Roscoe Pound Interpretations of Legal History
Roscoe Pound Interpretations of Legal History
Roscoe Pound Interpretations of Legal History
https://books.google.com
xperienti Ceuorum
Vevo
Scientia que VERO
Felibris
thur van Cross
GAEDA
BEQUEST OF
ARTHUR LYON CROSS
PROFESSOR OF ENGLISH HISTORY
TO THE
UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN
1940
CAMBRIDGE STUDIES IN ENGLISH LEGAL HISTORY
EDITED BY
INTERPRETATIONS
OF LEGAL HISTORY
THE MACMILLAN COMPANY
NEW YORK • BOSTON CHICAGO • DALLAS
.
1
grad
33061300
1-11
kepada
INTERPRETATIONS
OF
LEGAL HISTORY
BY
New York
THE MACMILLAN COMPANY
1923
All rights reserved
PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA
COPYRIGHT , 1923,
BY THE MACMILLAN COMPANY
Press of
J. J. Little & Ives Coinpany
New York , U. S. A.
To
1
THE JURIST'S EXPLANATION OF LEGAL
DEVELOPMENT IN ENGLAND
AND ELSEWHERE
author by telling him so, all the better." These words are as
applicable to a piece of juristic writing as they are to a poem .
Although they are very different from each other in many ways,
both these forms of literature possess at least one marked feature
in common. By virtue of its own particular qualities of style
and matter, every book on jurisprudential thought, no less than
every poem, has the power within itself to give the reader either
pleasure or displeasure; it has the faculty of making the reader
like it or dislike it. In the present volume of the Cambridge
Studies in English Legal History the reader comes across a new
work on jurisprudence, a history and criticism of certain aspects
of juristic thought in England and in other countries; and,
whether the reader be lawyer, historian, or philosopher, he will
find that this book gives him one of his greatest pleasures, that
it calls forth his honest liking, and that, indeed, it is a source of
his enlightenment and intellectual stimulus. In Lowell's apt
phrasing, the reading of Interpretations of Legal History is
“ like finding a new flower.” Such a pleasure comes but rarely
to the one who studies the literature of legal history and juris
prudence ; and " if, at the same time, one can please the author
by telling him so, all the better."
The author of this remarkable book in which, on request, he
has embodied his recent Cambridge lectures on the juristic and
philosophical explanation of the epochs, processes, and ends of
legal development, needs no presentation to the learned reader.
The Dean of the Law Faculty and the Carter Professor of
vii
viii GENERAL PREFACE
AUTHOR'S PREFACE XV
LECTURE
INDEX 167
I
Law must be stable and yet it cannot stand still. Hence all
thinking about law has struggled to reconcile the conflicting
demands of the need of stability and of the need of change.
The social interest in the general security has led men to seek
some fixed basis for an absolute ordering of human action
whereby a firm and stable social order might be assured. But
continual changes in the circumstances of social life demand
continual new adjustments to the pressure of other social
interests as well as to new modes of endangering security. Thus
the legal order must be flexible as well as stable. It must be
overhauled continually and refitted continually to the changes
in the actual life which it is to govern. If we seek principles,
we must seek principles of change no less than principles of
stability. Accordingly the chief problem to which legal thinkers
have addressed themselves has been how to reconcile the idea
of a fixed body of law , affording no scope for individual wilful
ness, with the idea of change and growth and making of new
law ; how to unify the theory of law with the theory of making
law and to unify the system of legal justice with the facts of
administration of justice by magistrates.
For, put more concretely, the problem of compromise be
tween the need of stability and the need of change becomes in
one aspect a problem of adjustment between rule and discretion,
between administering justice according to settled rule, or at
most by rigid deduction from narrowly fixed premises, and
administration of justice according to the more or less trained
intuition of experienced magistrates. In one way or another
almost all of the vexed questions of the science of law prove to
be phases of this same problem. In the last century the great
battles of the analytical and the historical jurists were waged
over the question of the nature of law - whether the traditional
I
2 LAW AND HISTORY
Once more the legal order was the revelation of a god. The new
juristic god was called “ reason,” and was represented as hostile
to authority. But his hostility extended only to the authority
of gods other than himself. Once the legal world had been
made over in his image the lines were to be as rigid and the
legal structures as firmly fixed and the doctrines as unbending
as under the reign of nature gods or religious gods or political
gods. For the philosophical revelation extended only to an ideal
picture of society. The details were filled in by lawyers, chiefly
from the materials of the law which had been taught them , and
once filled in got all the authority of the ideal plan. American
constitutional law is full of examples of common -law dogmas
made over to fit the ideal conception of the “ nature of American
institutions" and thus fixed as items of natural law beyond the
reach of legislative change.
Nevertheless the philosophical reconciliation of stability and
change was a notable advance in that, if it put the plan beyond
the reach of human law - givers, it called for continual scrutiny
of the building in all its details in order to be assured that they
conformed to the plan. Thus it took account of changes in the
positive law as such. Moreover, while the plan when found was
eternal and immutable, it was to be found by reason and it was
always arguable that what had been taken for the one authentic
plan was but an imperfect approximation. While legal systems
were freely absorbing materials from without, as in the develop
ment of equity and the taking over of the law merchant in
English law, the theory of natural law served well . But when the
absorption was complete for the time being and stability re
quired a pause to assimilate fully what had been taken up during
the period of growth and called for internal ordering and har
monizing and systematizing rather than for creation, it ceased
to satisfy. A reconciliation in terms of stability rather than in
terms of change was demanded and this reconciliation was
effected through history.
In law, as in everything else, the nineteenth century is the
century of history. As every eighteenth -century decision and
treatise and statute presupposes philosophy of law and is pro
tanto consciously or unconsciously a bit of philosophical ex
ROMAN LEGAL HISTORY-WRITING 7
3
* Jural Relations, transl. by Rattigan, pp. III-119.
