center of intelligence.
Each struggle remains singular and tied to its local conditions but at the same time is immersed in the
common web. This form of organization is the most fully realized example we have of the multitude.54
Both David Graeber and Immanuel Wallerstein regard the various networked movements since the
EZLN uprising in 1994 as a continuing "revolutionary cycle" or "Fourth World War." -- in Wallerstein's
opinion being “the beginning of the counteroffensive of the world left against the relatively short-lived
successes of the world right between the 1970s and 1994...."55
So rather than asking “What happened to Occupy?” or “What happened to M15?” as though they were
discrete entities with a beginning and an end, it makes more sense to think of the whole trajectory of move-
ments including the Arab Spring, M15 and Syntagma, Madison, Occupy, Quebec, the N14 General Strike,
and so on, as one loose global network of associated networked movements. This loose, networked move-
ment is always throwing up new avatars, with new names, which appear to decline after a while. But when
something new arises—and it always does, whether in the same country or halfway around the world—it's
built on the same infrastructure and foundations, and the same social capital, as its predecessors. And the
process represents a spiral rather than a mere cycle, with each iteration transcending the previous one.
Here's how Nathan Schneider described the phenomenon in an interview:
54 Antonio Negri and Michael Hardt, Multitude: War and Democracy in an Age of Empire (Penguin, 2004), pp. 213-217.
55 David Graeber, "Situating Occupy Lessons From the Revolutionary Past," InterActivist Info Exchange, December 4,
2011 <http://interactivist.autonomedia.org/node/36685>; Immanuel Wallerstein, “The Neo-Zapatistas: Twenty Years After,”
Immanuel Wallerstein, May 1, 2014 <http://www.iwallerstein.com/neozapatistas-twenty-years/>.
What did Occupy Wall Street succeed at? What did it fail at?
It very powerfully succeeded at introducing activists from around the country to one another and
turned a lot of people into activists that weren’t before. It produced a tremendous number of net-
works, both online and offline, which continue to mobilize people on a number of fronts, though few
are still called Occupy....
What innovation in this area do you think is in store for us in the future? What should we be
getting excited about?
...This is a movement that has an endless number of clever ideas appearing all the time, but it’s never
clear which ones are going to rise above the rest until it happens. The next big idea might very well not
be called “Occupy”, which may be a good thing — but the chances are high that, even so, it will be the
result of networks that were forged during the Occupy movement.56
John Holloway dismisses concerns about the institutional continuity or persistence of any particular
movement.
Before we can break with capital altogether, you suggest we begin by ‘cracking’ it in different places
and times. Yet these ‘cracks’, as you call them, seem to flourish particularly in times of crisis. We saw
this in the popular uprising in Argentina in 2001-’02, as Marina Sitrin powerfully portrayed in her
book Everyday Revolutions, and we’re seeing it in Southern Europe today. Do you think there is a way
to perpetuate such cracks beyond these economic ‘hard times’? Or is this type of autonomous popular
self-organization bound to be something that flourishes in times of crisis and then secedes back into
this kind of Kirchnerismo-style state capitalist populism?
I don’t know, first I don’t think times necessarily get better and secondly I’m not sure that we should
worry too much about perpetuation. If you look at Argentina, there was clearly a sense that things did
get better. Like the economy, rates of profit recovered, in which a lot of the movements of 2001 and
2002 became sucked in into the state. But the problems have obviously reappeared somewhere else. If
you look at Spain and Greece, firstly there are no short-term perspectives of things getting substantially
better. Secondly, if they did get better, then the crisis would move on somewhere else. And the search
for alternative ways of living moves on.
I think there is an accumulation of experience, and also an accumulation of growing awareness that
spreads from one country to another, that capitalism just isn’t working and that it is in serious problems.
I think that people in Greece look to Argentina and recognize the importance of the experiences of 10
years ago. And I think that people in Argentina – even if things have improved economically for them –
look to Greece and see the instability of capitalism. The failure of capitalism is showing up again in an-
other place. I think there is a growing sense throughout the world that capitalism isn’t working. There is
a growing confidence perhaps that the cracks we create or the crazinesses we create may really be the
basis for a new world and a new society, and may really be the only way forward.
What I don’t like about the idea of perpetuation is that it has to be a smooth upward progress. I don’t
think it works like that. I think it’s more like a social flow of rebellion, something that moves through-
out the world, with eruptions in one place and then in another place. But there are continuities below
the discontinuities. We have to think in terms of disrupting bubbling movements rather than thinking
that it all depends on whether we can perpetuate the movement in one place. If we think in terms of
perpetuation in one place, I think at times it can lead us into either an institutionalization, which I think
is not much help, or it can lead us into a sense of defeat, perhaps, which I don’t think is right.57
The most important thing to remember, as Graeber points out, is that “once people's political horizons
have been broadened, the change is permanent.
56 Joel Dietz, ““Occupy Wall Street turned movements into international networks that didn’t exist before,” OuiShare,
January 7, 2013 <http://ouishare.net/2013/01/nathan-schneider-occupy-wall-street/>.
57 Jerome Roos, “Talking About a Revolution With John Holloway,” John Holloway, April 13, 2013
<http://www.johnholloway.com.mx/2013/05/01/talking-about-a-revolution-with-john-holloway/>.
Hundreds of thousands of Americans (and not only Americans, of course, but Greeks, Spaniards,
and Tunisians) now have direct experience of self-organization, collective action, and human
solidarity. This makes it almost impossible to go back to one's previous life and see things the same
way. While the world's financial and political elites skate blindly toward the next 2008-scale crisis,
we're continuing to carry out occupations of buildings, farms, foreclosed homes, and workplaces—
temporary or permanent—organizing rent strikes, seminars, and debtors' assemblies, and in doing
so, laying the groundwork for a genuinely democratic culture, and introducing the skills, habits, and
experience that would make an entirely new conception of politics come to life. 58
But second, and at least as important, we have to ask ourselves what kind of "success" is likely to
be achieved by leavening predominantly horizontal movements with a bit of verticalism in the form of
electoral movements. Admittedly, the idea of supplementing horizontalist movements based on
prefigurative politics and counter-institution building, with auxiliary political parties aimed at capturing
the state and running political interference for the real effort of building the new society within the
shell of the old, or perhaps helping the transition process along, sounds superficially plausible. The
problem is that, in practice, such political parties wind up sucking the energy and life out of the
counter-institution building effort in civil society, and diverting it instead into parliamentary politics.
Or worse yet, when political parties formed out of horizontalist movements actually achieve state
power, as with Syriza in Greece, they actually sabotage the efforts of those movements or give away
their gains on the ground in order to cut a "realistic" deal with capitalist states.
https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/syriza-did-not-support-the-commons/2016/01/02
So far I've relied on Dyer-Witheford's schema for classifying liberal capitalist and non- or anti-
capitalist versions of techno-utopianism. But his categorization is hardly exhaustive.
Within the Marxist milieu, autonomism is just one in a series of Marxist theories of high-tech, post-
scarcity communism going back to Bogdanov, as well as existing within a broader category of post-
capitalist models based on mixtures of prefigurative politics and counter-institutions very similar to
Negri's and Hardt's Exodus.
