Crimp Douglas 1980 On The Museums Ruins
Crimp Douglas 1980 On The Museums Ruins
Crimp Douglas 1980 On The Museums Ruins
DOUGLAS CRIMP
1. Hilton Kramer, "Does Ger6me Belong with Goya and Monet?" New York Times, April 13,
1980, section 2, p. 35.
2. Theodor W. Adorno, "Valery Proust Museum," Prisms, trans. Samuel and Shierry Weber,
London, Neville Spearman, 1967, pp. 173-186.
3. Kramer, p. 35.
On the Museum's Ruins 43
puzzle, whose pieces are not, in my estimation, fitted together right, perhaps
because a crucial one is missing. The pieces Kramer has assembled are the
museum, art history, modernism, and postmodernism. To which I would add
photography, and complete the puzzle to look, I would say, something like this:
For I want to claim that Rauschenberg's art, using the medium of photography
and at the threshold of postmodernism, enacts a deconstruction of the discourse of
the museum, of its pretensions to anything we could possibly call knowledge.
One of the early instances of the term postmodernism as applied to the visual
arts occurs in Leo Steinberg's "Other Criteria," in the course of a discussion of
Rauschenberg's work and its transmutation of the picture surface into what
Steinberg calls a flatbed, referring, significantly, to a printing press.4 This flatbed
picture plane is an altogether new kind of picture surface, one that effects,
according to Steinberg, a radical shift from nature to culture. That is, it is a surface
which can receive a vast and heterogeneous array of cultural images and artifacts
that had not been compatible with the pictorial field of either premodernist or
modernist painting. (A modernist painting retains a "natural" orientation to the
spectator's vision, which the postmodernist picture abandons.) Although it is
doubtful that Steinberg had a very precise notion of the far-reaching implica-
tions of his term postmodernism, a term now used extremely promiscuously, his
reading of the revolution implicit in Rauschenberg's art can be both focused and
extended by taking this designation seriously.
Presumably unconsciously, Steinberg's essay suggests important parallels
with the "archeological" enterprise of Michel Foucault. Not only does the very
term postmodernism imply the foreclosure of what Foucault would call the
episteme, or archive, of modernism, but even more specifically, by insisting upon
the radically different kinds of picture surfaces upon which different kinds of data
can be accumulated and organized, Steinberg selects the very figure that Foucault
uses to represent the incompatibility of historical periods: the tables upon which
their knowledge is tabulated.
Foucault's project involves the replacement of those unities of humanist
historical discourse such as tradition, influence, development, evolution, source,
and origin with concepts like discontinuity, rupture, threshold, limit, series, and
transformation. Thus, in Foucault's terms, if the surface of a Rauschenberg
painting truly involves the kind of transformation that Steinberg claims it does,
then it cannot be said to evolve from, or in any way be continuous with a
modernist picture surface.5 And if Rauschenberg's flatbed pictures are experienced
as effecting such a rupture or discontinuity with the modernist past, as I believe
they do, and as I think do the works of many other artists of the present, then
perhaps we are indeed experiencing one of those cataclysmic ruptures in the
epistemological field that Foucault describes, a rupture as thorough as that which
separates the age of classicism (the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries) from the
age of modernism, the analysis of wealth from economics, natural history from
biology, general grammar from philology.6 But it is not, of course, only the
4. Leo Steinberg, "Other Criteria," Other Criteria, New York, Oxford University Press, 1972, pp.
55-91. This essay is based on a lecture presented at the Museum of Modern Art, New York, in March
1968.
5. See Rosalind Krauss's discussion of the radical difference between cubist collage and
Rauschenberg's "reinvented" collage in "Rauschenberg and the Materialized Image," Artforum,
XIII, 4 (December 1974), 36-43.
6. These are the subjects analyzed by Foucault in The Order of Things, New York, Pantheon,
1970.
On the Museum's Ruins 45
7. Of course, not all art historians would agree that Manet problematized the relationship of
painting to its sources. This is, however, the initial assumption of Michael Fried's "Manet's Sources:
Aspects of his Art, 1859-1865" (Artforum, VII, 7 [March 1969], 28-82), whose first sentence reads: "If a
single question is guiding for our understanding of Manet's art during the first half of the 1860s, it is
this: What are we to make of the numerous references in his paintings of those years to the work of the
great painters of the past?" (p. 28). In part, Fried's presupposition that Manet's references to earlier art
were different, in their "literalness and obviousness," from the ways in which Western painting had
previously used sources led Theodore Reff to attack Fried's essay, saying, for example, "When
Reynolds portrays his sitters in attitudes borrowed from famous pictures by Holbein, Michelangelo,
and Annibale Carracci, wittily playing on their relevance to his own subjects; when Ingres deliberately
refers in his religious compositions to those of Raphael, and in his portraits to familiar examples of
Greek sculpture or Roman painting, do they not reveal the same historical consciousness that informs
Manet's early work?" (Theodore Reff, "'Manet's Sources': A Critical Evaluation," Artforum, VIII, 1
[September 1969], 40). As a result of this denial of difference, Reff is able to continue applying to
modernism art-historical methodologies devised to explain past art, for example that which explains
the very particular relationship of Italian Renaissance art to the art of classical antiquity.
46 OCTOBER
opposed to the radically different pictorial logic that obtains at the beginning of
postmodernism. Just what it is that constitutes the particular logic of a Manet
painting is discussed in an essay by Foucault about Flaubert's Temptation of St.
Anthony:
Dejeuner sur l'Herbe and Olympia were perhaps the first "museum"
paintings, the first paintings in European art that were less a response
to the achievement of Giorgione, Raphael, and Velazquez than an
acknowledgement (supported by this singular and obvious connection,
using this legible reference to cloak its operation) of the new and
substantial relationship of painting to itself, as a manifestation of the
existence of museums and the particular reality and interdependence
that paintings acquire in museums. In the same period, The Tempta-
tion was the first literary work to comprehend the greenish institutions
where books are accumulated and where the slow and incontrovert-
ible vegetation of learning quietly proliferates. Flaubert is to the library
what Manet is to the museum. They both produced works in a self-
conscious relationship to earlier paintings or texts-or rather to the
aspect in painting or writing that remains indefinitely open. They erect
their art within the archive. They were not meant to foster the
lamentations-the lost youth, the absence of vigor, and the decline of
inventiveness-through which we reproach our Alexandrian age, but
to unearth an essential aspect of our culture: every painting now
belongs within the squared and massive surface of painting and all
literary works are confined to the indefinite murmur of writing.8
At a later point in this essay, Foucault says that "Saint Anthony seems to
summon Bouvard and Pecuchet, at least to the extent that the latter stands as its
grotesque shadow." If The Temptation points to the library as the generator of
modern literature, then Bouvard and Pecuchet fingers it as the dumping grounds
of an irredeemable classical culture. Bouvard and Pecuchet is a novel that
systematically parodies the inconsistencies, irrelevancies, the massive foolishness
of received ideas in the mid-nineteenth century. Indeed a "Dictionary of Received
Ideas" was to comprise part of a second volume of Flaubert's last, unfinished
novel.
Bouvard and Pecuchet is the narrative of two loony Parisian bachelors who,
at a chance meeting, discover between themselves a profound sympathy, and also
that they are both copy clerks. They share a distaste for city life and particularly
for their fate of sitting behind desks all day. When Bouvard inherits a small
fortune the two buy a farm in Normandy, to which they retire, expecting there to
meet head on the reality that was denied them in the half-life of their Parisian
offices. They begin with the idea that they will farm their farm, at which they fail
miserably. From agriculture they move to a more specialized field: arboriculture.
Failing that they decide upon garden architecture. To prepare themselves for each
of their new professions, they consult various manuals and treatises, in which they
are extremely perplexed to find contradictions and misinformation of all kinds.
The advice they seek in them is either confusing or utterly inapplicable; theory
and practice never coincide. But undaunted by their successive failures, they move
on inexorably to the next activity, only to find that it too is incommensurate with
the texts which purport to represent it. They try chemistry, physiology, anatomy,
geology, archeology... the list goes on. When they finally succumb to the fact
that the knowledge they've relied upon is a mass of contradictions, utterly
haphazard, and quite disjunct from the reality they'd sought to confront, they
revert to their initial task of copying. Here is one of Flaubert's scenarios for the
end of the novel:
They copy papers haphazardly, everything they find, tobacco pouches,
old newspapers, posters, torn books, etc. (real items and their imita-
tions. Typical of each category).
Then, they feel the need for a taxonomy. They make tables,
antithetical oppositions such as "crines of the kings and crimes of the
people"-blessings of religion, crimes of religion. Beauties of history,
etc.; sometimes, however, they have real problems putting each thing in
its proper place and suffer great anxieties about it.
-Onward! Enough speculation! Keep on copying! The page
must be filled. Everything is equal, the good and the evil. The farcical
and the sublime-the beautiful and the ugly-the insignificant and the
typical, they all become an exaltation of the statistical. There are
nothing but facts-and phenomena.
Final bliss.9
In a recent essay about the novel, Eugenio Donato argues persuasively that
the emblem for the series of heterogeneous activities of Bouvard and Pecuchet
is not, as Foucault and others have claimed, the library-encyclopedia, but
rather the museum. This is not only because the museum is a privileged term in
the novel itself, but also because of the absolute heterogeneity it gathers together.
The museum contains everything the library contains and it contains the library
as well:
10. Ibid., p. 220. The apparent continuity between Foucault's and Donato's essays here is mislead
ing, inasmuch as Donato is explicitly engaged in an attack upon Foucault's archeological methodol-
ogy, claiming that it implicates Foucault in a return to a metaphysics of origins.
11. Gustave Flaubert, Bouvard and Pecuchet, trans. A. J. Krailsheimer, New York, Penguin Books,
1976, pp. 114-115.
50 OCTOBER
In the period following World War II, perhaps the greatest monument to the
museum's discourse is Andre Malraux's Museum Without Walls. If Bouvard and
Pecuchet is a parody of received ideas of the mid-nineteenth century, the Museum
Without Walls is the hyperbole of such ideas in the mid-twentieth. Specifically,
what Malraux unconsciously parodies is "art history as a humanistic discipline."
For Malraux finds in the notion of style the ultimate homogenizing principle,
indeed the essence of art, hypostatized, interestingly enough, through the medium
of photography. Any work of art that can be photographed can take its place in
Malraux's super-museum. But photography not only secures the admittance of
objects, fragments of objects, details, etc., to the museum, it is also the organizing
device: it reduces the now even vaster heterogeneity to a single perfect similitude.
Through photographic reproduction a cameo takes up residence on the page next
to a painted tondo and a sculpted relief; a detail of a Rubens in Antwerp is
12. Donato, p. 223. No distinctions are made in Donato's essay, nor in my own, between the art
museum and its prototype, the natural history museum. The reasons for removing art to its own
special museum and the particular history of that institution must be the subject of another essay.
RobertRauschenberg.Exile. 1962.
52 OCTOBER
13. This comparison was first presented by Robert Rosenblum in a symposium entitled "Modern
Art and the Modern City: From Caillebotte and the Impressionists to the Present Day," held in
conjunction with the Gustave Caillebotte exhibition at the Brooklyn Museum in March 1977.
Rosenblum published a version of his lecture, although only works by Caillebotte were illustrated.
The following excerpt will suffice to give an impression of the comparisons Rosenblum drew:
"Caillebotte's art seems equally in tune with some of the structural innovations of recent non-
figurative painting and sculpture. His embracing, in the 1870s, of the new experience of modern
Paris . . . involves fresh ways of seeing that are surprisingly close to our own decade. For one, he seems
to have polarized more than any of his Impressionist contemporaries the extremities of the random and
the ordered, usually juxtaposing these contrary modes in the same work. Parisians in city and country
come and go in open spaces, but within their leisurely movements are grids of arithmetic, technologi-
cal regularity. Crisscrossing or parallel patterns of steel girders move with an A-A-A-A beat along the
railing of a bridge. Checkerboards of square pavement stones map out the repetitive grid systems we see
in Warhol or early Stella, Ryman or Andre. Clean stripes, as in Daniel Buren[l], suddenly impose a
cheerful, primary esthetic order upon urban flux and scatter." ("Gustave Caillebotte: The 1970s and
the 1870s," Artforum, XV, 7 [March 1977], 52). When Rosenblum again presented the Ryman-
Caillebotte slide comparison in a symposium on modernism at Hunter College this past March, he
admitted that it was perhaps what Panofsky would have called a pseudomorphism.
On the Museum's Ruins 53
as they are, all these objects... speak for the same endeavor; it is as
though an unseen presence, the spirit of art, were urging all on the
same quest.... Thus it is that, thanks to the rather specious unity im-
posed by photographic reproduction on a multiplicity of objects,
ranging from the statue to the bas-relief, from bas-reliefs to seal-
impressions, and from these to the plaques of the nomads, a "Babylo-
nian style" seems to emerge as a real entity, not a mere classification-
as something resembling, rather, the life-story of a great creator.
Nothing conveys more vividly and compellingly the notion of a des-
tiny shaping human ends than do the great styles, whose evolutions
and transformations seem like long scars that Fate has left, in pass-
ing, on the face of the earth.14
All the works of what we call art, or at least all of them that can be submitted
to the process of photographic reproduction, can take their place in the great
super-oeuvre, Art as ontological essence, created not by men but by Man. This is
the comforting "knowledge" to which the Museum Without Walls gives testi-
mony. And concomitantly, it is the deception to which art history, a discipline
now thoroughly professionalized, is most deeply, if often unconsciously, com-
mitted.
But Malraux makes a fatal error near the end of his Museum: he admits
within its pages the very thing that had constituted its homogeneity; that thing is
of course photography. So long as photography was merely a vehicle by which art
objects entered the museum, a certain coherence obtained. But once photography
itself enters, an art object among others, heterogeneity is reestablished at the heart
of the museum; its pretentions to knowledge are doomed. Even photography
cannot hypostatize style from a photograph.
14. Andre Malraux, Museum Without Walls, The Voices of Silence, Princeton, Princeton Univer-
sity Press, Bollingen Series XXIV, 1978, pp. 44, 46.
15. Flaubert, pp. 321, 300.
. ?;r/jraBC1
-rr 2
A? ?-
~
~:& ?t
56 OCTOBER
the art of painting might disappear, having lost its all-important aura through
mechanical reproduction.16 A denial of this power of photography to transform
art continued to energize modernist painting through the immediate postwar
period in America. But then in the work of Rauschenberg photography began to
conspire with painting in its own destruction.
While it was only with slight discomfort that Rauschenberg was called a
painter throughout the first decade of his career, when he systematically embraced
photographic images in the early sixties it became less and less possible to think of
his work as painting. It was instead a hybrid form of printing. Rauschenberg had
moved definitively from techniques of production (combines, assemblages) to
techniques of reproduction (silkscreens, transfer drawings). And it is that move
that requires us to think of Rauschenberg's art as postmodernist. Through
reproductive technology postmodernist art dispenses with the aura. The fantasy of
a creating subject gives way to the frank confiscation, quotation, excerptation,
accumulation, and repetition of already existing images.17 Notions of originality,
authenticity, and presence, essential to the ordered discourse of the museum, are
undermined. Rauschenberg steals the Rokeby Venus and screens her onto the
surface of Crocus, which also contains pictures of mosquitoes and a truck, as well
as a reduplicated Cupid with a mirror. She appears again, twice, in Transom, now
in the company of a helicopter and repeated images of water towers on Manhattan
rooftops. In Bicycle she reappears with the truck of Crocus and the helicopter of
Transom, but now also a sailboat, a cloud, an eagle. She reclines just above three
Cunningham dancers in Overcast III and atop a statue of George Washington and
a car key in Breakthrough. The absolute heterogeneity that is the purview of
both the museum and of photography is spread across the surface of every
Rauschenberg work. More importantly, it is spread from work to work.
Malraux was enraptured by the endless possibilities of his Museum, by the
proliferation of discourses it could set in motion, establishing ever-new series of
iconography and style simply by reshuffling the photographs. That proliferation
is enacted by Rauschenberg: Malraux's dream has become Rauschenberg's joke.18
16. See Walter Benjamin, "The Work ot Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction," Illumina-
tions, trans. Harry Zohn, New York, Schocken Books, 1969, pp. 217-251.
17. For further discussion of these postmodernist techniques pervasive in recent art, see my essay
"Pictures," October, 8 (Spring 1979), 75-88; and Craig Owens, "The Allegorical Impulse: Toward a
Theory of Postmodernism," October, 12 (Spring 1980), 67-86. That we are now experiencing the
"decay of the aura" that Benjamin predicted can be understood not only in these positive terms of what
has replaced it, but also in the many desperate attempts to recuperate it by reviving the style and
rhetoric of expressionism. This tendency is, needless to say, particularly strong in the marketplace, but
also in museum exhibitions.
18. Just how little inclined to agree with my analysis of the museum Rauschenberg would be is
clear from the proclamation he composed for the Metropolitan Museum's Centennial Certificate. It
reads: "Treasury of the conscience of man. / Masterworks collected, protected / and celebrated
commonly. Timeless in / concept the museum amasses to / concertise a moment of pride / serving to
defend the dreams / and ideals apolitically of mankind / aware and responsive to the / changes, needs
and complexities / of current life while keeping / history and love alive." The poster was signed by the
Museum's officials.
On the Museum's Ruins 57
But of course not everyone gets the joke. And so we are still told that order can be
made of this stuff; the Rebus can be read. It reads, in fact, "That reproduces sundry
cases of childish and comic coincidences to be read by eyes opened finally to a
pattern of abstract problems."19 Bouvard and Pecuchet would surely be confused.
19. This reading of Rauschenberg's Rebus appears in Charles F. Stuckey, "Reading Rauschen-
berg," Art in America, 65, 2 (March-April 1977), 82. I reproduce it here as a fairly typical example of the
blind application of traditional art-historical methodologies to contemporary art.