* " On the subject of divorce the Roman law is cited continually. But
Portalis and Maleville begin with a history of Roman divorce which is not
merely false, it is wholly impossible. For example, they both believe that
marriage could not be dissolved by one party but only by mutual consent,
thus making the whole law of the Pandects on this subject and even the
law of Justinian quite devoid of sense, and that divorce by mutual consent
in Roman law is only a consequence of a mistaken doctrine that marriage
rests upon the same basis as other contracts.” Vom Beruf unsrer Zeit für
Gesetzgebung und Rechtswissenschaft, chap. 7, 2nd ed. pp. 63-64.
SAVIGNY 17
( 1864 ) ; Felix , Der Einfluss der Religion auf die Entwickelung des Eigen
thums ( 1889) ; Bryce, Studies in History and Jurisprudence,Essay 13 ( 1901).
* L'Influenza del cristianesimo nella codificazione di Giustiniano ( 1909 ) ;
" Cristianesimo e diritto privato," Revista di diritto civile, 111, 37 ( 1911 );
“ Communio e comproprietà,” in Vinogradoff, Essays in Legal History,
33 ( 1913 ) . See Troplong, De l'influence du christianisme sur le droit civil
des romains ( 1843 ) ; Maas , Der Einfluss der Christenthum auf das Recht
(1886 ) ; Baviera , " Concetto e limiti dell'influenza del cristianesimo sul
diritto privato ," Mélanges Girard, 1, 67 ( 1912 ) ; de Zulueta, " The Girard
Testimonial Essays,” 30 Law Quarterly Review , 214, 216–217 ( 1914) .
* I have considered this at length in The Spirit of the Common Law,
Lecture II, “ Puritanism and the Law," pp. 32–59 ( 1921 ) ; and in "Puri
tanism and the Common Law ,” Proceedings Kansas State Bar Assoc. 1910,
45, reprinted in 45 American Law Review , 811 .
* I gave some examples in “ Consideration in Equity,” Wigmore Celebra
tion Essays, p. 435.
LAW AND MORALS 25
»
never wholly able to efface the stamp of this first impression.” 2
His way of thinking was a reaction from the natural-law iden
tification of the legal with the moral. According to the doctrine
of his school law and morals had a common origin but diverged .
in their development so that his successors were able to throw
over ethics and to hold that morals and what ought to be were
matters with which the jurist had no concern.3 But it was not
easy to shake off the long-established connection which, indeed,
was strengthened by the ambiguity of ius and its equivalents in
the languages of Continental Europe, whereby one never can
be wholly sure whether a writer is speaking of right or of law,
in terms of ethics or in terms of jurisprudence, or of both - nor
is the Continental jurist always careful to distinguish in his
own thought. Thus analyses of law were likely to be also
analyses of the idea of right; and after the period of growth
from the sixteenth to the eighteenth century, with large in
fusions into legal systems from without, as for example in
the case of the law merchant, a chief need was organizing,
systematizing and harmonizing of the internal content of
* Salvioli, Storia del diritto Italiano, 8th ed. $$ 622-624. Compare also
the influence of the church upon Continental criminal law , id. $ 728.
Recht des Besitzes, p. 3 ( 1880 ) .
• “ Investigation of the principles on which the direct improvement of
substantive legal rules should be conducted belongs nevertheless not to the
theorist on jurisprudence but to the theorist on legislation.” Maine, Early
History of Institutions, Lecture XII ( 1874 ). Clark , Roman Private
Law : Jurisprudence, 1, $ 3 ( 1914) .
26 ETHICAL AND RELIGIOUS INTERPRETATIONS
* Often these doctrinal histories had great systematic value and they
played an important role in the systematizing of the different special de
partments of Anglo-American private law which went on so effectively in
American law schools in the last quarter of the nineteenth century. Most
of the " case books" prepared for use in those schools in the last two dec
ades of the century proceed more or less in this way.
3 " Acts of will or voluntary choice are thus regarded only in so far as
they are free, and as to whether the action of one can harmonize with the
freedom of another according to a universal law.
"Right, therefore, comprehends the whole of the conditions under which
the voluntary actions of any one person can be harmonized in reality with
the voluntary actions of every other person, according to a universal law
of freedom.
" Every action is right which in itself, or in the maxim on which it
proceeds, is such that it can co-exist along with the freedom of the will of
each and all in action, according to a universal law.” Kant, Metaphysische
Anfangsgriinde der Rechtslehre, Introduction, $$ A, B ( 1797 ).
Compare : “ Man stands in themidst of the external world, and the most
KANT 29
suited them , and then held in that place by the legal order."
Roman lawyers gave the Greek theory practical effect by pic
turing social institutions which realized the nature of society
i.e. conformed to the ideal thereof - and legal institutions which
realized the nature of law - i.e, conformed to an ideal of main
taining the pictured social order. The Middle Ages took this
over for a society organized on the basis of relations and thought
of the end of law as maintenance of the social status quo by
enforcing reciprocal claims and duties involved in relations
established by tradition and maintained by authority.*
Securing of a maximum of individual self-assertion, the third
ideal of the end of law , begins to affect juristic thought in the
sixteenth century, takes form in the seventeenth century, and
is developed fully in the metaphysical and historical jurispru
dence of the nineteenth century. Its connection with the needs
or desires of an era of discovery and colonization and trade,
and later with the needs of an era of industrial development and
expansion, is obvious. Men were no longer solicitous to maintain
the social institutions by which effect was given to the system of
reciprocal claims and duties of the parties to relations. They
desired to be free of relations and duties that they might take
advantage of the new opportunities afforded to the active and
daring. The need was to satisfy the demands of individuals to
assert themselves freely in the new fields of activity which were
opening on every hand, and a new picture of the social order
and of the end of law was painted in terms of this need. Begin
ning as a political theory of securing men in a natural ( i.e. ideal)
equality, it became a juristic theory of securing them in their
natural rights ( i.e. ideal qualities whereby it was just that they
have certain things or do certain things ), and by a further sim
plification became a theory of securing them in an abstract free
dom of will. The first is aa scholastic version proceeding upon the
* Plato ,Republic , in , 397–398, Lows, VIII, 846d ; Aristotle, Nicomachean
Ethics, Bk v and Bk VII, 7, and 2-4, Politics, Bk 1, 1 , 9 and 13, Bk w,
I and 4-5, Bk iv , 12. Compare St Paul in Ephesians v. 22 ff. and vz 1-5.
· Cicero, De Officiis, 11, 12, De Republica, 1, 32; Institutes of Justinian, I,
1, pr. and § 3 ; Savigny, System des heutigen römischen Rechts, I, 407-410.
• Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae , I, 2, qu. 90-97 ; 11, 2, qu . 57-80,
120 , 122 .
32 ETHICAL AND RELIGIOUS INTERPRETATIONS
idea of the individual as the moral unit and hence as the political
unit, replacing the idea of relation, and of the equal moral
claims and moral responsibilities of these units. The second
is the natural -law version, proceeding on the idea of man as a
rational entity and of the qualities of such an entity whereby
he may co - exist with his fellows in a state of nature - i.e. in a
condition in which those abstract qualities of a reasonable being
are given their full effect. The third is the metaphysical version
of the nineteenth century. It begins with the individual con
sciousness as the ultimate datum and conceives of the problem
of the legal order as one of reconciling conflicting free wills of
conscious individuals independently exerting their wills in the
different activities of life.3 Kant formulated a theory of right
in these terms as a reconciliation through universal rules where
by the will of each actor may co - exist with the wills of all others
in action. As has been said, Savigny turned this into a theory
of law and his successors interpreted jurisprudence and legal
history in the light thereof.
We can make no greater mistake than to suppose that the
speculations of the metaphysical iurists were without practical
* Franciscus de Victoria, Relectiones theologicae, I, 354. 375 ( 1557 ) ; Soto,
De justitia et jure, I, qu. 5, art. 2 ; III, qu. 3, art. 2 ( 1589 ) ; Suarez, De
legibus ac deo legislatore, 1, 8, S8 I, 2 ; 1, 9 , § 2 ; II, 19, § 9 ; ill, 9, § 4 ; III,
11; III, 35, § 8 ( 1619) .
Grotius, De jure belli et pacis, 1, 1, 3-6, 8-11 ; II, I, 1 ; II, I, II ; II, 10, 1;
II, 17, 2, § 1 ( 1625 ) ; Pufendorf, De jure naturae et gentium , i, chap. 7. $$
6-17;; IV, chap. 4 ( 1672 ) ; Rutherforth, Institutes of Natural Low , 1, 2, § 3
( 1754 ) .
* "I must in all cases recognize the free being outside of me as such, that
is, must limit my liberty by the possibility of his liberty. ” Fichte, Grund
lage des Naturrechts, I, 89 ( 1796 ) .
“ We may define right as a principle ... governing the exercise of liberty
in the relations of human life.” Ahrens, Cours du droit naturel ( 8th ed. ) ,
I, 107 ( 1892) .
" The fundamental axiom, which forms the basis of the whole system of
natural justice, I conceive to be that one human being has no right to con
trol forhis own benefit the volition of another . ” Philipps, Jurisprudence,
pp. 80-81 ( 1863 ).
“ Law ...hasits basis in this,that men are beings endowed with a disposi
tion to free exertion of will." Arndts' Juristische Encyklopädie, § 12 ( 1893 ).
“Hence that which we have to express in a precise way is the liberty of
each limited only by the like liberties of all. This we do by saying : Every
man is free to do that which he wills provided he infringes not the equal
liberty of any other man .” Spencer, Justice, § 27 ( 1891 ).
METAPHYSICAL JURISPRUDENCE 33
472 ( 1871 ) .
• System des heutigen römischen Rechts, in , $ 124.
THE ROMANTIC TENDENCY 43
1
III
problems and of no value for its ends, is the most significant fea
ture of recent juristic thought. The narrowly limited legal sci
ence, indifferent to and even intolerant of light from without,
characteristic of the nineteenth century, reached its high-water
mark in the English and American analytical jurisprudence of
the immediate followers of Austin. The political interpretation
was the first of a succession of reactions therefrom which have
given jurisprudence a new aspect in the twentieth century.
Philosophically the ethical interpretation represents the in
fluence of Kant upon historical jurisprudence, resulting in an
interpretation of legal history and hence of law in terms of
Kant's theory of right. The political interpretation represents
the influence of Hegel. It is an interpretation in terms of
Hegel's proposition that right is " freedom as an idea .” The
word which we translate sometimes as " law " and sometimes as
" right,” which I have translated as " right " in the foregoing
formula, does not mean either exactly nor may we understand
it by combining the two. Hegel was formulating a conception
of what I have been calling the end of law. He means that
which the legal order is conceived as existing to bring about;
what we mean by “ justice ” when we say that the law exists
as a means to justice. Thus, he holds, law realizes the idea of
freedom, the idea that “ existence generalized is existence of the
free will.” 1 In the hands of jurists this interpretation regards
the idea in its political aspect or, we may say, takes a political
idea to be the idea which is realizing in legal history and is un
folding in legal rules and doctrines and institutions. Looked
at legally and politically the idea is freedom or liberty. Ideal
perfection in human relations is liberty. Jurisprudence and
politics have to do with different but closely allied phases of
liberty as realized in civil relations.2
3 “ This is right: that existence generalized is existence of the free will.
Accordingly generalized it is freedom as an idea." Hegel, Grundlinien der
Philosophie des Rechts, 61 ( 1820) .
? " The proximate object of jurisprudence, the object which it seeks as
a separate science, is liberty. But liberty being the perfect relation between
human beings, becomes a means towards the realization of their perfection
as human beings. Hence jurisprudence, in realizing its special or proximate
object, becomes a means towards the realization of the ultimate object
which it has in common with ethics. ” Lorimer, Institutes of Law , 2nd ed.
LAW AND REASON 47
1
1
INSTITUTIONAL HISTORY 53
Roman law were laid jurists believed that they could do no more
than interpret and apply the authoritative Roman texts. Hence
the analogies used were Roman analogies drawn from the
Corpus Juris. Accordingly while common-law ways of thinking
were determined by the analogies of the medieval, feudal,
relationally organized society in which they arose, the ways of
thinking in the modern Roman law were determined by the
analogies of the city -state political society of heads of house
holds in the stage of the strict law. These ways of thinking were
liberalized and idealized in the classical period of Roman law ,
from the first to the third century — and again during the reign
of the law -of -nature school in the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries. But the claims and duties of free men, Roman
citizens and heads of households, owning adjoining homesteads,
encountering each other in the streets and entering into under
takings toward each other in the various activities of life, shaped
Roman juristic thought and led Roman jurists and hence the
Romanists of today to think and speak of letting and sale and
mandate and contract of partnership as naturally as the recipro
cal rights and duties of men in relations, claiming this or that
against each other as an incident of the relation, shaped English
legal thought and led the common -law jurist to think and speak
of landlord and tenant, vendor and purchaser, principal and
agent and the partnership relation . It is noteworthy that in
our law of sales of chattels, shaped by the law merchant and
along the lines of the Continental Romanized commercial law
through the influence of nineteenth -century text-writers,' we
speak of the contract of sale and of what it implies. In the law
of sales of land, governed by the common law and developed
by equity on common-law lines, we think and speak of the
relation of vendor and purchaser. The will theory of legal
transaction as an idea of contract, upon which the political
interpretation builds, is not a universal idea of all law. It is
relative to Roman law. It is a generalization from doctrines
expressing the problem which chiefly concerned Roman lawyers
* The text -book of widest influence was Benjamin on Sales. Benjamin
was by original training a civilian and spent the formative portion of his
legal life inthe practice of law in Louisiana at a time when the law of that
state was essentially French .
60 THE POLITICAL INTERPRETATION
but such is not the case withsuch laws as we are now considering." State
v. Goodwill, 33 West Virginia Reports, 179 ( 1889).
· Soe State v. Loomis, 115 Missouri Reports, 307 ( 1890 ) .
• The court made this statement in State v . Haun, 61 Kansas Reports,
146, 161 ( 1900 ).
DEFECTS OF THE INTERPRETATION 65
ideal by which all things legal were to be judged. Accordingly
the courts saw rightly enough that if the doctrine was to be
a guide, they must carry it out to its conclusion. By doing so
rigorously they disproved the political interpretation as an
interpretation of Anglo -American legal history.
Looking back at the reign of the political interpretation, we
may perceive two respects in which it failed to satisfy at the
end of the last and at the beginning of the present century,
after general acceptance for a generation. In the first place it
was a negative juristic theory, carrying to the limit the idea of
the historical school that nothing was to be created — that
legislation was futile. In the hands of common-law lawyers
this became a conviction that an idealized form of the common
law was the legal order of nature and led to an excessive develop
ment of the doctrine of strictly construing statutes in derogation
of the common law and to strained interpretations in the direc
tion of holding new legislation to be merely declaratory of
traditional rules. Thus American state courts laid down dog
matically that general principles of constitutional law forbade
legislative adoption of the theory of the forum laesae civitatis
as the basis of jurisdiction over crimes. They kept back the
full legal emancipation of married women for fifty years by
holding the statutes rigidly to the precisely detailed changes
which they made in express terms rigidly construed .? They
kept American legal procedure in a backward state for half a
century by reading into codes of procedure an idealized system
of actions on a historico -analytical basis. They even began to
undo the work of the uniform commercial laws by treating them
in each state as declaratory of the local course of judicial de
cision prior to the statutes and so as perpetuating the condition
which they were meant to relieve . Secondly, it rejected all
* State v. Carter, 41 New Jersey Law Reports, 499, 501-503 ( 1859 ).
* I have discussed this phenomenon in "Common Law and Legislation ,”.
21 Harvard Law Rev. 383. Sec Carter, Law: Its Origin, Growth and
Function , 308–309.
A leading case was Supervisors v. Decker, 30 Wisconsin Reports, 624,
626-627, 629-639 ( 1872) , now happily overruled by Bruheim v. Stratton ,
145 Wisconsin Reports, 271 ( 1911 ).
' For recent examples, see Chafee, “Progress of the Law : Bills and
Notes," 33 Harvard Law Rev. 225, passim ( 1919) .
66 THE POLITICAL INTERPRETATION
effort and urged the decisive role of the psychic factors of civili
zation." Thus a wide breach was made in the juristic dogma of
the historical school. In the meantime a revival of philosophy
of law began, resulting in the social-philosophical jurisprudence
of today. With the beginning of the present century came uni
fication of
3
the methods of sociology,” unification of the social
sciences, the functional attitude - consideration of the work
ings of law more than of its abstract content - the attitude of
looking on law as a social institution which may be improved by
intelligent human effort, and belief that it is the duty of jurists
to discover the most effective means of directing and furthering
such effort. These things have come to be the accepted creed of
sociological jurists and in increasing measure are becoming the
creed of all jurists. What we shall be looking at is a stage in
this development. Experiments in psychological forms of
ethnological interpretation are a link betweenthe nineteenth
century search for a single all -explaining formula of legal de
velopment and the recognition of a plurality of factors which
marks the juristic thought of today.
It is convenient to distinguish two main types of these
transitional interpretations — the ethnological and the biological.
