Pluralisms in Truth and Logic 1St Ed Edition Jeremy Wyatt Full Chapter PDF

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 64

Pluralisms in Truth and Logic 1st ed.

Edition Jeremy Wyatt


Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://ebookmass.com/product/pluralisms-in-truth-and-logic-1st-ed-edition-jeremy-wy
att/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

Seeking Truth and Hiding Facts Jeremy L. Wallace

https://ebookmass.com/product/seeking-truth-and-hiding-facts-
jeremy-l-wallace/

Seeking Truth and Hiding Facts: Information, Ideology,


and Authoritarianism in China Jeremy L. Wallace

https://ebookmass.com/product/seeking-truth-and-hiding-facts-
information-ideology-and-authoritarianism-in-china-jeremy-l-
wallace/

The Historical and Philosophical Significance of Ayer’s


Language, Truth and Logic 1st Edition Adam Tamas Tuboly

https://ebookmass.com/product/the-historical-and-philosophical-
significance-of-ayers-language-truth-and-logic-1st-edition-adam-
tamas-tuboly/

Murdoch on Truth and Love 1st ed. Edition Gary Browning

https://ebookmass.com/product/murdoch-on-truth-and-love-1st-ed-
edition-gary-browning/
In Search of Truth Sharon Wray

https://ebookmass.com/product/in-search-of-truth-sharon-wray/

Applying Language Technology in Humanities Research:


Design, Application, and the Underlying Logic 1st ed.
Edition Barbara Mcgillivray

https://ebookmass.com/product/applying-language-technology-in-
humanities-research-design-application-and-the-underlying-
logic-1st-ed-edition-barbara-mcgillivray/

Back to the ‘30s? : Recurring Crises of Capitalism,


Liberalism, and Democracy 1st ed. Edition Jeremy Rayner

https://ebookmass.com/product/back-to-the-30s-recurring-crises-
of-capitalism-liberalism-and-democracy-1st-ed-edition-jeremy-
rayner/

The Bounds of Transcendental Logic 1st ed. 2022 Edition


Dennis Schulting

https://ebookmass.com/product/the-bounds-of-transcendental-
logic-1st-ed-2022-edition-dennis-schulting/

James Bond Uncovered (Palgrave Studies in Adaptation


and Visual Culture) 1st Edition Jeremy Strong

https://ebookmass.com/product/james-bond-uncovered-palgrave-
studies-in-adaptation-and-visual-culture-1st-edition-jeremy-
strong/
Pluralisms in Truth
and Logic
Edited by
Jeremy Wyatt
Nikolaj J. L. L. Pedersen
Nathan Kellen
Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy

Series Editors
Vincent Hendricks
University of Copenhagen
Copenhagen, Denmark

Duncan Pritchard
University of Edinburgh
Edinburgh, UK
Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy is a new series of monographs. Each
book in the series will constitute the ‘new wave’ of philosophy, both in
terms of its topic and the research profile of the author. The books will be
concerned with exciting new research topics of particular contemporary
interest, and will include topics at the intersection of Philosophy and
other research areas. They will be written by up-and-coming young phi-
losophers who have already established a strong research profile and who
are clearly going to be leading researchers of the future. Each monograph
in this series will provide an overview of the research area in question
while at the same time significantly advancing the debate on this topic
and giving the reader a sense of where this debate might be heading next.
The books in the series would be of interest to researchers and advanced
students within philosophy and its neighboring scientific environments.

More information about this series at


http://www.palgrave.com/gp/series/14689
Jeremy Wyatt
Nikolaj J. L. L. Pedersen • Nathan Kellen
Editors

Pluralisms in Truth
and Logic
Editors
Jeremy Wyatt Nikolaj J. L. L. Pedersen
Underwood International College Underwood International College
Yonsei University Yonsei University
Incheon, South Korea Incheon, South Korea

Nathan Kellen
University of Connecticut,
Storrs, CT, USA

Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy


ISBN 978-3-319-98345-5    ISBN 978-3-319-98346-2 (eBook)
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-98346-2

Library of Congress Control Number: 2018963837

© The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s) 2018


This work is subject to copyright. All rights are solely and exclusively licensed by the Publisher, whether
the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of
illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and trans-
mission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or
dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed.
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication
does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant
protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book
are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or
the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any
errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional
claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Cover illustration: Bashutskyy shutterstock.com

This Palgrave Macmillan imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature Switzerland AG
The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland
Preface

