Mesch W. Between Variety and Unity Platonic Dialectic
Mesch W. Between Variety and Unity Platonic Dialectic
Mesch W. Between Variety and Unity Platonic Dialectic
Plato’s dialectic has many faces. Most prominent, of course, is the general
distinction between different methods displayed in his dialogues: critical
enquiry or elenchus, hypothetical ascension and the twofold procedure
of division and collection. But these methods also show a considerable
variety depending on the topics discussed, argumentative aims, dialogical
settings and the ontological assumptions at play, suggesting an even more
diversified picture. In view of these findings, it seems far from obvious
that there is one single unified conception of dialectic in Plato’s dialogues.
Quite the contrary, we find ourselves confronted with the threat of incon-
sistencies, even with respect to fundamental issues. It is not even possible
to give an unambiguous and comprehensive answer to the important
question whether, for Plato, dialectic leads to knowledge of transcendent
ideas, because in some dialogues this appears to be the case, and in others
not, or at least not clearly.
Against this background, interpreters since the 19th century have
worked out developmental models, assuming an evolution of Plato’s
thought and ascribing different methods and conceptions to different sets
of dialogues written in successive periods of time. At first sight such an
assumption seems natural, since philosophers usually write most of their
texts one after the other and not all of them simultaneously. In addi-
tion, they often tend to change their minds over time by acquiring new
insights or doubts. And apparent inconsistencies can, at least sometimes,
be explained on the basis of such changes. When it comes to Plato, how-
ever, developmental models are not at all unproblematic. In particular,
it is far from clear whether the dialogues show a development or evo-
lution in his thought and in which sense this could be the case. Many
assumptions made in this regard have been severely criticised, especially
during the last decades, and in particular concerning extreme versions of
developmentalism that presuppose outright conceptual breaks between
different stages.2
I consider much of this criticism well-founded and think this also holds
for the developmental account of Plato’s dialectic. So even if there is a
DOI: 10.4324/9781003111429-9
170 Walter Mesch
certain kind of development, we still have to ask how the variety and
unity of dialectical methods in his dialogues can be understood. In this
chapter, I explain why many aspects of developmental interpretations are
problematic and suggest a more plausible account of Platonic dialectic.
The first and introductory section considers methodological matters, with
the primary aim of delineating in which sense the dialogues may actually
be said to show a certain development and in which senses this has to
be denied. The second and main section supplements this methodologi-
cal introduction with considerations regarding the objects of dialectical
methods. In view of the special status of transcendent forms, the primary
question here is whether certain methods are exclusively concerned with
certain objects. The third section finally tries to give an answer to my titu-
lar question, how to deal with Plato’s dialectic. I suggest that both variety
and unity are essential features of the dialectical enquiries we find in his
dialogues. Plato works with basically unchanging methods, but employs
them in a highly context-sensitive way according to an ambitious scheme
of philosophical investigation and education.
(1) Although it is natural to assume that Plato, just as any other phi-
losopher, acquired insights over time and to a certain extent changed
already established positions, there are no methodological, ontologi-
cal or other relevant breaks in his dialogues suggesting that his concep-
tion of dialectic can only be interpreted consistently by presupposing
a development of his thought in a psychological or intellectual sense.
Therefore, one should avoid making strong developmentalist claims.
(2) The only philosophically meaningful development when it comes
to Plato’s dialogues is the ongoing philosophical articulation of the
186 Walter Mesch
single and unitary conception of dialectic they themselves present.
In this articulation, we find first an emphasis on refutation, shifting
then to hypothesis and finally to division and collection. But this
emphasis should not be confused with a successive relevance of only
one method at a given time, because in one way or the other they are
very often employed in combination.
(3) Insofar as there is no definition without division and collection, at
least in the standard case of definitions presupposing a scheme of
subordinated concepts or forms, this has to be considered the cen-
tral method throughout. But the other methods are also important.
Refutation is necessary for dealing with inappropriate positions and
hypothesis for the combination or justification of definitions, which
are either still being investigated or already known. This structure
is quite varied in the dialogues, but relevant throughout. In order to
adequately understand the methods being employed it is as necessary
to discover the reason for the variation in each case (which is mainly
found in the topic of the given dialogue and its interlocutors), as it is
to see the underlying unity.
(4) This methodological unity, together with the other links discussed
in the long main section two above, have an ontological basis in the
link between the definitional question and transcendent forms. This
link is still relevant in the late dialogues, although here the empha-
sis lies less on the transcendent status of these forms than on their
formal presuppositions and on the possibilities of their application.
Nowhere in the late dialogues are transcendent forms abandoned or
missing altogether, not even in the very concrete and practically ori-
ented discussions of the Laws. The members of the nocturnal council
must know not only that the good and the beautiful are manifold,
but also in which sense they come together in a unity (966a). And the
same is required in the case of other important questions including
the unity of all virtues. Hence, it is hard to deny that the members
of the nocturnal council have to master key competences of dialectic
concerning transcendent forms (Frede 2004, 154).
(5) The plan for this continuous articulation can be seen best in the simi-
les of the Republic, although even they present only a very abbrevi-
ated sketch. Thus, in the simile of the line, dialectic is only mentioned
as a dialectical capacity of the intellect concerning transcendent
forms whereas perceptible things and their images seem to lie beyond
its scope. But it is, of course, the dialectician Socrates who is present-
ing all sections of the line and the corresponding way of education in
the simile of the cave. This speaks in favour of a broader understand-
ing of dialectic not limited exclusively to the upper half of the line,
but also relating to the lower half. It is far from clear how we should
understand the way up to the good as the unhypothetical principle
and the way down to the sensible world. The cave, however, shows at
Between Variety and Unity 187
least that education through dialectic leading first up to the good and
then down again does not start and end with transcendent forms, but
on the lowest levels with perceptible things and their images. Such a
broad understanding of dialectic fits better with the practice of the
middle dialogues, because it regards dialectic as primarily concerned
with transcendent forms without being limited to them.
(6) According to this scientific and educational scheme, the early dia-
logues start paving the way to knowledge through definitional ques-
tions and by refuting inadequate answers, thus pointing out the
deficiencies of opinions. But part of this task still has to be realised in
the middle and late dialogues. Another relevant part here is the hypo-
thetical ascension to higher stages already prepared in the Meno and
then suggested mainly by the Phaedo and the Republic. This ascent
is, however, not accomplished completely in the middle dialogues.
As we have seen, there are e.g. good reasons to interpret the greatest
kinds in the Sophist as the highest or most common forms reflecting
formal features essentially belonging to all transcendent forms. And
if this is correct, it seems natural to understand this formal reflec-
tion on transcendent forms as a late contribution to the ascent men-
tioned in the simile of the line. The double task of deducing from
higher principles and of descending back into the cave again is also
carried out in many different versions. Parallel to the simile of the
line, but not identical with it, deduction plays a special role in the
Phaedo, where Socrates suggests that one tests hypotheses not only
by ascending to higher ones but also by investigating whether their
logical consequences lead to contradictions (101d: cf. Stemmer 1992,
263). Moreover, for getting back into the cave, ethically or politi-
cally, the Republic and the Laws work out two different versions,
the first one more abstract, the second one more concrete. Thus, in
dealing with the leading scheme provided by the simile of the line, an
exclusivist allocation of certain dialogues to certain stages would be
inappropriate.
(7) The similes of the Republic and other key passages of Plato’s dia-
logues explicitly focusing on dialectic are of primary importance for
understanding his thought and have to be preferred to developmen-
tal or systematic presuppositions relying on external considerations
advanced by scholars. But even these passages should not be isolated
from the rest of the dialogues, since they only articulate general and
abstract schemes of dialectical methods. And such general articula-
tions are necessarily less rich or concrete than what the dialogues
show through the ongoing practice of these methods. How dialec-
tic is related not only to transcendent forms, but also to perceptible
things and souls only becomes clear when this dialectical practice is
taken into account. This is the reason why I did not limit myself to
well-known key passages on dialectic but also tried to bring in and
188 Walter Mesch
explain illuminating examples we find elsewhere in the dialogues.
As we have seen from these examples there is no need to assume a
tension between Plato’s explicit articulations of dialectic and his dia-
lectical practice. It simply has to be acknowledged that the concrete
understanding of dialectic the dialogues show throughout in their
ongoing practice is richer than the theoretical articulations of dialec-
tic. This is particularly clear with regard to the context-sensitive vari-
ations of the fundamental dialectical capacities. As I see it, however,
very much the same could be shown for the dialogical realisation
of dialectical methods not explicitly discussed in the key passages
on dialectic. I cannot enter into this issue here, but I think it is also
unnecessary to assume a conflict between dialectical methods and
their dialogical settings identified by some scholars (Roochnik 2003,
133–151). What we find is rather that the key passages on dialectic
concentrate on the theoretical foundations of dialectic and not on its
dialogical practice shown throughout Plato’s texts.
(8) The practice of dialectic can be considered important without relying
on problematic assumptions of an external systematic or develop-
mental origin. Before I finish, I would like to explain this in order to
point out where I mainly differ from Wolfgang Wieland and Charles
Kahn when it comes to the dialectical practice and its ongoing articu-
lation in Plato’s dialogues. Concerning systematic issues, it is neither
necessary to assume that the practical key competence of a dialec-
tician, being essentially non- propositional, cannot be articulated
theoretically in propositional statements, nor that dialogues, differ-
ing from treatises, are completely immune to the critique of writing
in the Phaedrus, as Wieland maintains (1982, 53 and 234–6). The
advantages of dialogues can be defended without such a preference
for practical competence alien to the Platonic unity of practice and
theory. Concerning developmental issues, it is not necessary to tie the
philosophical articulation of Plato’s dialectic to a temporal succession
in the way Kahn’s proleptic reading does. Kahn criticises historical
assumptions concerning Plato’s relation to Socrates and psychologi-
cal assumptions concerning Plato’s development, but still presupposes
a problem-answer-relation apparent to a so-called “original reader”
(Griswold 1990, 248–50). This is problematic since we know neither
exactly when the dialogues were written and appeared nor what an
original reader could have grasped. In the book summarising his pre-
vious articles, Kahn explicitly grants the first point, but still wants to
suggest an ideal reading order for his proleptic or ingressive interpre-
tation of the early dialogues referring to their relative distance from
the Republic (Kahn 1996, 48). I am not sure whether there is anything
like this ideal reading order, but I also think that many problems of
the early dialogues are solved in the middle ones. And it undoubt-
edly is better to interpret Plato’s articulation or gradual disclosure of
Between Variety and Unity 189
his dialectic without strong developmental or temporal assumptions
(Kahn 1996, 63–5). As I have tried to show, this also holds for the late
dialogues. What I want to recommend, in any case, is not to build a
hermeneutical or dramatical interpretation upon developmental pre-
suppositions concerning the writing and reading of Plato’s dialogues
but to combine it with systematic or argumentative accounts of the
represented methods and objects themselves.
Notes
1 I would like to thank Vivil Valvik Haraldsen, Kristian Larsen and Justin
Vlasits for their helpful criticisms and suggestions.
2 Classical examples of developmentalism are Stenzel 1931 and Robinson
19532. While Julius Stenzel primarily stresses the emergence of a new ver-
sion of division in the Sophist, hereby distinguishing ethical and theoreti-
cal dialogues (1–2, 45–71), Richard Robinson concentrates on the difference
between the elenchus of the early and the hypothesis of the middle dia-
logues and claims a “substantial alteration” for the meaning of “dialectic” in
Plato’s early, middle and late dialogues (70). Other influential developmental
interpretations are proposed by W. K. C. Guthrie (1975) and Terence Irwin
(1995). Gregory Vlastos (1991) presents a particularly extreme version to be
discussed later. Among works criticising developmentalism I found Wieland
1982, Kahn 1981, 1996, and Howland 1991 most helpful.
3 Even if a hypothesis sufficient in a given context (ti hikanon: Phd. 101e) may
not be quite the same as a completely unhypothetical principle (archē anhy
pothetos: R. 511b).
4 This view is developed in detail in Klaus Döring’s thorough, but sobering
study, according to which the modern Socrates research has not yielded any
universally or widely accepted results (1998, 141). For the many changes in
the views of Socrates worked out and defended since the 18th century, com-
pare also Hayden Ausland (2006).
5 I owe this point to Kristian Larsen.
6 Against the background of the Timaeus it may seem more adequate to say
that souls belonging to a visible cosmos are proper objects of an eikos logos
not to be identified with any dialectical inquiry. For Plato’s cosmology, this
clearly is an important restriction to be taken seriously (cf. Mesch 20162,
147–67). But when it comes to Plato’s psychology I do not find the conse-
quences of this cosmological perspective completely decisive. To my mind, it
is hard to deny that in the Republic and the Phaedo Socrates not only inves-
tigates forms dialectically, but also souls, and that he does this on the basis
of an essential similarity between souls and forms. Is there an inconsistency
between this dialectical treatment of souls and the cosmological treatment
we find in the Timaeus? I do not think this is necessarily so, since there is a
cosmological contribution to the ontological problem of methexis relying on
a mediating function of the soul. I will briefly come back to this later.
7 For more on the significance of Socrates’ youth in the Parmenides, see the
contribution by Francisco Gonzalez to this anthology.
8 In the famous controversy between Harold Cherniss (1957) and G. E. L.
Owen (1953) this was the main, if not the only reason for Owen to reject
the standard view that the Timaeus has to be considered a late dialogue.
Since he presupposed that the critique of forms we find in the Parmenides
190 Walter Mesch
was criticising Plato’s own theory of the middle dialogues and fatal for it, he
thought the Timaeus had to be placed before the Parmenides.
9 I thank Justin Vlasits for pointing out the importance of this passage to me.
10 As I see it, this is the ultimate basis for Socrates’ dialectical investigations of
the nature of human souls we find in the Republic and the Phaedo. And it
is also the ultimate basis for the role perceptibles play in the inductive argu-
ments of the early dialogues.
11 For the methods of dialectic this clearly means that divisions here play the
central part. Nevertheless, the method of the Visitor, who is introduced as
a god of refutation (theos elenktikos: 216b), also has a strong refutational
dimension apparent mainly in the section on being (Brown 1998, 182). And,
I think, the parallel definitions of the sophist, leaving it open at first which
one is the most reliable, also show an important hypothetical dimension. On
the basis of a rather formal similarity with the angler, the Visitor first starts
with the assumption that the sophist has a certain art which in the follow-
ing six definitions is spelled out in different ways, explaining the sophist as a
sort of hunter of young men, an importer and exporter dealing with lessons
for the soul, a retailer of the same things, a salesman selling his own lessons,
an eristic specialising in verbal battles or an expert at purifying the soul of
false beliefs. The sixth definition obviously has a special status since it rather
refers to Socrates than to sophists. But the other five are also doubtful, not
only because they differ, but also since they all presuppose that the sophist is
an artist, which someone having read the early dialogues can hardly find con-
vincing (Cf. e.g. Grg. 462b–c where rhetoric clearly is no art, but only a sort of
experience, and the same has to hold for sophistry: 465c). All these definitions
have the general form “If the sophist is an artist/has an art …” and specify it
according to different possible versions of it. This is, however, a problematic
hypothesis. In the Sophist the underlying problems become explicit at the
latest after it has been clarified that sophists claim to know everything which
in fact is not possible at all (233a). And this leads to the seventh definition,
focusing on the production of deceptive images. At first, the Visitor still seems
to maintain that we here find a deceptive art (techne: 236c). But after the
long ontological discussion when he comes back to the sophist he stresses
once again and even more that sophists do not have knowledge (267b–268d).
Thus, in the end, I think, the hypothesis that the sophist is an artist producing
deceptive images has to be questioned. In fact, he does not really have an art
but only a certain experience, routine or dexterity in producing such images.
If this is convincing, it must be important for the outcome of the dialogue to
reflect on the hypothetical status of the whole argument. So, here once again
all main dialectical methods are combined. We find not only the dominating
divisions but also hypothetical and refutational aspects.
References
Ausland, Hayden W. 2006. “Socrates’ Definitional Inquiries and the History of
Philosophy.” In A Companion to Socrates, edited by Sara Ahbel-Rappe and
Rachana Kamtekar, 493–510. Oxford: Blackwell.
Brisson, Luc. 1996. “Den Kosmos betrachten, um richtig zu leben: Timaios.”
In Platon. Seine Dialoge in der Sicht neuer Forschungen, edited by Burkhard
Mojsisch, 229–248. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
Brown, Lesley. 1998. “Innovation and Continuity. The Battle of Gods and Giants,
Sophist 245–249.” In Method in Ancient Philosophy, edited by Jyl Gentzler,
181–208. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Between Variety and Unity 191
Cherniss, Harold F. 1957. “The Relation of the Timaeus to Plato´s Later
Dialogues.” American Journal of Philology 78: 225–66.
Dancy, Russell M. 2004. Plato’s Introduction of Forms. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
De Vogel, Cornelia 1953. “Platon a-t-il ou n’a-t-il pas Introduit Le Mouvement
dans Son Monde Intelligible?” Actes du 13ième Congrès International de
Philosophie 12: 61–7.
Dixsaut, Monique. 2001. Métamorphoses de la Dialectique dans les Dialogues
de Platon. Paris: Vrin.
Döring, Klaus. 1998. “Sokrates, die Sokratiker und die von ihnen begründeten
Traditionen: § 13. Sokrates.” In Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie
(Ueberweg). Die Philosophie der Antike 2/1, edited by Hellmuth Flashar, 141–
78. Basel: Schwabe Verlag.
Ebert, Theodor. 1998. “Wer sind die Ideenfreunde in Platons Sophistes?“ In
Amicus Plato (Festschrift Wolfgang Wieland), edited by Rainer Enskat, 82–
100. Berlin: De Gruyter.
Frede, Dorothea. 1999. Platons “Phaidon”. Der Traum von der Unsterblichkeit
der Seele. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
———. 2004. “Dialektik in Platons Spätdialogen.” In Platon verstehen. Themen
und Perspektiven, edited by Marcel van Ackeren, 147–67. Darmstadt:
Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
Fronterotta, Francesco. 2011. “Some Remarks on the Senses of Being in
the Sophist.” In Plato’s Sophist, Proceedings of the Seventh Symposium
Platonicum Pragenese, edited by Aleš Havliček and Filip Karfik, 35–62. Prague:
OIKOYMENH Publishers.
Gonzalez, Francisco J. 2011. “Being as Power in Plato’s Sophist and Beyond.” In
Plato’s Sophist, Proceedings of the Seventh Symposium Platonicum Pragenese,
edited by Aleš Havliček and Filip Karfik, 63–95. Prague: OIKOYMENH
Publishers.
Griswold, Charles L. 1990. “Unifying Plato: Charles Kahn on Platonic Prolepsis.”
Ancient Philosophy 10: 243–62.
Guthrie, W. K. C. 1975. A History of Greek Philosophy, Volume IV: Plato, The
Man and His Dialogues. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hoffmann, Michael. 1996. Die Entstehung von Ordnung. Zur Bestimmung von
Sein, Erkennen und Handlung in der späteren Philosophie Platons. Berlin/
Boston: De Gruyter.
Horn, Christoph. 1997. “Platons epistēmē-doxa-Unterscheidung und die
Ideentheorie.” In Platon. Politeia, edited by Otfried Höffe, 291–312. Berlin:
Akademie Verlag.
Howland, Jacob. 1991. “Re-Reading Plato: The Problem of Platonic Chronology.”
Phoenix 45 (3): 189–214.
Irwin, Terence. 1995. Plato’s Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kahn, Charles H. 1981. “Did Plato Write Socratic Dialogues?” The Classical
Quarterly 31 (2): 305–20.
———. 1996: Plato and the Socratic Dialogue. The Philosophical Use of a
Literary Form. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kraut, Richard. 2006. “The Examined Life.” In A Companion to Socrates, edited
by Sara Ahbel- Rappe and Rachana Kamtekar, 228–42. Malden: Blackwell
Publishing.
192 Walter Mesch
Larsen, Kristian. 2019. “Measuring Humans against Gods: On the Digression of
Plato’s Theaetetus.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 101 (1): 1–29.
Mesch, Walter. 2007. “Analogien und Antistrophen. Zur Bestimmung der
Rhetorik in Platons Gorgias.” In Gorgias—Menon. Proceedings of the VII
Symposium Platonicum. Selected Papers, edited by Michael Erler and Luc
Brisson, 149–157. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag.
———. 2011. “Die Bewegung des Seienden in Platons Sophistes.” In Plato’s
Sophist, Proceedings of the Seventh Symposium Platonicum Pragenese, edited
by Aleš Havliček and Filip Karfik, 96–119. Prague: OIKOYMENH Publishers.
———. 20162. Reflektierte Gegenwart. Eine Studie über Zeit und Ewigkeit bei
Platon, Aristoteles, Plotin und Augustinus. Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.
Mittelstrass, Jürgen. 1997. “Die Dialektik und ihre wissenschaftlichen
Vorübungen.” In Platon. Politeia, edited by Otfried Höffe, 229–229. Berlin:
Akademie Verlag.
Owen, G. E. L. 1953. “The Place of the Timaeus in Plato’s Dialogues.” Classical
Quarterly NS 3: 79–95.
Prior, William James. 1985. Unity and Development in Plato’s Metaphysics.
London and Sydney: Croom Helm.
Robinson, Richard. 19532. Plato’s Earlier Dialectic. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Roochnik, David. 2003. Beautiful City. The Dialectical Character of Plato’s
Republic. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.
Rowe, Christopher. 2006. “Socrates in Plato’s Dialogues.” In A Companion
to Socrates, edited by Sara Ahbel- Rappe and Rachana Kamtekar, 159–70.
Malden: Blackwell Publishing.
Ryle, Gilbert. 1939. “Plato’s Parmenides.” Mind 48: 129–51, 302–25.
Schmidt-Wiborg, Petra. 2005. Dialektik in Platons Philebos. Tübingen: Mohr
Siebeck.
Stemmer, Peter. 1992. Platons Dialektik. Die frühen und mittleren Dialoge.
Berlin/New York: De Gruyter.
Stenzel, Julius. 1931. Studien zur Entwicklung der platonischen Dialektik von
Sokrates zu Aristoteles. Leipzig und Berlin: Teubner.
Strobel, Benedikt. 2004. “Attribute der Formen und die Form des Guten.
Gerasimos Santas über die metaphysische Theorie des Guten in Platons
Politeia.” In Platon verstehen. Themen und Perspektiven, edited by Marcel van
Ackeren, 111–34. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
Szlezák, Thomas Alexander. 2011. “Zur Bedeutung der Eingangsszene des
Sophistes (216a–218a).” In Plato’s Sophist, Proceedings of the Seventh
Symposium Platonicum Pragenese, edited by Aleš Havliček and Filip Karfik,
11–34. Prague: OIKOYMENH Publishers.
Taylor, Alfred Edward. 1961. Plato: The Sophist and the Statesman, edited by
Raymond Klibansky and Elisabeth Anscombe. London: Thomas Nelson.
Vlastos, Gregory. 1991. Socrates. Ironist and Moral Philosopher. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Wieland, Wolfgang. 1982. Platon und die Formen des Wissens. Göttingen:
Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.
Williams, Thomas. 2002. “Two Aspects of Platonic Recollection.” Apeiron 35
(2): 131–152.