The former interprets law and legal history in terms of race
spirit or race psychology or race institutions, which in the
systems of positivists are regarded usually as resulting from
physical environment. The latter interprets them in terms of
the Darwinian natural selection—in terms of struggle for
existence and survival of the fittest. The ethnological type
came first and served as a connecting link between Hegel and
the positivists, between the nineteenth -century philosophical or
metaphysical jurists and sociological jurisprudence. Accordingly
it takes three forms. In the first form it is idealistic. A race
idea is unfolding in the development of the legal institutions
of this or that people or, more generally, the idea is looked at
* Dynamic Sociology, 1, 468-472 ( 1883) ; The Psychic Factors of Civiliza
tion , 120 ( 1901 ); Applied Sociology, 13 (1906 ).
*Ward, Contemporary Sociology, reprint of papers in 7 American Jour
nal of Sociology, 475, 629, 749 ; Ward, Pure Sociology, 14. ( 1903),
* Ward, Pure Sociology, 12–14 ( 1903) ; Small, General Sociology, 91
( 1905 ) ; Small, The Meaning of Social Science, 87 ( 1910) .
BIOLOGICAL INTERPRETATIONS 75
1 Scherz und Ernst in der Jurisprudenz, pt. 3 ( 1884), roth ed ., 245 ff.
»
9
one left its mark on the public law of the modern world while
the other proved transient. The Middle Ages thought of
justice and right in fixed theological terms and conceived them
as above and beyond all action of sovereigns. Such ideas
coloured and gave direction to special movements that may have
had economic origins. The ethical interpretation sees only the
former ; the economic interpretation sees only the latter. If we
must choose, the ethical interpretation often has more for us.
But the argument breaks down in any event in its version of
the Statute of Westminster II.1 The legal order was entering
on a stage of strict law . Men were fearful of latitude in pro
cedure . If English law was to be systematized and developed
logically, as men saw had happened with the Roman law , the
issuance of writs must be reduced to a system . Accordingly
lawyers sought to cut down the wide discretion of chancery in
this respect and the judges were carrying out the spirit of the
statute when they understood it as they did. Blackstone looked
back at it through eighteenth - century spectacles and saw a
modern problem of unshackling procedure where the problem
of the thirteenth century was to tie it down.
Again, take the argument from the rise of the Court of
Chancery. We are told that in the class contest, which took the
outward form of a contest between the king and the barons,
when it had proved impossible to liberalize the law through the
common-law courts, the king turned to his council and began
to deal with causes directly through the council or committees
thereof, thus giving rise to a new type of courts. The most
effective weapon developed by this type of tribunal was the
writ of subpoena. So " whenever the gentry could control the
House of Commons they petitioned against the prerogative
courts and clamoured for aa return to the common law .” But the
process went on. “ Thus," we are told, " the Chancellor . .
" if justice could be sold to the highest bidder, their days were
numbered.” Hence they exacted a promise from John that he
would not sell justice and later insisted that the chancellor
should sell no new writs but should adhere to ancient usage.
But the volume of business in the king's courts became such
that the king's business could not be done with the existing
writs and parliament undertook to provide a remedy through
the Statute of Westminster II. The landed gentry were too
strong for the king. The judges fell " under the influence of
the great magnates of the time, as judges will, ” and the statute
achieved little.1
You will have perceived that the argument is based on Coke's
and Blackstone's version of the Statute of Westminster II and
the judicial interpretation thereof. Much of it must fall if that
version fails. Nor does it take account of related phenomena
which must be reckoned with in any interpretation. Down to
the thirteenth century we are at most in a stage of transition to
the strict law. Hence law is fluid and at times much depends
upon the wilful personality of the king. But Henry II was by
instinct a lawyer and Glanvill's book, based on writs, shows
that in the twelfth century the lawyer was at work upon them,
seeking to put system into them and to make a strict law out
of a mass of legal materials that had developed more or less
haphazard. In other words, a conscious endeavour for some
thing not dependent on will and resistant to class interest and
class influence must be recognized. Also we must remember
the medieval conception of law as an immemorial custom and
that the king was bound by the law. Nor may we forget that
aristocracies have always stood firmest for individual liberty
because, it may be, the aristocrat, in the heyday of an aristoc
racy, is apt to have a vigorous personality and to think in terms
of individual self -assertion. Accordingly if we compare the
provisions of Magna Carta with the statutory special privileges
of soldiers under the Roman empire, we shall see a significant
difference. In the former concrete propositions are put as
universal rules of general application. In the latter there are
no more than arbitrary special rules. It is no wonder that the
* Centralization and the Law , 31-35.
100 THE ECONOMIC INTERPRETATION
further than Markby along the same path and in his casting
out the science of legislation he but goes to the end of the path
laid down in Maine's Early History of Institutions."
When we turn to the proofs adduced in support of the
economic interpretation, we shall find that usually the chief
reliance is upon penal legislation of little permanence and
relatively little effectiveness in the actual ordering of society or
the every -day administration of justice. It is an interpretation
of the least enduring and least effective materials of the legal
order. But some American adherents of the doctrine have
sought to establish it by examination of the doctrinal and
institutional history of the common law and their arguments
must be looked into more in detail. Brooks Adams vouches the
history of the common -law writs from the Norman kings to the
Statute of Westminster II and judicial interpretation thereof,?
the history of the rise of the Court of Chancery 3 and the rise
of the nineteenth -century doctrine of liability as the corollary
of culpability.* Professor Bohlen has interpreted the doctrine
of Rylands v. Fletcher and its history in America with much
ability and ingenuity in terms of economics." Professor Wyman
has suggested a like interpretation of the development of a
law of public utilities . President Wilson interpreted the
common law as to injuries by the fault of a fellow servant and
assumption of risk along the same lines.? Let us consider some
of these and ask ourselves how far the case has been made.
As Brooks Adams sees the history of the common -law writs,
the king at first, when he wanted aa writ for any special purpose,
" ordered one to his liking ... and a clerk in chancery wrote
it. ” Presently this making of writs to order, as it were, became
9
In its last phase the search for a single supreme cause of all
legal phenomena turned from ethnology and biology to eco
nomics, a direction in which several philosophical paths at
length converged. One of these paths was idealism, leading to
what has been called historical materialism. Another was posi
tivism, through endeavour to discover economic laws by ob
servation of social and legal phenomena. Still another was
realism , through the so -called economic realism . The hegemony
of the natural sciences in the nineteenth century and consequent
naturalistic conception of the world led to increased attention
to men's physical surroundings, material wants and physical
activities to satisfy those wants. Likewise the problem of the
time has ceased to be political in form , as in the fore part of the
nineteenth century, and had taken on an economic form. The
question of reconciling political freedom with authority, which
had been agitated for a century, was superseded by the so
called social question, consequent upon change from an agri
cultural-commercial to an industrial economy and the rise of
the industrial labourers as a class-conscious group of political
importance urging demands under conditions for which the
traditional legal order made scant provision. Thus a shifting
from the political standpoint to the economic standpoint grew
out of new conditions with which the social sciences had to
deal and of new phenomena which they were required to
explain.
As is well known , economic interpretation 1 began in the fifth
decade of the nineteenth century when Marx applied the
Hegelian dialectic to English political economy, to the theories
* On the economic interpretation generally, see Seligman, The Economic
Interpretation of History, 2nd ed. ; Croce, Materialismo storico ed economia
mar.rista, 4th ed ., translated as Historical Materialism and the Economics
of Karl Marx. For the economic interpretation in jurisprudence, see Leist,
Privatrecht und Kapitalismus im neunzehnten Jahrhundert ( 1911 ) .
92
BIOLOGICAL INTERPRETATIONS 91
not some other and vital " facts " of social existence involved
in a statute imposing penalties upon certain publications, to be
judged with reference to constitutional guarantees of free
speech , over and above the interdependence through division of
labour that is so conspicuous in a modern industrial society ?
And if these are referred to " interdependence through similarity
of interest,” in that we are all human beings, which is to give
way or how are they to be reconciled or compromised ? In truth,
as Croce has observed , these positivist interpretations are apt at
bottom to be Hegelian. The idea of freedom is replaced by an
idea of "the social.” The inexorable law is not progressive
unfolding of freedom as an idea ; it is progressive unfolding of
“ the social” by organization of the social reaction against the
anti-social.
Ethnological forms of the biological interpretation picture a
conflict of race institutions with survival of the fittest. Enough
has been said of such theories in connection with the ethno
logical interpretation as such.
An economic form was urged by Vaccaro , who took legal
institutions and rules and doctrines to be the results of a class
conflict, or series of class conflicts, determined by survival of
the socially fittest. Expressing the needs or desires of the class
which was dominant socially or politically for the time being,
they came into conflict with rival institutions or rules or doc
trines expressing the needs or desires of other classes. Thus
what in political and economic history is class conflict, in legal
history is a conflict of institutions and ideas. As it is easy to
see that Gumplowicz's interpretation in terms of race conflict ?2
is a rationalization of the existing situation in late nineteenth
century Austria, put universally, so it is not hard to see that
Vaccaro's class conflict is aa rationalization of the industrial and
agrarian agitation in Italy, put universally. As we shall see
when we come to the economic interpretation, there is a kernel
of truth in Vaccaro's theory that gives it a certain plausibility.
But when we try it upon the difficult problems of legal science
* Vaccaro, Les bases sociologiques de droit et de l'état ( 1898 ), transl. of
Le basi del diritto e dello stato ( 1893 ). See also Bentley, The Process of
Government, 287 ( 1908 ) .
* Der Rassenkampf ( 1883).
BIOLOGICAL INTERPRETATIONS 87
* The term " bonitary ownership " appears first in the sixth century.
Theophilus on Inst., 1 , 5, 3.
* Jurisprudence, 3rd ed ., 1023-1036. See Pound, " Spurious Interpretation, "
7 Columbia Law Rev. 379 ( 1907 ). Compare: “The power of interpretatio
and formulation placed inthe hands of the Pontiffs was in effect a power
to alter the law by ingenious interpretations. ... There is not much to be
said for the logic of these interpretations, but there can be no doubt of
their utility . ” Buckland, Roman Law , 2.
.Gray, Nature and Sources of the Law , $$ 370–399 ( 1909 ).
132 THE GREAT -LAWYER INTERPRETATION
our own law, it has proved equal to the most refractory materials
of the legal system, and in other bodies of law the most rigid
codes and the most stringent provisions against judicial glossing
or developing of their texts have yielded to it. One need only
refer to such things as the interpretation of the Lex Aquilia,
which in the end made over the whole theory of delictual
liability, or Coke's juristic law -making by interpretation of
Magna Carta and of the statutes of Edward I , in proof of its
creative possibilities. But here again the process is not one that
goes on automatically. It is not a logical unfolding of what is
implicit in the text. In the case of Coke's Second Institute and
the interpretation of English legislation of the thirteenth cen
tury, we know who it was that made a body of law for modern
England and for America on the basis of these crude and some
times oracular texts and why he did so. Coke's purpose was to
prove his case in the contests between courts and crown in which
he was a chief actor. Recent historians who have re-examined
the material in writing histories of the King's Council, the Star
Chamber and the High Commission, assert that he grossly
perverted the texts. Very likely he did for he was a partisan
and an advocate. Undoubtedly he did from their standpoint
because they are asking what the provisions meant to those who
drew them in the thirteenth century for thirteenth -century
England. Coke's problem was what they must be made to
mean if justice was to be done in accordance with them and by
means of them in seventeenth-century England. The fiction of
interpretation enabled him and his contemporaries to believe
that the two things were the same.
Equity and natural law are yet bolder fictions allowing a more
sweeping creative activity. Maine showed this for equity
generally and Langdell and Maitland showed it for English
equity.” The chancellor did not purport to alter the law.
According to the law the penalty of aa bond was enforceable, the
estate of the mortgagee after condition unfulfilled was absolute,
* Usher, The Rise and Fall of the High Commission, 186–187, 191–192,
199–201, 222-235 ( 1913 ) .
Maine, Ancient Law, chap. 3 ( 1861) ; Langdell, Brief Survey of Equity
Jurisdiction, 13 ff. (written 1887) ; Maitland, Equity and the forms of
Action at Common Law , 19 ff. ( 1909 ).
EQUITY AND NATURAL LAW 133
socially, minded judges, who had the large vision to see what was
required and the good sense not to be hindered in doing it be
cause there had never been such things before. Today we find a
legal basis for it in the jurisdiction of chancery over infants.
We reconcile it with legal-historical dogmas on this basis. But
the jurisdiction of equity over infants was not a factor in cre
ating it. It arose on the criminal side of the courts because of
the revolt of those judges' consciences from legal rules that re
quired trial of children over seven as criminals and sentence of
children over fourteen to penalties provided for adult offenders.?
One should compare with these the creative judicial empiri
cism of the praetor's edict. Some lawyer, urged by the claims
of some particular client, conceives what will meet the needs of
his client, argues for it and persuades a praetor. A new idea
comes into the law with the remedy applied to that case . Some
times we know who invented what became the basis of a long
juristic development and wrote a chapter in the law. Thus in
the actio Serviana a concrete remedy was invented for a case
that called for more effective legal relief. It was carried for
ward in the actio quasi Serviana by an analogy bordering on
fiction. Then jurists, with the picture of natural law before
them , put a generalization behind it and aa whole theory of pledge
resulted . Today the Romanist puts tacit hypothecation to as
many uses as we do constructive trust. But the idea did not
create the actio Serviana. That resulted from a reaching out for
a concrete remedy to satisfy a special demand. This is brought
out in another way if we compare tacit hypothecation with con
structive trust. Each achieves much the same results ; each is
used remedially to prevent unjust enrichment of one person at
the expense of another. Yet note how different the two are in
legal idea. According to the one way of proceeding it is con
ceived that A's property is subject to aa real duty - a duty resting
on the res as against the whole world — to answer for a duty
1
* Mack , “ TheJuvenile Court," 23 Harvard Law Rev. 104 ( 1909 ) ; Flex
ner and Baldwin, Juvenile Courts and Probation , 1-7 ( 1915) ; Eliot, The
Juvenile Court , 1-2 ( 1914) .
* Inst.4 , 6 , § 7. Note also the interdictum Salvianum , Inst. 4 , 15, $ 3, the
name of which tells a like story.
• Windscheid, Pandekten , 1 , $$ 225-229.
136 THE GREAT-LAWYER INTERPRETATION
which in justice and equity is due from A to B. According to
the other it is conceived that A has something which he is
personally obligated to hold not for his own benefit but for the
benefit of B. There is a fiction in each case — a fiction that
something has been pledged which has not been pledged or a
fiction that something is held in trust where there is no trust.
Yet historical jurists saw an idea in each case which fixed the
lines of legal development.
Jhering called creative juristic science by the suggestive name
of juristic chemistry. That is, it is a combining of chosen
elements of the law, as it were, to make new compounds. But
it often goes further and brings in elements from without and
develops them by analogy or combines them with elements at
hand in the law to make even more novel compounds. Instead
of these compounds resulting from the unfolding of an idea,
they are oftenest the result of endeavour to provide for a con
crete case, leading to the application of a concrete solution,
behind which others proceed to put tentative generalizations
until finally the more inclusive order is worked out. Thus when
we look back at it we say that an idea was realizing. But the
idea served after the event to order and arrange and make
intelligible. It had no part in the creation which was the act of a
man seeking to satisfy a demand.
American law has notable examples of the creative possibili
ties of two other forms of juristic activity. At a time when it
was a serious question whether American states would receive
the common law of England in view of political bitternesses,
hostility to things English after the Revolution, and the aversion
to technical learning and special professional competence that
was so marked in the Jefferson Brick era of American politics,
Joseph Story, by a creative use of comparative law, was able so
to expound English commercial law and English equity as to
make them appear a body of universal principles, sanctioned by
experience and received by the reason of mankind, and to make
straight the way for their reception.” Here also it might be
a Geist des römischen Rechts, ii, 2nd ed. 11 ( 1871 ) .
2
* See Pound, " The Place of Judge Story in the Making of American
Law,” 48 American Law Rev. 646 ( 1914) .
CREATIVE LEGISLATION 137
AN ENGINEERING INTERPRETATION
seeds of the new are already at hand in what exists and as one
grows and the other decays new values are continually made
out of the old .” 1 It is not that we may have once for all an ideal
society with every one in his place and the law to keep him there.
Yet we cannot develop the utmost that is in human powers in
a mad scramble in which values are lost by friction and waste.
We must have a certain ordering of human activities that puts
limits to human action, that assigns each to do things in order
to protect existing values and to further the creation of new
ones. How far this ordering shall go must depend on the civili
zation of the time and place, on the values to be conserved and
the means at hand to create new ones. In rural, pioneer, agri
cultural America of the fore part of the last century, there was
no occasion to limit the contracts a labourer could make as to
taking his pay in goods. To have done so would have been
arbitrary. In urban, industrial America of the twentieth cen
tury, on the other hand, a régime of abstract freedom of con
tract between employer and employee often led to a destruction
of values. It led to sacrifice of the social interest in the human
life of the individual worker. Hence it was not unreasonable to
put limits upon what employer and employee might contract.