Pluralism has made inroads into a number of areas in philosophy. This


edited collection brings together 18 state-of-the-art articles on pluralism
about truth and logic.
We first discussed the possibility of an edited collection shortly after
the Truth Pluralism and Logical Pluralism Conference, held at the
University of Connecticut in April of 2015. Following this conference,
several additional pluralism-related events took place, including three
workshops hosted by the Cogito Research Centre at the University of
Bologna in 2015 and 2016 and Pluralisms Week, hosted by the Pluralisms
Global Research Network and the Veritas Research Center at Yonsei
University in June of 2016. A fair number of contributors were given the
chance to present and discuss their work at one or several of these events.
The University of Connecticut, University of Bologna, and Yonsei
University all provided financial support. We gratefully acknowledge
their support. Two of the editors, Pedersen and Wyatt, would also like to
thank the National Research Foundation of Korea for support (grants no.
2013S1A2A2035514 and 2016S1A2A2911800).
We are grateful to many colleagues who share our interest in pluralism.
Their collegial, constructive ways of conducting research and discussions
are much appreciated. We are grateful to many people who, in some way
or another, have helped along the way. These include Jc Beall, Elke
Brendel, Colin Caret, Roy Cook, Douglas Edwards, Will Gamester,
v
vi Preface

Patrick Greenough, Sungil Han, Jinho Kang, Jiwon Kim, Junyeol Kim,
Seahwa Kim, Teresa Kouri Kissel, Kris McDaniel, Graham Priest, Agustín
Rayo, Greg Restall, Jisoo Seo, Stewart Shapiro, Gila Sher, Paul Simard
Smith, Erik Stei, Elena Tassoni, Pilar Terrés, Cory D. Wright, Crispin
Wright, Andy D. Yu, Luca Zanetti, and Elia Zardini. Special thanks go to
Filippo Ferrari, Michael P. Lynch, Sebastiano Moruzzi, and Joe Ulatowski.

Incheon, South Korea Jeremy Wyatt


 Nikolaj J. L. L. Pedersen
Storrs, CT, USA Nathan Kellen
Contents

Part I Truth    1

Introduction  3
Nikolaj J. L. L. Pedersen, Jeremy Wyatt, and Nathan Kellen

Truth: One or Many or Both? 35


Dorit Bar-On and Keith Simmons

Truth Pluralism, Quasi-Realism, and the Problem of Double-­


Counting 63
Michael P. Lynch

The Metaphysics of Domains 85


Douglas Edwards

Strong Truth Pluralism107


Seahwa Kim and Nikolaj J. L. L. Pedersen

vii
viii Contents

Methodological Pluralism About Truth131


Nathan Kellen

Normative Alethic Pluralism145


Filippo Ferrari

Truth in English and Elsewhere: An Empirically-Informed


Functionalism169
Jeremy Wyatt

Part II Logic 197

Core Logic: A Conspectus199


Neil Tennant

Connective Meaning in Beall and Restall’s Logical Pluralism217


Teresa Kouri Kissel

Generalised Tarski’s Thesis Hits Substructure237


Elia Zardini

Logical Particularism277
Gillman Payette and Nicole Wyatt

Logical Nihilism301
Aaron J. Cotnoir

Varieties of Logical Consequence by Their Resistance to


Logical Nihilism331
Gillian Russell
Contents ix

Part III Connections 363

Pluralism About Pluralisms365


Roy T. Cook

A Plea for Immodesty: Alethic Pluralism, Logical Pluralism,


and Mixed Inferences387
Chase B. Wrenn

Logic for Alethic, Logical, and Ontological Pluralists407


Andy D. Yu

Pluralisms: Logic, Truth and Domain-Specificity429


Rosanna Keefe

Aletheic and Logical Pluralism453


Kevin Scharp

Index473
Notes on Contributors

Dorit Bar-On is Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, and


Director of the Expression, Communication, and the Origins of Meaning
Research Group, University of Connecticut. Bar-On is well known for her work
in philosophy of language, mind, and meta­ethics. She is author of Speaking My
Mind: Expression and Self­Knowledge (Clarendon Press, 2004) and has published
in journals such as The Journal of Philosophy, Mind & Language, Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, Noûs, Synthese, and Philosophical Studies.
Roy T. Cook is Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University
of Minnesota. Cook specializes in the philosophy of logic, philosophical logic,
philosophy of mathematics, and aesthetics. He is the author of Paradoxes (Polity,
2013) and The Yablo Paradox: An Essay on Circularity (OUP, 2014), as well as
many papers in journals such as Mind, Analysis, Journal of Symbolic Logic,
Philosophia Mathematica, and Australasian Journal of Philosophy.
Aaron J. Cotnoir is Senior Lecturer, Department of Philosophy, University of
St Andrews. Cotnoir’s work is centered around metaphysics and philosophical
logic. He is the editor of Composition as Identity (OUP, 2014, with Donald
Baxter) and co-author of Mereology (OUP, forthcoming). His articles have
appeared in Journal of Philosophy, Mind, Noûs, Australasian Journal of Philosophy,
and more.
Douglas Edwards is Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Department of
Philosophy, Utica College. Edwards’ research centers around metaphysics, the
philosophy of language, and metaethics. He is the author of Properties (Polity,