All these Marxist subcurrents are haunted by the spirit of Gramsci's concept of the "War of
Position" -- a prolonged process of culture change and institution-building in civil society, aimed at
surrounding the state as last bastion of capitalist power, as an alternative to a direct assault ("War of
Maneuver") aimed at capturing the state itself. The only difference is that the autonomists and other
prefigurative movements no longer see the war of position as a preparatory state for the war of
maneuver -- a final all-out assault on the state. For Gramsci the War of Maneuver -- the conquest of
state power -- was still the final step; it was just to be postponed until the cultural sappers had finished
their preparatory work.
For the autonomists and like-minded thinkers, the goal is Exodus rather than taking power. Since
the means of production are increasingly coextensive with our relationships in civil society, we no
longer need the obsolescent institutions of state and capital. We just need to tear down their enclosures
of the social economy we've already built -- and that can be done, to a large extent, by circumvention
rather than conquest.
John Holloway. A good contemporary specimen of the type is John Holloway's approach of
"changing the world without taking power." That means
58 Graeber, The Democracy Project, xix-xx.
to create, within the very society that is being rejected, spaces, moments, or areas of activity in
which a different world is prefigured. Rebellions in motion. From this perspective, the idea of
organization is no longer equivalent to that of the party, but rather entails the question of how the
different cracks that unravel the fabric of capitalism can recognize each other and connect....
...In the last twenty or thirty years we find a great many movements that claim something else: it
is possible to emancipate human activity from alienated labor by opening up cracks where one is
able to do things differently, to do something that seems useful, necessary, and worthwhile to us; an
activity that is not subordinated to the logic of profit.
These cracks can be spatial (places where other social relations are generated), temporal (“Here,
in this event, for the time that we are together, we are going to do things differently. We are going to
open windows onto another world.”), or related to particular activities or resources (for example,
cooperatives or activities that pursue a non-market logic with regard to water, software, education,
etc.). The world, and each one of us, is full of these cracks....
If we’re not going to accept the annihilation of humanity, which, to me, seems to be on
capitalism’s agenda as a real possibility, then the only alternative is to think that our movements are
the birth of another world. We have to keep building cracks and finding ways of recognizing them,
strengthening them, expanding them, connecting them; seeking the confluence or, preferably, the
commoning of the cracks.
...[L]et’s bear in mind that a precondition for the French Revolution was that, at a certain point,
the social network of bourgeois relations no longer needed the aristocracy in order to exist.
Likewise, we must work to reach a point where we can say “we don’t care if global capital isn’t
investing in Spain, because we’ve built a mutual support network that’s strong enough to enable us
to live with dignity.”59
Holloway sees socialist models based on taking state power as reproducing rather than abolishing
the capital-labor relationship in many ways. It takes for granted the existence of alienated wage labor
under capitalism, set over against institutional structures like corporate management and the state
which are separate from and above labor. The traditional Left aims at capturing these structures and
using them for the benefit of labor:
...a movement that struggles to improve the living standards of workers (considered as victims and
objects) immediately refers to the state. Why? Because the state, due to its very separation from
society, is the ideal institution if one seeks to achieve benefits for people. This is the traditional
thinking of the labor movement and that of the left governments that currently exist in Latin
America.60
The state option, including the seizure of state power by movements like Syriza and Podemos,
entails channeling aspirations and struggles into institutional conduits that, by necessity, force one to
seek a conciliation between the anger that these movements express and the reproduction of capital.
Because the existence of any government involves promoting the reproduction of capital (by
attracting foreign investment, or through some other means), there is no way around it. This
inevitably means taking part in the aggression that is capital. It’s what has already happened in
Bolivia and Venezuela, and it will also be the problem in Greece or Spain. 61
The new networked, horizontalist movements take just the opposite approach:
The rejection of alienated and alienating labor entails, at the same time, a critique of the institutional
59 Amador Fernández-Savater, "John Holloway: cracking capitalism vs. the state option," ROAR Magazine, September 29,
2015 <https://roarmag.org/essays/john-holloway-cracking-capitalism-vs-the-state-option/>.
60 Ibid.
61 Ibid.
and organizational structures, and the mindset that springs from it. This is how we can explain the
rejection of trade unions, parties, and the state that we observe in so many contemporary
movements, from the Zapatistas to the Greek or Spanish indignados.62
Nicos Poulantzas's structuralism is relevant here. Under capitalism, the state is forced by structural
imperatives to serve the needs of capital regardless of the personnel who compose it or their political
ideology. And regardless of the domestic balance of power between capital and the state, the same
analysis applies -- as Immanuel Wallerstein has shown -- to the relationship between the domestic
socialist state and the forces of global capital when a country is part of the larger division of labor in a
capitalist world-system.
Compare Holloway's views on state socialism to Negri and Hardt's comment on the Social
Democratic agenda as being “to reintegrate the working class within capital.”
It would mean, on the one hand, re-creating the mechanisms by which capital can engage, manage,
and organize productive forces and, on the other, resurrecting the welfare structures and social
mechanisms necessary for capital to guarantee the social reproduction of the working class. 63
To work, social democracy would have to first use the state to forcibly integrate production under
the control of capital even when capital was technically obsolete, either by outlawing competition from
more efficient forms of production or giving legacy capitalist interests a “property” right in the ability
to put the new forms of production to work. It’s an essentially Hamiltonian approach of propping up the
worth of large concentrations of capital by artificially maintaining a need for them.
This also entails a Schumpeterian approach (explained in our discussion of Romer above) which
views size and capital-intensiveness as inherently "progressive," which adds yet another reason for
hostility to new production technology.
The verticalist approach is obsolete in another sense. If the new horizontalist Left depicts the
boundaries between production process and society as blurred by the dissolution of the production
process into the workers' social relationships in society at large, Old Left workerism did the reverse,
blurring the boundaries between factory and society. Verticalism is characterized by the Old Left's
lionization of the industrial proletariat, and a model of society built around the workplace as its central
institution. Guy Standing used the term "labourism" to describe this tendency on the Old Left
(including Leninist Communism, Social Democracy and CIO-style industrial unionism). Unlike earlier
socialist and anarchist models that looked forward to increasing leisure and autonomy and a shrinkage
of both the cash nexus and the wage system, social democracy and industrial unionism presupposed
universal full-time employment at wage labor as the norm. They aimed at “full employment” with good
wages, benefits and job security, with the understanding that management would be allowed to manage
and labor would stay out of matters regarded as “management prerogatives” in return for these things.
The “full employment” agenda meant
all men in full-time jobs. Besides being sexist, this neglected all forms of work that were not labour (in-
cluding reproductive work in the home, caring for others, work in the community, and other self-chosen
activities). It also erased a vision of freedom from labour that had figured powerfully in radical thinking
in previous ages.64
62 Ibid.
63 Negri and Hardt, Commonwealt, p. 294.
64 Guy Standing, A Precariat Charter: From Denizens to Citizens (London, New Delhi, New York, Sydney: Bloomsbury,
2014), p. 16.
But since then—especially in the past two decades—the conventional full-time wage employment model
has become increasingly irrelevant. The size of the full time wage labor force has steadily shrunk as a por-
tion of the total economy; both the permanently unemployed and the precariat (the underemployed, part-
time workers, temporary workers, and guest workers) have grown as a share of the economy. For these
workers the old model of a workplace-based social safety net does not exist, and it has been radically scaled
back even for remaining full-time workers. Further, the precariat for the most part do not identify with the
workplace or wage employment as their parents and grandparents, and often have value systems more in
common with earlier socialists who saw their economic identity in terms of social or guild relations outside
the workplace.
Put bluntly, the proletariat's representatives demand decent labour, lots of it; the precariat wishes to es-
cape from labour, materially and psychologically, because its labour is instrumental, not self-defining.
Many in the precariat do not even aspire to secure labour. They saw their parents trapped in long-term
jobs, too frightened to leave, partly because they would have lost modest enterprise benefits that de-
pended on 'years of service'. But in any event, those jobs are no longer on offer to the precariat. Twenti-
eth-century spheres of labour protection—labour law, labour regulations, collective bargaining,
labourist social security—were constructed around the image of the firm, fixed workplaces, and fixed
working days and work-weeks that apply only to a minority in today's tertiary online society. While
proletarian consciousness is linked to long-term security in a firm, mine, factory or office, the pre-
cariat's consciousness is linked to a search for security outside the workplace.
The precariat is not a 'proto-proletariat', that is, becoming like the proletariat. But the centralization
of unstable labour to global capitalism is also why it is not an underclass, as some would have it. Ac -
cording to Marx, the proletariat wanted to abolish itself. The same could be said of the precariat. But
the proletariat wanted thereby to universalize stable labour. And whereas it had a material interest in
economic growth and the fiction of full employment, the precariat has an interest in recapturing a pro-
gressive vision of 'freedom of labour', so establishing a meaningful right to work.65
All this suggests we need a new model for struggle and for the post-capitalist transition.
Michel Bauwens. Left-wing theories of systemic transition to a high-tech post-capitalist economy
are hardly limited to Marxism. One of the most useful non-Marxist schools is the post-capitalist model
of commons-based peer production, which inclues that of Michel Bauwens of the Foundation for Peer-
to-Peer Alternatives.
Late capitalism, Bauwens writes (with Franco Iacomella), is beset by two main structural
irrationalities: artificial abundance and artificial scarcity.
1. The current political economy is based on a false idea of material abundance. We call it
pseudo-abundance. It is based on a commitment to permanent growth, the infinite accumulation of
capital and debt-driven dynamics through compound interest. This is unsustainable, of course,
because infinite growth is logically and physically impossible in any physically constrained, finite
system.
2. The current political economy is based on a false idea of “immaterial scarcity.” It believes
that an exaggerated set of intellectual property monopolies – for copyrights, trademarks and patents
– should restrain the sharing of scientific, social and economic innovations. Hence the system
discourages human cooperation, excludes many people from benefiting from innovation and slows
the collective learning of humanity. In an age of grave global challenges, the political economy
keeps many practical alternatives sequestered behind private firewalls or unfunded if they cannot
generate adequate profits.66
of the Commons" in David Bollier and Silke Helfrich, eds., The Wealth of the Commons: A World Beyond Market and State
(Levellers Press, 2013). Online version at <http://wealthofthecommons.org/essay/peer-peer-economy-and-new-civilization-
centered-around-sustenance-commons>.
cultivators only on condition of paying tribute to the engrosser, or a landed oligarchy is superimposed
on existing cultivators. Other forms of artificial scarcity are regulatory entry barriers that impose
unnecessary capital outlays for undertaking production or limit the number of producers, regulations
that impose artificial floors under the cost of subsistence, restraints on competition between producers
that facilitate administered pricing, and restraints on competition in the issuance of credit and currency
that enable those engaged in that function to charge usurious prices for it. Perhaps the most important
form of artificial scarcity today is so-called "intellectual property," which is a legal monopoly on the
right to perform certain tasks or use certain knowledge, rather than engrossment of the means of
production themselves.
Artificial scarcity, like artificial abundance, is becoming increasingly unsustainable. Copyright is
rapidly becoming unenforceable, as the proprietary content industries are learning to their dismay. And
the implosion of necessary capital outlays for manufacturing and of the feasible scale for micro-
manufacturing, coupled with the ease of sharing digital CAD/CAM files, is raising the transaction costs
of enforcing industrial patents to unsustainable levels. Intensive growing techniques like Permaculture
are far more efficient in terms of output per acre than factory-farming, thus reducing the necessity and
value of engrossed land for people to feed themselves. And the explosion vernacular building
technologies, coupled with the fiscal exhaustion of states that enforce zoning regulations and building
codes and the like, means that the imposition of artificial costs of comfortable subsistence is likewise
becoming unsustainable.
Meanwhile, as capitalism reaches these terminal crises, it is generating its successor -- its
gravedigger classes -- from within its own interstices. Like the classical slave economy and feudalism,
capitalist political economy is reaching crises of extensive inputs and will be supplanted by a successor
system that is able to pursue intensive use of inputs in ways its predecessor couldn't. And the phase
transition includes an "Exodus" very much like that envisioned by Negri and Hardt.
The first transition: Rome to feudalism
At some point in its evolution (3rd century onwards?), the Roman empire ceases to expand (the
cost of of maintaining empire and expansion exceeds its benefits). No conquests means a drying up
of the most important raw material of a slave economy, i.e. the slaves, which therefore become more
‘expensive’. At the same time, the tax base dries up, making it more and more difficult to maintain
both internal coercion and external defenses. It is in this context that Perry Anderson mentions for
example that when Germanic tribes were about to lay siege to a Roman city, they would offer to free
the slaves, leading to an exodus of the city population. This exodus and the set of difficulties just
described, set of a reorientation of some slave owners, who shift to the system of coloni, i.e. serfs.
I.e. slaves are partially freed, can have families, can produce from themselves and have villages,
giving the surplus to the new domain holders.
Hence, the phase transition goes something like this: 1) systemic crisis ; 2) exodus 3) mutual
reconfiguration of the classes.
This whole process would of course take five centuries. In the First European Revolution, ... the
feudal system would only consolidate around 975, the date of the political revolution confirming the
previous phase transition, and setting up a consolidated growth phase for the new system (doubling
of the population between 10 and 13th century). 67
...[T]he failure of extensive development is what brought down earlier civilizations and modes
of production. For example, slavery was not only marked by low productivity, but could not extend
this productivity as that would require making the slaves more autonomous, so slave-based empires
70 Section 2.1.B. The emergence of peer to peer as technological infrastructure, in Bauwens, The Peer to Peer Manifesto:
The Emergence of P2P Civilization and Political Economy (MasterNewMedia: November 3, 2007)
<http://www.masternewmedia.org/news/2007/11/03/the_peer_to_peer_manifesto.htm>.
71 Section 3.1.B. The Communism of Capital, or, the cooperative nature of Cognitive Capitalism, in Bauwens, The Peer to
Peer Manifesto.
72 Section 7.1.B. P2P, Postmodernity, Cognitive Capitalism: within and beyond, in Bauwens, The Peer to Peer Manifesto.
73 2.1.B. The emergence of peer to peer as technological infrastructure, in Bauwens, The Peer to Peer Manifesto.
74 7.1.B. P2P, Postmodernity, Cognitive Capitalism: within and beyond, in Bauwens, The Peer to Peer Manifesto
production shows a new form of creating value, that is in fundamental aspects ‘outside the
market’. Typically, in commons-based production we have a common pool, accessible to
everyone (Linux, Wikipedia), around which an ecology of business can form to create and sell
scarcities (usually services and experiences). In sharing-oriented production (YouTube, Google
documents), we have proprietary platforms that enable and empower the sharing, but at the same
time, sell the aggregated attention (a scarcity), to the advertising market. Finally, in the third
crowdsourcing mode, companies try to integrate participation in their own value chain and
framework.
So the good news is that indeed business is possible. But I would like the readers to entertain the
following proposition, nl. That:
1) The creation of non-monetary value is exponential
2) The monetization of such value is linear
In other words, we have a growing discrepancy between the direct creation of use value through
social relationships and collective intelligence (open platforms create near infinite value through the
operations of the laws of Metcalfe and Reed), but only a fraction of that value can actually be
captured by business and money. Innovation is becoming social and diffuse, an emergent property
of the networks rather than an internal R & D affair within corporations; capital is becoming an a
posteriori intervention in the realization of innovation, rather than a condition for its occurrence;
more and more positive externalizations are created from the social field.
What this announces is a crisis of value, most such value is beyond measure, but also essentially
a crisis of accumulation of capital. Furthermore, we lack a mechanism for the existing institutional
world to re-fund what it receives from the social world. So on top of all of that, we have a crisis of
social reproduction: peer production is collective sustainable, but not individually.
For all of this, we will need new policies, major reforms and restructurations in our economy and
society.
But one thing is sure: we will have markets, but the core logic of the emerging experience
economy, operating as it does in the world of non-rival exchange, is unlikely to have capitalism as
its core logic.
It can no longer grow extensively, but it cannot replace it by intensive growth. The history of
slave empires and their transition to feudal structures is about to repeat itself, but in a different
form.75
The successor society centered on peer production will not have capitalism's core logic (material
abundance, immaterial scarcity) at all. It will be steady-state and sustainable, with true cost pricing, in
its use of physical resources, and it will permit the free replication, sharing and use of information
without limit.76
Much as when "Marx identified the manufacturing plants of Manchester as the blueprint for the
new capitalist society," Bauwens sees commons-based peer production as the core logic of the post-
capitalist successor society.77
A new class of knowledge workers, in its broad sense already the majority of the working
population in the West, and poised to be in the same situation elsewhere in a few decades, are
creating new practices and tools that enable them to do what they need to do, i.e. knowledge
84 Ibid.
85 Bauwens and Iacomella, op. cit.
not their actual production. If we can diminish that transportation, we can have a much lighter
impact on the planet.''
Bauwens suggests an economic model involving micro-factories that produce designs created
via open-source networks.86
Bauwens sees commons-based peer production as a post-capitalist mode of production that will
succeed capitalism, growing out of it in a matter analogous to how the manorial economy emerged
from the collapse of the slave economy of classical antiquity and capitalism emerged from late
feudalism. And like the previous transitions, peer-production will evolve as a solution to the crisis
tendencies of late capitalism when the latter reaches its limits.
Although his approach is closer to the Exodus and horizontalism of Negri and Hardt, it is not purely
one of quietism towards the state. Bauwens sees a need for active engagement with the state to manage
the transition and to run interference on behalf of emergent P2P institutions, even if the primary path is
evolutionary rather than by seizure of the state and implementation of a post-capitalist successor
society through it.
A first step is to become aware of the isomorphism, the commonality, of peer to peer processes
in the various fields. That people devising and using P2P sharing programs, start realizing that they
are somehow doing the same thing than the alterglobalisation movement, and that both are related to
the production of Linux, and to participative epistemologies. Thus what we must do first is building
bridges of cooperation and understanding across the social fields....
...[T]he second step is to "furiously" build the commons. When we develop Linux, it is there,
cannot be destroyed, and by its very existence and use, builds another reality, based on another
social logic, the P2P logic. Adopting a network sociality and building dense interconnections as we
participate in knowledge creation and exchange is enormously politically significant. By feeding our
immaterial and spiritual needs outside of the consumption system, we can stop the logic which is
destroying our ecosphere. The present system may not like opposition, but even more does it fear
indifference, because it can feed on the energy of strife, but starts dying when it is shunted. This is
what is being expressed by Toni Negri's concept of Exodus, and what other call 'Desertion' . These
commentators note that it was 'the refusal of work' in the seventies, with blue-collar workers
showing increasing dissatisfaction with the Taylorist/Fordist system of work, that lead to the
fundamental re-arrangement of work in the first place. In the past, the labor movement and other
social movements mostly shared the same values, and it was mostly about a fairer share of the pie.
But the new struggles are mostly about producing a new kind of pie, and producing it in a different
way. Or perhaps an even more correct metaphor: it is about the right to produce altogether different
kinds of pie.
Today, the new ethic says that 'to resist is in the first place to create'. The world we want is the
world we are creating through our cooperative P2P ethos, it is visible in what we do today, not an
utopian creation for the future. Building the commons has a crucial ingredient: the building of a
dense alternative media network, for permanent and collective self-education in human culture,
away from the mass-consumption model promoted by the corporate media.
Thus, if there is an 'offensive' strategy it would look like this: to build the commons, day after
day, the process of creating of a society within society. In this context, the emergence of the internet
and the web, is a tremendous step forward....
Regarding the commons such an approach would entail:
1) a defense of the physical commons and the development of new institutions such as trusts to
86 Shane Gilchrist, "Sharing the Future," Otago Daily Times Online News (New Zealand), November 30, 2015
<http://www.odt.co.nz/lifestyle/magazine/364835/sharing-future>.
manage the environment;
2) an end to exaggerated private appropriation of the knowledge commons;
3) a universal basic income to create the conditions for the expansion of peer production;
4) any measure that speeds up the distribution of capital.
In the field of the gift economy: the promotion of reciprocity-based schemes, using alternative
currency schemes based on equal time (Time Dollars and the like)
Finally, peer to peer also demands self-transformation. As we said, P2P is predicated on
abundance, on transcending the animal impulse based on win-lose games. But abundance is not just
objective, i.e. also, and perhaps most importantly, subjective. This is why tribal economies
considered themselves to live in abundance, and were egalitarian in nature. This is why happiness
researchers show that it is not poverty that makes us unhappy, but inequality. Thus, the P2P ethos
demands a conversion, to a point of view, to a set of skills, which allow us to focus ourselves to
fulfilling our immaterial and spiritual needs directly, and not through a perverted mechanism of
consumption. As we focus on friendships, connections, love, knowledge exchange, the cooperative
search for wisdom, the construction of common resources and use value, we direct our attention
away from the artificial needs that are currently promoted, and this time we personally and
collectively stop feeding the Beast that we have ourselves created. 87
90 Ibid.
such with an insurrectionist or parliamentary politics aimed at seizure of the state. But in fact the
autonomist Exodus is very much a class struggle, and also treats technology as a political weapon
insofar as it frees self-organized social labor from dependence on the enormous heaps of obsolescent
capital controlled by the ruling class.
Michel Bauwens compares the Accelerationist approach to politics to that of the P2P Foundation:
What is seems to be in the end, is that the combined demand for full automation and the basic
income, functions as an utopia, and while utopias are very useful to free the mind and the desires
and show possibilities, they are also dangerous. They appear to be a political program to unite a
variety of forces, who win power and then, afterwards, can start changing things. But what if we do
not gain power this way ?
At the P2P Foundation, we see that a bit differently. The first task is to create prefigurative
livelihoods which actually embody different post-capitalist logics, and to build social and political
forces around this concrete transformative change....
