Justice Pius Langa
Justice Pius Langa
Justice Pius Langa
Introduction
Both the Constitutional Court2 and other courts3 view the
Constitution as transformative. The previous Chief Justice has
written that a ‘commitment ... to transform our society...lies at the
heart of the new constitutional order.’4 It is clear that the notion of
transformation has played and will play a vital role in interpreting
the Constitution. The main purpose of this address is to determine
what barriers exist to the achievement of that transformation.
1
accepted definition. The current Deputy Chief Justice has said in
this regard: ‘the meaning of transformation in juridicial terms is as
highly contested as it is difficult to formulate.’5 It is perhaps in
keeping with the spirit of transformation that there is no single
stable understanding of transformative constitutionalism.
Firstly, the new society is one based on substantive equality. unequal shall be
Writing in the South African Journal of Human Rights in 1998, treated unequally
Albertyn and Goldblatt make the point that the movement from the
one side of this bridge to the other will
5 D Moseneke ‘The Fourth Bram Fischer Memorial Lecture: Transformative Adjudication’ (2002) 18 SAJHR 309 at
315.
6 Constitution of the Republic of South Africa Act 200 of 1993.
2
opportunities which allow people to realise their full
human potential within positive social relationships.7
7 C Albertyn & B Goldblatt ‘Facing the Challenge of Transformation: Difficulties in the Development of an
Indigenous Jurisprudence of Equality’ (1998) 14 SAJHR 248 at 249.
8 Soobramoney (supra n 2) at para 8.
9 See City of Johannesburg (supra n 2) at paras 51-52.
10 See Van Rooyen and Others v S and Others 2002 (8) BCLR 810 (CC) at para 50 (Chaskalson CJ)(‘[T]ransformation
involves not only changes in the legal order, but also changes in the composition of the institutions of society, which
prior to 1994 where largely under the control of whites and, in particular, white men.’); Minister of Finance and Another
v Van Heerden 2004 (11) BCLR 1125 (CC) at para 142 (Sachs J)(‘The substantive approach [to equality], on the other
hand, requires that the test for constitutionality is not whether the measure concerned treats all affected by it in
identical fashion. Rather it focuses on whether it serves to advance or retard the equal enjoyment in practice of the
rights and freedoms that are promised by the Constitution but have not already been achieved. It roots itself in a
transformative constitutional philosophy which acknowledges that there are patterns of systemic advantage and
disadvantage based on race and gender that need expressly to be faced up to and overcome if equality is to be
achieved. In this respect, the context in which the measure operates, the structures of advantage and disadvantage it
deals with, the impact it has on those affected by it and its overall effect in helping to achieve a society based on
equality, non-racialism and non-sexism, become the important signifiers.)
3
It was Ettienne Mureinik who pointed out that the true shift from
apartheid to post-apartheid South Africa is a move from ‘a culture of
authority’ to
11 E Mureinik ‘A Bridge to Where? Introducing the Interim Bill of Rights’ (1994) 10 SAJHR 31 at 32.
12 Moseneke (supra n 4) at 317.
4
critical scholars have offered a third conception that builds on, but
also goes beyond the first two.13 For them, the traditional metaphor
of a bridge is misleading as it seems to suggest that transformation
is a temporary event, that at some point we will reach the other side
of the bridge. Transformation then ends because we have reached
our desired destination. According to Andre van der Walt, ‘[i]n this Change itself
vision of transformation there is no longer room for imagining that can change
things could be different, that there might be further options and
more complex alternatives to the two places between which we
have chosen to choose.’14 What is contended is that we should
instead view the bridge of the interim Constitution as a space
between an unstable past and an uncertain future. There is no
preference for one side over the other, rather, the value of the bridge
lies in remaining on it, crossing it over and over to remember,
change and imagine new and better ways of being.
13 See for example H Botha ‘Metaphoric Reasoning and Transformative Constitutionalism (Part 1)’ (2002) TSAR
612; H Botha ‘Metaphoric Reasoning and Transformative Constitutionalism (Part 2)’ (2003) TSAR 20; W le Roux
‘Bridges, Clearings and Labyrinths: The Architectural Framing of Post-Apartheid Constitutionalism’ (2004) 19 SAPL
629; J van der Walt Law and Sacrifice (2005)
14 A van der Walt ‘Dancing with Codes – Protecting, Developing and Deconstructing Property Rights in a
Constitutional State’ (2001) 118 SALJ 258 at 296.
5
as a means to arrive at a destination. What Van der Walt is telling us
is that we should promote and sustain transformation itself, rather
than view it merely as a means to construct a new society.
Challenges
Let me now, finally, turn to the main theme of this address: the
challenges facing transformative constitutionalism in South Africa.
Many of the challenges are inter-related. Taken together they
create a substantial impediment to the realisation of our
constitutional dream. My list is by no means conclusive. There are
many others and many more that will arise only in the future.
However, these are to my mind the most pressing obstacles at the
moment.
6
chain, not only police, but lawyers, prosecutors, judges
and prison officers, as well as many issues beyond the
criminal justice system. But a “one-size-fits-all” does
not work.15
South Africa has its own unique problems when it comes to access
to justice. In the face of high levels of crime, the criminal justice
system faces a serious challenge to ensure that victims have the
satisfaction of knowing that those who harmed them or their loved
ones are brought to justice. Legal representation remains beyond
the financial reach of many South Africans and it is true that more
money ensures better representation. That is not equal access to
justice and the challenge we face is what strategies we should
adopt to rectify the position. The Constitution should not become a
tool of the rich. Equal justice means that the fruits of justice are
there for all to enjoy. The provision of equal access to justice is
therefore a priority in reaching our transformative goal.
Legal education
The next challenge I see to transformation is in the sphere of legal
education. The way we teach law students and the values and
philosophies we instil in them will define the legal landscape of the
future. Most of us here today are familiar with a traditional legal
education that focuses predominantly on private and commercial
law and rewards the rational deduction of inevitable conclusions
from unquestionable principles. That is how we were taught and it
is a vital part of any lawyer’s arsenal. We would be failing in our
duty to both the students and the public if we did not pass on the
tradition of analytical argument and a full knowledge of the legal
principles that govern everyday human interaction and form the
main part of a lawyers work.
7
at the very heart of legal education. It requires that we regard law
as part of the social fabric and teach law students to see it as such.
They should see law for what it is, as an instrument that was used
to oppress in the past, but that has that immense power and
capacity to transform our society.
Much has been done to bring legal education in line with these
ideals. Constitutional and human rights law now form a much
greater part of the curriculum and the vast majority of courses and
text-books on traditional private or commercial areas devote
sections to the impact of the Constitution on that field of law.
However, we must be careful that the influence of the Constitution
does not become simply another set of cast-in-stone legal principles.
The change to legal education is a change in mind-set, not simply a
change in laws.
Legal Culture
But what of the existing legal community that has already received
their legal education and training? In his article ‘Legal Culture and
Transformative Constitutionalism’, Karl Klare highlights what he
terms the inherent conservatism of South African legal culture and
he compares it with what he believes it should be.16 ‘Conservatism’
in this context applies to a jurisprudential approach, not a political
outlook. When he talks about ‘legal culture’, Klare is referring to
‘the professional sensibilities, habits of mind and intellectual
reflexes’ of lawyers or those ingrained ideas about how the law
works and what arguments are and are not convincing. Our
recourse to this culture is often subconscious as it is such a basic
part of how we approach legal problems.
8
culture18 and argue that it is still based on formal rather than
substantive legal reasoning.19 This formal reasoning prevents an
inquiry into the true motivation for certain decisions and presents
the law as neutral and objective when in reality it expresses a
particular politics and enforces a singular conception of society.
Johan Froneman refers to this as a ‘delusional danger’ and states
that it has not been wiped away by the advent of the new
Constitution. The Constitution, like any law can be interpreted
formally and thus allow judges to avoid engagement with substance
and evade the search for justice.
Let me however make two important caveats. First, not all South
African lawyers are guilty of the conservatism and formalism they
seem to be accused of. Indeed, much of the resistance to apartheid
was built on the idea that, to be enforceable, laws must be
substantively just. That spirit still inspires many lawyers and judges
and they continue to play an incredibly invaluable part in taking us
forward in constitutional interpretation. Secondly, there is much to
be said for sticking to the rules when they are clear and good. It is
when adherence to the word is taken too far, when the upholding of
a law obscures or ignores that law exists to try, however difficult, to
ensure justice, that formalism becomes dangerous.
18 See for example H Botha ‘Freedom and Constraint in Constitutional Adjudication’ (2004) 20 SAJHR 249; A van
der Walt ‘Tradition on Trial: A Critical Analysis of the Civil-Law Tradition in South African Property Law’ (1995) 11
SAJHR 169;
19 J Froneman ‘Legal Reasoning and Legal Culture: Our “Vision of Law”’ (2005) 16 Stell LR 1.
20 Mistry v Interim National Medical and Dental Council of South Africa and Others 1998 (7) BCLR 880 (CC) at para 49.
9
idea of the separation of powers. The Constitution itself entrenches
the notion of different roles for the different arms of government: the
legislature makes the law, the judiciary interprets the law and the
executive enforces the law. Were the Courts to completely discard
any adherence to the text they would enter squarely into the domain
of the legislature as creators rather than interpreters of the law.
That is clearly not what the Constitution envisages.
That is what the late Chief Justice Mahomed had in mind when he
wrote that if certain steps are not taken,
10
to the future with heavy and dragged steps, delaying
and impeding a rapid and enthusiastic transition to the
new society at the end of the bridge’.21
21 Azanian Peoples Organisation (AZAPO) & Others v President of the Republic of South Africa & Others 1996 (4) SA 671
(CC) at para 18.
11
‘Where the focus is on perpetrators, victims are
necessarily defined as the minority of political
activists; for the victimhood of the majority to be
recognized, the focus has to shift from perpetrators to
beneficiaries. The difference is this: whereas the focus
on perpetrators fuels the demand for justice as criminal
justice, that on beneficiaries would shift focus to a
notion of justice as social justice. … A focus on power
that links power to privilege links perpetrator to
beneficiary, racialized power to racialized privilege, and
puts at center-stage the relationship between
beneficiary and victim as the majority. To recognize
this difference is, I think, key to thinking through how
to make the reconciliation durable.22
Conclusion
These then are the challenges that I see facing transformative
constitutionalism: legal education, legal culture, maintaining the
22 Mahmood Mamdani When Does Reconciliation Turn into a Denial of Justice? (1998) at 14.
12
separation of powers while ensuring that all arms of government
work together and reconciliation. Can we overcome these
dilemmas? I do not know. But I take solace in the idea that perhaps
rather than obstacles, these factors can be viewed as enabling
conditions for transformation. For as long as they exist there will be
a drive to overcome them, there will be a tension that keeps alive
the idea that things can be different. When all the challenges are
gone, that is when the real danger arises. That is when we slip into
a useless self-congratulatory complacency, a misplaced euphoria
that where we are now is the only place to be. That is when we stop
dreaming, imagining and planning that things could be different,
could be better. That, for me, is the true challenge of
transformation.
I thank you.
13