(07b) Learning The Language of Just War Theory
(07b) Learning The Language of Just War Theory
(07b) Learning The Language of Just War Theory
ABSTRACT This paper argues that the significance of Michael Walzer’s seminal Just and
Unjust Wars (JUW) lies in its excellence as a spur to political activism and debate. If JUW
teaches us anything, it is the value of political engagement. It reminds us that we all have a
responsibility as citizens to participate in the body politic, by holding our leaders accountable for
their foreign policy and international endeavours, among other things. The signal achievement of
JUW is that it teaches us how to do this, by providing instruction in the language of engagement
and the art of political argument. In doing so, it does us an invaluable service and provides a useful
resource for coming to grips with the world we live in. By teaching us how to argue about war, this
book has armed us for the struggles, both military and ideological, that the ‘war on terror’ will
surely present us with in the coming years. This essay will focus upon the manner by which Walzer
achieves this lofty end, revolving mostly around his innovative re-interpretation of just war theory
as a moral language.
Introduction
Like many others, I was introduced to the study of war and military ethics by
Michael Walzer’s Just and Unjust Wars (JUW). I first encountered this book
as an exchange student at SUNY, New Paltz, in 1999. Previously shy to
engage in political discussions not for want of holding an opinion, rather
because I lacked the means to express these opinions I found in JUW a
powerful resource. It provided an entry point for me, and my classmates, into
the rough and tumble of international politics as we discussed the rights and
wrongs of modern war, both during and after class, and often late into the
night. More than that, though, it taught us how to engage with the world by
providing us with a language and a vocabulary through which we might make
sense of, and address, the burning issues of the day. Consequently, when I
reflect upon what JUW might mean to us today, I am inclined to respond that
its significance lies in its excellence as both an invitation and a spur to
political activism and debate. It has inspired generations of readers to
participate in the cut and thrust of political argument by instructing them in
the language of engagement. This essay will focus upon the manner by which
Correspondence Address: Cian O’Driscoll, Department of Politics, Adam Smith Building, University of
Glasgow, Glasgow G12 8RT, UK. Tel.: 44-(0) 141-3302002. E-mail: [email protected]
JUW achieves this lofty end, revolving mostly around Walzer’s innovative re-
interpretation of just war theory as a moral language.
The first section of this paper will explain in more detail what it means to
treat just war theory as a language. Section two delves a little deeper into
the theory of language, drawing upon the work of Michael Oakeshott and
James Boyd White to demonstrate the evolutionary or protean character of
all language, including just war theory when it is understood in this way.
Section three switches attention to those critiques that have been levelled
against Walzer’s approach in JUW. In particular, it will consider the charges
of conservatism and historical relativism that have been laid at Walzer’s
door. Finally, Section four will appraise the utility of Walzer’s brand of just
war theory today, and will address the big question facing the contempor-
ary just war community: can just war theory still serve as a site of critique
at a time when the terminology of just war has been so successfully
appropriated by political and military leaders? By way of conclusion, I will
contend that the analysis provided by Walzer in JUW still has a lot to
offer with respect to the vocation of arguing about war in a so-called time
of terror.
tradition made available to him (Walzer 1992: xxv). So while it is true that this
language may be used instrumentally, it also possesses ‘its own structure’
which determines what may be argued to some extent (Walzer 2004: 12).
The just war tradition, then, ought to be understood as a language through
which we can access, debate, and contribute to the moral questions that every
war inevitably provokes. It provides us with a ‘medium of shared under-
standing and an arena of action’ with which to make sense of, and respond
to, the moral experience of war (Ball et al. 1989: 2). The terms of the just
war, Walzer writes, ‘reflect the real world . . . They are descriptive terms,
and without them we would have no coherent way of talking about war’
(Walzer 1992: 14).
If Walzer understands the just war tradition as a descriptive language, he
recognizes that it is also constitutive of the moral reality of war that it
purports to describe. The just war tradition not only provides us with a
glossary of terms to describe war, it also assigns (moral) meaning to war, and
establishes our relation to it. How we ‘arrange and classify and think’ about
war in moral terms is deeply delimited, or partly determined, by the
‘conceptual, argumentative, and rhetorical resources’ of the tradition (see
Ball 1988: 4). As Walzer (1992: 15) writes:
Reiterated over time, our arguments and judgments shape . . . the moral reality of war
that is, all those experiences of which moral language is descriptive or within which it is
necessarily employed. It is important to stress that the moral reality is not fixed by the
actual activity of soldiers but by the opinions of mankind. That means, in part, that it is
fixed by the activity of philosophers, lawyers, publicists of all sorts.
While Walzer acknowledges that our arguments and judgments do not take
place in isolation from the experience of combat, and have value only insofar
as they render that experience comprehensible, he still wishes to argue that
they contribute to how we experience combat in the first place. It is, he argues,
how we argue about war that ‘makes [it] what it is’ (Walzer 1992: 15). As a
language, then, just war theory does two distinct things, though they can
hardly be separated: first, it contributes to the moral reality of war by
establishing it as a frame of reference, and, second, it provides us with a set of
terms with which to make sense of that reality.
society. Its principles and terms are merely expressions of the moral realities
of war which are embedded in the conventions of international society.