In the end, asking for two utopian demands that are extremely hard to achieve and impose,
seems an expression of the traditional leftist strategy, that we must first win power, and then ‘we
will change everything’. The alternative is to build the future right now, to change the mode and
relations of production where we can, right now, and to build political power and transition
proposals on the basis of a counter-hegemony that has already changed reality through its practice
and strength.91
There's a whole host of left-wing critiques of the capitalist version of techno-utopianism, centered
on the Silicon Valley tech industry and corporate-enclosed sharing economy. A good example is
Richard Eskow's think piece on the "techno-libertarians."92 It focuses on the likes of Peter Thiel and
Uber; the problem with this culture, he writes, is that their business model treats products primarily as a
source of revenue -- or more accurately rents -- rather than an end in themselves. This primary evil
carries with it a number of secondary symptoms, like the pathological culture of motivation-speak and
buzzwords and the cult of "Great Men" like Bill Gates, Steve Jobs and Mark Zuckerberg. Monopolies
transfer income from workers and consumers to rentiers. And the authoritarian form taken by the
technologies, as they are developed under a proprietary information regime, regards users less as the
ultimate reason for the technologies than as a revenue stream to be permanently locked in via user
agreements and licensing.
So if networked communication and cybernetic technologies are so potentially liberating, why are
they so authoritarian in the forms they currently take? The Italian Marxist Antonio Gramsci, who died
in Mussolini's prisons in the 1930s, once wrote that "the old world is dying, and the new one struggles
to be born; now is the time of monsters." In the case of the new world offered by liberatory
technologies, most of the birth struggle results from the principalities and powers of the old world
fighting to imprison the forces of the new world in their old institutional framework.
Lewis Mumford borrowed a term from geology -- "cultural pseudo-morph" -- to describe the
process by which new, potentially liberating technologies were instead incorporated into the
91 Michel Bauwens, "Michel Bauwens on P2P and Accelerationism (1)," P2P Foundation Blog, January 14, 2016
<https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/53466-2/2016/01/14>.
92 Richard Escow, "Rise of the Techno-Libertarians," Salon.com, April 12, 2015 <https://www.salon.com/2015/04/12/
rise_of_the_techno_libertarians_the_5_most_socially_destructive_aspects_of_silicon_valley_partner/>.
institutional forms of the old world, like new mineral deposits that gradually formed a fossil in the
shape of buried organic matter. He was referring in particular to the technologies of what he called the
neo-technic age, like the electric motor, which by nature were low-overhead and decentralizing. The
optimal use of such technologies would have been to replace the paleotechnic order (in which large
factories were built to economize on steam power by running as many machines as possible off a prime
mover) with a new model of manufacturing where a motor of any size could be built into a machine
wherever it was used, the machine could be scaled to production flow, production flow could be scaled
to immediate demand, and the site of production could be located close to the point of consumption.
Instead, the forces of the old paleotechnic world were strong enough to put the new wine of
electrical power into the old institutional framework of Dark Satanic Mills, in the form of mass
production (which threw away all the special advantages of electric power for decentralized, lean
production).
Although Mumford didn't live to see it, the internal crisis tendencies and inefficiencies of mass
production eventually led, from the '70s on, to the outsourcing of actual production to small job-shops
owned by independent contractors. The new technological wine still remained in the old corporate
bottles, thanks to the use of patents and trademarks to enforce a corporate monopoly on the distribution
of a product they didn't actually make. But the rapid implosion in cost and scale of tabletop CNC
machinery, especially open-source versions, are unleashing productive forces that are making
"intellectual property" unenforceable. It's only a matter of time before garage factories using small-
scale general-purpose machinery to produce on a craft model are ignoring patents and trademarks and
making goods for local neighborhood markets all over the world.
The same is true of network communications and digital culture. The kinds of thinkers on the Left
we've been surveying here see commons-based peer production as the kernel of a post-capitalist society
that will gradually emerge from within the interstices of the present system, coalesce into a new
system, and supplant the old one.
These new technologies of abundance are still held captive within proprietary frameworks like
Windows and OSX operating systems, corporate-owned sharing apps like Uber and AirBNB, and the
like -- enclosed in a neo-feudal "intellectual property" framework to enable the extraction of rents.
But the days of this intermediate stage are numbered. The productive forces unleashed by these new
technologies cannot be contained by the old authoritarian class relations, for all the reasons we've
examined here. So the right-wing version of techno-libertarianism is a counterfeit of the real thing, a
last-ditch effort to capture the technologies of freedom and abundance and harness them to their own
greed.
V. Paul Mason
Most recently in this general framework is Paul Mason's book Postcapitalism. As we shall see
below it's very much in the same tradition of "War of Position" and "Exodus" that we've been
examining so far. On the whole it's a very positive development. Having achieved publicity roughly
comparable to David Graeber's Debt and Thomas Picketty's Capital in the 21st Century, it's probably
brought more mainstream attention to these currents of left-wing techno-utopianism than they've ever
received before.
Perhaps the weakest part of Mason's book (although his political program, which I'll come to later,
is also a contender) is his treatment of the crisis tendencies of late capitalism.
In some ways his analysis closely resembles that of Bauwens -- most notably, the inability of
93 Quoted in Sheldon Richman, "Bastiat on the Socialization of Wealth," Center for a Stateless Society, March 23, 2013
<https://c4ss.org/content/17835>.
capitalism to capture the value created by peer-production.94 In this, he is entirely correct. Still, his
analysis comes off as weak, in my opinion, compared to the clarity of Bauwens's framing of the twin
structural contradictions of capitalism (its inability to capture the value created by peer production, and
the peak resource input crises resulting from the growing socialization of cost). Mason does devote
considerable space to the narrower problem if climate change in the latter part of his book, but not to a
systematic analysis of resource input shortages as a broader structural problem.
Mason is also correct, as he argues in Chapter Two, that the current crisis is secular and structural
rather than cyclical, because capitalism has failed to generate a new Kondratieff wave to renew itself
for another epoch. But his explanation of why this is true is a bit garbled, mainly because he rejects the
most useful conceptual basis for explaining why the Kondratieff wave is failing this time around: the
over-accumulationist/under-consumptionist model of late capitalist crisis. Mason rejects all economic
models based on the idea of a chronic mismatch between levels of investment and levels of
consumption.95
Mason's analysis would have benefited greatly from incorporating the over-investment model of the
Monthly Review group, going back to Baran and Sweezy's Monopoly Capital. The reason new
Kondratieff waves give capitalism a renewed life is that they periodically generate another large-scale
wave of large-scale investment in fundamentally new infrastructures, and provide an outlet to soak up
surplus investment capital for another generation and reset the crisis of over-accumulation.
As Mason points out, people like Carlota Perez argue for generating a new Kondratieff wave based
on "info-tech, biotech and green energy."96 But the reason such agendas are doomed to failure is that the
nature of the new technology itself works directly counter to the need for a new "engine of
accumulation" to provide a sink for surplus capital and restore the rate of profit.
For the past generation or so, new production technology has been decreasingly capital-intensive
(or increasingly ephemeral), starting in the '70s and '80s with new small-scale CNC machinery suited
for the job-shops of Emilia-Romagna and Shenzhen, and running through the current generation of
open-source tabletop CNC routers, cutting tables, 3D printers, and forth that can be built for under a
thousand dollars. The result is that it takes much, much less capital for production and a great deal
more superfluous capital is left sitting around without a profitable outlet for investment than in
previous technological revolutions.
Douglas Rushkoff remarked on the same phenomenon, in the realm of immaterial production:
The fact is, most Internet businesses don't require venture capital. The beauty of these technologies
is that they decentralize value creation. Anyone with a PC and bandwidth can program the next
Twitter or Facebook plug-in, the next iPhone app, or even the next social network. While a few
thousand dollars might be nice, the hundreds of millions that venture capitalists want to—need to—
invest, simply aren't required....
The banking crisis began with the dot.com industry, because here was a business sector that did
not require massive investments of capital in order to grow. (I spent an entire night on the phone
with one young entrepreneur who secured $20 million of capital from a venture firm, trying to
figure out how to possibly spend it. We could only come up with $2 million of possible
expenditures.) What's a bank to do when its money is no longer needed?...
[Decentralized value creation] is, quite simply, cheaper to do. There's less money in it. Not
necessarily less money for us, the people doing the exchanging, but less money for the institutions
that have traditionally extracted value from our activity. If I can create an application or even a Web
94 Mason, Postcapitalism: A Guide to Our Future (Allan Lane, 2015),pp. 25-26.
95 Ibid., pp. 61-62, 69.
96 Ibid., p. 46.
site like this one without borrowing a ton of cash from the bank, then I am also undermining
America's biggest industry—finance.97
For Mason the new Kondratieff wave, rather than generating a new cycle of large-scale
infrastructure development based on new technologies, to replace a decaying earlier generation's
infrastructure, results from capital's technological innovation to the power of labor. And the last
Kondratieff wave failed because of the unprecedented defeat of the forces of labor by neoliberalism.98
So compared to that of Bauwens and the Monthly Review Group, Mason's analysis of the crisis
tendencies of late capitalism falls a bit flat. Nevertheless, his general framing has a familiar Marxian
ring to it, in the same general tradition we've been considering: the technologies and institutions of
post-capitalism are unleashing productive forces that cannot be contained within the productive
relations of capitalism, and therefore must eventually "burst out of their capitalist integument" and
become the basis for a fundamentally new system.
...[T]he technologies we've created are not compatible with capitalism -- not in its present form and
maybe not in any form. Once capitalism can no longer adapt to technological change, postcapitalism
becomes necessary. When behaviours and organizations adapted to exploiting technological change
appear spontaneously, postcapitalism becomes possible. 99
His view of the nature of the technological changes within the capitalist system that doom it to
extinction have a lot in common with both the autonomists and Bauwens.
First, information technology has reduced the need for work, blurred the edges between work
and free time and loosened the relationship between work and wages.
Second, information goods are corroding the market's ability to form prices correctly. That is
because markets are based on scarcity while information is abundant. The system's defense
mechanism is to form monopolies on a scale not seen in the past 200 years -- yet these cannot last.
Third, we're seeing the spontaneous rise of collaborative production: goods, services and
organizations that are appearing that no longer respond to the dictates of the market and the
managerial hierarchy.100
These new social forms amount to a new system arising "within the shell of the old," that will build
a new system within the interstices of capitalism, coalesce and finally supplant it.
Almost unnoticed, in the niches and hollows of the market system, whole swathes of economic
life are beginning to move to a different rhythm. Parallel currencies, time banks, cooperatives and
self-managed spaces have proliferated, and often as a direct result of the shattering of old structures
after the 2008 crisis.
New forms of ownership, new forms of lending, new legal contracts: a whole business
subculture has emerged over the past ten years, which the media has dubbed the 'sharing economy'.
Buzz-terms such as the 'commons' and 'peer-production' are thrown around, but few have bothered
to ask what this means for capitalism itself. 101
And the stigmergic, horizontal forms of organization facilitated by networked communications
have drastically reduced the transaction costs of coordinating action outside of traditional institutional
hierarchy. They have made the central planning of the large corporation as obsolete as the central
planning of Gosplan.
97 Douglas Rushkoff, "How the Tech Boom Terminated California's Economy," Fast Company, July 10, 2009
<https://www.fastcompany.com/1307504/how-tech-boom-terminated-californias-economy>.
98 Mason, Postcapitalism, p. 78.
99 Ibid., xiii.
100 Ibid., xv.
101 Ibid., xv.
Economists like to demonstrate the archaic nature of command planning with mind-games like
'imagine the Soviet Union tried to create Starbucks'. Now, here's a more intriguing game: imagine if
Amazon, Toyota or Boeing tried to create Wikipedia. 102
But, much as Bauwens has argued, Mason sees capitalism attempting to prolong its own life by
incorporating the new technologies and social relationships into a corporate institutional structure, and
enclosing them as a source of rents.
Once you can copy/paste a paragraph, you can do it with a music track, a movie, the design of a
turbofan engine and the digital mockup of the fctory that will make it.
Once you can copy and paste something, it can be reproduced for free. It has, in economics-
speak, a 'zero marginal cost'.
Info-capitalists have a solution to this: make it legally impossible to copy certain kinds of
information....
With info-capitalism, a monopoly is not just some clever tactic to maximize profit. It is the only
way an industry can run....
...Only intellectual property law and a small piece of code in the iTunes track prevent everybody
on earth from owning every piece of music ever made. Apple's mission statement, properly
expressed, is to prevent the abundance of music. 103
This applies just as much to control of the physical means of production. When small-scale CNC
manufacturing tools fall in price by two orders of magnitude, so that craft production with high-tech,
general-purpose tools once again comes within the economic means of individual artisans or small
cooperative shops, capitalist ownership of the machinery for profit extraction is replaced by capitalist
ownership of the patents.
Mason, in Marxist terms, stresses the contradiction between new productive forces and old social
relations of production:
Today, the main contradiction in modern capitalism is between the possibility of free, abundant
socially produced goods, and a system of monopolies, banks and governments struggling to
maintain control over power and information. That is, everything is pervaded by a fight between
network and hierarchy.104
Like Dyer-Witheford, Mason also appeals to Marx's "Fragment on Machines" from the Grundrisse
as anticipating the destruction of capitalism by "General Intellect."
In an economy where machines do most of the work, where human labour is really abou
supervising, mending and designing the machines, the nature of the knowledge locked insie the
machines must, he writes, be 'social'....
In the Fragment on Machines, these two ideas -- that the driving force of production is
knowledge, and that knowledge stored in machines is social -- led Marx to the following
conclusions.
First, in a heavily mechanized capitalism, boosting productivity through better knowledge is a
much more attractive source of profit than extending the working day, or speeding up labour.... [A]
knowledge solution is cheap and limitless.
Second, Marx argued, knowledge-driven capitalism cannot support a price mechanism whereby
the value of something is dictated by the value of the inputs needed to produce it. It is impossibly
value inputs when they come in the form of social knowledge. Knowledge-driven production tends
I mentioned above the tendency of the establishment Left and verticalist types, with their fixation
on organizational mass and structure and their insurrectionary model of social change based on seizure
of the state, to reflexively conflate the liberal capitalist and Leftist versions of techno-utopianism.
Stephanie McMillan. One of the least thoughtful specimens of this genus is Stephanie
McMillan,130 as revealed in her response to Mason's article "The end of capitalism has begun"131 (a
preview article in The Guardian essentially summarizing the arguments of his book).
129 Ibid., p. 279.
130 Stephanie McMillan, " So-Called “Post-Capitalism” is Just Another Crappy Capitalist Snowjob," SkewedNews, July 22,
2015 <http://skewednews.net/index.php/2015/07/22/called-post-capitalism-just-another-crappy-capitalist-snowjob/>.
131 Paul Mason, "The end of capitalism has begun," The Guardian, July 17, 2015 <http://www.theguardian.com/books/
2015/jul/17/postcapitalism-end-of-capitalism-begun>.
She dismisses Mason's post-capitalist vision as "just another crappy capitalist snowjob" (the title of
her article). The problem is, it's not exactly clear from one paragraph to the next whether her critique is
based on a careless reading of Mason's actual article, or she's treating him as a type and telescoping
together what he actually says with other stuff said by a lot of "New Economy" and Silicon Valley
types she doesn't like.
She wouldn't be the first figure on the Left to lump decentralism, networks and high tech together
with Gingrichoid dotcom capitalism under a general heading of "things I don't like," and to
unjustifiably dismiss left-wing visions of commons-based peer production and open-source as Trojan
horses for Peter Thiel-style capitalism. Thomas Frank is the classic example of this tendency. I've also
encountered it in personal exchanges with Doug Henwood of the Left Business Observer, a sort of
centrist social democrat. Henwood -- in a conversation where he defended copyright as a protection for
creators against my advocacy of information freedom -- told me the model of commons-based peer
production and information freedom advocated by Bauwens sounded "like 90s dotcom capitalism." All
I can say is that anyone who seriously compares Richard Stallman to Bill Gates is out of their
intellectual depth.
McMillan is obviously doing the same thing herself, based on all the "theys" she cites in this
passage and their (to put it kindly) tangential relationship to anything Mason actually says:
First they offer reassuring-sounding it-won’t-be-that-bad schemes like “cradle to cradle,”
“conscious capitalism,” “social entrepreneurship,” and “green capitalism.” But these are
quickly revealed to be the same old crap in prettier packaging.
Then they decry capitalism’s “excesses” by defining the problem not a capitalism itself, but
as errors within an otherwise acceptable economic system. They add qualifiers: crony
capitalism, disaster capitalism, corporate capitalism, blah blah blah. They build stellar careers
as public intellectuals by offering the comforting thought that if we could simply eliminate its
worst elements, the system might yet be saved. But this formula sounds increasingly hollow, as
people figure out that the worst aspects of capitalism aren’t a mistake. They’re inherent to it. 132
McMillan, based on her other writing in SkewedNews, favors an insurrectionary approach in which
the global working class, organized into a mass movement, seize the means of production. But the
problem isn't that she disagrees with Mason's vision of post-capitalism as a future system that will grow
out of the present one the way capitalism grew out of feudalism. It's that she doesn't even do him the
courtesy of acknowledging that that is, in fact, what he envisions. She suggests, in a disregard of what
he actually wrote that not only borders on disingenuousness but spends a bit of time sightseeing there,
that he views the existing sharing economy and precaritization of labor as post-capitalism already in
being.
In a Guardian article anticipating his new book “Postcapitalism,” he spreads the good
news that we have already entered the post-capitalist era, “without us noticing.”
But hold off on the victory party, comrades. If we were beyond capitalism, we would have
noticed. I don’t know about you, but I imagine that a post-capitalist world would feel a little
less like the same old frenzied forced march on the treadmill of anxiety, alienation, and failure
to make ends meet.133
To repeat, it's hard not to suspect this misconstruction of being flat-out disingenuous or wilfully
obtuse, considering how many times Mason unambiguously repeats that "[w]ithout us noticing, we are
entering the postcapitalist era" only in the sense that the nuclei around which post-capitalism will
Kate Aronoff. Other critics are more thoughtful than McMillan (it would be hard to be less so).
Kate Aronoff, for example, recognizes the liberatory potential of the new technologies, despite her fear
that they will be successfully hijacked by Silicon Valley capitalism absent political action to divert the
currents of change into a more progressive channel. And above all she gets credit for at least describing
Mason's position honestly.
Mason’s call to “direct all actions towards the transition — not the defense of random elements
of the old system,” to focus solely on building alternatives, is a false dichotomy. If Syriza’s project
in Greece has shown anything, it’s that combining a broad-based solidarity economy with political
power is deeply threatening to neo-liberalism, the top brass of which will risk self-implosion to
stamp it out. Acting alone, Solidarity for All didn’t provoke a sadistic backlash from Greece’s
creditors. Syriza’s victory at the polls, its leadership’s presence at the negotiating table in Brussels,
and the egalitarian populist parties grasping at state power across the Mediterranean did — but
neither the challenge nor the solution could exist without the other.
Millennial-led movements from Black Lives Matter to Occupy Wall Street have already put the
social technologies Mason describes into practice, and are writing new rules for how popular
uprisings work in the 21st century. Podemos, Spain’s ascendant populist party, uses a sub-Reddit to
make decisions among members at the national level. Thankfully, technology is changing
organizing at least as much as it is the economy. Capitalism isn’t going anywhere without a fight, no
matter how inventive the alternatives.
If the early 20th century labor heroine Lucy Parsons were alive now, she might add an
addendum on to the statement she’s best remembered by: “Never be deceived that the rich will
permit you to innovate away their wealth.” Today’s movements will need to be at least as creative as
the forces they’re taking on, and be building solutions that are even more so. Post-capitalism is
coming, but a new and even more disruptive tradition of organizing will have to clear the way
first.142
The problem is that Aronoff conflates "political action" as such with political action aimed at
controlling the state. It may well be that networked movements like Occupy Wall Street or Syntagma
are useful both in articulating the subjectivity of the classes building the new society, and in running
political interference and mobilizing the public in defense of the new counter-institutions where the
state actively menaces them. The swarming done by the worldwide support movement for the EZLN,
back in the '90s, is a good example of this approach. The direct actions taken by Occupy Wall Street
and Occupy Oakland, the Block the Boat campaign on the U.S. west coast, and Black Lives Matter, are
also good examples. And such movements can exist as direct outgrowths of the groups engaged in
building counter-institutions, if not actually coextensive with them. And Podemos, which Aronoff also
mentioned, has a much more distributed and locally focused character, functioning much more as a
facilitating platform for the local counter-institutions themselves -- arguably closer to Bauwens's
idealized Partner State model than to Syriza.
"Political action" focused mainly on representation in the state, and working through it, on the other
hand, is a different matter altogether. And the choice of the Syriza movement as a positive example is
particularly unfortunate, for all the reasons we considered earlier.
Political action may be necessary. As Aronoff suggested, it is indeed a mistake to create a false
dichotomy with counter-institution building. But framing "political action" as primarily state action,
rather than a component of the counter-institution building movements themselves, is precisely the kind
of false dichotomy we need to avoid. Political models centered on the conquest of power, and
collective action through captured institutional hierarchies, are -- to repeat -- obsolete.
We don't need the state's policy apparatus to implement the new society, as envisioned by Marxist
models of the transitional proletarian dictatorship. All we need is to block efforts by the state to
suppress the emergence of the new society; and for that purpose movements outside the state, engaged
in swarming, blocking and sabotage, are what is needed.
Aronoff's revision of Lucy Parson's notwithstanding, we're not talking about the rich letting us do
anything. The whole point of all the horizontalist analyses we've seen of the internal contradictions of
capitalism is that they can't stop us. The technological changes that are destroying the capitalist state's
enforcement mechanisms are part and parcel of the technologies of the new society itself. The same
technologies that serve as building blocks of the new society are rendering the state unable to suppress
the new society. In that sense, we can indeed innovate our way out of capitalism.
Conclusion
142 Kate Aronoff, "Have reports of the death of capitalism been greatly exaggerated?" OpenDemocracy.net, July 28, 2015
<https://www.opendemocracy.net/transformation/kate-aronoff/have-reports-of-death-of-capitalism-been-greatly-
exaggerated>.
As I noted at the outset of this study, there are two broad groups -- sometimes using superficially
similar rhetoric but in fact fundamentally opposed -- that celebrate the emergence of a new kind of
society based on current technological trends. One such group, whose material interests center on
putting new wine in old bottles, enclosing the new liberatory technologies of abundance within a
corporate framework of artificial scarcity for the sake of rent extraction, are trying to pass off a
counterfeit of the real thing. Another group is promoting the real thing -- among them autonomists like
Dyer-Witheford, Hardt and Negri, groups like Oekonux that see peer-production and free and open-
source software as kernels of a future communist society, and thinkers like Michel Bauwens of the P2P
Foundation who envision a system incorporating non-capitalist markets along with cooperative
production based on the natural resource and information commons.
Mason, I think, falls unmistakably in the latter category.
The false prophets of corporate information capitalism do a great deal of harm in passing
themselves off as the real thing. But deluded figures on the Left like McMillan, who pretend that the
two groups are the same, arguably do even more damage by discrediting our best hope for a post-
capitalist society.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Kate Aronoff. "Have reports of the death of capitalism been greatly exaggerated?"
OpenDemocracy.net, July 28, 2015 <https://www.opendemocracy.net/transformation/kate-
aronoff/have-reports-of-death-of-capitalism-been-greatly-exaggerated>.
Ronald Bailey. “Post-Scarcity Prophet: Economist Paul Romer on growth, technological change,
and an unlimited human future” Reason, December 2001 <http://reason.com/archives/2001/12/01/post-
scarcity-prophet/>
Michel Bauwens. "Can the Experience Economy Be Capitalist?" P2P Foundation Blog, September
27, 2007 <https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/can-the-experience-economy-be-capitalist/2007/09/27>.
Michel Bauwens. "Michel Bauwens on P2P and Accelerationism (1)" P2P Foundation Blog,
January 14, 2016 <https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/53466-2/2016/01/14>.
Bauwens. Peer to Peer and Human Evolution: On "the P2P relational dynamic" as the premise of
the next civilizational stage (Foundation for P2P Alternatives, Draft 1.93, May 21, 2005)
<http://p2pfoundation.net/Manifesto>.
Bauwens. The Peer to Peer Manifesto: The Emergence of P2P Civilization and Political Economy
(MasterNewMedia: November 3, 2007)
<http://www.masternewmedia.org/news/2007/11/03/the_peer_to_peer_manifesto.htm>.
Bauwens. "The Political Economy of Peer Production" CTheory.net, December 1, 2005
<http://www.ctheory.net/articles.aspx?id=499>.
Bauwens. "Three Times Exodus, Three Phase Transitions" P2P Foundation Blog, May 2, 2010
<https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/three-times-exodus-three-phase-transitions/2010/05/02>.
Michel Bauwens and Franco Iacomella. "Peer to Peer Economy and New Civilization Centered
Around the Sustenance of the Commons" in David Bollier and Silke Helfrich, eds., The Wealth of the
Commons: A World Beyond Market and State (Levellers Press, 2013). Online version at
<http://wealthofthecommons.org/essay/peer-peer-economy-and-new-civilization-centered-around-
sustenance-commons>.
Manuel Castells. The Rise of the Network Society (Blackwell Publishers, 1996).
Tom Coates. "(Weblogs and) The Mass Amateurisation of (Nearly) Everything..." Plasticbag.org,
September 3, 2003
<http://www.plasticbag.org/archives/2003/09/weblogs_and_the_mass_amateurisation_of_nearly_every
thing>
Nick Dyer-Witheford. Cyber-Marx: Cycles and Circuits of Struggle in High-Technology Capitalism
(Urbana and Chicago: University of Illinois Press, 1999).
Amador Fernández-Savater. "John Holloway: cracking capitalism vs. the state option" ROAR
Magazine, September 29, 2015 <https://roarmag.org/essays/john-holloway-cracking-capitalism-vs-the-
state-option/>.
Shane Gilchrist. "Sharing the Future" Otago Daily Times Online News (New Zealand), November
30, 2015 <http://www.odt.co.nz/lifestyle/magazine/364835/sharing-future>.
David Graeber. "Situating Occupy Lessons From the Revolutionary Past" InterActivist Info
Exchange, December 4, 2011 <http://interactivist.autonomedia.org/node/36685>.
Rakesh Khurana. From Higher Aims to Hired Hands: The Social Transformation of American
Business Schools and the Unfulfilled Promise of Management as a Profession (Princeton and Oxford:
Princeton University Press, 2007).
Christopher Lasch. The New Radicalism in America (1889-1963): The Intellectual as a Social Type
(New York: Vintage Books, 1965 ).
Paul Mason. "The end of capitalism has begun" The Guardian, July 22, 2015
<http://www.theguardian.com/books/2015/jul/17/postcapitalism-end-of-capitalism-begun>.
Mason. Post-Capitalism: A Guide to Our Future (Allan Lane, 2015).
Stephanie McMillan. " So-Called “Post-Capitalism” is Just Another Crappy Capitalist Snowjob"
SkewedNews, July 22, 2015 <http://skewednews.net/index.php/2015/07/22/called-post-capitalism-just-
another-crappy-capitalist-snowjob/>.
Antonio Negri. The Politics of Subversion: A Manifesto for the Twenty-First Century. Translated
by James Newell (Cambridge, UK: Polity Press, 1989).
Antonio Negri and Michael Hardt. Commonwealth (Cambridge: Belknap Press, 2009).
Negri and Hardt. Multitude: War and Democracy in the Age of Empire (Penguin, 2005).
Sheldon Richman. "Bastiat on the Socialization of Wealth" Center for a Stateless Society, March
23, 2013 <https://c4ss.org/content/17835>.
Paul M. Romer. “Endogenous Technological Change” (December 1989). NBER Working Paper No.
W3210.
Douglas Rushkoff. "How the Tech Boom Terminated California's Economy" Fast Company, July
10, 2009 <https://www.fastcompany.com/1307504/how-tech-boom-terminated-californias-economy>.
Niki Seth-Smith. "Post-Capitalism and the Precariat" Precarious Europe, August 24, 2015
<http://www.precariouseurope.com/power/postcapitalism-precariat>.
Yehouda Shenhav. Manufacturing Rationality: The Engineering Foundations of the Managerial
Revolution (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1999).
Nick Srnicek and Alex Williams. "Manifesto for an Accelerationist Politics" Critical Legal
Thinking, May 14, 2013 <https://syntheticedifice.files.wordpress.com/2013/06/accelerate.pdf>.
Guy Standing. A Precariat Charter: From Denizens to Citizens (London, New Delhi, New York,
Sydney: Bloomsbury, 2014).
"Toni Negri: from the refusal of labor to the seizure of power" ROAR Magazine, January 18, 2015
<https://roarmag.org/essays/negri-interview-multitude-metropolis/>.
Immanuel Wallerstein. “The Neo-Zapatistas: Twenty Years After.” Immanuel Wallerstein, May 1,
2014 <http://www.iwallerstein.com/neozapatistas-twenty-years/>.