xi
xii Notes on Contributors

2014) and The Metaphysics of Truth (OUP, 2018) and the editor of Truth: A
Contemporary Reader (Bloomsbury, under contract). His articles have appeared
in a number of journals, including the Journal of Philosophy, Australasian Journal
of Philosophy, and Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, amongst others.
Filippo Ferrari is Postdoctoral Research Fellow at the Institute of Philosophy,
University of Bonn. His research focuses primarily on two clusters of topics: the
normative aspects of enquiry and the debate about the nature of truth. He has
published his work in journals such as Mind, Synthese, Analysis, and Philosophical
Quarterly.
Rosanna Keefe is Professor of Philosophy and Head, Department of
Philosophy, University of Sheffield. Keefe specializes in philosophy of logic, phi-
losophy of language, and metaphysics. She is the author of Theories of Vagueness
(Cambridge, 2000) and numerous articles in journals such as Mind, Analysis,
Philosophical Studies, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, and Synthese.
Nathan Kellen works at the Department of Philosophy, University of
Connecticut. Kellen’s work is on truth, the philosophy of logic, philosophy of
mathematics, and ethics. Currently his main research project is an investigation
of truth pluralism and logical pluralism. He explores both of these views indi-
vidually but likewise examines how they might be connected.
Seahwa Kim is Professor of Philosophy and Dean, Scranton College, Ewha
Womans University. Kim specializes in metaphysics and the philosophy of
mathematics. Her articles have appeared in journals such as Australasian Journal
of Philosophy, Philosophical Studies, and Erkenntnis.
Teresa Kouri Kissel is Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Old
Dominion University. Kouri Kissel specializes in philosophy of logic, philoso-
phy of mathematics, and mathematical and philosophical logic. Her dissertation
develops a new, neo­Carnapian form of logical pluralism. Her articles have
appeared in Philosophia Mathematica, Erkenntnis, and Topoi.
Michael P. Lynch is Professor of Philosophy and Director, Humanities
Institute, University of Connecticut. Lynch’s work focuses on questions in meta-
physics, the philosophy of language, epistemology, and metaethics. He is author
of Truth in Context (MIT, 1998), True to Life (MIT, 2004), and Truth as One
and Many (OUP, 2009), as well as two books for popular audiences and a num-
ber of different articles in journals such as Philosophical Quarterly, Australasian
Journal of Philosophy, and Philosophical Studies.
Notes on Contributors xiii

Gillman Payette is Postdoctoral Fellow at the University of British Columbia.


His main research interests are philosophical logic and the philosophy of logic.
He has published in journals such as Journal of Philosophical Logic, Australasian
Journal of Philosophy, Synthese, Logique et Analyse, and Notre Dame Journal of
Formal Logic.
Nikolaj J. L. L. Pedersen is Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of
the UIC Research Institute and Veritas Research Center, Underwood
International College, Yonsei University. He has been the principal investigator
of several collaborative research projects. Pedersen’s main research areas are truth,
epistemology, and metaphysics. He has published in journals such as Noûs,
Analysis, Philosophical Quarterly, Synthese, Erkenntnis, and The Monist. He is a
co­editor of New Waves in Truth (Palgrave Macmillan, 2010), Truth and Pluralism:
Current Debates (Oxford University Press, 2013), Epistemic Pluralism (Palgrave
Macmillan, 2017), Epistemic Entitlement (Oxford University Press, 2019), and
The Routledge Handbook of Social Epistemology (2019).
Gillian Russell is Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy,
University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill. Russell specializes on the philoso-
phy of language, philosophy of logic, and epistemology. She is the author of
Truth in Virtue of Meaning: A Defence of the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction (OUP,
2008) and her articles have appeared in journals such as Journal of Philosophical
Logic, Philosophical Studies, and Australasian Journal of Philosophy.
Kevin Scharp is Reader in Philosophy, Department of Philosophy and Director,
Arché Philosophical Research Centre, University of St Andrews. Scharp special-
izes in the philosophy of language, logic, metaphysics, philosophy of science,
and the history of analytic philosophy. He is the author of Replacing Truth (OUP,
2013) and numerous articles in journals such as The Philosophical Review,
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Erkenntnis, and Philosophical Studies.
Keith Simmons is Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy,
University of Connecticut. Simmons specializes in logic, philosophy of lan-
guage, and metaphysics. He is the author of Universality and the Liar (OUP,
1993) and has had articles appear in Philosophical Studies, Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, and Journal of Philosophical Logic, amongst other
journals.
Neil Tennant is Arts and Humanities Distinguished Professor of Philosophy,
Department of Philosophy, Ohio State University. Tennant specializes in logic,
philosophy of mathematics, and the philosophy of language. He is the author of
xiv Notes on Contributors

