20117531
20117531
20117531
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Synthese
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ELIJAH MILLGRAM and PAUL THAGARD
DELIBERATIVE COHERENCE*
ABSTRACT. Choosing the right plan is often choosing the more coherent plan: but what
is coherence? We argue that coherence-directed practical inference ought to be represented
computationally. To that end, we advance a theory of deliberative coherence, and describe
its implementation in a program modelled on Thagard's ECHO. We explain how the theory
can be tested and extended, and consider its bearing on instrumentalist accounts of practical
rationality.
1.
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
64 ELIJAH MILLGRAM AND PAUL THAGARD
long history of the concept" (BonJour 1985, 93f). For a very long time,
philosophers have been using the notion of coherence without having any
thing to back it up, and, unlike the newly clothed emperor of the children's
story, have never really been called on it. Anybody who proposes to use
the concept of coherence has to do better than this: at a minimum, one
needs a way of saying what coherence is, and when one system (of beliefs,
or motivations) is more coherent than another. In Sections 4-6, we will
propose a technique for generating comparative judgments of deliberative
coherence. This technique will provide a substantive, albeit partial, account
of deliberative coherence. We will discuss how this account of coherence
can be tested and extended.
The best way to address the second problem is to narrow it. Our interest
is in coherence-driven revision of motivational systems: in techniques that
alter one's motivational system to make it more coherent. In this context,
justifying the appeal to coherence means finding occasions on which the
use of techniques that increase coherence is justified. Once we have a
substantive specification of the principles of deliberative or motivational
coherence, we can also address the demand for justification by considering
what can be said for particular principles embodied in those techniques.
Our strategy will be to address these problems for deliberative coher
ence by using as a guide what we know about reasoning aimed at producing
beliefs rather than decision (or 'theoretical reasoning'). Because the ter
ritory is muddy there too, we will have to make claims about theoretical
reasoning that are themselves controversial; fortunately, their function here
will be only heuristic, so they will not require the attention or argument that
they would have to be allotted otherwise. We will take the two problems
in reverse order, and begin by asking when coherence considerations are
in place in the revision of systems of belief.
2.
You can have contradictory or inconsistent beliefs, and when you do, some
thing's got to give: if you are rational, you modify your beliefs.1 Just how
contradictory beliefs are adjusted is not well understood. Logic textbooks
give out at this point, saying either that if you arrive at a contradiction, a
premise must be rejected (but without telling you which premise to reject),
or that if you arrive at a contradiction, you may legitimately infer anything
whatsoever. Such advice is respectively unhelpful and unrealistic.
However, while the process of revising incompatible beliefs is not well
understood, it is reasoning nonetheless. Reasoning consists not just in
drawing inferences from one's beliefs, but in figuring out what to do when
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
DELIBERATIVE COHERENCE 65
one's beliefs turn out to be inconsistent. How is this done? Examples from
the history of science suggest that coherence is a central consideration
(Thagard 1992c), and day-to-day experience concurs. For instance, Max
answered the phone at his home number all day, so I assumed he was at
home; but Martha tells me they spent most of the day out. Of the various
explanations (Martha is lying, I was hallucinating, and so on), one makes
everything hang together better than the others. (Max has just gotten call
forwarding, and wouldn't that be just like him.) This new belief ties as much
as possible of my prior system of beliefs together in as coherent a manner
as possible; I adopt it and clean up my system of beliefs appropriately. The
revision of contradictory or inconsistent systems of belief \k evidently an
occasion for deploying coherence considerations.
Is there a motivational analog of inconsistent systems of belief? As a
matter of fact, there are two, corresponding to two senses of '^oal'. Talk
about goals can be about either intentions or desires. In the first sense,
to say that someone has a goal is to say something on the order of: l^e
is pursuing the goal, or is following a plan for attaining the goal. In the
second sense, to say that he has a goal is to say that he desires it, even if he
is not actively pursuing it or planning to pursue it. (Someone may desire
something, i.e., have a goal in the second sense, without intending to attain
it, i.e., without having a goal in the first sense, if, for example, attaining the
goal would be incompatible with something he thinks is more important.)
It is a commonplace that one can discover that one's goals conflict, that
is, that one cannot attain them all. I want, and had been planning to buy,
a new car and a ticket to Thailand. If I am rational, when I discover that I
cannot afford both, I adjust my intentions, giving up at least one of what
had been my goals (in the first sense).
It is less of a commonplace that I may be put in a similar position with
respect to goals in the second sense. I may have to stop intending to go to
Thailand this fall, but clearly I am not irrational if I keep on wanting to.
And it is in fact often taken for granted that one is never rationally required
to give up a desire that does not itself involve a factual mistake or that is
not derived by means-end reasoning from some further desire; this view
frequently gets described, with a certain amount of historical license, as
'Humean'. However, there are nevertheless desires that plausibly require
rational revision. Oedipus wants to marry Jocasta and wants not to marry
his mother. If he discovers before the ceremony that Jocasta is his mother,
he discovers that he has desires that are directly incompatible. It would be
untrue to the phenomena, and probably does not make sense, to suppose that
Oedipus merely gives up one intention or the other, leaving an unsatisfied
background desire. Oedipus' motivational system readjusts, after which
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
66 ELIJAH MILLGRAM AND PAUL THAGARD
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
DELIBERATIVE COHERENCE 67
Even if it is granted that desires or goals can conflict in a way that makes
abandoning or otherwise revising some of them make sense, it might still
be objected that we do not have reason to think that the revision should be
such as to increase or maximize the coherence of the motivational system.
After all, there are many ways of removing conflict, not all of which favor
what we would be inclined to call coherence. For example, I could replace
the conflicting goals in my list of errands with a sudden intention to give up
eating fish, or to scour the Himalayas for tranquillity and spiritual uplift,
or, less fancifully, to get the packing tape but not the boxes, and see a movie
on impulse. Why coherence?
The real answer to this question lies in the connections between descrip
tive and normative theories of rationality, on the one hand, and our actual
practices, on the other; we will touch on these issues briefly below. As a
stopgap, here are two shorter answers. First, because goals compete for
limited resources, goals that hang together, and which naturally produce
overlapping plans of action, tend to be more easily jointly satisfied.5 A
policy of adopting new goals that are unrelated to my current goals ? for
example, replacing or supplementing my list of errands with a Himalayan
trek?makes it less likely that I will accomplish many of my goals: sudden
swerves squander sunk cost. Second, the point of practical reasoning is
to guide us in the decisions that shape our lives. When goals belong to
human beings, they are components of lives, and for something to be a
life, it has to be coherent. So practical reasoning should tend to increase
the coherence of systems of goals.6 (This consideration is of course only
indirectly applicable when we are considering not human beings but tools
such as planning systems.)
Perhaps a caveat is in place here as well. After a certain point, increas
ing coherence increases fragility. When everything fits together, finding
out you were wrong about one thing has ramifications for everything you
believe or desire. It is probably better for human beings if everything does
not fit together too tightly; if you have a number of relatively independent
motivational bases (job, family, and so on), you are better able to handle
having any one of them kicked out from under you. So there are prob
ably limits to the desirability of deliberative or motivational coherence.
However, we will not further consider these here.
3.
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
68 ELIJAH MILLGRAM AND PAUL THAGARD
puter program (ECHO). Together, TEC and ECHO provide a general and
testable account of explanatory coherence. Both are described at much
greater length in Thagard (1989 and 1992c, ch. 4). Here we present a
concise and informal statement of TEC and ECHO adapted from Thagard
(1992a).
TEC consists of seven principles:
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
DELIBERATIVE COHERENCE 69
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
70 ELIJAH MILLGRAM AND PAUL THAGARD
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
DELIBERATIVE COHERENCE 71
and the people it models may be doing what they do because the task
cannot be done without cutting corners.11
Perspicuous representation of an inference pattern is an important step
towards seeing if it is justified. First, it may be that perspicuous representa
tion is itself a good deal of the argument: a pattern of inference, e.g., modus
ponens, is displayed and recognized as a legitimate form of inference. And
secondly, the use of a pattern of inference under consideration to rationally
reconstruct available bodies of inference has traditionally been taken to be a
very strong argument for its legitimacy; for example, the ability of Frege
Russell logic to reconstruct large bodies of mathematical argument was
as telling as the straight-off plausibility of its rules and axioms. Rational
reconstructions of this kind normally require the perspicuous representa
tion of the basic patterns of inference that they deploy; without them, it is
hard to tell what has been successfully reconstructed and what has not.
The techniques predominantly used to represent patterns of inference
have been those familiar from logic textbooks: the inference is rewritten
in a formal language designed to highlight its structure and make it easy to
verify that only allowable transitions have taken place. These techniques
have proven enormously fruitful in some areas; however, they have not
been as successful when applied to such patterns of reasoning as inference
to the best explanation. Other representational techniques may turn out
to be the most helpful in studying patterns of inference that have resisted
the traditional style of formalization. (The right medium of representation
depends in part on what one is trying to represent: a picture can be worth
a thousand words, and there are things one can do with words that one
cannot do with pictures.) ECHO is an example of the use of computational
techniques to represent a pattern of inference that has hitherto resisted
formalization. ECHO can be used to display perspicuously what a certain
type of coherence-based inference comes to. It can be used descriptively,
to model actual cognitive processes; but it can also be used normative
ly, to rationally reconstruct them. Rational reconstructions of this kind
are arguments for the legitimacy of the pattern of inference that ECHO
represents.
We propose using ECHO as a model for addressing the analogous
problem of deliberative or motivational coherence. An ECHO-like program
can provide a way of rendering comparative judgments of deliberative
coherence, and in so doing, spell out the notion's content. Such a program
can be an experimental tool, allowing the same kind of testing and feedback
that ECHO makes possible in studying explanatory coherence. And using
such a program to develop rational reconstructions of available bodies of
inference would be a way of arguing for the legitimacy of the pattern of
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
72 ELIJAH MILLGRAM AND PAUL THAGARD
inference modelled by the program. We are calling the first version of the
proposed program DECO, for Deliberative Coherence.
4.
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
DELIBERATIVE COHERENCE 73
The Principle of Facilitation expresses the way in which the actions and
subsidiary goals that jointly contribute to achieving an end hang together
with each other and with the end they promote. If getting the car into
driving condition requires fixing the oil leak, replacing the brake hoses,
adjusting the idle time, and putting on a couple of new tires, it will make
some sense to do all of these if one is going to do any of them; and of
course doing these will make some sense if one is interested in getting the
car into running condition. We will consider later the question whether the
goal of getting the car running can be made sense of by its subgoals.
The third clause of the Principle of Facilitation expresses & preference
for simplicity. Other things being equal, simpler plans are to be preferred
to more complicated plans. This is because the point of a plan is that it
work, and simpler plans have a better chance of working. When the Space
Shuttle was being developed, it was proudly described as the most complex
vehicle ever built; as many realized after the Challenger catastrophe, pride
in its complexity was misplaced. Simpler plans also tend to consume fewer
resources; the surplus time, money and so on can be devoted to other goals.
The Principle of Incompatibility allows for rough and ready distinctions
between degrees of difficulty in performing actions or achieving goals.
Strongly incoherent goals may include those that are directly incompatible
(Oedipus wanting to marry Jocasta and not marry his mother), and goals
that, while not directly incompatible, are not jointly realizable (becoming
a concert pianist while earning a living as a jackhammer operator). Weakly
incoherent goals are compossible but difficult (getting one's errands done
and getting home in time to put the baby to bed). Notice that difficulty
can come in many forms: if it is hard to serve four soups for dinner, this
is not because one is physically unable to make four soups. Note also
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
74 ELIJAH MILLGRAM AND PAUL THAGARD
that it is not intended that the Principle of Incompatibility require the fine
discriminations between probabilities demanded by the expected utility
model.
The Principle of Goal Priority acknowledges the fact that some things
are simply desired for their own sakes. But it does not state that goals
thought to be intrinsically valuable cannot be abandoned when they inco
here with one's other goals and actions. Goal priority also allows for other
non-coherence reasons for taking something to be desirable: that one's par
ents or peers say it is, or that experience has shown that it matters. Goals
that are desirable for non-coherence reasons we will call priority goals.
Goals designated as priority goals in the context of one problem may
have that status as a way of representing their coherence with further
goals and actions that are not now being considered. Recall the problem
of figuring out which group of errands to run when the traffic makes it
impossible to run them all. And suppose that one of my errands is to
collect the $5000 in cash that I have just won. I may choose to collect
the $5000, even though it does not cohere with any of the other errands
on my list, and let the apparently more coherent groups of errands go. To
model this choice, we can assign the goal of collecting the cash a very high
priority. But this may make it seem like coherence is playing a far less
important role than simple utility calculations.
This impression would be misleading. The importance of collecting
the $5000 is not merely brute. It is hard to make sense of its importance
except in terms of the ways in which it coheres with other goals to which I
am committed.13 Now I cannot consider the coherence of all my goals and
actions at once; Ranney (forthcoming) suggestively compares the ability to
focus one's attention on questions of coherence to a spotlight: coherence
oriented adjustments are only made among the elements within the current
circle of the beam. One way to represent the coherence of an element 'in
the beam' with further plans, aims, and so on not now under consideration
is to treat the factor in question as a high priority item. But the priority
of the factor in one's present deliberations represents not brute intrinsic
desirability but further coherence considerations.
The Principle of Judgment expresses the idea that whether one takes one
factor to facilitate or compete with another depends on what one believes
? and what one believes in turn depends on the coherence of competing
clusters of beliefs. If it seems very unlikely to you, in light of other things
you believe, that an action A is a way of bringing about a goal G, then A
should not cohere with G in virtue of being a means to G. There may be
other ways in which judgment matters for deliberative coherence. Some
judgments may cohere with actions (e.g., "It would be courageous to save
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
DELIBERATIVE COHERENCE 75
the infant" plausibly coheres with saving the infant) even when facilitation
and compossibility are not at issue. DECO does not attempt to represent
coherence-inducing relations of this kind.
5.
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
76 ELIJAH MILLGRAM AND PAUL THAGARD
and essay writing, and opting to double-major when one finds that one is
in any case only two courses short of the second major. Adopting such
higher level goals organizes and further motivates pursuit of the original,
lower level goals, and makes it more likely that the lower level goals will be
attained; and it may have further benefits.16 Because DECO implements the
Principle of Symmetry, experimenting with DECO will help answer several
questions: What commitments are involved in the Principle of Symmetry?
Can the Principle of Symmetry account for the ways in which people
revise their primary goals? Answering these questions will help address the
further question: Is revision of this kind rational? And is rational revision of
one's primary goals possible with the extremely spare apparatus that DECO
allows itself? If one takes the only coherence-inducing relations to be those
that an instrumentalist would acknowledge to be legitimate, can coherence
based decision differ substantively from instrumentalist decision?17
6.
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
DELIBERATIVE COHERENCE 77
TABLE I
DECO inputs and their effects
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
78 ELIJAH MILLGRAM AND PAUL THAGARD
7.
For a more concrete sense of how DECO works, and of how it can be used in
thinking about deliberative coherence, consider the following small agenda
planning problem. On the one hand, I could spend my day in Berkeley.
I would meet Florence at Cafe Venezia, get my brakes fixed, and xerox
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
DELIBERATIVE COHERENCE 79
B2 -0.86 BI -0.78
A2 0.76 A3 0.76 ..- --; -O
B3 -0.86
AI 0.72 ^ / B4 -0.89
A9 0.75
B5 -0.88
A5 0.56
B6 -0.53
O
B7 -0.89
A6 0.43 A8 0.53
B8 -0.87
Figure 1. Network constructed for the agenda planning problem. Priority goals are repre
sented by filled circles, excitatory links by unbroken lines, and inhibitory links by dashes.
Final activation values are shown following unit labels. Not all inhibitory links are shown.
course materials at the library. (Call this "Plan A".) On the other, I could
run a number of errands in Oakland, such as going to the post office and
having the cat flea-dipped, and I could catch up on a number of tasks at
home. (Call this "Plan B".) Because time is limited, and because I cannot
be in both Berkeley and Oakland at the same time, the factors that comprise
the respective plans are for the most part incompatible. Plan A differs from
Plan B in that its elements hang together much more closely. Driving into
Berkeley facilitates, and so coheres with, getting to the restaurant, having
my brakes repaired, and meeting Florence; Florence and I can discuss the
syllabus for my new course, I will be able to follow her suggestions up at the
library later on, and so on. My various Oakland-based activities, however,
would hardly hang together at all; they have for the most part nothing to
do with each other. (Table II shows part of the input for this problem; full
listings of the inputs and DECO runs for the examples given in the text
are available at http://cogsci.uwaterloo.ca.) As one would expect, DECO
selects Plan A.
This agenda planning problem highlights the differences between a
coherence-based and a utility-based approach to planning. Plans A and B
each include the same number of priority goals, so from the utility-oriented
standpoint, the two plans should be running neck-to-neck in competition.
But when DECO chooses between them, the more coherent Plan A handily
trounces Plan B.
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
80 ELIJAH MILLGRAM AND PAUL THAGARD
TABLE II
Sample DECO input from an agenda planning problem
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
DELIBERATIVE COHERENCE 81
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
82 ELIJAH MILLGRAM AND PAUL THAGARD
TABLE III
Sample DECO input from a menu-planning problem
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
DELIBERATIVE COHERENCE 83
Overall, DECO does not do too badly, but the task is one which DECO
(and the current TDC) is not fully up to. While most of DECO's proposed
meal plan makes sense, there is a surprising category of exceptions: it
recommends purchasing some ingredients for recipes that will not be pre
pared. Obtaining the ingredients is facilitated by a trip to the supermarket,
so, by the Principle of Symmetry, DECO treats the trip to the supermarket
as a reason to get those ingredients. (People occasionally do this also:
"While I'm there, I might as well get these items too".) And while DECO
also treats buying the ingredients as a reason to make the dish, that rea
son is not always decisive. DECO does much better at selecting among
preformulated plans than it does at generating them.
We said earlier that one of the uses of DECO is to investigate the
implications of the Principle of Symmetry. Running DECO on examples
like this one shows what one is committed to by TDC, and so allows one to
make an informed judgment as to its plausibility. Since one does not want
to be committed to adopting subgoals but not the higher-level goal which
gives them their point, we seem to have a reason to reject the Principle of
Symmetry, and the TDC of which it is part.
That conclusion is not yet warranted. Responsibility for the surprising
result must be shared by the Principle of Symmetry and by one of DECO's
limitations, to which the result directs our attention. Connectionist net
works like DECO are clumsy at representing numerical and Boolean con
straints. Instrumental reasoning, however, involves the application of such
constraints. (Here the constraint is roughly that both the goal and some suf
ficient set of its subgoals must be selected, or neither.) We cannot assign
responsibility for such results to the Principle of Symmetry until we have
seen how to supplement DECO with a mechanism for representing such
constraints. (Activation-dependent links, of the kind used in CARE (Nel
son et al., 1994) are a promising candidate.) Perhaps this would take DECO
one step closer towards being a plan generator; in any case, the next step
to take in improving DECO is evidently to modify it (and its associated
TDC) to represent constraints of this kind. The meal-planning example
shows rather neatly how a computational representation of a theory of
deliberative coherence can not only allow the theory to be assessed by
comparing its judgments to those of human beings, but can focus attention
on those aspects of the theory that need change or further development.22
8.
Prior to the twentieth century, "Logic" was the name for the study of forms
of thinking and inference rather than the title of a branch of mathematics.
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
84 ELIJAH MILLGRAM AND PAUL THAGARD
NOTES
* We are grateful to Nina Amenta, Michael Bratman, Christoph Fehige, Harry Frankfurt,
Susan Hardy, Derek Hawley, Wilfried Hinsch, Jenann Ismael, Ziva Kunda, Nick Little
stone, Michael Ranney, Gabriel Richardson, Patricia Schank, Bill Talbott, Carol Varey and
UC/Berkeley's EMST Reasoning Group for helpful discussion. An ancestor of Section 2
benefitted from comments by and discussion with Alyssa Bernstein, Hilary Bok, Tamar
Gendler, Philip Klein, Tony Laden, Mitzi Lee, Robert Nozick, Hilary Putnam, Tim Scanlon,
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
DELIBERATIVE COHERENCE 85
Sanford Shieh and, especially, Candace Vogler. We thank Susan Hardy and Roy Fleck for
programming assistance. Thagard's research was supported by the Natural Sciences and
Engineering Research Council of Canada.
1 This claim needs a certain amount of qualification. It may be very difficult to find and
extirpate hidden or hard-to-resolve inconsistencies in one's beliefs, and it might be entirely
rational not to work too hard to uncover these inconsistencies; similarly, it might be rational
not to resolve an acknowledged inconsistency of little practical import (Harman 1986,15ff).
We will ignore these issues here.
2 Saying when desires merely conflict and when they are directly incompatible and require
revision is a hard problem. We will not explore it further here. The idea that some desires
might demand adjustment in this way is due to Candace Vogler.
3 There may be faster alternatives to the 0(2n) calculation, but even these shortcuts are
likely to be beyond my capacities. (Bayesian networks are an analogous shortcut to updat
ing one's probability assignments, and they also prove to be often too demanding. See note
4, below.)
4 The argument here is analogous to Thagard's argument for preferring coherence-driven
progams such as ECHO to Bayesian networks (in press). Bayesian networks are computa
tionally expensive, and often intractable; and they require information about probabilities
that actual agents normally do not have.
5 For related discussion, see Pollack, 1991.
6 This is not to say that agents should adjust their systems of goals to make them more
coherent because they have the further goal of coherence. To see that this is the wrong
kind of justification for our reasoning the way we do, consider an analogous justification
for means-end reasoning, that we engage in it as a means to the goal of being means-end
reasoners.
7 The relative explanatory coherence of two competing theories is not determined by com
puting some index of explanatory coherence for each plan separately and comparing the
indices. (While indices of this kind - e.g., "harmany" - have been proposed, they are ill
suited for comparing graphs with very different numbers of nodes and links. And it is in any
case unclear that the notion of relative coherence should be well-defined for explanations
that are not competitors.) Rather, the fact that, at the end of an ECHO run, one explanation
remains activated while its competitor does not is interpreted to mean that the former is
more coherent than the latter.
8 Cases studied include Lavoisier's argument for the oxygen theory, Darwin's argument
for evolution by natural selection, arguments for and against continental drift, the case
of Copernicus versus Ptolemy, the case of Newton versus Descartes, and contemporary
debates about why the dinosaurs became extinct. Thagard (1989, 1991), Thagard and
Nowak (1990), Nowak and Thagard (1992a, 1992b).
9 Ranney and Thagard (1988), Ranney (forthcoming), Schank and Ranney (1991), Miller
and Read (1991), Read and Marcus-Newhall (1993).
10 See Thagard (1992c), note 1, p. 66.
11 For discussion of related issues, see Millgram (1991).
12 Hurley (1989), esp. chs. 10-11; Kant (1785/1981); Nell (1974); Broadie (1981); Richard
son (1987). On analogy, see Holyoak and Thagard (1989,1995), Thagard et al. (1990); for
related discussion, see Nozick (1993).
13 It is likely that most or all extremely high priority goals will turn out to have their
priority partly in virtue of coherence with plans, commitments, and so on, not now under
consideration, at any rate in the case of rational and reasonable agents. While 'I just feel
like it' may account for assignment of moderate priority, treating as overriding a goal that
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
86 ELIJAH MILLGRAM AND PAUL THAGARD
fails to cohere with other considerations - e.g., insisting on washing the car rather than
driving to the airport in time for one's plane, because one feels that one has to, but for no
further reason - is a hallmark of compulsive behavior.
14 The question is complicated by the fact that although the Principle of Symmetry gov
erns the representations of systems of goals constructed by DECO, Goal Priority produces
asymmetries in the ways DECO treats goals. We will return to this point below.
15 The example is due to Mike Thau.
16 See Frankfurt, 1992.
17 One important question that needs to be addressed is how supergoal adoption can be
distinguished from intending unwanted side-effects. To adapt an example from Pollack,
1991, going swimming facilitates getting chlorine in my hair. Getting chlorine in my hair
is an unwanted side-effect because, although I accept it as part of the plan to go swimming,
I will not take further steps to make it happen, such as buying a bottle and rubbing it on my
scalp. DECO does not now model the distinction, and with a little ingenuity one can design
inputs for which DECO makes a choice that is tantamount to intending the side-effect.
However, DECO is a promising experimental testbed for exploring this problem.
18 The new activation level is given by
where aj (t + 1 ) is the unit's updated activation level; aj (t) is its previous activation level; 6
is a decay parameter; min is the minimum activation (?1); max is the maximum activation
(1); and netj is the net input to the unit, defined as ?\ Wijdi(t), where Wij is the weight
of the link between i and j.
19 A parallel mistake is made by Clark Glymour's discussion of ECHO (1992, pp. 470f);
for a reply, see Thagard (1992b).
20 For an example of unintentional bias, see note 22, below.
21 For discussion of the problem in ECHO, see Thagard (1992c, p. 89); for an experiment
that examines intercoder reliability in ECHO, see Schank and Ranney (1992).
22 Experimentation with the computational representation of a TDC can also show that
some problems are not nearly as pressing as they might seem a priori. For instance, it might
seem that coherentist choice would be unduly biased in favor of better understood, but
not necessarily better, plans. Imagine an engineer who works for the Coca-Cola company
designing Coke machines; during his break, he has to choose between coffee from the
coffee machine and a Coke from the adjacent Coke machine. Because he is familiar with
the internal workings of the one machine, but not the other, his representation of his plan
for getting a Coke is much more complex, detailed, and structured - in DECO's terms,
much more coherent - than his representation of the competing plan for getting a coffee.
But this is not a good reason for choosing the Coke over the coffee. (The objection is due to
Michael Bratman.) Now of course sometimes it does make good sense to choose the better
understood over the more poorly understood plan. But this is not one of those times. And,
as Bratman has emphasized (1987), because one of the points of having plans is to be able
to fill them in as one goes, incompleteness should not normally rule a plan out.
However, although one might think that DECO would be bound to choose the more
detailed of the two plans, the actual DECO runs show neither of the competing plans com
ing out a clear winner.
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
DELIBERATIVE COHERENCE 87
REFERENCES
Bonjour, L.; 1985, The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Harvard University Press, Cam
bridge, MA.
Bratman, M.; 1987, Intention, Plans and Practical Reason. Harvard University Press,
Cambridge, Mass.
Brink, D. O.: 1989, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics. Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge.
Broadie, S. W.: 1987, The Problem of Practical Intellect in Aristotle's Ethics', in J.
Geary (ed.), Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, Vol. Ill
University Press of America, Lanham, pp. 229-252.
Frankfurt, H.: 1992, 'On the Usefulness of Final Ends', lyyun 41, 3?19.
Glymour, C: 1992, 'Invasion of the Mind Snatchers', in R. Giere (ed.), Cognitive Models of
Science, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 15, University of Minnesota
Press, Minneapolis, pp. 465?471.
Harman, G.: 1986, Change in View, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Holyoak, K. and P. Thagard: 1989, Analogical Mapping by Constraint Satisfaction', Cog
nitive Science 13, 295-355.
Holyoak, K. and P. Thagard: 1995, Mental Leaps: Analogies in Creative Thought. MIT
Press/Bradford Books, Cambridge, Mass.
Hurley, S.: 1989, Natural Reasons, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Kant, I.: 1785/1981, Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, Hackett, Indianapolis.
Miller, L. C. and S. J. Read: 1991, 'On the Coherence of Mental Models of Persons and
Relationships', in F. Fincham and G. Fletcher (eds), Cognition in Close Relationships,
Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ, pp. 69-99.
Millgram, E.: 1991, 'Harman's Hardness Arguments', Pacific Philosophical Quarterly
72(3), 181-202.
Nell, O.: 1974, Acting on Principle, Columbia University Press, New York.
Nelson, G., P. Thagard, and S. Hardy: 1994, 'Integrating Analogy with Rules and Explana
tions', in J. A. Barnden and K. J. Holyoak (eds), Advances in Connectionist and Neural
Computation Theory, Vol. 2: Analogical Connections, Ablex, Norwood, NJ, pp. 181?205.
Nowak, G. and P. Thagard: 1992a, 'Copernicus, Ptolemy, and Explanatory Coherence',
in R. Giere (ed.), Cognitive Models of Science, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of
Science, Vol. 15, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp. 274-309.
Nowak, G. and P. Thagard: 1992b, 'Newton, Descartes, and Explanatory Coherence", in
R. Duschl and R. Hamilton (eds), Philosophy of Science, Cognitive Psychology and
Educational Theory and Practice, SUNY Press, Albany, pp. 69-115.
Nozick, R.: 1993, The Nature of Rationality, Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Pollack, M.: 1991, 'Overloading Intentions for Efficient Practical Reasoning', Nous 25(4),
513-36.
Ranney, M.: forthcoming, 'Explorations in Explanatory Coherence', in E. Bar-On and B.
Eylon (eds), Designing Intelligent Learning Environments: From Cognitive Analysis to
Computer Implementation, Ablex, Norwood, NJ.
Ranney, M. and P. Thagard: 1988, 'Explanatory Coherence and Belief Revision in Naive
Physics', in Proceedings of the Tenth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society,
Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ, pp. 426^432.
Rawls, J.: 1971, A Theory of Justice, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
8 8 ELIJAH MILLGRAM AND PAUL THAGARD
Elijah Millgram
Department of Philosophy
Princeton University
Princeton, NJ 08544
[email protected]
Paul Thagard
Department of Philosophy
University of Waterloo
Waterloo, Ont. N2L3G1
[email protected].
This content downloaded from 152.2.176.242 on Sun, 17 Jul 2016 11:37:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms