III Unit
III Unit
Unit-III
The sources of law
Ramesh Arjun
Legal and Historical sources
S
ources of law can be classified as either legal or historical.
The former are those sources which are recognized as such by the law itself.
The latter are those sources lacking formal recognition by the law.
The legal sources of law are authoritative, the historical are unauthoritative.
The former are allowed by the law courts as of right the latter have no such
claim.
They influence more or less extensively the course of legal development, but
they speak with no authority.
No rule of law demands their recognition.
Thus both the statute book and the work of jermy Bentham are material
sources of English law.
The legal sources are the only gates through which new principles can find
entrance into the law.
Historical sources operate only mediately and indirectly.
They are merely the various precedent links in that chain of which the
ultimate link must be some legal source to which the rule of law is directly
attached.
For every legal system contains certain rules of recognition determining the
establishment of new law and the disappearance of old.
That is to say, it contains certain rules to this effect;
2
that all new principles which conform to such and such requirements are to
be recognized as new principles of law and applied accordingly in
substitution for or as supplementary to the old.
Thus it is itself a principle of English law that any principle involved in a
judicial decision has the force of law.
Similar legal recognition is extended to the law-producing effect of statutes
and immemorial customs.
Rules such as these establish the sources of the law.
A source of law, then, is any fact which in accordance with such basic legal rules
determines the recognition and acceptance of any new rule as having the force of
law.
The nature of legislation
The term legislation is derived from two Latin words, Legis meaning law and
latum meaning to make, put or set.
Etymologically, legislation means the making or the setting of law.
Legislation is that source of law which consists in the declaration of legal
rules by a competent authority.
To legislate is to make new law in any fashion.
In this sense, any act done with the effect of adding to or altering the law is
an act of legislative authority.
As so used, legislation includes all the sources of law, and not merely one of them.
Thus when judges establish a new principle by means of a judicial decision, they
may be said to exercise legislative, and not merely judicial power. In the strict
sense, however, legislation is the laying down of legal rules by a sovereign or
subordinate legislator.
Here we must distinguish law-making by legislators from law-making by the
courts.
3
Legislators can lay down rules purely for the future and without reference to
any actual dispute;
The courts, in so far as they create law, can do so only in application to the
cases before them and only in so far as is necessary for their solution.
Judicial law-making is incidental to the solving of legal disputes;
Legislative law-making is the central function of the legislator.
Law that has its source in legislation may be most accurately termed enacted
law, all other forms being distinguished as unenacted.
Supreme and subordinate legislation
According to salmond, legislation is either supreme or subordinate.
Supreme legislation is that which proceeds from the sovereign power in the
state.
It cannot be repealed, annulled or controlled by any other legislative
authority.
On the other hand, subordinate legislation is that which proceeds from any
authority other than the sovereign power.
It is dependent for its continued existence and validity on some superior
authority.
The Parliament of India possesses the power of supreme legislation.
However, there are other organs which have powers of subordinate
legislation.
Subordinate Legislation
1. Salmond refers to five kinds of subordinate legislation. As regards
subordinate legislation in the colonial field, the powers of self-government
entrusted to the colonies and other dependencies of the crown are subject to
the control of the imperial legislature which may repeal, alter or supersede
any colonial enactment.
4
2. In certain cases, legislative power has also been given to the judiciary. The
superior courts are allowed to make rules for the regulation of their own
procedure. It is a true form of legislation although it cannot create new laws
by way of precedents.
3. Municipal authorities are also allowed to make bye-laws for limited
purposes within their areas. According to Allen by a series of enactments,
notably the Public Health Acts, 1875-1976, the Municipal Corporations Act,
1882 and the Local Government Acts, 1888-1933, local authorities-country,
borough, rural and urban district councils-have powers to enact bye-laws are
punishable on conviction by summary process by fines usually not
exceeding 5. The range of subjects dealt with is immense; to take the
commonest, we may note building, advertisements, care of the sick
(hospitals, vaccination, infectious diseases), cleanliness of dwelling-houses,
housing of the working classes, town-planning schemes, nuisances,
scavenging and cleansing, police, rating, education, traffic, highways,
burials, and the conduct generally of persons in public places.
4. Sometimes the state allows private persons like universities, railway
companies, etc., to make bye-laws which are recognized and enforced by
law courts. Such legislation is usually called autonomic. The railway
company may make bye-laws for the regulation of its undertaking. Likewise
a university may make statutes for the government of its members.
Delegated Legislation:
Another kind of subordinate legislation is executive legislation or delegated
legislation.
It is true that the main function of the executive is to enforce laws but in
certain cases, the power of making rules is delegated to the various
departments of the government.
5
social conditions which may not last. Perhaps none but British Judges could have
worked it in such a way of preserving the system is to take a bold attitude towards
antiquated precedents, and to form the law in terms of broad principles. But others
take the view that law reform should be left to the legislator. As a result the judicial
approach to law reform, under a precedent system, is increasingly uncertain, and
more influenced by changes in the judicial approach to law reform, under a
precedent system, is increasingly uncertain, and more influenced by changes in the
judicial personnel than a code law system. Consequently the sphere left to judicial
law-making diminishes steadily, even if it tries to engraft itself upon statutory
interpretation.
Advantages of Precedent over Legislation
1. Precedent also has certain advantages over legislation. According to dicey
the morality of the courts is higher than the morality of the politicians.
Politicians are always swayed by popular passions and are liable to make
bad laws. On the other hand, judges decide cases in a calm atmosphere and
can afford to hold the scales even between the contending parties. They
perform their functions impartially and fearlessly.
2. According to salmond, case law enjoys greater flexibility than statute law.
Statute law suffers from the defect of rigidity. Courts are bound by the letter
of law and are not allowed to ignore the same. In the case of precedent,
analogical extension is allowed. It is true that legislation as an instrument of
reform is necessary but it cannot be denied that precedent has its own
importance as a constitutive element in the making of law although it cannot
abrogate law. In the case of England, the courts of common law by means of
precedents.
3. According to Amos, law does not become more uncertain when it is based
on precedents than when it is founded on enacted law. Although French law
12
is codified, it is still far from being uncertain. The uncertainty of English law
is nothing when compared to that of France. A French advocate has to wade
through a set of French codes, interpretations and commentaries as an
English lawyer has to do. The enactment of a law is no cure for uncertainty
in a legal system. Neither legislation nor precedent alone can completely
meet all eventualities. The gaps have to be filed by legislation and
precedents.
4. According to Gray, case law is not only superior to statute law but all law is
judge-made law. To quote him in truth, all the law is judge made law. The
shape in which a statute is imposed on the community as a guide for conduct
is that statute as interpreted by the courts. The courts put life into the dead
words of the statute.
5. It is submitted that in the present age, both legislation and precedent are
equally important and one cannot attain its end without the other. The aim of
the law is the protection and progress of society and individual. For a
planned progress, legislation is necessary. To interpret it and to apply and to
adapt it to a particular case, case law is equally necessary. Both legislation
and precedents contribute equally to the development of law.
PRECEDENT
Precedent as Source of Law
Judicial precedents are an important source of law.
They have enjoyed high authority at all times and in all Countries.
The one reason why precedent occupies so high a place in the English
system is that English judges have occupied a very high position in the
country.
They have been experts in their line and consequently their decisions have
enjoyed high reputation.
13
Nature of Precedent
A precedent is purely constitutive and in no degree abrogative.
This means that a judicial decision can make a law but cannot alter it.
Where there is a settled rule of law, it is the duty of the judges to
follow the same.
They cannot substitute their opinions for the established rule of law.
Authority of Precedent
The reason why a precedent is recognised is that a judicial decision is
presumed to be correct.
That which is delivered in judgment must be taken for established
truth and in all probability, it should be held to be true.
The practice of following precedents creates confidence in the minds
of the litigants.
Law becomes certain and known and that in itself is a great
advantage.
Decisions are given by judges who are experts in the study of law.
When the law is settled, it gets into the text-books which are a very
considerable guide to practitioners.”
According to Dr. Julius Stone: “Precedent had played and will
continue to play a most important part in common law judicial
achievement.
Circumstances which destroy or weaken the binding force of precedent
The operation of precedent is based on the legal presumption that
judicial decisions are correct.
A matter once decided is decided once for all.
What has been delivered in a judgment must be taken to be an
established truth.
14
yet not appreciate its relevance to the matter in hand. Such a mistake also vitiates
the decision. Even a lower court can refuse to follow a precedent
(iv) Inconsistency with Earlier Decisions of Higher Court.-A precedent
loses its binding force if the court that decided it overlooked an inconsistent
decision of a higher court. Thus, if the High Court of Delhi decides a case in
ignorance of a decision of the Supreme Court of India, the decision of the High
Court of Delhi is not a precedent and hence is not binding on any lower court. Such
a decision is said to be per incuriam.
(v) Inconsistency between Earlier Decisions of the Same Rank.–A court
is not bound by its own previous decisions that are in conflict with one another.
The court of appeal and other courts are free to choose between conflicting
decisions, even though this might amount to preferring an earlier decision to a later
decision, preferring an unreported decision to a reported decision and preferring a
decision of a court of coordinate jurisdiction to its own decision.
Where authorities of equal standing are irreconcilably in conflict, a lower
court has the same freedom to pick and choose between them. The lower court may
refuse to follow the later decision on the ground that it was arrived at per incuriam,
or it may follow such decision on the ground that it is the latest decision. Which of
these two courses the Court adopts depends upon its own view what the law ought
to be.
(vi) Precedents sub silentio or not Fully Argued.–When a particular point
involved in a decision is not taken notice of and is not argued by a counsel, the
court may decide in favour of one party, whereas if all the points had been put
forth, the decision may have been in favour of the other party. Hence such a rule is
not an authority on the point which had not been argued and this point is said to
pass sub silentio. This rule can be traced in English law to 1661 when in a famous
16
English case, the counsel said, “a hundred precedents sub silentio are not material,”
and the judge agreed.
(vii) Decisions of Equally Divided Courts.–Where an appellate court is
equally divided, the practice is to dismiss the appeal. The rule adopted in the
House of Lords is that the decision appealed from becomes the decision of the
House of Lords. This problem is not a serious one today as it is the usual practice
of most appellate courts to sit with an uneven number of judges like three or five.
(viii) Erroneous Decisions.–Decisions may also eror by being founded on
wrong principles or by conflicting with fundamental principles of common law.
Logic suggests that court should be free to disregard those decisions, but practical
considerations may require that perfection may be sacrificed to certainty. Where
the decision has stood for some length of time and has been regarded as established
in the law, the people must have acted while relying on it and dealt with the
property and made contracts on the strength of it and in general made it a basis of
expectations and a ground of mutual dealings. In such circumstances, it is better
that the decision, though founded in error, should stand. However, courts may
overrule erroneous decisions of long standing which involve injustice to the citizen
or which concern an area of law such as taxation where it is important for the
citizen that the courts should establish what the correct law is.
Circumstances which increase the authority of a precedent
There are circumstances which tend to increase the authority of a precedent.
The number of judges constituting the Bench and their eminence is a very
important factor in increasing the authority of a precedent. To some extent, the
eminence of the lawyers who argued the case enhances the authority of a
precedent. A unanimous decision carries more weight. Affirmation, approval or
following by other courts, especially by a higher tribunal, adds to the strength of a
precedent. If an Act is passed embodying the law in a precedent, the precedent
17
gains an added authority. To a limited extent, the lapse of time adds to the
authority of a decision. Likewise, if a precedent is not followed for a long time, its
authority starts deteriorating.
Stare Decisis
The doctrine of stare decisis has been recognised by the Constitution of
India. Article 141 provides that the law declared by the Supreme Court of India
shall be binding on all courts in India. Although the expression “all courts” is wide
enough to cover the Supreme Court of India itself, it has been held in Bengal
Immunity Co. Ltd. v. State of Bihar that the expression does not include the
Supreme Court of India. The result is that like the House of Lords, the Supreme
Court is free to depart from its previous decisions if valid reasons exist for doing
so.
In Mahadeolal v. Administrator-General of West Bengal, the Supreme Court
held that judges of coordinate jurisdiction should not set aside one another’s
judgments, for judicial decorum no less than judicial propriety, forms the basis of
judicial procedure and certainty in law is not only desirable but also essential.
When a single judge of a High Court is of the opinion that the previous decision of
another single judge of the same High Court on a point of law is erroneous, he
should refer the matter to a larger bench and should not himself hold that the
previous decision is wrong. This rule applies not only to judges sitting singly but
also to divisional benches. One division bench should not set aside the decision of
another division bench of the same High Court.
In Sheshamma v. Venkata Rao, the Madras High Court held that a division
bench is the final court of appeal in a High Court in India. If a division bench does
not accept as correct the decision, on a question of law, of another division bench
of that court, the only proper course is to refer the matter to a full bench. (1940
Mad U 400).
18
A similar view was taken by the Andhra Pradesh High Court in Yedlapat
Venkateshwarlu v. state of Andhra Pradesh. It was held that if one division bench
of a High court has expressed a view and another division bench is not inclined to
agree with it, the latter cannot, by itself, express a contrary view, but must refer the
matter to a full bench.
Under the stare decisis rule, a principle of the law which has become settled
by a series of decisions is generally binding on the courts and should be followed
in similar cases. This rule is based on expediency and public policy. Although this
rule is generally followed by the courts, it is not applicable in all cases. The reason
is that previous decisions should not be allowed to perpetuate a wrong if the court
is convinced that the previous decision is wrong. The rule of stare decisis is not so
imperative or inflexible that it cannot be departed from but its application must be
determined in each case by the discretion of the court and previous decisions
should not be followed to the extent that error may be perpetuated and grievous
wrong may result.
A similar view was taken by the Supreme Court of India in Bachan Singh v.
state of Punjab. It was urged before the Supreme Court that the question of
constitutional validity of death sentence stood concluded against the petitioners by
the decision of a Constitution Bench of 5 Judges of the Supreme Court in
Jagmohan Singh v. State of UP and could not therefore be allowed to be reagitated
before a bench consisting of the same number of judges. The plea was rejected by
the Supreme Court. It was pointed out that the rule of state decisis, though a
necessary tool in what Maitland called the legal smithy is only a useful servant and
cannot be allowed to turn into a tyrannous master. Reliance was placed on the
following observation of brandies, J. in state of Washington v. Dawson and co…
“Stare decisis is ordinarily a wise rule of action. But it is not a universal and
inexorable command.” If the rule of stare decisis was followed blindly and
19
mechanically, it would dwarf and stultify the growth of law and affect its capacity
to adjust itself to the changing needs of society.
The Supreme Court emphasised the necessity of ridding stare decisis of
something of its petrifying rigidity and warned with Cardozo, J. that “in many
instances the principles and rules and concepts of our own creation are merely
apercus and glimpses of reality” and “the need of reformulating them or at times
abandoning them altogether when they stand condemned as mischievous in the
social Consciousness of the hour, the social consciousness which it is our business
as judges to interpret as best as we can.”
The Supreme Court pointed out that in the present case there were
supervening circumstances which justified a reconsideration of the decision in the
case of Jagmohan Singh. One circumstance was the introduction of the new Code
of Criminal Procedure in 1973 by which Section 354(3) made life sentence the rule
in case of offences punishable with death or in the alternative imprisonment for life
and provided for imposition of sentence of death only in exceptional cases for
special reasons. Another supervening circumstance was the decision of the
Supreme Court in Maneka Gandhi v. Union of India which gave a new
interpretation to Articles 21 and 14 of the Constitution of India. The new
dimension of Articles 21 and 14 rendered death penalty provided in Section 302 of
the Indian Penal Code read with Section 354(3) of the Code of Criminal Procedure,
1973, vulnerable to an attack on a ground which was not available at the time when
the case of Jagrnohan Singh was Singh decided in 1973. (Moreover, since the case
of Jagmohan Siagh was decided, India had ratified two international instruments of
human rights and particularly the International Covenant on Civil and Political
Rights. Under those circumstances, the Supreme Court did not follow the principle
of stare decisis.
20
Ratio Decidendi
According to Salmond: “A precedent is a judicial decision which contains in
itself a principle. The underlying principle which thus forms its authoritative
element is often termed the ratio decidendi. The concrete decision is binding
between the parties to it but it is the abstract ratio decidendi which alone has the
force of law as regards the world at large.”
Rupert Cross says that a ratio decidendi is a rule of law expressly or
impliedly treated by the judge as a necessary step in reaching his conclusion.
Professor Goodhart points out that the ratio decidendi is not the reason for
the decision because the reason may be bad and yet the case may come to be an
authority. The ratio decidendi is also not necessarily the proposition of law stated
in the judgment. There may be no rule of law expressly set out or there may be
several rules of law set out by different judges as in appellate decisions. The rule
may be broader than is necessary to cover the facts of the case before the court.
The view of Goodhart is that ratio decidendi is nothing more than the decision
based on the material facts of the case. There are certain rules by which the
material facts can be discovered. Certain facts may be presumed to be immaterial
unless expressly stated to be material. Such would be the facts regarding time,
place, name, amount, etc. If the judgment does not give the facts, the facts stated in
the report must he assumed to be material. If the judgment does state the facts, we
must not look beyond that. The difficulty is as to how much of these facts the judge
has treated as material. The view of Goodhart is that facts such as time, place, etc.,
are presumed to be immaterial unless expressly stated to be material. If the
judgment does not distinguish between the material and immaterial facts, all facts
mentioned in it must be considered to be material except facts regarding time,
place, etc. All facts which the judge has expressly or impliedly treated as
immaterial must be ignored. The ratio decidendi is the decision as applied to the
21
follow them. They can take advantage of them but they are not bound to follow
them. Obiter dicta help in the growth of law. These sometimes help the cause of
the reform of law. The judges are expected to know the law and their observations
are bound to carry weight with the government. The defects in the legal system can
be pointed out in the obiter dicta. The judges are not bound to make their
observations on a particular point unless that is strictly relevant to the point in issue
but if they feel that they must speak out their own minds on a particular point, the
public should be grateful to them for their labour of love.
According to Professor Patterson, an obiter dictum is a “statement of law in
the opinion which could not logically he a major premise of the selected facts of
the decision”. In Lickbarrow v. Mason, Ashhurst, J. observed that “wherever one
of the two innocent persons must suffer by the acts of a third, he who has enabled
such third person to occasion the loss must sustain it”. This could logically have
formed the major premise of the decision if it is ever permissible to treat such a
statement as a major premise and the decision that the defendant should have
judgment is the conclusion of any syllogism. The observation of Ashhurst, J. was
nonetheless a dictum and has been so treated ever since it was made. The ratio
decidendi was that the right of stoppage in transitu is unavailable against an
indorsee for value of a bill of lading.
Dr. Goodhart defines obiter dictum as “a conclusion based on a fact the
existence of which has not been determined by the court”.
It is a truism upon which there is no need to enlarge that dicta are of varying
degrees of persuasiveness. At the end of the scale we have the considered opinion
of all the members of the House of Lords who sat to hear a case. At the other end
of the scale we have broad observations made on the spur of the moment such as
the remark which prompted Lord Abinger to say: “It was not only an obiter dictum,
but a very wide divaricating dictum.” Dicta of the highest degree of persuasiveness
23
CUSTOM
Definition
Custom is also an important source of law and it is desirable to define the
same. According to Salmond, custom is the embodiment of those principles which
have commended themselves to the national conscience as principles of justice and
public utility.
According to Keeton, customary law may be defined as those rules of human
action, established by usage and regarded as legally binding by those to whom the
rules are applicable, which are adopted by the courts and applied as sources of law
because they are generally followed by the political society as a whole or by some
part of it.
According to Carter: “The simplest definition of custom is that it is the
uniformity of conduct of all persons under like circumstances.” According to
Holland, custom is a generally observed course of conduct. According to Austin,
custom is a rule of conduct which the governed observe spontaneously and not in
pursuance of law settled by a political superior.
According to Allen, custom as a legal and social phenomenon grows up by
forces inherent in society, forces partly of reason and necessity and partly of
suggestion and limitation.
Origin of Custom
Custom is the oldest form of law-making.
A study of ancient law shows that in primitive society, the lives of the
people were regulated by customs which developed spontaneously
according to circumstances.
It was felt that a particular way of doing things was more convenient
than others.
25
When the same thing was done again and again in a particular way, it
assumed the form of custom.
Holland rightly points out that custom originated in the conscious
choice by the people of the more convenient of the two acts.
Imitation also must have played an important part in the growth of
customs.
a moral well-being;.
Nature perpetuates itself by repetition and the three fundamental
forms of repetition are rhythm or undulation, generation and imitation.
They grew up by gradual process in the households and daily relations
of the clans, and the magistrate only came in at a later stage, when the
custom was already in operation, and added to the sanction of general
recognition the express formulation of judicial and expert authority.”
A study of ancient society shows that law-making was not the
business of the kings.
Law of the country was to be found in the customs of the people.
The people were accustomed to a particular way of living and doing
things and that was to be found in the customs of society.
The King was anxious to rule the people according to the popular
notions of right and wrong and those were to be found in their
customs.
Later on, the same custom was recognised by the sovereign by putting
his imprimatur on it.
It was in this way that Custom was transformed into law.
Custom was vague in the beginning but it became definite