Theories of Film Andrew Tudorpdf - Compress
Theories of Film Andrew Tudorpdf - Compress
Theories of Film Andrew Tudorpdf - Compress
il \
'^m'' *14
CHILIS SUT^L/FFB
m m Cinema One
23 Theories of Filiri
f; ^ iTTfT- - "L - r
r.t
, , i
, I • * ;'i ;
I 'v
* . -4 •ifcr!
*♦
I • '
Theories of Film
Andrew Tudor
London
General Editors
Penelope Houston and David Wilson (Sight and Sound)
Christopher Williams (Educational Advisory Services Department)
1. Introduction
6. Epilogue
Bibliography
Acknowledgements
Theories of Theories
Most obviously we have to begin by asking what constitutes a
theory of film. In a sense this whole book offers an answer. But
in a more limited way there is some use in putting the question
specifically. In particular, what has traditionally been meant by
the phrase 'theory of film'? Now there are two well-known
books of precisely this title, but neither of them is clear as to
the 'theory' in question. The one, by Bela Balazs, is a collection
of general and often rather dated fragments only tenuously
interlinked. The other, by Siegfried Kracauer, is a massively
desperate attempt to justify realist cinema as aesthetic perfec
tion. The one thing they do have in common - in retrospect the
lowest common denominator of their 'theories' - is a desire to
make general statements about tJie cinema. To advance
propositions which transcend particular films and thence apply
to film in general. Like Eisenstein, Balazs expresses it at its
strongest in his avowed interest in the 'intrinsic laws of
development' of the art, though in practice, also like Eisenstein,
he leaves such laws unspecified.
Minimally, then, the expression 'theory of film' has been
applied to any attempt to make general assertions about the
medium. Much everyday usage corresponds to this meaning.
Any critic concerned to talk about characteristics of the
medium as well as about particular movies has been labelled,
for good or ill, a theorist, a terminology which is clearly far
too vague. While generalization is undoubtedly a necessary
component of 'theory', all generalizations do not therefore
constitute theories. A theory is not simply the sum total of our
general knowledge ofa subject; its functions are not exhausted
in the presentation of ad hoc sets of assertions linked only in
thatthey all apply to film. It has, in its way, a creative character
of its own. By explicitly linking together its various com
ponents we are made aware of relationships and regularities
which would not otherwise be apparent. We are able to clarify,
for example, the links between conceptions of film editing and
of film acting, and their joint consequences for the process of
film communication. The classic Russian arguments about
typage and montage involve just such links.
This enables us to further pin down the notion of film theory.
It is not simply a question of the generality of our statements,
of their status as presumptive 'laws' which always hold true.
There is also an issue of method involving the systematization
of our thought. The film theorist is distinguished from the film
essayist (who might also make general statements) by his stress
on the systematic. To theorize is, of necessity, to invoke the
criterion of logical consistency, and so logically to interrelate
various diverse elements into theories. As a body of such
theory is formed, each stage in its development gives us a new
vantage point on our subject. It provides a different pair of
spectacles, a different 'theoretical framework', much as, for
example, the collective propositions of Newtonian mechanics
historically offered a new perspective on the dynamics of mov
ing bodies. At root, our every act of observation invokes some
implicit framework; to theorize is to make such a framework
explicit so that it might be explored for cracks. Given all this
there is still obviously a range of meanings of 'theory'. At one
end there is the minimal demand that writers on film render
explicit their assumptions. At the other extreme a maximal
demand that we must work toward formulating a general and
systematic body of empirically tested knowledge about film; in
effect, a science of film. Recent years have seen a fairly wide
spread critical demand for 'minimal' theory: the breakdown in
communication between different 'schools' has made such a
need evident to a wide range of interested parties. This has
inevitably led to a more philosophically developed discussion
of cinema. On the other hand, 'maximal' theory has become
increasingly hived off into outside specializations. From the era
of Eisenstein, whose intention it was to create a mighty, over
arching, scientific theory of film, we have come to the age of
the specialist. Eisenstein attempted to invoke his own psy
chology, sociology, and film 'linguistics'. For him the impetus
came from a central concern with film. Nowthe psychologists,
sociologists, and linguists fragment the subject into its dis
ciplinary variants. For them the impetus is extra-cinematic. At
its most general, one task of 'maximal' theory could be to
reunite these elements.
It should be clear that I am using 'theory' in a fairly general
way. It would obviously be possible to limit the term quite
drastically; in some circumstances it might even be essential.
Thus, 'theory' could be conceived as part of a process of
hypothesis formulation, testing, and, if necessary, refor
mulation on the basis of empirical materials. In short, the
application of 'scientific method' to the task of expanding our
knowledge of film. But most people do not limit 'theories of
film' in this way, and this book is primarily concerned with
what is and only partially with what ought to be. Much of what
has passed as theory of film has really been an attempt to lay
bare the assumptions and arguments which have underlain
certain critical practices. Bazin, Kracauer, the 'auteur theory',
are cases in point. They are elaborations of particular critical
'world-views', special frameworks for the analysis of films.
They canhardly be by-passed as notconstituting theory proper,
for we have much to learn from them.
This enlarged area of interest brings with it its own
•k
particular problems. We are to be concerned with theoretical
frameworks employed for a range of purposes and deriving
from a number of disciplinary viewpoints. One difference, in
particular, needs attention. It is possible to study film in order,
primarily, to understand the empirical operation of the
medium, or, primarily, as a basis for making judgements of
quality. Evidently, the clearer our understanding the better the
factual basis on which our judgements are founded; equally
(believers in the myth of 'objective criticism' apart) our 'scien
tific' study could not be conducted in an evaluative vacuum.
But there is a definite distinction of aim between the two, and
their confusion can be, at the very least, misleading. Eisenstein,
as I shall discuss, is sometimes dismissed as guilty of aesthetic
monomania: of offering montage as the ultimate aesthetic
arbiter of taste. In fact, he was much more concerned with
montage as part of a theory of howfilm infact affected people,
than with making all-pervasive judgements of value. For the
want of terms I shall refer to the former interest as developing a
model of film, to the latter as developing an aesthetic of film.
The intertwining of such interests has elsewhere caused the
exact status of propositions to become confused. Bazin, for
example, argued that Citizen Kane was a film of high quality in
that it was a film of realism. Realism was an axiom of his
aesthetic position. But the statement which links this axiom
with the specific aesthetic judgement of Citizen Kane raises
problems. The realism of the film, Bazin argues, derives from
its use of deep-focus photography and minimal cutting. Such
techniques minimize fragmentation of the real world. The
trouble is that this could be a definition of realism as non-
fragmentation, or an assertion that films employing such
techniques are perceived as more real. The latter, unlike the
former, is open to empirical test, although Bazinuses it as a self-
evident aesthetic judgement. Thus, although there is nothing
inherently wrong with the argument, it does involve different
sorts of statements with consequent different criteria of
adequacy. Such shiftsshouldbe madeclear, thoughthey seldom
are.
• -r
ti>iS
i|k
. '» li it
The 'art' of film: The Cabinet of Dr. Caligari (Robert Wiene); Mother (Pudovkin)
shoots growing from these seeds were to split film aesthetics in
two; the symbolic opposition between Lumiere and Melies
hovers perpetually over aesthetic debate.
The crucial polarity, then, became that between, on the one
hand, realism, naturalism, and the minimum interference of the
film-maker, and on the other hand, fantasy, expressionism, and
the formative influence of the film-maker. Which is not to say
that realism versus fantasy is identical to naturalism versus
expressionism; it was merely made to seem that way. One of
the earliest interests of film aesthetics- the attempt to establish
that film could indeed be justly called Art - was deeply
involved in this division. The silent films which were claimed as
'artistic' were those in which the 'creative' interference of the
artist was most evident. The painting-influenced designs and
'serious' subjects of German Expressionism were invoked as
evidence, as were the newly developed montage techniques of
the Russians. Caligari, Potemkin and Mother were used to
define the 'art' of film. Another source of artistic respectability
lay in the extravagant Freudian symbolism of the French
avant-garde. Films like Un Chien Andalou, The Seashell and
the Clergyman and Menilmontant were used to demonstrate
that the cinema could be just as experimental as its artistic
neighbours. By the time the silent era reached its culmination
aesthetic orthodoxy took the part of what Kracauer calls the
formative tendency'. In the generic imagery, Melies was on
top! And worse still, a bowdlerized version of Fisenstein
became an accepted Old Testament.
Fisenstein's major interest was in the workings of film
'language',and he conceived montageasa crucial elementin such
a process. But as we shall see his notion of montage was by no
means simple, and certainly never as simple as the version held
by the aesthetic orthodoxy. His analysis was complex to a
degree, requiring and making a number of conditioning
assumptions. The social and psychological contextsin which the
cinema operated were the primary focus ofthese assumptions.
Lumiere; A Boat Entering Harbour
Dialectics ofFilm
Although a loose idea of montage appears quite early, more
systematic analysis begins in the 1929 essay, 'A Dialectical
Approach to Film Form'.^ Here, Eisenstein argues for a
parallel between the method of thought termed 'dialectical
materialism', which arises from the 'projection of the dialec
tical system of things into the brain', and art, which arises from
the projection of the same dialectical system of things into the
creative process. Artistic creation develops from the inter
action ofcontradictory opposites; thedialectical process (thesis-
antithesis-synthesis) is the baseline on which the theory of
2. Sergei Eisenstein, Film Form, Dobson, London, 1951, pp. 45-63.
A".
:£
montage rests. The fundamental assumption is that all things in
the world are related in a dialectical manner, and so this
'universal' dialectic must find its place in film as much as
anywhere else. It is this rather extravagant claim that first
marks Eisenstein off from the other Soviet film directors. There
is, at least at fi.rst, a considerable pressure apparent in his work
to use the mould of 'dialectics' to hold his thoughts, accom
panied by an equally obvious tendency for them to overflow the
sides of the container.
There is a clear sense in which the dialectic provides a
rationale for Eisenstein's particular interpretation of the
Kuleshov experiments. One, in particular, seemed important to
Eisenstein, although the whole set developed a similar theme.
By splicing a strip of film showing a shot of Moszhukhin's
expressionless face to various other shots in turn (a bowl of
soup, a coffin, etc.) and then showing the results to an audience,
the experimentors succeeded in showing that the audience
believed the face to be expressing the appropriate emotion (e.g.
hunger, sadness, etc.) in each case. From this, it followed that
one of the important factors influencing an audience's response
to a film revolves around the juxtaposition of the shots
involved. In a word, montage. Now, thus far in film history
editing had been primarily dictated according to the narrative
needs of the film. A cut, when it came, was necessary to move
on to the next camera set-up. Only Griffith, most notably in
Intolerance, had begun to explore the immense formal possibili
ties of editing, so to the Russians the Kuleshov discovery had
all the marks of a fundamental insight.
Characteristically, Eisenstein took it to its most extreme
limits. Where Pudovkin, ever pragmatic, saw montage as a
process of 'building', of laying 'bricks' end-to-end, Eisenstein
tried to conceive it in a theoretically more sophisticated way.
For him it was from the 'collision' of independent shots that the
meaning arose in the minds of the audience. Now there is one
clear respect, which later proves to be' important, in which
5*^ A
# *
"V
k'
1^' '
. JSiL£^ (
Sketch by Eisenstein for Ivan the Terrible-, and (right) Nikolai Cherkasov as Ivan ^
i
than in their histrionic talents. Nevertheless, the theory under
goes a generalization and montage becomes, effectively, a way
of formulating the relations of parts to wholes. A stage actor,
for example, creates his persona out of many detailed elements;
together they make up the character. A director creates a theme
through all the various partial representations of it. The
modified view can be expressed thus:
Before the inner vision, before the perception of the creator, hovers a
given image, emotionally embodying his theme. The task that con
fronts him is to transform this image into a few basic partial
representations which, in their combination and juxtaposition, shall
invoke in the consciousness and feelings of the spectator, reader, or
auditor, that same initial general image which originally hovered
before the creative artist.'
%
'in «# K • •%
5^.** .--g
IT
Ik ^
P
T " i, 1\ • ^ #
9 %i
"i ft "
Sji*
V® *
•
••' ™* T Ml
between general statement and detailed analysis. There are
similar problems with 'pathos', the process whereby a spectator
is lifted 'out of himself, electrified, raised into ecstasy. How to
reach such intensity is again only partly clear, although
Eisenstein makes much of the parallel between montage tech
niques and the pattern of the creative process.
The strength of montage resides in this, that it includes in the creative
process the emotions and mind of the spectator. The spectator is
compelled to proceed along the selfsame creative road that the author
travelled in creating the image.
One element, then, is in the shared creative ecstasy produced
through the montage process. The spectator is also artist. But,
as a cursory look at his films would- suggest, Eisenstein was
also very much aware that this formal element was not the
whole story. Other factors would needs be invoked. What does
remain clear, however, is that 'pathos' is very much the aim of
Eisenstein's cinema. The goal is, in his unfortunate termin
ology, to ereate the 'pathetic' film!
This militant, fiery, pathos style, this 'kino-fist', is the style,
Eisenstein says, of Strike, Potemkin, Mother, and Arsenal. It
arises from the social militancy of the revolution and, in the
later case of Alexander Nevsky, from the fervour of Soviet
nationalism. But 'kino-fist' is not all, and Eisenstein is forced to
remark, in passing, a rather more prosaic means of attaining
'pathos'. This 'quieter' method is epitomized in the Maxim
Gorki trilogy, but it is clear that Eisenstein's sympathies lie
elsewhere. In the end they can be traced back to the Pavlovian
reflex psychology with which all of Eisenstein's thought is
permeated. Given the correct set of stimuli, there then follows
the correct 'pathetic' response. Modify this slightly with the
notion of organic unity (loosely formulated) of the elements of
film, and we know why Potemkin is experienced as intensely
moving all over the world. Even, Eisenstein suggests, the class
15. Sergei Eisenstein, The Film Sense, op. cit., p. 34.
Kino-fist: Strike
Prosaic pathos: The Childhood of Maxim Gorki (Donskoi)
Great Beginnings?
One way of answering this question is to ask how his work can
be of use to us today. We have become accustomed to the idea
of Eisenstein as the arch-prophet of editing, particularly the
techniques of contrast and irony developed in October. For
criticism and appreciation of film this provides a useful view
point on one formal aspect of the medium. For the rest, the
argument might go, we must look elsewhere. This is evidently
only partly true, as Eisenstein was himselfaware. The charge of
creating, in montage, a monistic criterion for assessing a film
is an unfortunate exaggeration. His views on criticism were
rather less extreme. Thus, in his essay 'A Close-Up View' he
draws an analogy between the use of long shot, medium shot,
and close-up in film making and three aspects of film criticism.
A film can, and should, be looked at in these three ways. The
'long shot' which is concerned to explore the ideological (or
moral) correctness of a film. The 'medium shot', the view of the
normal spectator and primarily concerned with the 'living play
of emotions'. Finally, the 'close-up', which is concerned to
break down the film, analyse its parts and the manner of its
working. All these are essential elements for the consideration
of the critic; no singleone can justify accepting a film as good if
others are defective. All three approaches must be pursued.
The relation of this scheme to the rest of Eisenstein's theor
izing is obvious. The theorizing itself is the 'close-up' technical
analysis. The understanding attained in this way is directed
toward involving the ordinary spectator in the intense emotion
of the 'pathos' structure. Through this involvement 'the general
characteristics ofthe theme enter the spectator's consciousness en
passant. The generalized concept of the event is embedded in
the spectator's feelings.'The spectator grasps thematic con
tent through his emotional response to the film; form and
content are united. Eisenstein's tragedy was that the established
Stalinist position elevated the form-content distinction to a
fundamental law. The ideologically proper position must imbue
the whole film; Eisenstein's wish to grip the spectator in an iron
fist led to insufficiently obvious ideological rectitude. Reality
was there and Eisenstein wanted to mess with it. As we shall
presently discuss, that allegation is still being made. But it is to
his credit that he did not try to elevate some master belief to the
level of sole arbiter of aesthetic taste. Sometimes, in his more
polemical discussions of montage, he hovered near to it, but
always the position was finally rescued. His thinking at least
has the virtue of flexibility.
Still, other than as 'advice to young critics', what use is
Eisenstein's work? The answer I think can take two forms. One
involves a long-term investment in the ultimate usefulness of
his views of the languageof film, the creation of pathos, vertical
montage and the rest, as a partial basis for a more thorough
going theory of film. The other hasto do with using his thought
in the course of our analysis of particular films as and when it
proves useful. Clearly our understanding of the formal mon
tage elements of film can be facilitated by using Eisenstein's
views at least as signposts. The more a film (or sequence)
depends on montage techniques, then the more useful the
theories. Some directors, Howard Hawks, John Ford,
Michelangelo Antonioni, for instance, make virtually no use of
classic montage techniques. Since we are not elevating
Eisenstein's ideas into a system of aesthetic values this implies
nothing about the quality of their work. Others, Alfred
Hitchcock, Don Siegel, Sam Peckinpah, are variously depen
dent on montage for some elements of their cinema. This has
16. Sergei Eisenstein, Film Essays, op. cit., p. 151.
no consequences for the intensity of any 'pathos' that may
result: both Ford and Peckinpah can be as intensely moving as
any directors I know, using very different techniques. Indeed,
Peckinpah seems to me to be above all the modern montage
director, at least in his two epic films - the tattered Major
Dundee and The Wild Bunch. Let me illustrate some uses of
Eisenstein's work in exploring the formal determinants of the
intense effects of the final reel of The Wild Bunch.
The sequence I have in mind begins with Pike and the Gorch
brothers in the brothel. At this point the montage is solely
concerned to carry the simple narrative. There is no clear
metric or rhythmic pattern; the pace and visual tones are gentle
and subdued. This combines with two thematic references to
elsewhere in the film: the solitary guitar recalls Angel's playing
at an earlier camp, while the Mexican girl and her child locate
Pike firmly in the 'might have been' world of his past love. This
poignancy is reinforced in the formal technique, the 'vertical
montage' between music and visual tonality. The mood hangs
and flutters likethe briefly intercut bird on a string. Finally it is
broken, aurally and visually,by the first synchronized words of
the scene. For the last time comes Pike's ritual'Let's go!'; 'Why
not?' is the reply. Again the intercut bird, now panting on its
back. Like the ants and scorpions at the beginning, like the
peacock in October, this is a typically Eisensteinian imagistic
comment. The peaceful intermezzo is over; the bird is in its
final throes.
Collecting Dutch, they move to their horses. In narrative
terms we are still unaware of what they intend. But as they
form up and arm, in what irresistibly look like pre-determined
positions, the wide screen is suddenly dominated by the pattern
of the four men in a row. They set off to rescue Angel and there
follows a tour deforce. Every montage technique is involved at
one level or another. The basic tempo is laid down by the
metric cutting pattern, accelerating slightly as the sequence
progresses. This is the baseline of growing tension. Overlaid on
i K
'f
this is the rhythmic montage, cutting on the basis of movement
within the frame. Here there is mutual reinforcement between
the 'stepping out' of the four men (like the soldiers on the steps
in Potemkin and, incidentally, in many of the angles involved,
like the march to the corral in Gunfight at the OK Corral) and
the beat of the metric montage. From front or back four-shots
of the Bunch filling the screen the cut is either to side-angled
two-shots (one very notable one of Pike and Dutch) of head and
shoulders moving irresistibly on, or to various static groups of
Mapache's troops. This supplies a rhythmic montage contrast
between Bunch and troops, much as a similar technique did
with troops and populace on the Odessa Steps. Tension is built
and everything carries us with the Bunch. They become gar
gantuan. On top of this is added the tonal montage pattern, on
the basis of the clean visual line of the Bunch and the messy,
chaotic scatter of the troops. To match the visual pattern,
the troops are shot in a sort of dust-haze while the Bunch
remain optically clear. Thus the basic tempo and 'melody'
montage techniques screw us to an increasingly high emotional
pitch.
Over this basic pattern Peckinpah adds further elements of
vertical montage: in particular, the music. This is a combin
ation of the guitar and voices of the villager's farewell song and
the rhythmic side-drum first heard in the build up to the
opening massacre. In tempo it matches the metric and rhythmic
montage, thus providing a perfect combination of visual and
aural patterns, and its volume increases as the tension grows.
But the music itself is also based on a montage conflict. The
drum recalls the massacre while the song evokes the beauty of
the departure from the village. Embedded in it is the thematic
joining ofthe extreme violence ofthe Bunch tothe romantic and
idyllic appeal of the village. The music thus performs the
double function of supporting both the formal intensification of
'pathos' and the thematic development that, for the first time,
the Bunch is involved for 'altruistic' reasons. Through the total
The death of Angel
Housing Problems
< J-^- a -- A
I
h
'kJ- p- •
.
A o ♦
' -
• *
»•-w ?A
* /
l!>4*
from the beginning - when we first separated our public purpose
theories from those of Flaherty - an 'anti-aesthetic' movement.®
Grierson asks that the cinema come to earth. Although his
argument for realism over and against aestheticism is made in
the context of the documentary movement, it must clearly
apply to the whole range of cinema. If he seriously wished to
achieve his social aim then the whole cinematic castle must be
captured, not just the outposts. Heasks that the cinema should
keep in touch with the 'common people', and is saddened by
this failure in the later films of Eisenstein, Pudovkin and
Dovzhenko. The General Line, Deserter and Earth, he says,
suffer in that their directors are alien to the material with which
they are working. Interestingly it is the neglected Ermler —
occasionally remembered for the montage ingenuity of
Fragment of an Empire —whom Grierson singles out from the
Russians. The truth is that Grierson's populism derives not a
little of its power from a deep-seated mistrust of 'highbrows' in
particular, and the middle-class in general. As we have already
seen, Hitchcock was allegedly undone by the highbrows. In a
more evangelical strain Grierson is concerned for Cagney:
It [the cinema] began in the gutter and still trails the clouds of glory
with which its vulgar origin was invested. But if we ask it to go deep,
be sure we are not just asking it to go middle-class. And be sure that
the next phase of cinema may not be to eliminate the Cagneys in
favour of the Colmans and indeed to Colmanise Cagney himself.'
The implied siding with 'popular' culture as against 'high' is
a brave sally in advance of its time and a reflection of
Grierson's frequent expression of his cinematic aim as
sociological. This last, presumably, in the traditional English
sense: what has been aptly called 'a kind of Marxified
Fabianism'!
Whatever sympathy one might feel for Grierson's position,
8. Forsyth Hardy (ed.), Grierson on Documentary, p. 179.
9. ibid., p. 72.
and it would be difficult not to feel any, his aesthetic argument
is clearly problematic. Even allowing the particular social
analysis it is not at all clear why realism should follow of
necessity. His intention, after all, is not simply to show one half
of the world how the other half lives. Although the early years
of the movement saw the production of many such films,
Grierson came to conceive of them as the weakest weapon in
the armoury. More important to him was to enter the arena of
social debate, and, ultimately, change people's ways of thought,
their cultures. What he is really asking for is a purposive
cinema; if you like, a 'moral' cinema. Obviously not in the
limited sense, but an attempt to encompass the concept of
social responsibility in the cinema, to include the 'moral'
dimension in criticism as the overriding concern. But,of course,
there is no good reason to suppose that Grierson's realism, its
material shot 'in the raw', is any more powerful in its effect
than is staged cinema. Propaganda is a far more subtle business
than it seemed some thirty years ago. As a justification for
realism Grierson's argumentdoes not hold water; his is reallya
case for 'responsible propaganda'. Propaganda that is 'right'.
At heart Grierson sees film aesthetics as a by-product of
historical 'destiny'. Society is far too complex to be unified and
stabilized in the old familiar ways. The close-knit community
has gone, and industrial democracy is unworkable on the old
bases. A new and 'Democratic' culture is to be forged and film
is the medium to do it. Not merely through spreading infor
mation, though this is part, but by creating a cultural context in
which social interdependency is a practical possibility. Once
Grierson expands his case beyond the simple spread of know
ledge then we find two separate strands to the argument. Both
begin with a sociological assumption about the nature of the
changes experienced in modem society. In the terms developed
by the French sociologist, Emile Durkheim, the passage from
mechanical to organic solidarity. The form of solidarity
characteristic of modern societies is organic: resting on the
complex interdependence of the members of that society. For
Grierson —although he did not employ these terms —the
problem lies in providing a cultural basis for this organic
solidarity; a system of beliefs which will make modern, demo
cratic, industrialized societies work. It is not possible to live by
total consensus on all points (Durkheim's mechanical solidar
ity) any longer, and, as I have suggested, Grierson puts forward
two interlinked but separable arguments. The one, which leads
to documentary in particular and realism in general, sees the
spread of information about the range of differences between
man and man as a basis for social solidarity. The weakness of
this argument, at least as an exclusivecase, is that it approaches
the problem of organic solidarity with the weapons of
mechanical solidarity. It assumes that a consensus achieved by
increasing knowledge of the 'real' world will bind society
together. Knowing how the other half lives will enable us to
recognize and hold on to our common humanity. This assump
tion does not seem entirely realistic, unless we also assume that
the simple spread of knowledge automatically promotes mutual
understanding. The evidence hardly favours such an optimistic
Grierson himself was obviously not happy with this as it
stood. His later essays implicitly develop the view that the
problem is rather more complicated than can be dealt with in
these terms. So we find a further case made for 'propaganda'.
Information and realism are not sufficient. Our films must
involve the individual in the process of creating solidarity, in
the interdependence of his society, in the 'drama of his citizen
ship'; in Eisenstein's terms, the need is for 'pathos'. Although
we no longer live in a simple society depending on common
agreement, there is a level at which we can be 'persuaded' to
agree: the level of recognizing our interdependence as
transcending our differences. And this, of course, is not a brief
for any particular aesthetic limitation such as realism. It is an
argument that, whatever the particular form, the crucial factor
is its social role vis-d-vis this fundamental need for solidarity.
In the last analysis Grierson's position leads in the direction of
the end (providing a culture to underwrite the workings of
modern democratic societies) justifying the means (any form of
propaganda directed toward this morally accepted end).
Context Domination
Grierson's theory, then, is context-dominant. It elevates one
area of contextual concern above all other factors. Pushed to
the limit it can have no implications for our aesthetic judge
ments of film separate from the social function performed by
the film. The measures of aesthetic taste are limited to two: the
social responsibility of the film, and its effectiveness in achiev
ing this socially responsible aim. As it stands the Grierson
argument is no basis for anything more than this and, as such,
it exemplifies the problems which have been attendant upon the
few attempts to specifically involve context factors in theories of
film. The problem is more acute in aesthetic argument; in
developing models of film there is at least a further arbiter, how
well the models fit the reality. If they do not, then we may be
forced to revise the particular form of our contextual assump
tions. But aesthetic argument is directed toward the justifi
cation of a set of general evaluations on the basis of certain
axioms, and some of these latter are invariably contextual
assumptions. In Grierson's case the position is extreme in that
aestheticjudgements about film are not simply conditioned by
contextual assumptions about the social and psychological role
of cinema, they are dominated. Aesthetics is reduced to
morally prescribed social theory. 'Purposive cinema' em
phasizes the 'purposive' at the expense of the cinema.
It would be entirely wrong, however, to take this as a reason
for avoiding the context issue in aesthetic discussion. The
attempt to develop a context-free aesthetic - the effective aim
of the 'philosophical realists' — is just as problematic as
Grierson's context-domination. The problem is to find a
balance between evasion and subjugation. Aesthetic argument
can be reduced neither to 'essence' nor to social (or psy
chological) discussion. It may be that it ought to combine both.
And equally film models are neither created in a vacuum (which
implies unstated assumptions) nor can they be reduced to a
sociology or psychology of film. Whatever our theories they
must in some ways be abstractions and simplifications. To
attack the issue of context is to begin to specify the precise
ways in which they are so. Grierson's theoretical importance
lies in the impetus he gives to this endeavour.
4: Aesthetics of Realism: Bazin and
Kracauer
Musical 'realism'? Fred Astaire and Ginger Rogers in Top Haf, and (right) Gene •
Kelly in Singin' in the Rain
Si
•7 ^
wfw
?T».'
Nr.''
I,
f
tMAI) f. ••!
sr '
^1^
I i I A* itiit.
j I'^'®^W-?-1^
iir.^
' • TT?
•'• "•m
j*
t' If
r"*
21 •'•-•> If-:!!
^ §*Jt .^T—••^
• -^'fL' ® '
V-« w
r t • . %
—• -^.iSr- -« ^ C- w.
sometimes laborious drawing out of the implications of the
theory. I do not intend to much concern myself with the
inconsistencies and oddities of this last. Pauline Kael's scathing
review (most reviews were highly complimentary), 'Is There a
Cure for Film Criticism?"' provides ample evidence of his
specific peculiarities. Perhaps one or two will serve as signposts
for the rest. Witness the way in which he squeezes the Musical
into the 'goody' category by dint of arguing that Astaire's
dancing emerges from the real-life events of his films, though
Top Hat hardly seems a paragon of realism. And, evidence of
the peculiar limits of his discussion, he fails entirely to mention
the Gene Kelly of AnchorsAway and Singin' in the Rain, who
is probably a far better example in support of his case. Or
again, the way in which he rescues Song of Ceylon from hell-
fire and perdition by arguing that its montage sequence (a sin
against realism, though since he likes early Eisenstein perhaps
only sometimes a sin) serves to make the 'real' sequences
around it that much more real. This ignores the fact that the
sequence in question is a way of developing forcefully one of
the main themes of the film. Or, lastly, his failure to recognize
that the romanticism of Louisiana Story is more than 'simply'
a moral issue, but can also impinge on the 'realism' of the
movie. And so it goes on, with Kracauer turning this way and
that apparently in an effort to 'fit in' all his favourite movies.
As a practical guard to the gates of cinematic heaven his
judgements are odd. To understand why we must turn to the
chapter and verse.
Kracauer makes two central arguments in support of his
position. One is fundamental to the whole theory; a second is
added almost as an afterthought. I shall briefly suggest the
second, and then explore the first in some detail. Kracauer's
4. Pauline Kael, 'Is there a Cure for Film Criticism? or: Some Unhappy
Thoughts on Siegfried Kracauer's Nature of Film: The Redemption of
Physical Reality', Sight and Sound, 31, 2, 1962. Reprinted in Pauline
Kael, I Lost it at the Movies, Jonathan Cape, London, 1966.
Romantic realism: Flaherty's Louisiana Story
Forty-Second Street ^
; ' . «ll!l»i| -
4»aj'
"o'pfj
4 .C.*
r Zf '
"m
ttr* -f'
i
r
assumption for which no grounds are presented-for accepting it
as right.
Proposition (d) falls for a number of very obvious reasons.
Even accepting that photography is the top priority in film, the
dilution of the 'nature of photography' arguments leaves us
only with the assertion that 'film-makers can variously interfere
with the cinematic process'. But even by-passing this objection,
other of Kracauer's specific assertions can bear further
scrutiny. Some of the emphases in his discussion of the basic
nature of the medium have changed in the move from photo
graphy to cinema. 'The basic properties [of film] are identical
with the properties of photography. Film, in other words, is
uniquely equipped to record and reveal physical reality and,
hence, gravitates toward it.'^ Because a medium is well
equipped to fulfil some task it naturally 'gravitates' in that
direction. The general assumption is that media tend to operate
in the field for which they are best equipped. If we are to take
this at its face value all the many films from Melies to Planet of
the Apes which are not in the puritan tradition of realism
(including many that Kracauer favours) are not just bad films,
they are contrary to the natural tendency. They should never
have gravitated in this direction at all. Some new laws of nature
must be in operation! Since Kracauer can hardly mean this, he
must, presumably, mean that films are only really films in so
far as they record and reveal physical reality. Anything else is
simply not a film.
But what exactly is this 'physical reality' to the revelation of
which the cinema should be devoted? The answer is fascinat-
• j,
^•' . • • . '• ;••••':.• -..-V^-fi^-' :.5« •» • .
l|!«a»(*l^
:,. 'iW'!,?.
v^: •••
f
'-SSfe"'' -
'-s-£
» '
M
Neo-realism: Umberto D
•^T.
,
%
n
and it meets with the same sort of problems. If the 'pseudoreal'
fools both eye and mind, then who is to say that it is not truly
real? To found an aesthetic on a distinction of this type is
rather like founding a morality on the view that murder is only
wrong if you get caught. Contrast such a position with that
expressed six years later in 'Theatre and Cinema'.
The realism of the cinema follows directly from its photographic
nature. Not only does some marvel or some fantastic thing on the
screen not undermine the reality of the image, on the contrary, it is
its most validjustification. Illusion in the cinema is not based as it is
in the theatre on convention tacitly accepted by the general public;
rather, contrariwise, it is based on the inalienable realism of that
which is shown. All trick work must be perfect in all material
respects on the screen. The 'invisible man' must wear pyjamas and
smoke a cigarette.'®
Which implies, surely, that the only reality is the reality of
which the audience is convinced; quite conceivably, the
pseudorealism which fools the eye and mind. There is a clear
contrast between the 'purist' position wherein the cinema taps a
fixed 'true' reality and this latter case in which the cinema, by
its nature, lends realism to something which is illusory. The
most obvious conclusion from the second argument is that the
cinema is dedicated to representing '... a plausible reality of
which the spectator admits the identity with nature as he knows
it.' Presumably 'as he knows it' is flexible and depends on a
series of social and psychological conditions. Few of us in
1970 'know' the lunar landscape of 2001: A Space Odyssey in
any but the most indirect sense, yet we are willing to accept its
realism. But an audience in 1930 would probably have found it
much more difficult. In other words, our acceptance of illusion
is a sort of convention having nothing to do with our metaphy
sical conceptions about the 'inalienable realism' of the camera.
Clearly there is some strain between the components of the
argument. Bazin, an incurable metaphysician, wants to talk of
16. Andre Bazin, What is Cinema? op. cit., p. 108.
Frau im mond
the nature of the medium, its inalienable realism. But his wish
to allow 'some fantastic thing' to appear on the screen leads
him to the position that something is real if we are fooled into
thinking it so. And this depends on a range of factors which
have nothing to do with the 'nature' of the medium. Predic
tably, Bazin expresses unhappiness with the 'plausible reality'
explanation. It is over-simplified; insufficiently 'subtle'. Al
though the failure (to Bazin) of the stagey and implausible
decors of The Cabinet of Dr Caligari and the rest of German
Expressionism lend support to the thesis, there are, he feels,
more basic explanations. Like Kracauer, he is unhappy faced with
relativism. To make aesthetic judgements on the basis of'plausi
bility' raises the familiar bogey: plausible to whom? We are
returned (and why not?) to 'I think this is plausiblethough you do
not'. And faced with this, theorists ofthe persuasion of Bazin and
Kracauer produce the same old response. Back to the funda-
mental-nature-of-the-medium argument. Again the comparison
between Bazin's 'pure' and 'impure' positions is instructive.
Thephotographic image is the object itself, the object freed from the
conditions of time and space that govern it... The aesthetic qualities
of photography are to be sought in its power to lay bare the realities.
It is not for me to separate off, in the complex fabric of the objective
world, here a reflection on a damp sidewalk, there the gesture of a
child. Only the impassive lens, stripping its object of all those ways
of seeing it, those piled up preconceptions, that spiritual dust and
grime with which my eyes have covered it, is able to present it inall
its virginal purity to my attention
Apart from its extravagant romanticism the most interesting
characteristic of this passage is its stress on the identity be
tween image and object. Photography impassively reveals the
realities of the 'objective' world; it is this reality by its very
nature. Compare this once more with 'Theatre and Cinema'.
We are prepared to admit that the screen opens on an artificial world
provided there exists a common denominator between the cinemato
graphic image and the world we live in ... We may say, in fact,...
that 'the cinematographic image can be emptiedof all reality saveone
- the reality of space'.'*
'Identity' has become 'common denominator'; 'objective world'
has become 'artificial world'. Initially, the fundamental nature
of the medium revolves round the absolutes of 'identity' and the
'objective' world. But by 1951 the absolutes have been some
what mitigated. What Bazin is then concerned to discover are
the characteristics shared by the 'artificial' world of the film
and the world around us. And the most basic of these, he
argues, is our normal conception of space. The natural distribu
tion of objects in their spatial context. It is this factor which is
then crucial in determining cinematic reality.
17. Andre Bazin, What is Cinema? op. cit., pp. 14-15, my italics.
18. p. 108, my italics.
Rossellini: Paisd
&ili!^liiM
The wedding in The Best Years of Our Lives
Montage and decor are not the only ways of destroying the
visual unity of space; almost anything does. Why should they, in
particular, be singled out? The immense camera movements of
Touch ofEvil break up the world just as much as montage, and,
indeed, serve much the same function in terms of the tempo of
the film. If Bazin is really serious about spatial realism a lot
more than just montage will have to go. In the end, given that
he champions the neo-realists, he must be returned to the
argument for pure realism, to the romantic naturalist aesthetic.
Peter Wollen puts it well: 'Of Bicycle Thieves Bazin wrote that
it was the first example of pure cinema. No more actors, no
more plot, no more mise en scene-, the perfect aesthetic illusion
of reality. In fact, no more cinema.'^'*
24. Peter Wollen, Signs and Meaning in the Cinema, Seeker and
Warburg/British Film Institute, London, 1973, p. 131.
No More Cinema
If I have spent these many pages attacking the realist aesthetic
it is not —as it might have been —because I wish to support a
contradictory aestheticism. That debate should be certified
dead. Too much time has already been wasted in its by-ways.
Both those who take Melies and those who take Lumiere as
exemplifying the 'great tradition' are guilty of the same error;
an error which Kracauer and Bazin have in common. Refusing
the fence of relativism they gallop blindly into the ditch of
essentialism. Unwilling to admit the rightful subjectivity of our
aesthetic judgements, they dodge the consequent hail of non-
problems by recourse to a non-argument. The fundamental
character of film, they say, is naturally such-and-such, so
any film that fulfils this nature is therefore good. This, hope
fully but wrongly, is independent of subjective judgement.
Ultimately, both Bazin and Kracauer want a cinema and
an aesthetic from which human interference is absent. An
immaculate conception!
The tradition is a well-developed one. It reflects above all a
romantic faith in nature. Art must passively reveal the natural
world. And this faith is very much connected with the equally
nineteenth-century conviction that there is some great objective
world out there at which we may point our 'artistic' sensi
bilities. But romantic aesthetics and positivism are not quite the
powers that they once were. If we are tempted to reinstate them
we would do well to look at Bazin and Kracauer to see where
they lead. They lead, as Wollen suggests, to 'no more cinema'.
To the paradox that the fundamental essence of film is to
destroy everything which distinguishes it as film. And yet
Bazin and Kracauer obviously dearly loved a number of films
well outside the ambit of their respective pure aesthetics. One
can imagine a fitting epitaph: 'Here lie two theories. Their
cinematic eyes were bigger than their aesthetic stomachs, and
they perished from indigestion.'
5: Critical Method: Auteur and
Genre
Auteur
The most misleading development in contemporary English
language writings on film lies in the joining of the two terms
'auteur' and 'theory'. It is something called the auteur theory
which has provided the touchstone of many a violent dispute.
Yet the direct ancestor of the auteur usage is to be found in the
'politique des auteurs' of Cahiers du Cinema, in the now
famous criticism of Truffaut and his colleagues. How 'policy',
the most obvious translation of 'politique', became 'theory' is a
tributary in the history of ideas which need not be dealt with
here. Sufficient to note that when the Cahiers group said
'policy' they meant 'policy'. Their use of auteur was exactly
that: a polemical position marking their views off from the
orthodox tradition in French criticism and, ultimately, when
they started making films, from the rest of the French cinema.
In the England of this period (the early and mid-1950s) op
position to the traditional approach was marshalled under the
banners of realism and commitment. Like Grierson before
them, these critics mistrusted the commercial American
cinema. But in France, fathered though not controlled by Bazin,
Cahiers used a partisan support of certain American directors
against the 'serious' Continental cinema. Which directors
exactly varied from critic to critic and group to group, but
names like Hitchcock, Ford, Hawks, Ray, Losey, Preminger,
and Walsh recurred. It was this polemical and exclusive sup
port for these American figures that was characteristic of the
'politique des auteurs'.
There were thus two notions central to the use of auteur
from the very beginning. First, the old idea that the director
was the true creator of the film. However controversial this
may have been in the past (Spottiswoode dedicated his 1935
book to 'the future of the director's cinema')^ it has surely now
passed forever into the realms of acceptability. The old
arguments, often tied to the attempt to 'prove' that film was
indeed the seventh art, have by and large been successfully
arbitrated. While no one would deny the collective nature of
film production, the crucial importance of the director's con
ception is part of the orthodox canon. The Antonionis, the
Bergmans, the Godards, and the Fellinis, are accepted as, at the
very least, the creative integrators of the disparate elements of
film. If auteur were simply this then it would have ceased to be
controversial years ago. But the second notion involved in the
Cahiers usage led in a breakaway direction. Applying the
notion of director as auteur to the maligned commercial
2. Raymond Spottiswoode, A Grammar of Film, Faber and Faber,
London, 1955.
Hollywood cinema raised a whole new series of bogeymen. In
Europe the director was thought to be relatively free from the
commercial pressures of Hollywood. It was this 'freedom'
which allowed him to be an auteur. But for years past conven
tional wisdom had seen Hollywood as a collection of variously
qualified craftsmen turning out variously competent films. Of
course, it was never entirely clear that the contrast between the
American and European situation was so great; folklore, how
ever, could always fall back on the great artists ruined by the
commercial citadel: Stroheim, Murnau, even Eisenstein. What
the Cahiers critics did was to find auteurs where none had been
dreamt of before. Directors like Welles, Hitchcock, and to a
lesser extent Ford, had always been accorded some admira
tion. The fate of the emigres had been bemoaned: Lang, the
paradigm case, was frequently and wrongly claimed to have
declined in Hollywood. But until Cahiers the rest were simply
a part of the commercial forest. ART was to be found else
where, by definition.
It was this singling out of American directors which was
first taken up in the English and American critical context. In
America Andrew Sarris provided a focus in the pages of Film
Culture-, in Britain the group of critics writing in Movie for
mulated their own set of American auteurs. In both contexts, as
indeed in France, there were inevitable extravagances. In em
ploying the notion of auteur as a basis for evaluating films there
was always the open invitation to elevate the worst films of an
auteur over the best films of another director as a matter of
course. Because an auteur made the film it must be good. The
reductio ad absurdum of this position is that it is not necessary
to actually see the films, sufficient only to know who directed
them. It becomes self-evident that bad Hitchock {Topaz) is
better than good Rossen {The Hustler or Lilith); bad Hawks
{Hatari) is better than good Zinnemann {High Noon)-, bad
Preminger {Exodus) is better than good Lumet {TheHill). And
all of them are better than the 'respectable' European directors.
Ironically enough, it is probably a good measure of the dilet
tantism of traditional criticism that the Anglo-American auteur
critics veered so close to these absurdities. For such extreme
positions are only really intelligible in terms of the polemical
needs of the situations in which they arose. This was guerrilla
warfare against an apparently safely established enemy. It was
no time for sweet reason.
Hence 'politique des auteurs' led to the formulation of lists,
of slogans. The 'Ten Best' ideas were no longer parlour games
but declarations of position. The guilty party who added the
notion 'theory' to this loosely formulated policy appears to
have been Andrew Sarris. In 'Notes on the Auteur Theory in
1962'^ he provided a rather highly coloured suit of clothes for
the polemically naked emperor, and, in addition, an easy open
ing for attack from the 'traditionalists'. It is only necessary to
demonstrate the peculiarities of Sarris' article - hardly difficult
- and we can forget about auteur forever! The invitation was
avidly taken up by that '... lady critic with a lively sense of
outrage', Pauline Kael, who, carried away on a rising wave of
sarcasm, pushed herself into some equally strange corners."*
She made the still common mistake of throwing out all the
auteur babies with Sarris' admittedly murky bathwater.
Between his theoretical premises and her vituperation most of
the point was lost. Sarris, no doubt moved by the salutary
experience, made some amends next time round. In a much less
extravagant piece he admitted that'... the auteur theory is not
so much a theory as an attitude,' ^ which is, of course, exactly
what it had been up to the Sarris-Kael exchange. Were it not
that the rumpus in question is still invoked as the nail in the
coffin of the 'auteur theory' (Roy Armes' almost hysterical
3. Andrew Sarris, 'Notes on the Auteur Theory in 1962', Film Culture,
27, 1962-3.
4. Pauline Kael, 'Circles and Squares, Joys and Sarris', I Lost it at the
Movies, Jonathan Cape, London, 1966.
5. Andrew Sarris, The American Cinema, op. cit., p. 30
•*%£
Genre
Auteur at least originated in film criticism in the recent past;
genre had a lengthy pedigree in literary criticism long before
the advent of the cinema. Hence the meaning and uses of the
10. A longerand slightly different versionof this sectionwas publishedas
'Genre: Theory and Mispractice in Film Criticism', Screen, 11, 6,
1970.
The Man Who Shot Liberty Valance
yi
isolated, for which purposes a criterion is necessary, but the
criterion is, in turn, meant to emerge from the empirically
established common characteristics of the films. This 'empiricist
dilemma' has two solutions. One is to classify films ac
cording to a priori chosen criteria depending on the critical
purpose. This leads back to the earlier position in which the
special genre term is redundant. The second is to lean on a
common cultural consensus as to what constitutes a 'Western',
and then go on to analyse it in detail.
This latter is clearly the root of most uses of genre. It is this
usage that leads to, for example, the notion of conventions in a
genre. The 'Western', it is said, has certain crucial established
conventions - ritualistic gun-fights, black/white clothing corre
sponding to good/bad distinctions, revenge themes, certain
patterns of clothing, typed villains, and many, many more. The
best evidence for the widespread recognition of these conven
tions is to be found in those films which pointedly set out to
invoke them. Shane, for example, plays very much on the stereo
typed imagery contrasting the stooping, black-clad, sallow,
be-gloved Palance with the tall (by dint of careful camera
angles), straight, white buckskinned, fair, white-horsed Ladd.
The power of this imagery is such that the sequence in which
Shane rides to the showdown elevates him to a classically
heroic posture. The point is reinforced by comparing Stevens'
visualization of his characters with the very different descrip
tions offered in Schaefer's novel. The film 'converts' the images
to its own conventional language. Other obvious examples are
provided by the series of Italian Westerns. The use of Lee Van
Cleef in leading roles depends very much on the image he has
come to occupy over two decades of bit-part villains. Actors in
the series - Van Cleef, Eastwood, Wallach, Jack Elam, Woody
Strode, Henry Fonda, Charles Bronson - perpetually verge on
self-parody. The most peculiar of the films —Once Upon a Time
in the West —is a fairy-tale collection of Western conventions,
verging on self-parody, and culminating in what must be the
most extended face-off ever filmed. Indeed, the most telling
suggestions as to the importance of conventions are to be found
in the gentle parodies of Cat Ballon, Support Your Local
Sherriff, and The Good Guys and the Bad Guys. Without clear,
shared conceptions of what is to be expected from a 'Western'
such humour is not possible. One of the best sequences in Cat
Ballon encapsulates the importance of the imagery, the
sequence in which Lee Marvin is changed from drunken wreck
to classic gunfighter. Starting very humorously with Marvin
struggling into a corset, the transformation not only alters him
but brings out a response in us as piece by piece the stereo
typed image appears.
In short, to talk about the 'Western' is (arbitrary definitions
apart) to appeal to a common set of meanings in our culture.
From a very early age most of us have built up a picture of a
'Western'. We feel that we know a 'Western' when we see one,
though the edges may be rather blurred. Thus in calling a film a
'Western' the critic is implying more than the simple statement,
'This film is a member of a class of films ("Westerns") having
in common x, y, z'. He is also suggesting that such a film would
be universally recognized as such in our culture. In other
words, the crucial factors which distinguished a genre are not
only characteristics inherent to the films themselves; they also
depend on the particular culture within which we are operating.
And unless there is world consensus on the subject (which is an
empirical question) there is no basis for assuming that a
'Western' will be conceived in the same way in every culture.
The way in which the genre term is applied can quite con
ceivably vary from case to case. Genre notions - except the
special case of arbitrary definition - are not critic's classifi
cations made for special purposes; they are sets of cultural
conventions. Genre is what we collectively believe it to be.
It is for precisely this reason that genre notions are so
potentially interesting. But more for the exploration of the
psychological and sociological interplay between film-maker.
r
m/1
fe
' 'Jd
Cat Ballou
Critical Methodology
Both auteur and genre started life deeply implicated in sets of
aesthetic judgements. Auteur as part of a glorification of the
American cinema, a way of looking at trees; genre as a con
demnation of the American cinema, a way of merging trees into
forests. In the course of the 1960s, however, they have becom.e
increasingly divorced from this context. Much of their
evaluative content has been drained off, leading to their use in
an increasingly descriptive sense. Whatever the difficulties and
assumptions in their use, and I have tried to show that they are
not inconsiderable, they reflect a growing interest in detailed
and responsible critical interpretation. The stress on thematic
structure in the use of the auteur principle has led to an interest
in the application to film of methodologies from other
disciplines, in particular techniques borrowed from structural
linguists and anthropology. The attempt to find a construc
tive use for genre terms has led to an interest in techniques for
analysing the recurrent motifs in groups of films. Often this has
been more concerned with the visual iconography of the genre.
Either way, thcwight on film has shifted away from theoretical
interests toward discussion of the methodology of analysis.
There is now much more self-conscious interest in the
processes involved in analysing, comprehending, and evaluat
ing films.
It is much too early to say whether the methodologies under
consideration will prove fruitful. Although it seems obviously
potentially rewarding to look at the thematic structures implicit
in a director's work, the particular structuralist techniques
invoked are rarely satisfactory. To reduce the thematic con-
cerns of a group of films to a set of polarities may be adequate
in some contexts - consider, for instance, Peter Wollen on
Hawks or Alan Lovell on Siegel - but not in others. The
assumptions necessary in order to analyse all content in terms
of polar opposites are far from safely established. Structures do
not 'leap out' from the subject matter as one notable structur
alist has suggested; they are at least partly imposed by the
consciousness of the observer. Any schematizations produced in
this way must, therefore, be treated as hypotheses to be tested
against the material, not conclusively established truths. The
problems of detailed analysis still remain. The 'structural'
method is hardly a magic formula.
Still, such methods have shown some pay-off. The search for
otherwise unnoticed patterns, encouraged by the auteur prin
ciple and the crude application of structural techniques, is not
an inconsiderable achievement. It breaks down the regal
isolation of the film as basic unit of analysis. Similarly with the
use ofgenre, demanding, as it does, thata film or group offilms
be considered in a larger context. And in the end, auteur and
genre do not retreat into methodology as totally as they
initially seem to do. Although they serve to focus our attention
predominantly on problems of descriptive analysis, such
analysis in turn leads back to theoretical questions. Aesthetic
issues, becausethe greater our analysis the greater the invitation
to judge or criticize. Models of film, because there are no final
methodological answers to our problems of understanding. If
the auteur principle is to be pursued it is not sufficient to pick
out the clearest thematic oppositions; to do so risks losing that
which makes film specifically film. We also need to know how
film works, the means of expression at levels other than the
narrative surface, in a word, what language a film is speaking.
It remains to be seen whether semiology (the general science of
13. Peter Wollen, Signs and Meaning in the Cinema, Seeker and
Warburg/British Film Institute, London, 1969, pp. 81-94; Alan
Lovell, Don Siegel —American Cinema, op. cit.
signs) will provide us with a starter in this respect. It has not
started too well. But certainly such demands return us to the
interests initially developed by Eisenstein over thirty years ago.
If genre notions are also to be developed we will inevitably be
led to sociological and psychological theories of film, to
questions about the context within which the cinema is operat
ing. The form of such questions remains unclear but there is no
doubt that they will be asked. Perhaps Eisenstein's self-imposed
task of creating a unified theory of film, of understanding the
medium in which he was so involved, may yet be completed. If
we can escape the aesthetic disputes of the past, and some of the
more anti-intellectual prejudices of the present, film theory
might yet receive the attention that it merits.
6: Epilogue
A'
l!i% »
; -»>
theless remains that Tourneur's later —and excellent - Night of
the Demon (also known as Curse of the Demon) and Wise's The
Haunting have not uncommon similarities with the earlier
Lewton films, besides a cinematic reference group in the notion
of a horror genre. Clearly the horror film, the Western, the
thriller —given the difficulties raised in Chapter Five - are all
in principle amenable to analysis of structure. The individual
artistic persona is not the only possible hypothetical 'explan
ation' of the existence of a communality of structures across a
range of films. A set of genre conventions may be equally
apposite.
But this almost purely decoratively terminological use of the
notion of structure says little or nothing about the problems of
application. This has always been the limitation of straight
forward genre or auteur applications. What are the categories
of thematic and/or stylistic structure? What class of units are
involved? How are they related? Any fully-fledged discussion
of film must of necessity deal with such questions, and as a
priority. But in the main the 'structuralist' impetus has not yet
led to refinement at this level. It has instead given rise to a
methodology of analysis based largely on dichotomization; to
the idea that culture, thought, or whatever, is innately struc
tured in terms of a series of dichotomies. This has been mainly
derived from a vulgarization of the work of Claude Levi-
Strauss, an anthropologist who has proved something of a
critical messiah. His analysis of the structure of myth in similar
terms has led the unwary to claim 'myth' status for the film
genre in modern society. And where application of 'structur
alism' has not directly involved such sociological absurdity, it
has invariably been simplified in terms of a descending series
of dichotomies. Through such techniques it is hoped to render
explicit the 'deep' structures of the films in question: what used
to be termed in more mundane and facetious manner, the
'hidden meanings'. But of course there is no a priori reason for
employing dichotomization, particularly when it is assumed —
as it frequently is - that these dichotomically related themes
are inherent in the films themselves independent of the obser
ver. Dichotomization can be at best only an epistemological
\veapon. Its claim to ontological universality is deeply prob
lematic.
In practice a great deal of criticism labelled 'structural' has
little to do with this reductio ad Levi-Strauss. It simply reflects
some degree of interest in the structure of relationships be
tween thematic clusters in, say, a director's work. And the
development of that focus was, as we have seen, largely
independent of contemporary ideas about 'structuralism'. The
act of analysing structure and structural/s/n may usefully be
kept separate. Apparently structuralist work, such as Peter
Wollen's analysis of Sam Fuller, is only superficially so; a
focus on auteur and a desire for method would be sufficient to
generate the approach.' Indeed, what is valuable about such
work is not that it is sufficiently similar to other disciplines to
claim some part of their intellectual legitimacy, but that it
persists in directing attention toward the notion of structure. It
demands that we explicitly look at the film(s) as a total config
uration rather than a discrete set of elements. But basically it
tells us little more. It does not, as it stands, seriously address
itself to the problem of film language, of how films in fact
communicate these various allegedly structured clusters. In this
context other associated inputs have proved more interesting, if
not yet more lucrative.
The model for this much more specified interest in film
language has been linguistics. Thus, there has been a suggestion
that it might be possible to create a cinematic equivalent to
Chomsky's transformational grammar. Such a theory would
enable us to generate all possible grammatical statements in
the 'language'. But this hope leans heavily on the possibility
of analogous development, a faith which may be misplaced.
1. See Peter Wollen, 'Notes towards a Structural Analysis of the Films of
Samuel Fuller', Cinema, 1, Dec. 1968.
Perhaps the non-cognitive element is so important in film
(along with most other arts) that linguistic strategies are too
cognitively oriented for constructive application. It is a little too
early to know, but even Bernstein's now familiar distinction
between restricted and elaborated codes has a suspiciously
cognitive bias. Applications, as opposed to programmatic
suggestions, have not been common. More often than not
'linguistic' inclinations have manifested themselves in relation
to semiology, the general science of signs. But again, we have
yet to see a developed semiological mode in relation to film.
Writers on the subject have often been basically more con
cerned to illumine the ontological nature of film as a stage in
developing an aesthetic position. Metz, in one guise or another,
develops and reiterates versions of Bazin's classic position.^
And while Wollen makes illuminating general use of Peirce's
distinction between iconic, indexical, and symbolic signs, the
traditional semiological focus on the symbolic or arbitrary sign
prevents us from adequately filling in the detail.^ And reference
to Barthes' works is demonstration of the stringent limitations
on semiological analysis of more complex communication
systems."
We are then relatively well provided with sources of'linguis
tic' sensitization, but little more. Excellent cases have been
made for focusing on the persistent structures running through
one or a series of films. By and large, however, this interest has
developed in relation to theme at the expense of style; needless
to say there is no reason to think of this as a necessary con-
See, among many others, Christian Metz, 'Le dire et le dit au cinema:
vers le declin d'un vraisemblable'. Communications, 11, 1968;
'Propositions methodologiques pour I'analyse du film'. Social Science
Information, VII, 4, 1968.
Peter Wollen, Signs and Meaning in the Cinema, Seeker & Warburg/
BFI, London, 1969, pp. 120fT.
Roland Barthes, Elements of Semiology and Writing Degree Zero, both
published by Jonathan Cape, London, 1967.
junction, though style is undoubtedly more difficult to handle.
But a clear prerequisite, if'structural' analysis is to be anything
more than a dressed up list of dichotomous distinctions, must
be the development of a detailed theory of film language.
Whether this will derive from a general science of signs or will
later be slotted into it remains open. Most likely both strategies
will be involved in some part. But at the moment all we really
have is an a priori faith derived partly from the respectable
overtones of terms like 'structuralism' and 'semiology'. As far
as film criticism is concerned both labels are still getting by on
credit. They constitute very general pointers in the direction of
'progress' but have thus far shown little real analytical power.
Naive structuralism especially might be argued to have had
predominantly negative consequences in reducing analysis to a
formula simplification of a few themes. And none of the major
contemporary approaches have come to terms with the par
ticular structured relations which were of so much interest to
Eisenstein: rhythm, tempo, and formal compositional contrast.
Undoubtedly there is promise but it remains largely unfulfilled.
We have only a few fragmentary clues as to our best directions
of development.
Theories of Film
It is a commonplace to suggest that all processes of comprehen
sion involve a framework of assumptions, propositions, and the
like. Attempts to evaluate the aesthetic importance of an object
as much as attempts to empirically investigate it are basically
processes of 'mapping' the object into some previously consti
tuted framework. Neither endeavour exists in a vacuum. Of
course, nothing follows as such from this observation: several
further premises are needed for that. But it does seem that
experience in other areas of inquiry suggests that there are
important payoffs to be derived from explicit discussion of
such frameworks. Their nature, their internal consistency, and
the manner of their relation to their subject. For facts do not
L'Annee Derniere a Marienbad