Full Ebook of Critical Theory and Psychoanalysis From The Frankfurt School To Contemporary Critique 1St Edition Jon Mills Online PDF All Chapter
Full Ebook of Critical Theory and Psychoanalysis From The Frankfurt School To Contemporary Critique 1St Edition Jon Mills Online PDF All Chapter
Full Ebook of Critical Theory and Psychoanalysis From The Frankfurt School To Contemporary Critique 1St Edition Jon Mills Online PDF All Chapter
https://ebookmeta.com/product/critical-theory-and-feeling-the-
affective-politics-of-the-early-frankfurt-school-1st-edition-
simon-mussell/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/critique-as-social-practice-
critical-theory-and-social-self-understanding-1st-edition-robin-
celikates/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/enriching-psychoanalysis-
integrating-concepts-from-contemporary-science-and-
philosophy-1st-edition-john-turtz/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/diffractive-reading-new-
materialism-theory-critique-new-critical-humanities-2nd-edition-
shelley-rigger/
Social Theory Classical and Contemporary A Critical
Perspective 1st Edition Berch Berberoglu
https://ebookmeta.com/product/social-theory-classical-and-
contemporary-a-critical-perspective-1st-edition-berch-berberoglu/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/critical-theory-and-economics-
philosophical-notes-on-contemporary-inequality-1st-edition-robin-
maialeh/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/the-populist-century-history-
theory-critique-1st-edition-pierre-rosanvallon/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/the-routledge-companion-to-
critical-approaches-to-contemporary-architecture-1st-edition-
swati-chattopadhyay/
https://ebookmeta.com/product/contemporary-sculpture-and-the-
critique-of-display-cultures-tainted-goods-1st-edition-dan-adler/
‘This remarkably well-curated book offers us tremendous insight into the
horrors of our planet, ranging from authoritarianism and anti-Semitism
to racism and colonialism. The esteemed editors and contributors have
provided us with much depth-psychological wisdom and have reminded
us of the importance of studying the core concepts of critical theory and
psychoanalysis. Every politician should read this text!’
Professor Brett Kahr, Senior Fellow, Tavistock Institute
of Medical Psychology, London, and Honorary
Director of Research, Freud Museum, London
DOI: 10.4324/9781003215301
Typeset in Times New Roman
by Apex CoVantage, LLC
Contents
Index 303
About the Contributors
Daniel Burston has a PhD in social and political thought and a PhD in
psychology, both from York University in Toronto. He is Associate Pro-
fessor of Psychology at Duquesne University in Pittsburgh and the author
of numerous books and journal articles on psychoanalysis and critical
theory, ranging from The Legacy of Erich Fromm (Harvard University
Press, 1991) to Psychoanalysis, Politics and the Postmodern University
(Palgrave McMillan, 2020). His most recent book is titled Anti-Semitism
and Analytical Psychology: Jung, Politics and Culture (Routledge, 2021).
Burston is a member of Cheiron – the International Society for the His-
tory of the Behavioral and Social Sciences, and a lifetime supporter of the
Nexus Institute.
Joel Whitebook received his PhD in philosophy from the New School
for Social Research, a PhD in clinical psychology from the City Univer-
sity of New York (CUNY), and received his psychoanalytic training at the
New York Freudian Society. He has been in private practice for decades
and has taught at the New School, Columbia University, as well as in a
number of clinical settings. He is currently on the faculty of Columbia’s
Center for Psychoanalytic Training and Research and is the former direc-
tor of its Psychoanalytic Studies Program. His books include Perversion
and Utopia: A Study in Psychoanalysis and Critical Theory and Freud: An
Intellectual Biography.
Preface
In the midst of these burgeoning crises, the Far Right exploits the sense
of victimization felt by middle and working class people by providing
them with scapegoats who are depicted as dangerous or expendable, rather
than as vulnerable human beings who are entitled to dignity and human
rights. Anti-Semitism is a prominent feature of many of these movements,
which often use hostility to immigrants and minorities as their primary
recruiting tool. Many have scripted George Soros, a Jewish billionaire, in
the role of a demonic Jewish adversary who is using his wealth to flood
their respective countries with immigrants and criminals. He is accused of
undermining national sovereignty and traditional values through his sup-
port of liberal civic organizations. This idea is expressed repeatedly in the
official media in Victor Orban’s Hungary. And we heard a variation on the
same message (in abbreviated form) among the neo-Nazis who marched in
the Unite the Right rally in Charlottesville in August 2017, chanting, “The
Jews will not replace us!”
The Far Left’s narrative about Jews is quite different, of course. In the
United States, many left-wing activists now insist that Jews enjoy all the
perks of White privilege and therefore “uphold” rather than oppose White
supremacy, the very thing Far Right activists insist Jewish people are
secretly intent on destroying. Despite the recent uptick in anti-Semitism
in communities of color, and the enduring influence of Louis Farrakhan,
many activists still claim that anti-Semitism is just a “White on White”
issue that has nothing to do with White supremacy or systemic racism
and is therefore not worthy of their attention or concern. Unlike right-
wing extremists, who abhor multiculturalism and promote Islamophobia,
the Far Left espouses a strange brand of multiculturalism that typically
excludes and devalues Jewish experience but often embraces Islamist
movements and organizations in what it imagines is a progressive, anti-
imperialist coalition.
As democracy falters and authoritarianism spreads, some aspects of our
current crises resemble the situation in the years preceding WWII. For
example, racism and conspiracy theories abound, and Jewish people and
institutions are now targeted by mobs and vigilantes much as they were
in the 1930s across Europe and the United States, when Father Charles
Coughlin and industrialist Henry Ford spread their anti-Semitic venom
all across this continent. However, as illuminating and disturbing as these
parallels may be, it is important to remember that Jews are merely the pro-
verbial canaries in the coal mine, that the scale and severity of the chaos
Preface xv
already unfolding in our backyards will soon engulf everybody and have
a far more damaging impact on our planet than the two world wars that
ravaged the twentieth century.
Strange as it sounds, in the midst of these worrisome developments,
many conservative pundits nowadays blame critical theory for our current
societal malaise and, more specifically, for spawning something called
“cultural Marxism,” which ostensibly threatens our cultural cohesion. But
what is cultural Marxism, actually? A term coined by the Norwegian mass
murderer Anders Breivik, adopted by White supremacist Kevin MacDon-
ald and conspiracy theorist Alex Jones (Braune, 2019). Despite its inaus-
picious derivation, the term “cultural Marxism” shows up with surprising
regularity in the podcasts and publications of more mainstream media
personalities like Christopher Rufo and Jordan Peterson, among others,
who repeat the popular mantra that proclaims that Marxism begat criti-
cal theory, which begat postmodernism, which (supposedly) begat cultural
Marxism.
The problem with this narrative is that it is simply not true. It is a straw
man, which only seems plausible if you cherry-pick and decontextualize
ideas from these various schools of thought, something Christopher Rufo is
particularly skilled at doing. Unfortunately, this popular mythology about
critical theory and cultural Marxism encourages a kind of smug, know-it-
all attitude that masks intellectual laziness and complacency among many
contemporary conservatives, who crafted this oversimplified narrative to
assure themselves that they are right to mistrust and dismiss all critical
social theory. There is also something ahistorical and conspiratorial about
this line of thinking, as if the radical thinkers of today are simply putting
old wine into new bottles, instead of putting forward genuinely new ideas
of their own in response to new social and political realities. In truth, how-
ever, there are profound differences between Marxism and critical theory,
and between critical theory and postmodernism. In order to grasp them
clearly, one has to understand the social and historical contexts in which
these movements arose.
To put these reflections in context, please consider the following. In
1794, Nicholas de Condorcet (1743–1794) wrote a book titled Sketch for
a Historical Picture of the Progress of the Human Mind. Condorcet was
a leading figure in the French Enlightenment who depicted progress as a
slow but inexorable process that would eventually dispel ignorance and
superstition through the development of science and confer previously
xvi Preface
Marxism” by its critics, an ideology that was used to justify a bloody reign
of terror.
Then, in 1929, the stock market crashed – the biggest crisis of capitalism
to that point – and contrary to expectation among Western Marxists, the
European proletariat did not mobilize on cue to mount the revolution that
Marx had predicted should eventually ensue. Indeed, critical theory arose
primarily as a response to the failure of Marx’s predictions at this histori-
cal juncture. Granted, the first director of the Frankfurt Institute for Social
Research was an orthodox Marxist. But his successor, Max Horkheimer,
who took over in 1930, was not. Horkheimer and associates rejected revo-
lutionary vanguardism and claimed that the European and British working
class were failing in their historic mission because of social psychologi-
cal processes that orthodox Marxism was not equipped to elucidate or
address. So with the help of Erich Fromm, the only analyst working among
the institute’s faculty, Horkheimer and associates attempted to develop a
Marx-Freud synthesis that would account for the failure of the working
class to lead the transition to a classless society.
In addition to integrating psychoanalytic perspectives on social psychol-
ogy, critical theorists deviated from orthodox Marxism by rejecting eco-
nomic determinism and promoting interdisciplinarity, integrating ideas and
insights from a wide range of non-Marxist theorists in sociology, anthropol-
ogy, philosophy, and literature. In the process, as Perry Anderson observed,
their emphasis shifted away from the pragmatics and exigencies of class
struggle toward a critique of social factors that Marx had deemed to be
“superstructural,” notably, literature, the arts, radio and cinema, popular
music, and propaganda, which they deemed to be more consequential than
Marx had ever imagined in perpetuating the status quo (Anderson, 1983).
Finally, remember that Marx shared the Enlightenment’s enthusiasm for
technological innovation, nowadays called technophilia. He believed that
new technologies were intrinsically liberating and should be welcomed
because they dramatically altered social conditions and power relations
between classes of people, hastening the crisis of capitalism that would
set the stage for the proletariat to seize the means of production from the
capitalist class and effect a more equitable distribution of goods, services,
and opportunities for education and personal self-expression.
Though they still clung to Enlightenment ideals, Horkheimer and
Adorno et al. had witnessed the galloping Nazification of Germany at close
quarters before they fled Germany in 1935. As a result, they were quite
xviii Preface
critical theory, which has its roots in Marx and Freud, postmodernism
borrows extensively from anti-Enlightenment thinkers like Friedrich
Nietzsche and Martin Heidegger. This was an odd and unprecedented
move for Left-leaning intellectuals, because Nietzsche and Heidegger had
nothing but contempt for the masses and no interest whatsoever in pro-
moting a program of universal human emancipation. Indeed, Nietzsche
argued forcefully for the continuation of slavery, while Heidegger was
an unrepentant Nazi. That being so, this gradual migration of intellec-
tual capital from right-wing philosophers to left-wing theorists in the
Cold War era is one of the strangest episodes in the history of philosophy
(Burston and Frie, 2006).
Generally speaking, postmodernists and post-structuralists are dismiss-
ive of historical materialism and the very idea of progress, which they
regard as just one more “grand narrative” that is vacuous, self-serving, or
ripe for deconstruction. And unlike Marx and Freud, they claim that there
is nothing like a universal human nature that all people share, which ren-
ders it possible for us to empathize with the experience of someone whose
cultural context is radically different from our own. On reflection, then,
the differences between Marxism, critical theory, and postmodernism are
pretty clear and pivot largely around their attitudes toward the Enlighten-
ment. Marx was unabashedly enthusiastic about the Enlightenment, while
Critical Theory, informed by Freud, waxed ambivalent toward it. Postmod-
ernism and post-structuralism, by contrast, are generally quite dismissive
or derisive in their appraisals of Enlightenment thought. Besides, Marx
stressed the primacy of praxis, labor, and economics in the shaping of
society, while Freud and his followers stressed the primacy of instincts and
their vicissitudes, or “the economics of the libido.” By contrast with both
Marx and Freud, postmodernists and post-structuralists generally stress
the primacy of language, which they often maintain is culture constitutive.
Despite the gravity of our current situation, the essays in this volume
attest to the continuing vitality and relevance of critical theory today, but
they do so in different ways and from differing perspectives. When we
circulated our call for papers, we deliberately solicited contributions from
relative newcomers as well as from well-established scholars. In that, we
succeeded. Moreover, rather than seeking to promote uniformity of opin-
ion, we welcomed the efforts of scholars who have engaged seriously with
the legacy of the Frankfurt School but without attempting to minimize or
ignore their differences. The result is a collection of essays whose subject
xx Preface
matter converge and overlap in many ways but without giving anyone
“the final word.” So for example, Joel Whitebook’s chapter relates how
three generations of critical theorists have fruitfully engaged with psycho-
analysis. The papers of Adrian Johnston and Robert Pfaller probe some of
the subtler, far-reaching implications of Freud’s brand of materialism and
ponder the extent to which it was (or could be rendered) compatible with
a more Marxist understanding of (historical) materialism. Kurt Jacobsen’s
paper takes aim at what he describes as the quietist and stoic implica-
tions of Lacanian theory. Three other papers – those of Benjamin B. Stros-
berg, Paul Bishop, and John R. White – delve deeply into the substance
of Horkheimer and Adorno’s book The Dialectic of Enlightenment and
its relevance to contemporary social thought. Frank Pittenger’s delight-
ful essay dwells on problems in Freud’s metapsychology and its impact
on Adorno and Marcuse, while Gary Clark offers us a refreshing new
look at Erich Fromm’s contributions to critical theory and his intellectual
development after leaving the Frankfurt School. Daniel Burston’s papers
apply the lens of critical theory to the study of left-wing authoritarianism
and the impact of critical race theory and whiteness studies on contempo-
rary psychoanalytic discourse. Finally, Jon Mills’s two papers address the
prevalence of dysrecognition in contemporary culture and offers a critique
of Axel Honneth’s recent reflections on the relationship between psychoa-
nalysis and critical theory.
As our planetary crises deepen, right-wing populism and ethno-
nationalism pose the gravest threats to democracy, not critical theory,
and certainly not the mythical boogeyman manufactured by conservative
pundits. Evidence for this, if any is needed, was furnished by the insur-
rection on Capitol Hill on January 6, 2021, and more recently by Putin’s
brutal and senseless invasion of Ukraine. But with that said, there are
some worrisome developments on the Left that should be addressed as
well. In Chapter 16 of Grand Hotel Abyss: The Lives of the Frankfurt
School, Stuart Jeffries notes that the concept of left-wing authoritarianism –
which Habermas dubbed “Left Fascism” – only arose in critical theory
circles long after the publication of The Authoritarian Personality, and
more specifically, in 1967–1968, when aggrieved students occupied the
Institute for Social Research and disrupted Theodor Adorno’s lectures,
which were thronged by noisy students attempting to de-platform him for
not lending his unqualified support to their movement (Jeffries, 2017).
While Adorno never published anything on this topic, he did discuss it
Preface xxi
because they feel that their departments or universities have been thor-
oughly captured or compromised by the new activist Zeitgeist. So while
cultural Marxism is indeed a myth, cancel culture is not (German, K. and
Lukianoff, G., 2022). Indeed, we have many friends and colleagues in aca-
demia who live in fear of losing their livelihoods, or being “cancelled” for
saying or doing something that offends the activist sensibilities of their
colleagues and students. The resulting self-censorship places invisible
constraints on academic freedom. It is therefore detrimental to the basic
functioning of the university. And let’s not kid ourselves. Thriving democ-
racies actually need intact universities to foster critical thinking and an
informed and responsive citizenry. Absent these qualities, citizens devolve
into mere consumers and conformists who lack the judgment, resolve, and
the sense of solidarity with others to mobilize in defense of their increas-
ingly fragile freedoms.
Sadly, the crisis in our universities is also compounded by the aston-
ishing growth of the managerial caste in the last four decades. While
the numbers of administrators in universities and colleges grows in
leaps and bounds, the number of tenured professors is shrinking stead-
ily, and those that remain have been drastically de-professionalized.
Rather than treating them as colleagues and respected professionals,
university administrators frequently treat faculty as mere employees
who should meekly forgo any meaningful role in the governance of the
university and accept their decisions without question (Burston, 2020).
Indeed, even tenured faculty are increasingly regarded as expendable
and certainly not worthy of the increasingly extravagant salaries and
bonuses administrators routinely award themselves. Worse yet, this
trend toward administrative bloat was accompanied by the precipitous
decline of the liberal arts and the explosive growth of diversity, equity,
and inclusion programs, which are now an $8 billion industry in the
United States, although evidence for their long-term effectiveness is
vanishingly scarce. So why do university administrators insist on them?
To boost enrollments? Certainly. But promoting DEI programming of
various kinds is also a vehicle for collective virtue signaling, helping
administrators cultivate an image of themselves as good people who
are genuinely concerned about social justice, even though they are too
timid or indifferent to come to the defense of faculty who are unjustly
Preface xxiii
accused and harassed, and increasingly happy to dismiss them for trivial
offenses, without just cause or due process.
We conclude with a quote from Max Horkheimer, who addressed the
student activists of the 1960s and 1970s in a preface to an earlier collection
of essays on critical theory as follows:
An open declaration that even a dubious democracy, for all its defects,
is always better than . . . dictatorship seems necessary for the sake
of truth. . . . Rosa Luxemburg, whom many students venerate, said
fifty years ago that “the remedy of Trotsky and Lenin have found, the
elimination of democracy as such, is worse than the disease it is sup-
posed to cure.” To protect, preserve and where possible, to extend the
ephemeral freedom of the individual in the face of the growing threat
to it is a far more urgent a task than to issue abstract denunciations of
it or endanger it by actions that have no hope of success.
(Horkheimer, 1972, p. viii)
References
Al Yafai, F. 2017. “The cult of Bashar extends from the far right to the far left.”
Retrieved from www.thenational.ae/opinion/the-cult-of-bashar-extends-from-
the-far-right-to-the-far-left.-1.621909.
Anderson, P. 1983. In the Tracks of Historical Materialism. London: Verso.
Black, H. 2017 (March 21). “ ‘The painting must go’: Hannah Black pens open
letter to the Whitney about controversial biennial work.” Art News. Retrieved
from www.artnews.com/2017/03/21/the-painting-must-go-hannah-black-pens-
an-open-letter-to-the-whitney-about-controversial-biennial-work/.
Braune, J. 2019. “Who’s afraid of the Frankfurt school? ‘Cultural marxism’ as
an anti-semitic conspiracy theory.” Journal of Social Justice, vol. 9, pp. 1–25.
Burston, D. 2020. Psychoanalysis, Politics and the Postmodern University.
Cham: Palgrave MacMillen.
Burston, D. and Frie, R. 2006. Psychotherapy as a Human Science. Pittsburgh:
Duquesne University Press.
Gandesha, S. 2019. “The ‘authoritarian personality’ reconsidered: The phantom of
‘left fascism’.” The American Journal of Psychoanalysis, vol. 79, pp. 601–624.
German, K. and Lukianoff, G. 2022 (March 25). “Don’t stop using the term ‘can-
cel culture’.” The Daily Beast. Retrieved from <thedailybeast.com>.
Hartocollis, A. 2017 (June 16). “A campus argument goes viral. Now the campus is
under siege.” New York Times. Retrieved from www.nytimes.com/2016/06/16/
us/evergreen-state-protests.html.
Hensman, R. 2018. Indefensible: Democracy, Counter-Revolution and the Rheto-
ric of Anti-Imperialism. Chicago, IL: Haymarket Books.
Horkheimer, M. 1972. Critical Theory: Selected Essays. New York: Continuum
Books.
Horkheimer, M. and Adorno, T. 1947. The Dialectic of Enlightenment, translated
by Edmund Jephcott. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002.
Jeffries, S. 2017. Grand Hotel Abyss: The Lives of the Frankfurt School. London:
Verso.
Shultz, D. 2017. Open Casket [Painting]. New York: Whitney Museum.
Tuvel, R. 2017 (March 29). “In defense of trans-racialism.” Hypatia. Retrieved
from https://doi.org/10/11/11/hypa.1237.
Vigo, J. and Garano, L. 2017. “Open letter on the hypatia controversy.” Feminist
Current. Retrieved from www.feministcurrent.com/2017/05/25/open-letter-
hypatia-controversy/.
Chapter 1
Introduction
In the 1930s, the philosophers and social scientists of the Institute for Social
Research were the first members of the conservative German academy to
not only treat the disreputable avant-garde new discipline of psychoanaly-
sis seriously – whose membership was almost entirely Jewish – but also to
accord Freud the same stature as the titans of the philosophical tradition.
The radicalism of psychoanalysis fit with the radicalism of the position
they were attempting to develop, and the appropriation of psychoanalysis
provided one of the pillars on which critical theory was constructed (Jay
1973: 86–112).
In addition to the theoretical affinity between the Frankfurt School and
psychoanalysis, the relationship between the two intellectual movements
was also practical. The Institute for Social Research and the Frankfurt Psy-
choanalytic Institute shared a building, in which they held their classes in
the same rooms, and jointly sponsored public lectures by such eminent
analysts as Anna Freud, Paul Federn, Hans Sachs, and Siegfried Bernfeld.
Indeed, the connection between the two organizations went even further.
Max Horkheimer, the director of the Institute for Social Research, sat on
the board of the analytic institute, while Eric Fromm – a trained analyst
and member of both groups – helped the critical theorists educate them-
selves about the workings of psychoanalysis.
A major concern that led the critical theorists to turn to psychoanalysis
was a deficit in Marxian theory: it lacked a so-called subjective dimension
and tended to treat subjectivity simply as an epiphenomenon, that is, as a
reflection of the material base. With the economic crisis of the 1930s, this
concern became especially pressing. Objective conditions obtained that
Marxian theory predictions should have produced the radicalization of the
DOI: 10.4324/9781003215301-1
2 Joel Whitebook
working class. But just the opposite was happening: a large portion of
the European proletariat was turning to fascism instead. Max Horkheimer,
Eric Fromm, and Herbert Marcuse, among others, undertook Studies in
Authority and the Family to account for this supposedly anomalous fact
(Horkheimer 1936; Jay 1973: 113–142; Wiggershaus 1994: 149–156).
In one sense, the study was groundbreaking for, along with Wilhelm
Reich’s work, it represented the first attempt to incorporate psychoanalysis
into Marxian theory. But in another sense, its innovations remained lim-
ited. Studies on Authority and the Family still remained Marxist – albeit,
of highly heterodox sort – insofar as it retained the general framework of
political economy. Furthermore, the work drew on the less radical the-
ories in the Freudian corpus, for example, those pertaining to character
formation, rather than Freud’s late, more scandalous cultural texts, which
Horkheimer and Adorno turned to in conjunction with their reconstitution
of critical theory in the 1940s.
After immigrating to California, Adorno joined with colleagues outside
of the institute to conduct another psychoanalytically oriented interdiscipli-
nary research project that returned to many of the same themes contained
in Studies on Authority and the Family. Their findings were published
in The Authoritarian Personality: Studies in Prejudice (Adorno 1982).
Despite its initial influence, the work was later criticized on methodologi-
cal grounds and fell out of fashion. But as Peter Gordon has recently sug-
gested, with the election of Donald Trump and the rise of authoritarian
leaders around the world, revisiting The Authoritarian Personality might
be in order (Gordon 2017).
When Horkheimer and Adorno received news that the Nazis had set
the final solution into motion and that their colleague Walter Benjamin
had committed suicide while trying to escape the Gestapo on the Spanish
frontier, they concluded that it was necessary to radicalize their theory in
order to do justice to the enormity of the catastrophe that was unfolding in
Europe (Rabinbach 1997). That catastrophe, as they saw it, involved more
than the failure of the proletariat to fulfill its historical task. It resulted
from the self-destruction of the project of Enlightenment itself. “Why,”
they asked, was “humanity . . . sinking into a new kind of barbarism” pre-
cisely at the point where, according to the (Baconian) Enlightenment, the
material conditions had been created that could produce a “truly human
state” (Horkheimer and Adorno 2002: xiv)?
The radicalization of critical theory consisted in a move from the cri-
tique of political economy to the philosophy of history centering on the
domination of nature (Jay 1973: 253–280). In addition to Freud, the two
philosophers drew on Nietzsche, Weber, Mauss, as well as others to write
a depth-psychological and depth-anthropological Urgeschichte or primal
history of civilization. The new position was articulated in Dialectic of
Enlightenment, which became the defining text of the Frankfurt School
during its classical phase. Where the domination of nature in general – as
opposed to economic exploitation and class struggle – became the over-
arching theme of the new philosophy of history, the idea of the domination
of inner nature provided the specific link through which Horkheimer and
Adorno incorporated Freud into their new theory.
For the mature Freud, the reality principle, understood as Ananke or Atro-
pos (necessity or the ineluctable), defined the human condition (White-
book 2017: Chapter 10). It designated the price that nature inevitably
exacted from us finite transient beings, in the form of physical suffer-
ing and decay, loss, and ultimately death. By reading Marx’s theory of
exchange back into prehistory, Horkheimer and Adorno sought to inte-
grate his economic theory with Freudian anthropology. They maintained
that the law of equivalence – the principle that everything that happens
must pay for having happened – governed mythical thought, and they
saw the capitalist principle of exchange as the latest and most complete
instantiation of the law of equivalence. The practice of sacrifice, which
aims at mitigating the law’s effects, follows from it. For example, the sac-
rifice that our so-called primitive ancestors performed to placate the gods
after a successful hunting expedition constituted an attempt to control
4 Joel Whitebook
the price they would have to pay for their good fortune by offering an
advanced propitiatory payment.
According to Horkheimer and Adorno, enlightenment consists in the
attempt to escape mythic fate and sacrifice. Deploying his cunning, which
was the precursor of instrumental reason, Odysseus, who is the prototype
of the enlightened individual, sought to outsmart the law of equivalence
through “the introversion of sacrifice.” Rather than sacrificing a piece of
external nature, for example, the hindquarter of an ox, Odysseus sacrificed
a piece of his inner nature, which is to say, renounced a piece of his
unconscious-instinctual life. By repressing his inner nature in order to
form a purposeful, autocratic, virile, and rational (qua calculating) ego,
Odysseus believed he could dominate external nature, thereby escaping
its dangers, outsmart mythical fate, and evade the law of equivalence.
Horkheimer and Adorno argue, however, that the strategy was flawed.
Their thesis is that “the denial of nature in human beings,” which consti-
tutes “the core of all civilizing rationality,” contains “the germ cell of pro-
liferating mythic irrationality” out of which the dialectic of enlightenment
ineluctably unfolds (Horkheimer and Adorno 2002: 42).
An erroneous Baconian assumption, which was taken over by Marx,
underlies the program of the domination of nature: namely, its demand
for renunciation is justified for, in the long run, the domination of nature
will create the material conditions that are the prerequisite for what Bacon
called “the relief of man’s estate” – or the emancipation of the humanity, to
put it in Marxian terms. But there is a hitch in this program, and it gener-
ates the self-defeating logic of the dialectic of enlightenment. Because it
represents “the introversion of sacrifice,” the renunciation of inner nature,
which seeks to escape sacrifice, remains a form of sacrifice, albeit a dis-
placed one. And as such, it is still subject to the law of equivalence. The
math, Adorno and Horkheimer maintain, does not work: “all who renounce
give away more of their life than is given back to them, more than the life
they preserve” (Horkheimer and Adorno 2002: 43).
More concretely, the faulty math produces a calamitous result. In order
to carry out the domination of nature, the subject must form a purposive
calculating self by repressing its unconscious-instinctual life. It thereby
reifies itself at the same time and to the same degree that it reifies external
nature. It follows that at the point that nature has been thoroughly reified
and dominated in order to produce the presumptive material precondi-
tions for emancipation – which Horkheimer and Adorno assume had been
Psychoanalysis and the Frankfurt School 5
approximated by the first half of the twentieth century – the self will have
been thoroughly reified as well. In the process of creating the preconditions
for its emancipation, the subject has, in short, so deformed itself – has so
“annihilated” itself – that it is in no condition to appropriate those precon-
ditions and create a better form of life. Hence, the self-defeating logic of
the dialectic of enlightenment: “[w]ith the denial of nature in humans, not
only the telos of the external mastery of nature, but also the telos of one’s
one life becomes opaque and confused.” Instead of emancipation, barba-
rism results. It should be noted that, for Horkheimer and Adorno, “nature
in the human being” constitutes that which is sacrificed in the process
of dominating nature, as well as (in some unspecified fashion) that for
the sake of which the entire process is pursued (Horkheimer and Adorno
2002: 42).
Because of their anti-Hegelian opposition to all modes of final recon-
ciliation and their thesis of a totally administered world, Horkheimer and
Adorno opposed all utopian solutions, indeed, positive solutions as such.
Nevertheless, logically there is an unthematized utopian implication of
their hyperbolic analysis – which they would surely have rejected had
it been explicitly presented to them: that only the cessation of renuncia-
tion in toto, only the emancipation of inner nature and unfettered fulfill-
ment, could prevent the dialectic of enlightenment from unfolding. Short
of this implicit utopian solution, the most that Horkheimer and Adorno do
is hint at one other possible way out of the dialectic’s fateful logic, namely,
“the remembrance of nature within the subject” (Horkheimer and Adorno
2002: 32). But they do not provide the idea with much content.
After the war, however, there was one place where Adorno might have
speculated on non-reified forms of subjectivity. But his prohibition against
speculating on positive conceptions of the self prevented him from pur-
suing this path (Adorno 1968; Jay 1984: Chapter 5; Whitebook 1996:
152–164). Despite his reservations about false reconciliation, in his aes-
thetic theory, Adorno allows himself to speculate about non-reified forms
of synthesis – different relations between part and whole, particular and
universal. Borrowing an idea from Kant, he argues that the truly advanced
work of avant-garde art exhibits “a non-violent togetherness of the mani-
fold” that provides a glimpse of what a non-reified world might be like.
But Adorno stopped there, refusing to extrapolate from his aesthetic theory
in order to envision less violent and more desirable forms of the together-
ness of the self, that is, of ego-integration.
6 Joel Whitebook
Herbert Marcuse
But in an effort to break out of the Dialectic of Enlightenment, Herbert
Marcuse did play the utopian card, first as a theoretical exercise, then as a
concrete theoretical program. In the midst of the seemingly closed world of
the 1950s, which appeared to confirm Horkheimer and Adorno’s progno-
sis, Marcuse’s Eros and Civilization attempted to provide a philosophical
demonstration that a “nonrepressive civilization” – that is, a civilization in
which the sacrifice-repression of inner nature was no longer necessary so
that it could be liberated – was possible. But it was just that, philosophical.
At the time, Marcuse did not advocate an attempt to realize that society
(Marcuse 1955: 5; Whitebook 1996: 26–41, 2004: 82–89).
In Eros and Civilization, Marcuse undertakes an immanent critique of
Freud, whose “own theory,” he argues, “provides reasons for rejecting the
identification of civilization with repression” (Marcuse 1955: 4). Mar-
cuse’s strategy is to historicize Freud’s basic framework. Where Freud
presented the fundamental opposition between the reality principle and
pleasure principle as transhistorical and therefore immutable, Marcuse,
with the aid of Marx, attempts to “de-ontologize” it by historicizing the
Reality Principle. His entire argument rests on this central move.
As mentioned earlier, the mature Freud understood the reality principle
as Ananke (necessity) or Atropos (the ineluctable). But in what amounts
to a Marxifying sleight of hand, Marcuse alters the meaning of that prin-
ciple and reconceptualizes it in economic terms. Instead of transhistori-
cal necessity, Ananke is recast as historically variable Lebensnot (scarcity)
and is defined in terms of “struggle for existence” (Marcuse 1955: 132).
The term now refers to the metabolism between humanity and nature that
will exist in any conceivable society and to the amount of toil that, to
one degree or another, will be necessary to extract the means of existence
from the natural environment at a particular level of economic develop-
ment. Toil requires unpleasure, that is, frustration, delayed gratification,
and the repression of the pleasure principle. Thus, insofar as the reality
principle refers to the quantum of toil that is necessary in a given society,
it also refers to the degree of repression of the pleasure principle – of inner
nature – that is required to carry it out.
The redefinition of Ananke allows Marcuse to introduce another distinc-
tion that is obviously modeled on Marx’s distinction between necessary
and surplus labor, that is, between basic or necessary repression on the one
Psychoanalysis and the Frankfurt School 7
hand and surplus repression on the other. Necessary repression denotes the
ineliminable quantum of repression that will be required in any conceiv-
able society in virtue of the fact that we are embodied beings who will,
to one degree or another, always have to extract the means of existence
from nature. Surplus repression, as the name suggests, refers to the excess
repression beyond the basic repression that could be eliminated in a given
society on the basis of the development of its scientific and technological
means of production. Marcuse’s thesis is that surplus repression is largely
exploitative and is enforced in the interests of the dominant class. Indeed,
the difference between necessary and surplus repression can be taken as a
measure of the degree of exploitation in a given society.
Marcuse maintains that surplus repression comprises the largest portion
of repression in advanced capitalist societies, and he refers to the particular
historical instantiation of it that obtains in them as the performance prin-
ciple. His claim is that the performance principle – which is maintained in
the economic interest of the capitalist ruling class – is perpetuated by the
endless creation of false consumerist needs in the population and through
capitalism’s perpetual production of (often useless) commodities that can
fulfill them.
There is, however, if not an outright contradiction, at least a serious
tension lurking in this configuration. The advanced state of the means of
production, according to Marcuse, generates the potential and therefore
the pressure for a qualitatively different socioeconomic order in which sur-
plus repression could in principle be eliminated. And this potential is at
odds with an arrangement where the performance principle is artificially
enforced. Given a differently constituted system of needs – one not based
on the incessant multiplication of false needs – advanced science and tech-
nology could be employed to vastly reduce the amount of toil necessary
to produce the material requirements not only for existence but also for
the satisfaction of true needs that were not artificially inflated. The tension
between the existing state of affairs and the potential of advanced science
and technology might, Marcuse suggests, contribute to the motivation for
a radical transformation of society.
Reinterpreting Marx’s notion of the transition from the realm of neces-
sity to the realm of freedom in psychoanalytic terms, Marcuse attempts
to envisage a utopian transformation of society. If the highly developed
means of production in the advanced world were to be properly appro-
priated, a social transformation could be affected that would drastically
8 Joel Whitebook
reduce the amount of toil necessary for securing the necessities of life.
With the elimination of scarcity, surplus repression could also be elimi-
nated. This, in turn, would make it possible to establish a nonrepressive
society – that is, one in which only the minimal amount of basic repression
remained – and to emancipate inner nature.
Marcuse draws on the psychoanalytic theory of perverse sexuality to
provide content for the vision of a utopian society beyond “the established
reality principle” (Marcuse 1955: 129). His rather questionable reason-
ing is this: because the sexual perversions have somehow eluded, indeed,
rebelled against the Oedipally structured historical reality principle, they
can offer an indication of what form a different arrangement of human sex-
uality might assume. Marcuse goes so far as to claim that primary narcis-
sism constitutes not only a stage of preoedipal psychosexual development
but also that the concept contains “ontological implications” that point
“at another mode of being” – one that would be reconciled with external
nature (Marcuse 1955: 107 and 109). What Marcuse fails to appreciate is
that perverse sexuality, whatever that may mean in today’s context, does
not constitute an unalloyed expression of the pleasure principle, but is,
like all psychical productions, multiply determined. (In a similar romantic
vein, the young Foucault made a related mistake when he maintained that
madness contained a privileged form of truth that had escaped contamina-
tion by normalizing rationality [Whitebook 2002, 2005].)
Freud never denied that the reality principle contained an economic
component. This is especially true in The Future of an Illusion, his most
Marxist book, which progressives regularly cite. But to reduce the con-
cept to economic scarcity is to substantially diminish its philosophical
depth. Paul Ricoeur has argued that the mature Freud’s introduction of
the term Ananke to denote the reality principle indicated a transformation
of the concept from a “principle of ‘mental regulation’ ” into “a cypher
of possible wisdom . . . beyond illusion and consolation” (Ricoeur 1970:
262 and 325). Freud was staunchly anti-utopian, and his tragic wisdom
consisted in the resignation to Ananke, that is, the disconsolate acceptance
of the fact that human reality is constituted by transience and inevitably
permeated with loss and death (Whitebook 2017: 329).
But Marxists typically dismiss Freud’s tragic vision as the ideologi-
cal prejudice of a fin-de-siècle bourgeois patriarch whose world and
worldview were crumbling. And it cannot be denied that a number of the
questionable anthropological assumptions upon which Freud’s political
Psychoanalysis and the Frankfurt School 9
that rejected the false system of needs and the creation of a “new sensibil-
ity” embodying an alternative to them – was a necessary condition for the
transformation of the established order and the creation of new form of life
(Marcuse 1969: 23–48). As opposed to Adorno, Marcuse guilelessly and
enthusiastically celebrated the countercultural and radical political move-
ments of the 1960s as an expression of that new sensibility, at least in an
incipient form (Adorno and Marcuse, “Correspondence” 1999: New Left
Review I/233, January – February).
But as those movements receded further and further into the past, his
position increasingly appeared hopelessly and perhaps even embarrass-
ingly naive. Ronald Reagan and Margaret Thatcher’s Counter-Revolution
successfully quashed the 1960’s vision of the good life and succeeded in
reinstating the pursuit of wealth as the summum bonum. The entrepreneur
in a pinstriped suit replaced the civil rights worker in overalls as the new
culture hero. Moreover, with the collapse of communism and the trium-
phant ascendance of liberal political theory, the discussion of the good as
opposed to the right was often condemned as illicit. Indeed, it was some-
times suggested that to countenance the distinction between true and false
needs, as Marcuse emphatically did, was to begin down the slippery slope
to totalitarianism. The liberal turn in political theory, in short, appeared to
exclude the notion of a new sensibility from legitimate discourse and to
limit its parameters to a consideration of rights.
But “after the brief interlude of liberalism,” which, one can argue, lasted
from the fall of the Berlin Wall to the economic crisis of 2008, the idea
of a new sensibility may not seem so daft (Horkheimer and Adorno 2002:
68). It might be the case that a rights-oriented politics cannot adequately
address the rapacious dynamics of the globalized capitalism – the system’s
incessant and methodical “colonization of the lifeworld” and the environ-
ment – and its lethal effects on the global ecosystem (Habermas 1989:
332–372). Furthermore, where liberal and postmodern critics tend to dis-
miss Adorno and Horkheimer’s theory of the cultural industry as elitist,
the two critical theorists were, in fact, diagnosing embryonic tendencies
that have now developed beyond their wildest imagination. The capac-
ity of today’s social media and celebrity culture to deflect, disarm, and
confuse critical thinking, while simultaneously creating a simulacrum of
popular debate, has surpassed their worst fears. As unlikely as the emer-
gence of a new sensibility might seem given our current conditions, it is
difficult to imagine how, from a purely logical point of view, a social and
Psychoanalysis and the Frankfurt School 11
political movement that can address the problems that are confronting us
can be formed without one. On this point, Marcuse may not have been that
naive after all.
Jürgen Habermas
Because it occurred at the beginning of his career, Habermas’s only sus-
tained Auseinandersetzung with Freud is conflicted and difficult to sort
out. At the time, Habermas had one foot planted in the psychoanalytically
informed materialism of the first generation of the Frankfurt School. But
with the other, he was stepping into the world of linguistified Kantianism
that came to define him. Although the early Habermas tried on the mantle
of the first generation of critical theorists for size, because he possessed
substantially different pre-theoretical intuitions, he was never entirely at
home in it and therefore moved beyond it relatively quickly (Rabinbach
1997: 168–170).
The first generation’s experience, which was shaped by Weimar, emigra-
tion, the war, Nazism, Stalinism, and the Holocaust, resulted in the choice
between hyper-radical utopianism and quietist resignation. Habermas’s
experience was different. As someone who, as an adolescent, had been
glued to the radio listening to the broadcasts of the Nuremburg Trials and
who entered adulthood as the Federal Republic was being established, the
either/or of quietism versus revolution was unacceptable. Possessing the
instincts of a radical reformer, Habermas placed the solidification, cultiva-
tion, and defense of German democracy at the top of his political agenda.
And he cannot be commended enough for his exemplary career as a public
intellectual and for the many courageous political stances he has taken. At
the same time, however, it must also be admitted that his resolute defense
of democracy has often been coupled with excessive progressivist Whig-
gishness. This has not only led him to deny the darker antisocial forces in
human nature documented by Freud, but it has also prevented him from
effectively addressing the irrational forces that are so evident in today’s
politics around the globe. For example, while progressive Protestants or
reformed Jews might find his position on religion congenial, he sidesteps
the really hard problem: how to address fundamentalism. For someone
with a fundamentalist mindset would find the position he is advocating
well-nigh unfathomable. How does one enter into a rational dialogue with
someone who has not cathected the idea of rational dialogue?
12 Joel Whitebook
In the 1960s, Freud was required reading for a budding critical theorist,
and it is clear from Knowledge and Human Interests that Habermas’s Aus-
einandersetzung with the psychoanalyst’s work was comprehensive and
deep (Habermas 1971). But he did not share the first generation’s elec-
tive affinity with the founder of psychoanalysis. As Thomas McCarthy
observes, Habermas’s “orientation to Freud’s work” was less substan-
tive and “more methodological than was theirs” (McCarthy 1978: 195).
Furthermore, this methodological orientation was one aspect of a larger
point of difference separating their younger colleague from the authors
of Dialectic of Enlightenment. Horkheimer and Adorno were prepared to
resign themselves to the self-referential implication that followed from
their analysis: namely, that they could not elucidate their own theoreti-
cal standpoint. They therefore abstained in principle from any attempt to
clarify the methodological foundations of critical theory. At best, they dia-
lectically circled them.
For Habermas, this abstention was unacceptable on theoretical as well
as political grounds. Still situating himself within a Marxist vein, he drew
on the new working-class theory current at the time and argued that after
the Second World War, science and technology had come to occupy a new
strategically decisive position in the productive apparatus of the capital-
ist economy. Therefore, if critical theory hoped to influence a progres-
sive transformation of advanced capitalist society, it would have to engage
members of scientific and academic communities. To do so, it would be
necessary for critical theorists to clarify and defend the methodological
foundations of their position in a way that was acceptable to those commu-
nities of investigators. If the representatives of the first generation of the
Frankfurt School sometimes (and somewhat disingenuously) made a fet-
ish of being outsiders, Habermas wanted to challenge the academic com-
munity on its own terms, forcing its members to reflect on the dogmatic
assumptions underlying their positions.
Where Horkheimer, Adorno, and Marcuse were attracted to psychoa-
nalysis because of its scandalousness, Habermas wanted to use it to make
the project academically legitimate and critical at the same time. Strange
as it may sound today when the field is in such disrepute, in the 1960s, he
believed that psychoanalysis provided a model of a social science that was
not simply successful but successful qua reflective and critical. “Psychoa-
nalysis is relevant to us,” he wrote, because it is “the only tangible example
of science incorporating methodological self-reflection” (Habermas 1971:
Psychoanalysis and the Frankfurt School 13
124). He believed that the discipline provided a model case from which
general methodological (and normative) principles for a critical theory of
society could be extrapolated. To accomplish this task – and to rectify what
he, like Lacan, mistakenly saw as Freud’s biologism – Habermas sought to
apply the findings of the linguistic turn, which was in full force at the middle
of the twentieth century, to psychoanalysis. He reinterpreted neurosis and
ideology as two structurally homologous forms of false consciousness and
conceptualized them as forms of systematically distorted communication.
It is at this point that the serious tensions emerge in Habermas’s posi-
tion. (A) On the one hand, he continues to not only use the language of
the first generation’s materialistically inflected interpretation of Freud but
also to gesture toward the substance of that interpretation. (B) On the other
hand, however, this strain of his argument is at odds with the linguistify-
ing and transcendentalizing dynamic that he introduces with the notion of
systematically distorted communication.
Regarding (A): when, for example, Habermas set out to refute
Nietzsche’s Darwinian reductionism, he deployed Freud’s instinct theory
(Triebtheorie) – a theory which, if he did not totally repudiate, he radi-
cally altered and diluted under the linguistifying pressures of his program.
Habermas responds to Nietzsche’s claim that reason is nothing but “an
organ of adaptation for men just as claws and teeth are for animals” in the
following way. He grants Nietzsche’s claim that reason is a natural organ
of self-preservation, but over the course of evolution, he argues, it also
develops into something more than nature. And Habermas uses the con-
cept of libido to explain that something more, that is to say, the “cultural
break with nature.” Human drives are excessive – superabundant – in that
they overshoot the requirements of self-preservation, of mere life. “Along
with the tendency to realize natural drives,” Habermas claims that the cul-
tural formations that have emerged over the course of evolution “have
incorporated the tendency toward release from the constraint of nature,”
latent in the excessiveness of the drives (Habermas 1973: 312).
At this point, Habermas bursts into a downright Marcusean panegyric to
the utopian significance of Eros: “an enticing natural force, present in the
individual as libido, has detached itself from the behavioral system of self-
preservation and urges toward utopian fulfillment” (Habermas 1973: 312).
Habermas also enlists Marcuse’s distinction between necessary repression
and surplus repression as a means for elucidating the critique of ideology
and as a device for measuring the amount of exploitation in a given society
14 Joel Whitebook
society or language all the way down – that “the self is socially consti-
tuted through and through” (Habermas 1992: 183). Given the reaction-
ary uses for which biology has often been employed in discussions of
race and gender – epitomized in the slogan “biology is destiny” – one
can understand the skepticism toward it among progressives. Neverthe-
less, as Jean Laplanche has pointed out, sociologism is every bit as much
in error as biologism, and both forms of one-sidedness must be avoided
(Laplanche 1989: 17ff).
The linguistic strain and the transcendental strain converged in Haber-
mas’s theory and steadily moved him away from the psychoanalytic mate-
rialism he had flirted with in Knowledge and Human Interests. The idea
of systematically distorted communication that Habermas introduced to
elucidate Freud’s theory of neurosis funneled his thinking into the increas-
ingly transcendental channel that he followed for the remainder of his
career. The concept of systematically distorted communication can be
compared to Descartes’s notion of totalized delusion, resulting from the
machinations of a malevolent genius, that the founder of modern philos-
ophy employed in his philosophical construction. And just as Descartes
required an Archimedean point outside the totalized delusionary cosmos,
so Habermas must locate a standpoint outside the structure of systemati-
cally distorted communication. On purely logical grounds, systematically
distorted communication requires a concept of undistorted communication
from which its distortions can be recognized as distortions and corrected.
As Habermas observes,
At the spaceport we shook hands and Hoppy hung back after the
others had gone up the gangway. He put his hand on my shoulder.
"I'm sorry about this Adam thing, Harry."
"Forget it."
"I know how you feel, and I wish we could help. But you know how it
is...."
"Sure. I know how it is."
"The Administration's all wound up in the Rearmament Program.
Doubling the size of the space fleet. Everybody's edgy, wondering
whether there's going to be war with the Centauri crowd. Hardly
anyone remembers there is such a place as Fairyland. If we go back
and kick up a fuss, no telling what might happen. Most of the
Government budget is earmarked for defense. We might all find
ourselves among the unemployed."
I looked at him for a long time, until his eyes couldn't meet mine any
more. "Hoppy," I said quietly, "how long has it been since they
stopped thinking of Fairyland as a practical possibility?"
He shrugged, still not looking at me. "I don't know, Harry. Twelve,
maybe fifteen years, I suppose. There aren't many Happy Hooligans
around any more—at least they aren't working at it. They're all
getting rich off the defense effort."
"So they're just letting us drift along out here because it's easier than
disbanding the thing and trying to rehabilitate the Kids. That right?"
He nodded. "That's about it."
I took a deep breath, and shook my head. "Why, Hoppy? Why?"
"Oh, hell!" he blurted. "Let's face it, Harry. The whole idea just isn't
practical. It would never work."
"Never work!" I shouted. "It's been working for forty years!"
"Sure, sure—it works here. On an isolated desert planet a billion
miles from Earth, it works fine. But you can't remake the whole world
into a Fairyland, Harry. You just can't do it!"
There was a sinking, sickening feeling in my guts. "Okay, Hoppy.
Okay.... Blast off."
He stood looking at me for a moment, then turned and hurried up the
gangway.
Just as he reached the hatch, two figures emerged suddenly from
the ship. One wore the uniform of a Space Fleet astro-navigator. The
other was Adam-Two.
I ran up the gangway in time to hear the navigator telling Hoppy, "I
found him in the forward chart room."
"Adam!" I yelled. "What are you up to now?"
"I wanted to go along," he said. "I wanted to see if they were really
going to the cold side of Number One Sun."
I grabbed his arm and hustled him down to the mono-car. We slid
clear of the dock and about half a mile away I stopped the car to
watch them blast off.
Adam's eyes were wide with wonderment. "What makes it go?"
"Rocket motors," I said absently. I watched the ship, now just a mote
disappearing in the twilight sky. And I thought, There goes the tag
end of a twenty-year dream.
That was all it had ever been; I knew that now. Just a dream, and a
stupid one at that. I'd deluded myself even more than the Kids.
"What's a rocket motor?"
I looked at Adam. "What? What did you say?"
"I said, what's a rocket motor?"
"Who said anything about rocket motors?"
"You did. I asked you what makes it go and you said, rocket motors."
I frowned. "Forget it. Magic makes it go. Santa Claus magic."
"Okay, Daddy. Sure."
Something about his tone made me look sharply at him. He was
grinning at me; a cynical, adult-type grin. Yesterday it would have
made me furious. Today, for some crazy reason, it made me burst
out laughing. I laughed for quite a long time, and then as suddenly
as it began, it was over. I rumpled his hair and started the car.
"Adam," I said, "take a tip from your Daddy. Stop trying to find out
about things. Hang onto your dreams. Dreams are happy things, and
truth is sometimes pretty ugly...."
CHAPTER IV
That night after Taps I told Ruth about the Council meeting and
about my chat with Hoppy at the ship. She came and sat beside me
and, in the age-old manner of a loyal wife, assured me that
everything was going to be all right.
I stood up and began prowling around the room. "It's not all right.
The plain and simple truth is that we've thrown away twenty years on
this pipe dream. All for nothing!"
"You don't mean that, Harry. Not for nothing."
"The hell I don't! Remember how skeptical we were when we first
heard about this place? Then old Hogarth, Daddy-Two, came to see
us. Remember how we fell for it? We were going to be doing
something important! We were the vanguard of a world revolution—
the greatest thing since the invention of people. A great sociological
advancement.... What a laugh! Fairyland is nothing but a—an orphan
home! And mark my words, sooner or later they're going to come
and close the place down!"
Ruth patted the seat beside her. "Harry, come back and sit down."
I scowled at her. But I sat.
"Harry," she said, "I'm just a woman. I don't know much about world
revolutions or sociology. But I know one thing. No matter what
happens, these twenty years haven't been wasted. We've been
happy, Harry. And so have the Kids."
"I wonder.... Are they happy, Ruth? Do we even know what
happiness is?"
She smiled. "Darling, please don't go abstract on me. I know they're
happy."
"And what about Adam?"
She shook her head. "I suppose he's not. But the percentage is still
pretty high, don't you think? You said Fairyland is nothing more than
an orphan home, and maybe you're right. I guess I never really
thought of it any other way."
I stared at the woman who had been my wife for twenty-three years
as if I'd never seen her before. "You mean you never, not even at the
beginning, believed in the idea of Fairyland?"
"I just didn't think much about it, Harry. I believed in the Kids, that's
all. I figured that our job was to look after them and keep them happy
and well. We've done that job, and I think it's a pretty fine
achievement. I'm proud—for both of us!"
"Thanks," I said dully. "You know, Mommy, I'd almost forgotten...."
"Almost forgotten what, Daddy?"
I laughed shortly. "What it feels like to find out there's no Santa
Claus!"
I talked for six hours, until I was so hoarse my voice was cracking on
every other word. He took it all in stride, injecting a question here
and there, absorbing it all like an unemotional sponge. But when I
began to talk about war, he became a little upset. I explained how it
had begun as individual struggles for survival or supremacy in the
days of the cavemen, how it had evolved along with society into
struggles between families and tribes, then nations, and now—
between planets.
"But why do they kill each other, Daddy? That doesn't prove
anything."
I laughed. "Son, if I could answer that one, I'd be Daddy Number
One of the whole universe!"
We finally packed Adam off to bed in the spare room, after promising
him we'd talk some more the next night. I'd shown him my library and
told him he could come and read any time he liked, though of course
he mustn't take any books out of the house where the Kids might
see them.