Thus, the propositions of the legalist paradigm reflect the rules governing
interstate conduct. These rules, it is supposed, have been worked out over
time by members of international society in their dealings with one another
(Walzer 1992: 63). It is worth noting that even in those cases where Walzer
opts to revise the legalist paradigm as in his desire to acknowledge the
justice of humanitarian war or a more expansive right of anticipatory war
his stated aim is to reconcile the paradigm more closely with ‘the judgments
we actually make’ (1992: 75).
meaning. There is, then, for Walzer, a certain timelessness about just war
theory, though it is best characterized as historical, sociological, and
contingent. So while it displays a potential for renovation and change, the
theory also reflects a strong element of continuity. Subsequently, we can be
relatively confident that when we tap into the language of the just war, we are
participating in a trans-historical dialogue with the great and the good of
previous generations (for discussion see Johnson 1981: 38).
Conclusion
By way of concluding, I would like to return to the claim made in the opening
remarks that the significance of JUW lies in its excellence as both an
invitation and a spur to political activism and debate. Indeed, if JUW teaches
us anything, it is the value of political engagement. It reminds us that we all
have a responsibility as citizens to participate in the body politic, by holding
our leaders accountable for their foreign policy and international endeavours,
among other things. The only other choice is disengagement and withdrawal
from the world, which is not desirable. Disengagement and withdrawal simply
cede power, only this time unchecked, to those who have no qualms in
abusing it. Moral quietism is achieved at the expense of good-faith citizen-
ship. Instead of allowing this to happen, we must be prepared to step into the
political fold and grapple with the burden of power (our own as well as that of
others). We must participate in the political process rather than stand back
from it. The signal achievement of JUW is that it teaches us how to do this. It
provides instruction in the language of engagement and teaches us the cut and
thrust of the art of political argument. In doing so, it does us an invaluable
service and provides a useful resource for coming to grips with the
contemporary political and security environment. By teaching us how to
argue about war, and by extension how to argue about politics, this book has
armed us for the struggles, both military and ideological, that the ‘war on
terror’ will surely present us with in the coming years.
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank Alex Bellamy for inviting me to participate in this
symposium, Serena Sharma for her helpful and insightful comments, Ian
Clark for his advice over the past few years, and Toni Erskine for sharing her
understanding of Walzer’s work with me.
Notes
1
I am leaning heavily here on David Kennedy’s (2006) recent analysis of the relationship between the
practice of war and the discourse of international law.
2
George Orwell, ‘Politics and the English Language’, Horizon (April 1946).
References
Ball, T. (1988) Transforming Political Discourse: Political Theory and Critical Conceptual History (Oxford
and New York: Basil Blackwell).
Ball, T., Farr, J. & Hanson, R. L. (1989) Editors’ Introduction, in: T. Ball, J. Farr & R. L. Hanson (Eds),
Political Innovation and Conceptual Change, pp. 1 6 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Booth, K. (2001) Ten Flaws of Just Wars, in: K. Booth (Ed.), The Kosovo Tragedy: The Human Rights
Dimensions, pp. 314 324 (London: Frank Cass).
Dworkin, R. M. (1983) To Each His Own, New York Review of Books , April.
Elshtain, J. B. (1992) Reflections on War and Political Discourse: Realism, Just War, and Feminism in a
Nuclear Age, in: J. B. Elshtain (Ed.), Just War Theory, pp. 260 279 (Oxford: Blackwell).
Elshtain, J. B. (2004) Just War Against Terror: The Burden of American Power in a Violent World (New
York: Basic Books).
116 C. O’Driscoll
Downloaded By: [2007-2008 National Cheng Kung University] At: 15:02 9 April 2008
Erskine, T. (2007) Qualifying Cosmopolitanism? Solidarity, Criticism, and Michael Walzer’s ‘‘View from
the Cave’’, International Politics, 44(1), pp. 125 149.
Erskine, T. (forthcoming) Embedded Cosmopolitanism (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Johnson, J. T. (1981) Just War Tradition and the Restraint of War (Princeton: Princeton University Press).
Johnson, J. T. (2006) The Just War Idea: The State of the Question, Social Philosophy and Policy, 23, pp.
167 195.
Kennedy, D. (2006) Of War and Law (Princeton, NJ, and Oxford: Princeton University Press).
Oakeshott, M. (1975) On Human Conduct (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Rengger, N. J. (2004) Just a War Against Terror? Jean Bethke Elshtain’s Burden and American Power,
International Affairs, 80(1), pp. 107 116.
Schmitt, C. (2003) The Nomos of the Earth (New York: Telos Press).
Temes, P. (2003) The Just War: An American Reflection on the Morality of War in Our Time (Chicago: Ivan
R. Dee).
Walzer, M. (1983) Spheres of Justice: An Exchange, New York Review of Books, 30/12, July 21, 1983, p. 43.
Walzer, M. (1987) Interpretation and Social Criticism (Cambridge, MA, and London: Harvard University
Press).
Walzer, M. (1992) Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations [1977], 2nd edition
(New York: Basic Books).
Walzer, M. (2003) Universalism, Equality, and Immigration, in: H. Pauer-Studer (Ed.), Constructions of
Practical Reason: Interviews on Moral and Political Philosophy, pp. 194 213 (Stanford, California:
Stanford University Press).
Walzer, M. (2004) Arguing About War (New Haven and London: Yale University Press).
White, J. B. (1984) When Words Lose Their Meaning: Constitutions and Reconstitutions of Language,
Character, and Community (Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press).