Moreover, Kohler does not say that the law is to assign each
man his post and set him his task. But there must be some
system that does this. It may be done by political or politico
military machinery, as in the extreme case of Sparta ; by tradi
tion and stratified society resting on authority, as in the Middle
Ages ; by free competition, as we sought to do in the nineteenth
century, or by an economic régime, as today. In any event
it is the place of the law to uphold that system so that civiliza
tion may be maintained and furthered. This does not exclude
individual initiative to find one's place or make one's place
nor does it require aa social ordering through the law that puts
men in predetermined places and keeps them there. We are
not required to make a final and absolute election between two
strictly defined alternatives. Each may be destructive of values.
If the latter may cut off a mainspring of social progress and
repress individual self-assertion to the point of stunting the
* Lehrbuch der Rechtsphilosophie, 1 , para. 5.
KOHLER 147
them and will them — and are largely what the latter believe
them and will them to be. Yet it must give us an interpretation
in terms of conditioned activity, conditioned by the capacities,
the characters and the prejudices of those who plan and make,
by the materials with which they must work, by the circum
stances in which they must work, and by the special purposes
for which they work. Such an analogy seems to me to be af
forded by engineering. Let us think of jurisprudence for a
moment as a science of social engineering, having to do with
that part of the whole field which may be achieved by the order
ing of human relations through the action of politically organ
ized society.
Engineering is thought of as a process, as an activity, not
merely as a body of knowledge or as a fixed order of construc
tion. It is a doing of things , not a serving as passive instruments
through which mathematical formulas and mechanical laws
realize themselves in the eternally appointed way. The engineer
is judged by what he does. His work is judged by its adequacy
to the purposes for which it is done, not by its conformity to
some ideal form of a traditional plan . We are beginning, in con
trast with the last century, to think of jurist and judge and law
maker in the same way. We are coming to study the legal order
instead of debating as to the nature of law. ! We are thinking of
interests, claims, demands, not of rights ; of what we have to
secure or satisfy, not exclusively of the institutions by which we
have sought to secure or to satisfy them , as if those institutions
were ultimate things existing for themselves. We are thinking of
how far we do what is before us to be done, not merely of how
we do it ; of how the system works, not merely of its systematic
perfection. Thus more and more we have been coming to think
in terms of the legal order - of the process—not in terms of the
law - the body of formulated experience or system of ordering
-to think of the activity of adjusting relations or harmonizing
and reconciling claims and demands, not of the adjustment itself
and of the harmonizing or reconciling itself as a system in which
Kohler, Einführung in die Rechtswissenschaft, § 1, 1902 ; Levi, La
société et l'ordre juridique, 1911 ; Levi, Contributi ad una teoria filosofica
dell' ordine giuridico, 1914.
THE ADMINISTRATION OF JUSTICE 153
1
INDEX
Actio Publiciana, 130 , 131 Bohlen, Francis H., 100, 105-109
quasi-Serviana, 135 Boistel, 22, 69
Serviana, 135 Brandeis, Mr Justice, 137
Activist idealism, II Brazilian civil code, 26 , 80
Adams, Brooks, 96-100 Brown, W. Jethro , 67
Administration, 81-82 Bryce, Viscount, 22, 33
of justice, 153-155 Buckland, W. W., 26, 131
Agency, 110 Building,analogy of, 21 , 40
Ahrens , 22 , 32, 33, 144 Burdick , F. M., 110
Ames, James Barr, 17, 42, 120 Burke, Edmund, 13-14
Analogies, 151-152 Burlamaqui, 17
Analytical jurisprudence, 46, 128 Business, American law and, III
130, 155 II2
school, 18, 33, 84, 96
Anglo - American public law, ro- Campbell, Lord , 124-125
mance of , 43 Capitis deminutio, 16
Anglo-Indian codes, 68 , 81 Carle , 78
Anglo -Saxon law , 76 Carter, James C., 34–35, 47
Animals, liability for, 36
Application of law , individualized,
Chancery, court of, 100, 102–104
Change in law, 1, 2, 4
2-104
153-155 Charmont, 72, 150
Aristotle, 30, 31 , 89 Cicero, 31
Assumption of risk, 109 -III Civil death , 16
Austin, John, 26 , 46 , 98, 99 , 130, 155 Civilization interpretation, 143-150
Austrian code, 14, 80 critique of, 150–151
Authority, 3 Civilization , jural postulates of, 148
150
Bacon, 128 Clark, E. C., 18 , 25
Baden, code of, 80 Class conflict, 88-90, 95-105, 109
Baldwin , Simeon E., 37 Codification , 80-81
Bartolus, 52 Coke, 3, 8 , 9, 41 , 52 , 82, 99, 101 ,
Baty, Thomas, 138 128, 132, 139–140, 161
Bekker, Ernst Immanuel, 25 Collectivism , 109
Bentham , 98, 99, 112 Command- theory of law, 3.
Bergson , il , 154, 155 Common law, continuity of, 39
Berolzheimer , Fritz , 72, 73 fundamental idea in, 57-63
Bethell , Sir Richard , 129 Comparative law , 49
Beudant, 48 Conceptions, jurisprudence of, 119
Bigelow , Melville M., 17 124
Bills of rights, 51 Conring, Hermann, 8
Biological interpretations, 74–75, Consideration, 66
85-90 , 117 Conquered peoples, epos of the, 79
achievements of, 91 Constitutional law ( American), 16,
defects of , 90-91 123
economic, 88-90 Constructivé trust, 135-136
ethnological, 88 Continuity of content, fallacy of, 37,
idealistic, 85-86 39-41
Blackstone, 17, 41 , 98 , 101 , 102 Convenience, Coke on, 161
Blasting, injuries by, 122 Corporations, 37–38, ili
167
168 INDEX
2000
1
UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN