Murkens - Unintended Democracy - Final
Murkens - Unintended Democracy - Final
Murkens - Unintended Democracy - Final
Original citation:
Originally published in Grotke, K.L and Prutsch, Markus J, Constitutionalism, Legitimacy, and
Power: Nineteenth-Century Experiences. Oxford, UK, Oxford University Press, 2014 pp 351-370
LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the
School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual
authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any
article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research.
You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities
or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE
Research Online website.
This document is the author’s submitted version of the book section. There may be differences
between this version and the published version. You are advised to consult the publisher’s
version if you wish to cite from it.
Unintended Democracy:
Parliamentary Reform in the UK
Word count:
* Department of Law, London School of Economics & Political Science. Thanks are due to Roger
Cotterrell, Neil Duxbury, Eric Heinze, Rüdiger von Krosigk, Michael Lobban, Martin Loughlin, John
Pemble, and Volker Sellin for valuable comments and criticism. I would also like to express my gratitude
to Armin von Bogdandy and the members of his Dienstagsrunde at the Max-Planck-Institute for
International and Comparative Public Law, Heidelberg, to whom I presented an earlier draft on 15 March
2011.
En fait, avec ou sans suffrage universel, c’est toujours une oligarchie qui gouverne.
The constitution of the United Kingdom underwent a series of incremental and important reforms in the
period from 1815-1914. Suffrage was reformed in three waves (in 1831-2, 1866-7, and 1884-5), and
finalised in 1919, 1928 and 1948. In addition, local government was reformed in 1835 and 1888.
A.V. Dicey authoritatively articulated the doctrine of Parliamentary sovereignty in 1885 which today still
forms the central regulative idea of the modern, liberal democratic British constitution. But what is the
relationship between law and politics? Did the doctrine of Parliamentary sovereignty pave the way for
democracy and a universal franchise? Or does Parliamentary sovereignty only make sense in light of the
limited franchise that existed at the time Dicey wrote? This contribution argues that the political
motivation behind the Reform Acts of 1832 and 1867 was anti-democratic and served to restore and
stabilise the authority of the ruling class, and that this motivation is reflected in the doctrine of
Parliamentary sovereignty.
It is usually said that the United Kingdom became a modern democracy in the period
from 1815-1914 through the process of a series of incremental and important reforms.
Suffrage was reformed in three waves (in 1831-2, 1866-7, and 1884-5), and finalised in
1919, 1928 and 1948. In addition, local government was reformed in 1835 and 1888.
Government was gradually being equipped with the machinery of a modern state – the
Civil Service, procedural law, and the courts. Devoid of a (revolutionary) constitutional
moment that reconstructed de novo the whole system of government, the transition from
oligarchy towards modern democracy took place through independent legislative acts. 1
Yet, there is a danger that one is ‘too easily seduced by the long course of
parliamentary history into believing that the coming of democracy in the twentieth
century was an inevitable result of gradual constitutional change’. 6 The motivation behind
and purpose of the Reform Acts of 1832 and 1867 were anything but democratic. At the
time, the constitutional consequences of expanding the electorate were feared even
amongst the reforming establishment who passed the Reform Acts in order to maintain
some of their prerogatives and privileges whilst preventing the exercise of arbitrary power
either by a monarch or an all-powerful assembly. The Acts created, to quote from the
Project statement, ‘a mechanism of inclusion and exclusion, defining permissible and
impermissible kinds of arguments as well as determining who may act and which
procedural channels must be followed in order to address a grievance’. They were anti-
democratic measures that served to strengthen government and the House of Commons
and to create legal obstacles that working class men and women still had to fight to
overcome.
This chapter seeks to add the background story to the conventional narrative. 7 The
starting point for contemporary public law is, invariably and inevitably, Albert Venn
Dicey’s seminal Introduction to the Law of the Constitution (first published in 1885) 8 whose
central articulation of the legislative supremacy of Parliament (the ‘despotism of the King
3 Bradley and Ewing 2011, p. 31 (‘evolutionary development’); Wicks 2006; critically: Mitchell 1960, p. 332.
4 Tomkins 2003, p. 165; Foley 1999, p. 20.
5 Dicey 1905, p. 48. By ‘democratic’ Dicey meant that every reform had been designed to increase the
Goldsworthy 1999, who covers the entire nineteenth century in a little more than six pages in Ch. 8. The
nineteenth century generally does not feature in public law textbooks. An exception is Loveland 2009, p.
201-214.
8 Dicey 1959.
in Parliament’) 9 is the closest the United Kingdom has to a constitutional text. But how
would the machinery of Parliamentary government and sovereignty, i.e. the model for the
mid-nineteenth century with a limited and unrepresentative electorate and a modest party
system, respond to universal suffrage and mass parties in the twentieth century? Is it
accurate to say that the political and legal developments in 1832 and 1867, even with
perfect hindsight, paved the way for democracy?
9 Ibid, p. 145.
10 See Vile 1998, chps. 3 and 5.
campaigns. ‘While 1688 envisaged Parliament as a consensual forum designed to identify
the national interest, it now operates as an arena of conflict intended to promote party
interests’. 11
Nostalgia began to creep in for the constitutional arrangements of 1832 which had
been lost to democracy. 16 But do the post-1832 developments amount to sufficient
evidence of the progressive unfolding of democracy? Or were democracy and the right to
vote, join trade unions, be educated etc argued for, fought for, and suffered for, by
working class men and later women? Perhaps, and with the benefit of hindsight, the
coming of democracy was inevitable. If it was, it was not the Reform Acts that
democratised the United Kingdom, but the changing political, economic and social
conditions and forces. As Norman Gash underlines, the three Reform Acts of 1832, 1867
and 1884 ‘were passed by men who had no belief in the kind of political democracy
implicit in universal suffrage and equality of electoral districts and who feared that the
introduction of such a system would lead to the tyranny of the illiterate many over the
However, the Reform Act was not designed to make the system more democratic, e.g.
by enhancing or ensuring fair popular representation. It was a necessary response to the
discontent experienced by ‘the bulk of informed and influential opinion in the country’ 20
that stemmed from insufficient or a complete absence of representation of new and
important (industrial) interests as well as an overrepresentation of (aristocratic)
individuals. Reform was also a tactical response to the fear of popular revolt and political
revolution. If there was a choice between bringing the middle classes, those ‘vast masses
of property and intelligence’, into an alliance with the old governing classes (and restoring
the balance of the constitution), or forcing them into an alliance with the lower classes
(and strengthening popular discontent and disorder), then ‘the essential point was to
attach the middle classes to the aristocratic constitution’. 21 By 1830, even the Tories had
come to accept the principle of Parliamentary reform which did not, however, imply
support for the Bill proposed by the Whigs. ‘Had it been a question of abstract principles,
the ground of difference between Grey’s ministry and the opposition would have been
narrow. It was because the controversy was over detail that room for a full-pitched battle
After more than half a century (1770-1830) of Tory dominance in the House of
Commons, and of latent revolution in England, the Whigs returned to power in 1830. 25
The new Prime Minister Earl Grey immediately set about reforming the electoral system
– a cause with which he had been identified since the 1790s and which was vital if his
ministry was to survive. 26 The Reform Bill 27 took on various forms over the fifteen
months it took to pass through the House of Commons. 28 In the end, the process of
getting the bill through the Commons was more significant than the changes it brought
about, a sentiment reflected by Bright when he described it as ‘not a good Bill, though…a
great Bill when it passed’. 29 On 7 June 1832, King William IV finally gave royal assent to
the Great Reform Act. 30 In order to get it through the House of Lords, the King had
threatened to alter the composition of that House in order to create a majority of
supporters for the Bill (a threat that would be repeated in relation to the removal of the
veto power of the aristocratic House of Lords by the Parliament Act 1911).
In 1832 electoral reform had become a pressing matter for a number of reasons. The
first impact of the Reform Act related to demographics. The electoral system had failed to
keep track of population growth and the electorate had in fact declined as a proportion of
the population from 5.2% in 1715 to 3.2% on the eve of the Reform Act 1832. 31 The
Reform Act increased the size of the electorate by about 41% to 614,654 (about one in
22 Gash 1985, p. 3.
23 Cannon 1973, p. 204.
24 Dicey 1905, p. 31.
25 On the difference between reform-minded European aristocrats and the mission of the specifically
English Whigs, which was ‘to lead the people in their aspirations, to make contact with them, and to give
practicality to their hopes’, see Mitchell in Blanning and Wende 1999, p. 25.
26 Gash in Birke and Kluxen 1985, p. 58.
27 The unofficial title that actually comprised three separate bills for England and Wales, Scotland, and
1992, p. 430.
30 2 Gul. IV, c.45.
31 O’Gorman 1989, p. 179.
seven of the adult male population). The Reform Act thus confirmed and accelerated a
trend that began long before 1832: the English electorate had already grown by 38% from
314,970 in 1820 to 434,530 in 1831. 32 The advance for democracy, however, was limited:
the male electors constituted a smaller proportion of the population than had enjoyed the
vote in 1640. 33 It would be ‘inappropriate’ to treat the Reform Act primarily as an
enfranchising measure; 34 and it would be ‘absurd to treat the electorate as the British
people, the ultimate source of power’. 35
The second impact of the 1832 Act relates to the archaic distribution of seats.
Representation had reflected the pre-modern importance of counties over towns (or
boroughs), and had been largely unchanged since 1675.36 This deprived the enterprising
bourgeoisie in the fast-growing industrialised areas of political influence. Earl Grey
wanted to get rid of the overrepresented ‘rotten’ and ‘pocket’ 37 boroughs and secure
representation for the UK’s new industrial towns and cities. The rotten boroughs were
towns or areas of medieval economic and political importance that had fallen into
economic insignificance whilst retaining their political power. It gave decayed boroughs in
Cornwall (with a couple of hundred inhabitants) the same level of representation (two
MPs) as county constituencies with more than a million. The Suffolk town of Dunwich,
formerly the capital of East Anglia, had practically ceased to exist, having fallen into the
sea over the centuries leaving 32 voters with two MPs. In 1831 the fabled Wiltshire
borough of Old Sarum contained three houses and eleven persons qualified to vote.
Otherwise, it consisted of ‘vast ditches and ramparts and fragments of the foundation
walls of houses and castle. A temporary building was erected under a tree for holding
elections’. 38 All told, sixty rotten boroughs lost their representation entirely, while large
towns (like Manchester, Birmingham, and Leeds) were given two members each.
The Reform Act was neither a revolutionary 44 nor a democratic measure. 45 The
debates at the time focused pragmatically on the defects of the unreformed system
(corruption, high taxation, loss of community) and not on natural rights, popular
sovereignty, fair representation, or the superiority of democracy to oligarchy. The
principal defects of the old system were redressed in a manner that deflected any
impending democratic ambitions. Although the rotten boroughs were eliminated, the
Reform Act also swept away the broadly democratic poor ratepayer ‘scot and lot’
franchise that had existed in some thirty-seven boroughs. In its place, a uniform
qualification was introduced, 46 enfranchising all adult males who owned and/or occupied
houses with a rental value of at least £10 per annum. For a county vote, the basic
qualification remained ownership of a forty-shilling (£2) freehold, but two new, and
wealthier, categories were created: on the one hand, a £10 property qualification that
they were deliberate: ‘A regular distribution of an equal proportion of members to equal population might
be a wise and great scheme, but the proposers of this measure had not thought fit to bring such a plan
before Parliament’ (Hansard, III, 207; cited in Gash 1953, p. 26).
43 Lord Durham: ‘…there is no principle affecting the representative system, that has not property for its
freeman, corporation, scot and lot, burgage, and freeholder. For an explanation of these terms see Cook
2005, p. 57; and in Fisher in Fisher 2009.
served to disenfranchise large numbers of working-class men, and on the other hand, the
£50 tenants-at-will (aka the ‘opulent serfs’) whose relative wealth, coupled with lack of
security of land tenure, made them easy targets for manipulation by landowners. 47 To the
excluded, the Act conveyed a very English social message, namely ‘that personal
fulfilment had come to be associated exclusively with private life, while political systems
were to be judged according to their utility’. 48
So, although it is true that the Reform Act rationalised the electoral machinery and
allowed more people to vote, it was more of the commercial middle class: the prosperous
county electorate increased by about one-third. Everyone below the arbitrary £10 line was
excluded – and the danger that the unrepresented working class could turn against
parliamentary institutions was well known at the time. 49 The government’s response to
that danger was ‘to make aristocratic government acceptable by purging away its most
corrupt and expensive features’. 50 The Reform Act thus created a division not between
Whigs and Tories, but between economic (rural vs. industrial) interests, classes, and also
the sexes. Whereas previously some female property holders had exercised the vote, after
1832 women were expressly forbidden to vote in national elections and, after 1835, in
local elections too. The new constituents were either aristocratic or wealthy and, of
course, educated and male.
‘Our ancestors gave Old Sarum representatives, because it was a large town;
therefore we give representatives to Manchester, which is a large town. I think we
are acting more as our ancestors would have acted, by letting in representatives for
47 See O’Gorman 1989, p. 217: The Reform Act ‘diminished the penetration of the electorate down the
social scale’.
48 Hilton 2006, p. 430.
49 Hilton 2006, p. 433.
50 Brock 1973, p. 44.
our great commercial and manufacturing towns, than by excluding such
representatives’. 51
The political diarist Charles Greville concluded that ‘a Reformed Parliament turns out
to be very much like every other Parliament…except that the Whigs have got possession
of the power which the Tories have lost’. 52
So, what was the significance of the Reform Act within the UK’s constitutional
system? First, it was the first time that any British government had successfully carried out
a major change to the electoral system, which set a crucial precedent for the future
extension of the vote. Second, it bound a larger class of people to the House of
Commons whose role was now explicitly a political tribunal where grievances were aired
and remedied. Third, it neutralised the revolutionary potential of Thomas Paine’s Rights of
Man whose validity after 1815 was assumed and already formed ‘the response of the
whole community’. 53
That left the revolutionary demands of the Chartists which emerged after the 1832 Act.
Why did the British constitution classify their demands (which were not particularly new,
having formed the platform of the Peterloo march twenty years earlier and of the
Levellers two centuries earlier) as radical in the 1830s and 1940s? Essentially, because they
went far beyond what parliamentarians were able to countenance. In fact, five of the Six
Points would not be fulfilled until the 1918 Representation of the People Act, while
annual or even fixed-term parliaments have so far never been realised. 54 The reason
Chartism peaked in the wake of 1832 is because basic ingredients of democracy had been
left out of the reformed system.
The contemporary response to the 1832 Act suggests that it was a conservative, good
housekeeping measure that did little more than tidy up a few rotten boroughs and grant
51 Hansard Parliamentary Debates, 3rd ser. (1830-91), ii. 1085-6 (01 March 1831). Sir Robert Inglis
(Conservative MP) rebutted the connection between representation and population. The reason Old
Sarum had been favoured was not due to its population (which had never been substantial) but due to a
personal favour Edward I had bestowed on the Earl of Salisbury by giving him a right of nomination in
the Commons. ‘Nothing is more certain than that boroughs were created by the mere will of the King,
sometimes at the requisition of a favourite’: Hansard Parliamentary Debates, 3rd ser. (1830-91), ii. 1098, 1103
(01 March 1831); both references in Hilton 2006, p. 431.
52 Cited in Vallance 2009, p. 357.
53 Thompson 1968, p. 660, 663.
54 But see the Fixed-Term Parliaments Bill 2010-11, which, for the first time, fixes the date of the next UK
General Election (at 7 May 2015), and provides for five-year fixed terms.
the right to vote to a limited number of middle class voters. Indeed, ‘…the prevailing
view in 1832 was that the Reform Act was a final settlement based on the 19th-century
concept of representation, not the first instalment of democracy’. 55 The old forms had
not been destroyed: the House of Commons continued to represent property, rather than
people, and it was the property-owning constituency that opposed the reforms. They
feared that the extension of the franchise carried with it a rise in political corruption
through the increase in the number of dependent voters capable of being bought. To
appease the middle classes, the property qualifications for MPs and voters not only
survived but increased – so that neither could be bought. 56 The Great Reform Act was
the least the politicians could do, and all that they were prepared to do.
However, Dicey looks beyond the form and practical consequences of the Reform Act
and points out that it did have one revolutionary quality:
‘It altered the way in which people thought of the constitution, and taught
Englishmen…that venerable institutions which custom had made unchangeable could
easily, and without the use of violence, be changed’. 57
Dicey suggests that the Reform Act inadvertently kick-started the process of
democratisation which it (equally inadvertently) also legitimised: it ‘fostered the conviction
or delusion that the will of the nation could be expressed only through elected
representatives’. 58
Dicey (and Walter Bagehot) saw the real value of the Act as lying in the opinions of the
next generations of law-makers which it helped to shape. 59 The 1832 Act thus destabilised
the constitution by allowing for a counter-narrative (politics driven by popular demand,
the possibility of universal suffrage) to develop alongside the constitutional hegemony (of
the balanced constitution, i.e. the relationship between Crown, Commons and Lords). It
was a cautious first step as well as the point of no return. Sir Robert Peel’s reason for
3. Parliamentary government
The argument of this chapter/section is that by placing government in the House of
Commons, the 1832 Act successfully averted autocracy (oligarchic government) and
democracy (public opinion) – which was precisely what its supporters (e.g. Lords
Melbourne and Holland) had intended 61 – and firmly established ‘Parliamentary
government’ in the United Kingdom. The year 1832 marked, quite possibly, the pinnacle
of Parliament as an institution: ‘The Commons had never been, and would never again
be, so important. The era of court politics was over; that of party politics had not yet
arrived’. 62 In 1832 the old view of class government transitioned to a government based
on the elected representatives of the middle class. The aims of old concepts, like checks
and balances, were now to be achieved by a balance between government and Parliament.
In 1832, a young scholar called John James Park coined the term ‘Parliamentary
government’ to capture the shift away from oligarchic (or prerogative) government. 63
Whether ‘the executive government has merged into the legislative, or the legislative has
merged into the executive’ is a separate question. 64 The fact was that executive and
legislative powers were conjoined, not separated. 65
‘We find that no sooner is an administration formed, than it immediately takes upon
itself not only what is properly called the executive government, but [also] the
60 Peel speaking during the House of Commons debate on the Second Reform Bill, 6 July 1831 (Hansard,
IV, 890).
61 Hawkins 1989, 649.
62 Pemble 2010, p. 34-35. The two-party presence in the Commons developed from about 1807 and took
on clearer contours after 1815. But the parties were not monolithic blocs of MPs. Discipline was loose,
and although the Tory and Whig parties were uniformly against and in favour of Reform, other questions
(Ireland, the church, free trade) divided the parties internally: See generally Fisher 2009.
63 On this point see Hawkins 1989, p. 638-663, 641.
64 Park 1832, p. 41.
65 Park 1832, p. 35: ‘…neither the making of laws,…nor the executing of the laws which are already made,
constitute more than a portion of the functions of political power. Parliament, if we watch its operations,
will be found very frequently engaged in functions which are not legislative; and the administration will be
found engaged, still more frequently, upon functions which are not executive’.
management, control, and direction, of the whole mass of political legislation,
according to its own views of political science and civil economy’. 66
In this new system, the House of Commons was an autonomous arena from which the
executive, as organised in the Cabinet, drew its authority. To function properly, executive
authority needed to be insulated from two powerful rival sources – the monarchy and the
people. In fact, the Crown’s attempt to control Parliament proved more and more
unsuccessful. To illustrate, in the autumn of 1834, William IV dismissed Lord
Melbourne’s Cabinet. That act was viewed by some Whigs as the exercise of the
tyrannical prerogative and an abuse of executive discretion. But the exercise of the King’s
powers was ultimately ineffective as Melbourne resumed the premiership merely a year
later. In other words, the Crown’s loss of power after the 1832 Act was a further aspect
of the political conditions that would (much later) pave the path for democracy: political
power had shifted from the Crown to the Commons (as analysed by J.J. Park). 67
The other problem, and the central one from that point onwards, was how to protect
parliamentary government from electoral dictate. How could the aristocracy remain in
power and be voted for by the middle classes? Which proposals for reform would be able
to reconcile the old restricted interests with the demands by the masses of new voters?
The answer, once again, was ‘Parliamentary government’ which accommodated the
development of political parties from the middle of the nineteenth century with relative
ease. Peel may have shown disdain for party organisation, but after his accidental death in
1850 the chances of the executive operating outside the party structure were drastically
reduced. ‘Peel’s death made possible the near-unanimous acceptance within Westminster
of parliamentary parties as the necessary and desirable source of executive authority’. 68
Peel’s successor, Lord Derby, linked the Conservative leadership as well as executive
authority to party support. The legitimacy of parties was concluded with the formation of
the Victorian Liberal Party in 1859, 69 and the form of Parliamentary government was
finalised with the acceptance of a new generation of politicians who had grown up under
the post-1832 system.
receive the sanction of popular consent, though it does not necessarily emanate from the will of the
people’.
74 Grey 1864, p. 49.
75 May 1863, p. ii, 1.
advantage of an irregular representative system. The notion of Parliamentary government
had clearly established itself as the centre of the political system: ‘The whole life of
English politics is the action and reaction between the ministry and the Parliament’. 76
Parliamentary government was workable in 1832, when parties had been parliamentary
groupings with some organisation inside Parliament. By the second half of the nineteenth
century, the Conservative and Liberal parties had become national, extra-Parliamentary,
autonomous institutions with mass membership, centralised bureaucracies, a relatively
homogeneous ideology, and independent candidates who were in charge of their own
campaigns. The groundwork for a two-party system had been laid. The foundations of
Parliamentary government that Park described in 1832, and which were supposedly
affirmed by the 1867 Act, were actually being undercut by the dominance of ‘party’ and
‘cabinet government’. At the same time, Erskine May and Bagehot were still claiming that
Parliament effectively controlled the executive. Parliament had been caught unawares:
‘No statute, no rule of common law, no resolution even of either House of Parliament
has yet recognised the Cabinet itself. The real organ of executive government under
our present system is a body yet unknown to the law’. 77
But if it was true that the House of Commons provided the prime political forum in
the country, then the arguments for franchise extension threatened to create a tyrannical
democracy by undermining the constitutional character and importance of the Commons.
And this was precisely Bagehot’s argument: without the checks and balances of the
eighteenth century balanced constitution, i.e. by the monarchy and aristocracy which the
Reform Act 1832 had relegated to ‘the dignified parts’ of the constitution, whichever
party controlled the Commons had absolute power.
The potted history of the 1867 Act has been told and re-told. Victory of the Union
over the Confederate States in the American Civil War demonstrated the viability of
democracy and strengthened the calls for reform. Lord Palmerston’s death in 1865
deprived the Liberal party of a unifying presence and breathed new life into the
Conservative party. It also removed an obstacle to further reform. Lord John Russell,
briefly the Prime Minister, introduced the Reform Bill in 1866. William Gladstone (1809-
1898), as Chancellor of the Exchequer, thought it would be prudent to widen the
franchise so that ‘every man who is not presumably incapacitated by some consideration
of personal unfitness or of political danger is morally entitled to come within the pale of
79 Herrick 1934, p. 216-233, 220: ‘…the nature of the bill itself shows little relation to the democratic idea
if the realities of power are considered as well as the mere act of voting’.
80 ‘The movement’s failures lay in the direction of securing legislation…Judged by its crop of statues,
Chartism was a failure. Judged by its essential…purpose, Chartism was a success. It achieved not the Six
Points, but a state of mind’: Ward 1973, p. 245.
81 Stapleton 1850; One of the Middle Class 1854; Bagehot 1859; The Danger of Democratic Reaction, and
suggestions for placing the franchise in a sound & defensible state while still possible 1864. Euclid 1866. Pochin 1866;
An Elector 1866; Cole 1866; Moncrieff 1867. A Reformer 1867.
the constitution’. 82 But the Bill split the Liberal Party: on the one hand, forty dissenting
Liberals, led by Robert Lowe and referred to by John Bright as the ‘Cave of Adullam’,
voted with the Tories and were supported by The Times; on the other hand, the pro-
reform wing was supported by radicals and reformers. The Tories had registered an
important success: the Liberal government was divided, Gladstone had been denied a
triumph, and Lord Russell had to resign. Lord Derby became Prime Minister, leading a
minority Conservative government, with Benjamin Disraeli (1804-1881) leader of the
Commons. The Adullamites were still anti-reform, but refused to buttress a Conservative
government.
Conservatives had few incentives to retain the 1832 settlement which had given them
only one majority government in thirty-five years. Disraeli argued that the Conservatives
were in danger of being seen as an anti-reform party. They had discussed the idea of
franchise extension, which made sense as a political strategy as it gave them control over
the reform process, attracted radical support, and did not injure Conservative interests. 83
Disraeli himself had introduced a bill in minority office in 1859. But how could an
unpopular leader of a minority government pass a reform bill in the Commons, having
blocked a Liberal Reform Bill only months earlier?
Within those months, the political climate had changed just enough for Disraeli’s
measure to gain political traction. At the conservative-reactionary end of the Liberal
spectrum, the Adullamites had split and ceased to be a reference point for the dissenting
voice. On the other side, the radicals had also split. John Stuart Mill’s entry into
Parliament in 1865 had provided a focal point for younger radicals. But William
Gladstone’s principled conversion to reform made him dependent on Conservative
support. Disraeli capitalised on this situation with remarkable skill, but also with
opportunism and courage.
It was opportunistic because one might easily suspect that Disraeli and the
Conservatives pursued radical suffrage reform out of political expediency or fear of public
82 3 Hansard Vol. 185, cols. 324-5, 11 May 1864. The phrase ‘within the pale of the constitution’ stems
from mediaeval Ireland that evoked images of the electorate as civilised settlers surrounded by savages
without. Gladstone’s bill excluded unskilled workers and what was known as the ‘residuum’, i.e. the
feckless and criminal poor.
83 By February 1867, when the question of household suffrage was formally introduced for the first time, a
But the measure was also courageous because without a working majority in the
Commons, Disraeli had to offer political concessions to Liberal backbenchers that were
unpalatable for members of his own party (in short, ‘wise concessions to enlightened
agitation’ 87). Lord Cranborne resigned in protest against what he perceived as a dramatic
extension of democracy. Conservative MPs decided to back reform if their own leaders
introduced it. Disraeli and Derby introduced a Reform Bill in February 1867. Derby’s
reputation and support from the Queen saw it through the Lords, and it became law in
June 1867. It was, in Derby’s words, ‘a leap in the dark’.
The point of this historical summary is to show that the reason the Reform Bill 1867
was enacted was not to advance democracy in any fundamental sense. The debates on the
Reform Bill were about the technicalities of householder franchise, 88 not about the merits
of democracy. Nor was the Reform Bill a direct response to the demands of the people,
but a Conservative measure. It was supported by the Times and opposed by the reformer
John Bright, and as such made no sense at all to most people. ‘Many Radical members
who had been asking for years for household suffrage were much more surprised than
pleased at the near chance of obtaining it; they had asked for it as bargainers ask for the
highest possible price, but they never expected to get it’. 89
favoured the £7 franchise so that the urban male working-class householders remained a minority of the
electorate. The £7 electors (but crucially not those below that threshold) were hailed as ‘our fellow
subjects, our fellow-Christians, and kin of flesh and blood’: 3 Hansard, 182: 873 (23 March 1866).
89 Bagehot 1872, p. xvi-xviii.
There is no unanimity in the literature as to whether the strength of the popular
movement on the streets coerced Disraeli into bringing about electoral reform. The end
of 1866 and the start of 1867 saw a preoccupation with political violence, which was
being discussed openly. Huge demonstrations were planned in Hyde Park on 23 July. The
government banned the meeting, but the order was disregarded and the police failed to
stop the demonstration. Technically, these demonstrations were more about the right of
assembly than about the right to vote. 90 Symbolically, however, the riots signified to the
governing elite the threatening power of the working men’s movement. 91 John Morley
attributes the ‘strange reversal’ leading up to the Act to the popular agitations and change
in public opinion. 92 Joseph H. Park thinks that the large, frequent and peaceful
demonstrations by the Reform League might have turned violent in the absence of
reform, and so public opinion indirectly did force Parliament to enact the Reform Bill. 93
However, Francis H. Herrick points out that reform was not a political issue in the
1865 election. On the Reform League, which had been founded in February 1865 and
spoke for the skilled working class, he asserts that not only was it ‘no more significant
than the meetings and societies to promote education, world peace, or economy in
government’, but also that the final Reform Bill bore little relation to its demands. 94
Instead, the Reform bill was the outcome of party competition: Disraeli’s minority
government was dependent on the Radicals. Herrick belittles the effect of public opinion
and popular agitations: ‘Why should a demonstration on July 23, 1866, which only
damaged an old fence and some shrubbery, 95 have much effect on parliament when it
assembled in February, 1867, to hear Disraeli’s Reform Bill? There is absolutely no
evidence that…the popular leaders even considered the use of violence, as was most
certainly done by Reformers in 1832’. 96 Gash attributes public indifference in the 1850s
and 1860s to a number of factors: the failure of Chartism, the social and economic
reforms of the 1830s and 1840s, the growing prosperity of Victorian society, and the
paperback edition of Bagehot 2001. It confirms damage to the fence and the flowerbeds. Another Reform
league meeting in 1867 took place quietly without damage to a single flowerbed, the railings or policemen.
96 Herrick 1934, p. 223; see also the account of the Hyde Park incident in Park 1920, p. 102-104.
increasing importance of the trade unions to the working class leaders. 97 Withdrawing the
Reform Bill of 1860, Lord John Russell said: ‘The apathy of this country is undeniable.
Nor is it a transient humour; it seems rather a confirmed habit of mind’. 98 This condition
can be attributed either to satisfaction (as late as January 1867 Bagehot was able to write:
‘The mass of the English people are politically contented as well as politically
deferential’ 99) or inebriation:
Second, the Act incorporated the ‘fancy franchises’ (special franchises for holders of
university degrees and bank depositors of over £50) to placate reactionary Tories. Their
presence harked back to the old system before 1832, except that the advantages
previously secured through corruption were now legalised and institutionalised. Instead of
reforming the franchise along fair and equitable principles, the pattern was deliberately
‘lopsided, typically English’, 108 emblematic of:
Writing in the Economist on 24 December 1864, Bagehot had recognised the need for
‘some new plan, some additional experiment, some uncommon conception’ – not to
bring about, but to prevent the emergence of democracy, i.e. ‘a worse America, in which
the lower classes are equally despotic, but are not equally intelligent. We must choose
between anomaly and democracy. There is no third alternative’. 110 From this perspective, the
asymmetric electoral system of the Reform Act 1867 (although Bagehot rejected it) was a
near-perfect solution, and not a defect. 111 Populist democracy had been abated: ‘The
element of conservatism in both of the chief parties maintained its position and found
published in 1842).
110 Reprinted as ‘Appendix on Reform’ in Bagehot 2001, p. 201.
111 See also Grey 1864, p.61: ‘…the success with which [the House of Commons] has been able to take so
active a part in the government of the Country, and its peculiar excellencies, are to be attributed, quite as
much as some of its faults, to what are regarded as defects and departures from principle in our
Representative system;’ and ‘…it is chiefly by means of these defects that the Ministers of the Crown have
enabled to obtain the authority they have exercised in the House of Commons’.
support in many characteristics of the electoral system, which were all to the disadvantage
of democracy’. 112
In sum, the ruling classes had successfully fought to defend and maintain their
supremacy in Parliament. The hierarchy of the political order had been kept intact, with
the monarch at the head, performing the functions of the sovereign in public. Using the
tried and tested procedure of 1832, the political impulses from below had been harnessed
within the existing institutional framework, thus uniting previously antagonistic classes
and binding them to the existing institutions: ‘…the politics of the excluded began to
become the politics of the included’. 113 Parliamentary government (as the form of
government) and the House of Commons (as the representative body of the nation) had
again claimed the political middle ground by providing the form and procedure for
resolving political disputes. Who needs a revolution when the same results can be
achieved by a political majority in a sovereign Parliament? Social and political reform had
become politically acceptable to such an extent that it even seemed possible to start
talking about creating a community or a nation ‘instead of a number of mutually exclusive
classes’, and a ‘national conception of politics, and a national government’. 114
The constitutional settlement (never entirely clear or fixed in the first place) was
simultaneously affirmed and undermined in 1867. 1867 upheld the system of
Parliamentary government that had begun in 1832. The suffrage, government, and
administrative reforms did not explicitly and fundamentally alter the legal conception of
the constitution. A third wave of reform between 1883 and 1885 rationalised the electoral
system which became uniform in England and Wales, Scotland, and Ireland: instead of
returning two or three MPs, henceforth the normal pattern was one. With the third
Reform Act in 1884 Gladstone extended the borough franchise to counties so that male
householders could vote whether they lived in town or country. In short, the UK
gradually acquired ‘the main features of the twentieth-century electoral system’. 115
But 1867 also destabilised the constitution. The imbalanced electoral system fuelled the
democratic counter-narrative (politics driven by popular demand, the possibility of
Conclusion:
The late-Victorian constitution is a synthesis of ‘two different but complementary
forms of possessive individualism – the oligarchic whiggery of the seventeenth century
and the democratic radicalism of the nineteenth’. 119 The royal absolutism of the Stuarts
had transformed into Parliamentary absolutism, and the Radicals’ demands (framed in
Thomas Paine’s rhetoric of natural rights and constitutionalism, and by the Chartists) had
been defused when Peel’s administration introduced social and economic reforms (and
ignored the demands for constitutional reform). 120
‘…no legislator, at any period of the world, has willingly placed the seat of active
power in the hands of the multitude: Because there it admits of no control, no
regulation, no steady direction whatsoever. The people are the natural control on
authority; but to exercise and to control together is contradictory and impossible’. 125
The actuality of the idea and practice of Parliamentary government had been overtaken
by the expansion of the electorate and the greater equality of constituencies, which
removed some of the anomalies cherished by Grey. In 1866, a reviewer of Earl Grey’s
book captured the shortcomings of Parliamentary government when he wrote of the
dangers of a weak government being elected by the ‘ignorant multitude’: 126
‘America during the last five years has only repeated to the world the lesson that
had already been taught in France, that, if you will have democracy, you must have
something like Cæsarism to control it. The feeble and pliable Executive of
England is wholly unsuited to such an electoral body. A Government that yields
and must yield to the slightest wish of the House of Commons, is only possible so
long as that House of Commons is the organ of an educated minority. Such an
instrument of Government has never yet in the history of the world been worked
by a Legislature chosen by the lower class.’ 127
‘Parliament under the progress of democracy became the representative, not of the
middle classes, but of the whole body of householders; parliamentary sovereignty,
therefore, came to mean…the unrestricted power of the wage-earners’. 130
Universal adult suffrage established itself as a basic requirement of democracy only after
1918. It is obviously a necessary condition of democracy, but maybe less obviously it is
not a sufficient one. By privileging the House of Commons, the political system
transforms (revolutionary) popular sovereignty into (institutional) Parliamentary
sovereignty, whilst simultaneously creating a political power hub that has been described
as uncontrolled and despotic. The upshot is that the UK continues to enjoy a special
variant of ‘democracy by consent and not by delegation, of government of the people, for
the people, with, but not by the people’. 131
An Elector. 1866. A Letter to the Rt. Hon. Earl Russell on an Extension of the Franchise
to the Intellectual and Industrious Classes, in a Constitutional and practical manner.
London.
Bagehot, Walter. [1867] 2001. The English Constitution. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Bagehot, Walter. 1872. Introduction to the Second Edition. London : H.S. King.
Blake, Robert. 1985. “The Development of the British Parliamentary System 1861-1901”.
In: Birke, Adolf M. and Kluxen, Kurt (Eds.). British and German Parliamentarism.
München: K.G. Saur.
Bradley, Anthony Wilfred and Ewing, Keith. 2011. Constitutional and Administrative
Law 15th Edition. Harlow: Pearson.
Burke, Edmund. 1791. An Appeal from the New to the Old Whigs. London: J. Dodsley.
Butterfield, Sir Herbert. 1931. Whig Interpretation Of History. London: G. Bell & Sons.
Cole, Henry Warwick. 1866. The Middle Classes and the Borough Franchise. London:
Longmans, Green, Reader & Dyer .
Cook, Chris. 2005. Britain in the Nineteenth Century, 1815-1914. London: Routledge.
Cowling, Maurice. 1967. 1867, Disraeli, Gladstone and Revolution: the Passing of the
Second Reform Bill. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dicey, Albert Venn. [1885] 1959. Introduction to the Study of the Law of the
Constitution, 10th Edition. London: Macmillan.
Dicey, Albert Venn. 1905. Lectures on the Relation between Law and Public Opinion in
England During the Nineteenth Century. London: Macmillan.
Dicey, Albert Venn. 1914. Lectures on the Relation between Law and Public Opinion in
England During the Nineteenth Century, 2nd Edition. London: Macmillan.
Dinwiddy, John Rowland. 1992. Radicalism and Reform in Britain, 1780-1850. London:
Hambledon Press.
Euclid, Political. 1866. The Reform Problem; its True Solution. London.
Fletcher, Ian C. 1997. “This Zeal for Lawlessness”: Dicey, Albert Venn. The Law of the
Constitution, and the Challenge of Popular Politics, 1885-1915. Parliamentary History
16(3), p. 309-329, 329.
Foley, Michael. 1999. The Politics of the British Constitution. Manchester: Manchester
University Press.
Gash, Norman. 1985. ‘The Social and Political Background to the Three British
Nineteenth Century Reform Acts”.
In: Birke, Adolf M. and Kluxen, Kurt (Eds.). British and German Parliamentarism.
München: K.G. Saur.
Gash, Norman. 1953. Politics in the Age of Peel: A study in the Technique of
Parliamentary Representation 1830-1850. London: Longmans Green.
Gillespie, Frances Elma. 1927. Labor and Politics in England, 1850-1867. Durham, North
Carolina: Duke University Press.
Grey, Earl. 1864. Parliamentary Government Considered With Reference to Reform, 2nd
Edition. London: John Murray.
Hall, Catherine. et al (Eds.). 2000. Defining the Victorian Nation, Class, Race, Gender
and the British Reform Act of 1867. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hawkins, Angus. 1987. Parliament, Party and the Art of Politics in Britain, 1855-59.
London: Macmillan.
Hearn, William Edward. 1867. Government of England: Its Structure and its
Development. London: Melbourne.
Hearn, William Edward. 1887. Government of England: Its Structure and its
Development, 2nd Edition. London: Longmans, Green, and co.
Herrick, Francis H. 1934. “The Reform Bill of 1867 and the British Party System”. In:
Pacific Historical Review 3(2), p. 216-233, 220.
Hewart, Lord. 1929. The New Despotism. London: Ernest Benn Limited.
Hilton, Boyd. 2006. A Mad, Bad, and Dangerous People? England 1783-1846. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Himmelfarb, Gertrude. 1966. “The Politics of Democracy: The English Reform Act of
1867”. In: The Journal of British Studies 6(1), p. 97-138.
Hirst, Derek. 1975. The Representatives of the People? Voters and Voting in England
under the Early Stuarts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Horwitz, Morton J. 1997. “Why is Anglo-American Jurisprudence Unhistorical?”. In:
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 17, 551-586, 568.
Jones, Gareth Stedman. 1983. Languages of Class: Studies in English Working Class
History 1832-1982. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lecky, William Edward Hartpole. 1896. Democracy and Liberty. London: Longmans.
Lizzeri, Alessandro and Persico, Nicola. 2004. “Why did the Elites Extend the Suffrage?
Democracy and the Scope of Government, with an Application to Britain’s ‘Age of
Reform’”. In: The Quarterly Journal of Economics 119(2), p. 707-765.
Loveland, Ian. 2009. Constitutional Law, Administrative Law, and Human Rights. 5th
Edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Maine, Henry James Sumner. 1885. Popular Government. London: John Murray.
Marquand, David. 1988. The Unprincipled Society: New Demands and Old Politics.
London: Fontana.
Martin, John Biddulph. 1884. “Electoral Statistics: A Review of the Working of our
Representative System from 1832-1881”. In: Journal of the Statistical Society of London
47(1), p. 75-124.
May, Thomas Erskine. 1863. The Constitutional History of England Since the Accession
of George III, 1760-1860, 3 vols. London: Longman.
McClelland, Keith. 1996. “Rational and Respectable Men: Gender, the Working Class and
Citizenship in Britain, 1850-1867”.
In: Frader, Laura L. and Rose, Sonya (Eds.). Gender and Reconstruction of Working
Class History in Modern Europe. Ithaca, Cornell University Press.
Mitchell, John David Bawden. 1965. “The Causes and Effects of the Absence of a System
of Public Law in the United Kingdom”. In: Public Law 95-118.
Mitchell, John David Bawden. 1960. “The Flexible Constitution”. In: Public Law 332-350.
Morley, Jon. 1867. “Young England and the Political Future”. In: Fortnightly Review I, p.
496.
Morley, Jon. 1903. The Life of William Ewart Gladstone, Vol. II. New York: Macmillan.
Newbould, Ian. 1976. “William IV and the Dismissal of the Whigs, 1834”. In: Canadian
Journal of History xi, p. 311-330.
O’Gorman, Frank. 1989. Voters, Patrons and Parties: The Unreformed Electoral System
of Hanoverian England 1734-1832. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
One of the Middle Class, 1854. A Few Practical Suggestions on Electoral Reform and the
Ballot. London.
Park, John James. 1832. The Dogmas of the Constitution. London: B. Fellowes.
Park, Joseph Hendershot. 1920. The English Reform Bill of 1867. London: P.S. King.
Pemble, John. 2010. “High Taxes, Hard Times”. In: London Review of Books 32(11), p.
34-35.
Philbin, J. Holladay. 1965. Parliamentary Representation, 1832, England and Wales. New
Haven: Carl Purington Rollins.
Pugh, Martin. 2002. The Making of Modern British Politics, 1867-1945. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Rendall, Jane. 2000. “The Citizenship of Women and the Reform Act of 1867”.
In: Hall, Catherine et al (Eds.). Defining the Victorian Nation, Class, Race, Gender and
the British Reform Act of 1867. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, chp. 3., p. 135-
136.
Rogers, James Edwin Thorold (Ed.). 1879. Public Address by John Bright. London:
Macmillan.
Rush, Michael. 1981. Parliamentary Government in Britain. New York: Holmes & Meier
Publishers.
Seymour, Charles. 1915. Electoral Reform in England and Wales. New Haven: Yale
University Press.
Stapleton, Augustus Granville. 1850. Suggestions for a Conservative and Popular Reform
in the Commons House of Parliament. London.
Stevens, Robert. 2005. The English Judges: Their Role in the Constitution. Oxford: Hart.
Thompson, Edward Palmer. 1968. The Making of the English Working Class. London:
Penguin.
Vallance, Edward. 2009. A Radical History of Britain. London: Little, Brown and
Company.
Vile, Maurice J.C. 1998. Constitutionalism and the Separation of Powers. 2nd Edition.
Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.
Walpole, Spencer. 1889. The Life of Lord John Russell, Vol. II. London: Longmans,
Green.
Ward, John Towers. 1973. Chartism. New York: Barnes and Noble.
Wicks, Elizabeth. 2006. The Evolution of a Constitution: Eight Key Moments in British
Constitutional History. Oxford: Hart.
Williams, Glyn and Ramsden, John. 1990. Ruling Britannia: A Political History of Britain,
1688-1988. London: Longman.