This Content Downloaded From 163.117.159.87 On Tue, 08 Feb 2022 09:32:12 UTC
This Content Downloaded From 163.117.159.87 On Tue, 08 Feb 2022 09:32:12 UTC
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Oxford University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
European Review of Economic History
REVIEW ARTICLE
This review article looks at the recent books on the British Industrial
Revolution by Robert Allen and Joel Mokyr. Both writers seek to explain
Britain's primacy. This article offers a critical but sympathetic account of
the main arguments of the two authors, considering both the economic
logic and the empirical validity of their rival claims. In each case, the ideas
are promising but the evidence base seems in need of further support. It
may be that eventually these explanations for British economic leadership
at the turn of the nineteenth century are recognized as complementary
rather than competing.
ι. Introduction
New books by Robert Allen (2009a) and Joel Mokyr (2009) contain
important, but competing, reinterpretations of the British Industrial
Revolution. They share common ground in placing the explanation of
sustained acceleration in technological progress at the heart of the story.
They differ, however, on the reasons for this. Allen stresses that the new
technologies were invented in Britain because they were profitable there
but not elsewhere, while Mokyr sees the Enlightenment as highly significant
and underestimated by previous scholars. They each think that the other's
argument is flawed.
This review article seeks first to set out the claims of the two authors and to
place them in some historiographie context, and then to evaluate them. The
tone will, I hope, be one of sympathetic criticism. The task of explaining why
the first Industrial Revolution took place in Britain in the late eighteenth and
early nineteenth centuries is far from trivial; indeed, it has been thought of
in the past as akin to a search for the Holy Grail. The endeavour undertaken
by Allen and Mokyr is most welcome, inter alia, as an antidote to the
fashionable approach of Unified Growth Theory (Galor 2005), which treats
the Industrial Revolution either as essentially a scale effect or as the outcome
of some Darwinian selection process. Taking technological change seriously
must be the hallmark of an economic historian's perspective on the transition
to modern economic growth and these two authors have over some decades
been established at the top of the premier league as analysts of the economic
history of technology.
Allen's explanation for the time and place of the first Industrial
Revolution can be summarized as follows. He concentrates on examining
what stimulated the technological breakthroughs associated with famous
inventions which then triggered off sequences of technological progress
(p. 135). His conclusion is deceptively simple: 'The Industrial Revolution,
in short, was invented in Britain in the eighteenth century because it paid to
invent it there' (p. 2).
This bottom line is reached in several steps. First, it is stressed that
'Britain's unique price and wage structure was the pivot around which
the Industrial Revolution turned' (p. 15). In particular, international
comparisons show Britain had relatively high wages but cheap capital and
very cheap energy. Second, Allen points to the high fixed costs of developing
'macro-inventions' into commercially viable technologies through research
and development; he argues that these will only be incurred where the
technology is profitable to adopt, a decision which turns on relative factor
prices, and where the market is big enough that success in perfecting the
technology will deliver enough sales to reward the proprietor (pp. 141-2,
151 -4). Third, the profitability of adopting several inventions including the
spinning jenny, Arkwright's mill and coke smelting is examined, with the
result in each case that adoption is rational at British but not at French
prices (chapters 8 and 9). Fourth, these technologies are improved markedly
through time in a process of micro-invention, which is Hicks-neutral rather
than labour-saving and eventually means that it is rational for them to diffuse
widely across the rest of the world. This 'tipping point' was typically reached
some decades later and then British competitive advantage was lost (pp.
154~5)· Fifth, it is recognized that a favourable configuration of prices and
wages would not be sufficient to deliver the Industrial Revolution. Allen
accepts that 'factors touching on the supply of inventors may explain why
the Industrial Revolution happened in 1800 rather than 1400' (pp. 268-9);
he notes that a cultural revolution had happened in the meantime and that,
by the latter date, the British economy had a much greater level of human
capital (p. 12).
Although Allen provides much greater detail and conceptual
sophistication, in essence, this argument is not new. Earlier vintages tended
to talk in terms of the role of 'shortages' in inducing technological progress
and to note that Britain differed from its rivals in this regard. For example,
Peter Mathias wrote that 'It is a commonplace to remark that Britain
had been fortunate in her scarcities' (1979, p. 8), while Francois Crouzet
1 These ι O are Richard Arkwright, Edmund Cartwright, Samuel Crompton, Henry Cort,
Abraham Darby, James Hargreaves, Thomas Newcomen, John Smeaton, James Watt and
Josiah Wedgwood.
Enlightenment did not matter much' (p. 252). Second, Allen considers
whether the inventors came from the upper class as he contends the
Enlightenment model predicts. There is some support for this, in particular,
merchants, lawyers and capitalists made up 4.6 per cent of the population
but 32.8 per cent of the inventors (p. 259); however, at the same time, the
fathers of many inventors were artisans. Third, Allen looks at inventors as
experimenters; he finds that 'Experimentation was ... the common feature
that characterized eighteenth-century inventors' (p. 255), but sees this as
nothing new and takes any increases in the volume of experimentation to
be more a consequence of better education than the Enlightenment per
se (pp. 257, 267). Interestingly, Allen says nothing about the impact of
the Enlightenment on institutions or economic reform. Presumably, this is
because he considers institutional quality to be unimportant as a reason for
English primacy in the Industrial Revolution (pp. 5, 15, 125).
4. Assessment
2 This puts Hicks's (1932) conjecture on a firm foundation. It should also be noted that in
this model, in general, technical change is biased towards factors that become relatively
more abundant in the sense that, at constant factor proportions, its relative marginal
product will be increased.
the bias, of technological progress. The key result is that this effect is positive
if technological change is strongly labour saving, i.e. it reduces the marginal
product of labour.3
Thus, notwithstanding Mokyr's dismissive reaction, Allen's analysis is
theoretically defensible and his emphasis on the costs of development of a
technology goes with the flow of recent growth economics. In the spirit
of Acemoglu's model, the decision to incur the development costs for
the technologies that were central to the Industrial Revolution would be
predicted to depend on the number of potential adopters. In turn, this would
depend both on whether it was profitable for firms to adopt the technology,
given factor prices, and also on how many firms were in the market, as Allen
points out (pp. 152-3). Either relative factor prices or market size might
undermine the viability of developing the technology and it would be nice to
distinguish clearly between the two. Let us review Allen's evidence with this
in mind.
3 Technology is strongly labour saving if in the production function Y = f(L, Ζ, Θ), where θ
is a vector of technologies where an increase in any component raises output, there are
decreasing differences in θ and L. This might be where machines replace tasks previously
undertaken by labour, as in Joseph Zeira (1998).
4 This also seems to be true of the Arkwright mill. Using a procedure analogous to that used
by Allen (2009, pp. 215-16) based on American wages divided by American jenny costs
relative to English wages divided by English jenny costs ( = 1.049), I calculate that the
potential rate of return on the Arkwright mill in Philadelphia was 32.5 per cent.
5 Allen makes a similar point about the invention of the steam engine; in comparing
England and Belgium, he appeals to the small size of the Belgian coal industry rather than
relative factor prices as Belgium's key disadvantage.
6 I am grateful to John Lyons for making the point to me that Allen's utilization rates appear
very low.
LVY
7 Their hypotheses are not mutually exclusive and the real argument may be about their
relative importance.
L/Y
Mokyr stresses that the ideology of the Enlightenment had a dual impact
on the first Industrial Revolution both because it was conducive to the
production of more useful knowledge while at the same time redu
access costs and through its effects in improving incentive structures thr
promoting better economic policy and institutions. This argument f
perfectly with endogenous growth theory in the tradition of Philippe Agh
and Peter Howitt (1992). Once again, the issues that arise are not so m
with the logic of the argument but its empirical validity.
In terms of Figure 2, the Enlightenment would raise λ, the innova
friendliness of the economy, thus shifting the Schumpeter relation
upwards and increasing the amount of technological progress expect
any level of the capital to effective labour ratio. The favourable impac
came both through lower costs of innovating and from better payoffs
innovating as the process of creative destruction was facilitated and
seeking opportunities were greatly reduced. Mokyr sees the breakth
of the British Industrial Revolution in terms of a transition to sustained
technological advance and thus the real contribution of the higher λ tha
to the Enlightenment was to underpin productivity growth through mi
invention (pp. 487-8).
Mokyr's argument is much more subtle than earlier discussions of
institutional change in the context of the Industrial Revolution. For example,
in emphasizing the effectiveness of the parliamentary system as an agent of
reforms that make markets work better he is more convincing on how the
Glorious Revolution mattered than North and Barry Weingast (1989), in
downplaying the role of the 'deeply flawed' patent system (p. 410) relative to
other aspects of institutional quality he rightly dismisses the claims of North
and Robert Thomas (1973), and in focusing on the incentives for micro
invention he need not be perturbed by the rejection of the institutional
improvement hypothesis by Greg Clark (2007) on the grounds that many
famous inventors made no money.
Mokyr can certainly point to evidence of improvements in institutions and
reductions in rent-seeking from the mid eighteenth to the mid nineteenth
century. Bogart and Richardson (2008) noted the number of parliamentary
Acts that reorganized property rights numbered about 2$ per year in the
1720s compared with 175 per year in the 1820s. Forrest Capie (2004)
calculated an increase in the coefficient of contract-intensive money (defined
as non-currency money divided by total money supply), a proxy for the
enforceability and security of property rights, from 0.26 in 1790 to 0.76 in
1870. William Rubinstein's research on probates (1992) showed that those
based on exploiting rent-seeking opportunities provided by the state were
still very prominent in 1809-39 but not thereafter.
That said, it has to be noted that Mokyr offers no quantification either
of institutional quality or its impact on technological progress and, indeed,
this may not be possible, especially if informal institutions are held to be the
key; λ is unobservable. Moreover, while Mokyr can point to better economic
policy in terms, for example, of the abolition of the Statute of Artificers, the
Bubble Act and the Usury Laws, the reform of the patent system, and.the
repeal of the Corn Laws, many of these were long-delayed. And it is easy
to point to major failures of government policy which might well disappoint
those imbued with Enlightenment views, for example, the refusal to promote
state-financed primary education despite the high social (and fiscal) rate of
return it could have delivered (Lindert 2009), the incompetent regulation of
the railway system that involved the construction of a seriously sub-optimal
network at high cost (Casson 2009; Foreman-Peck 1987), and the obvious
shortcomings of company law even in the second half of the nineteenth
century (Cottrell 1980). These really seem to be the outcome of interest
group politics not evidence-based policy design.
So did Enlightenment ideology matter as much as Mokyr claims? The most
serious and quantitative debate on the role of ideology in policy reform has
related to the repeal of the Corn Laws in 1846. Using various econometric
methodologies, results have differed but it would fair to conclude that it is
possible to detect roles for ideology, party affiliation and economic interests
in the crucial vote (McKeown 1989; McLean and Bustani 1999). However,
the ideology which is held to matter is not that of the Enlightenment.
The most sophisticated interpretation by Cheryl Schonhardt-Bailey (2003)
actually concludes that the success of repeal in 1846 was based on a weakening
of the role of ideology relative to constituency economic interest within the
split Tory party and the ideology in question relates to defending traditional
British institutions.
5. Concluding comments
Acknowledgements
I am grateful to Bishnu Gupta for comments on an earlier draft, to Steve Broadberry
and Tim Leunig for a number of very useful suggestions, to John Lyons for his
insights on cotton-spinning technology, and to Bob Allen for help with his data.
The usual disclaimer applies.
References