a number of books, including The Taming of the True (OUP, 2002) and Changes
of Mind: An Essay on Rational Belief Revision (OUP, 2012). His articles have
appeared in many journals, including Mind, Philosophia Mathematica, Review of
Symbolic Logic, and Noûs.
Chase B. Wrenn is Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy,
University of Alabama. Wrenn’s research focuses on truth, epistemology, and the
philosophy of mind and cognitive science. He is the author of Truth (Polity,
2014) and has had articles appear in journals including Australasian Journal of
Philosophy, Erkenntnis, Synthese, and The Philosophical Quarterly.
Jeremy Wyatt is Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Underwood International
College, Yonsei University. Wyatt’s main research interests are the philosophy of
language, metaphysics, and truth. His articles have appeared in Philosophical
Studies, Philosophical Quarterly, American Philosophical Quarterly, and Inquiry.
Andy D. Yu is JD student, University of Toronto. Yu completed a D.Phil. the-
sis (Fragmented Truth) at the University of Oxford. He works on philosophical
logic, the philosophy of language, metaphysics, and epistemology. He has pub-
lished in the Journal of Philosophy, Philosophical Quarterly, and Thought.
Elia Zardini is Mid­Career FCT Fellow, LanCog Research Group, University of
Lisbon. Zardini specializes in logic and epistemology and has had articles appear
in many journals, including The Review of Symbolic Logic, Philosophical Studies,
Analysis, and Journal of Philosophical Logic. He is also the editor or co­editor of
Scepticism and Perceptual Justification (OUP, 2014), Substructural Approaches to
Paradox (special issue of Synthese, forthcoming), The Sorites Paradox (CUP, forth-
coming), and The A Priori: Its Significance, Grounds, and Extent (OUP,
forthcoming).
List of Figures

Truth in English and Elsewhere: An Empirically-Informed


Functionalism
Fig. 1 Alethic functionalism 173
Fig. 2 Consistency of interlinguistic and intralinguistic pluralism 177
Fig. 3 Updated functionalism 184
Core Logic: A Conspectus
Fig. 1 From classical logic to core logic 203
Fig. 2 Important system containments 204
Varieties of Logical Consequence by Their Resistance to Logical
Nihilism
Fig. 1 A truth-table proof of Modus tollens 343
Fig. 2 A paraconsistent truth-table of Modus tollens 344

xv
Part I
Truth
Introduction
Nikolaj J. L. L. Pedersen, Jeremy Wyatt,
and Nathan Kellen

1 Pluralisms
The history of philosophy displays little consensus or convergence when
it comes to the nature of truth. Radically different views have been pro-
posed and developed. Some have taken truth to be correspondence with
reality, while others have taken it to be coherence with a maximally coher-
ent set of beliefs. Yet others have taken truth to be what it is useful to
believe, or what would be believed at the end of enquiry.1 While these
views differ very significantly in terms of their specific philosophical com-
mitments, they all share two fundamental assumptions: monism and sub-
stantivism. The views all assume that truth is to be accounted for in the

N. J. L. L. Pedersen (*)
Underwood International College, Yonsei University, Incheon, South Korea
e-mail: [email protected]
J. Wyatt
Underwood International College, Yonsei University, Incheon, South Korea
N. Kellen
University of Connecticut, Storrs, CT, USA

© The Author(s) 2018 3


J. Wyatt et al. (eds.), Pluralisms in Truth and Logic, Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-98346-2_1
4 N. J. L. L. Pedersen et al.

same way across the full range of truth-apt discourse (monism) and that
truth is a substantive property or relation (substantivism).
The deflationist reaction to the traditional debate is to reject substantiv-
ism and, in some cases, to endorse monism. Truth, if it has a nature at all,
has a uniform nature across all truth-apt discourse, but there is not much
to say about it. The traditional debate went off-track exactly because
truth theorists thought that there was a whole lot to say about truth—
that somehow it had a deep or underlying nature that could be uncovered
through philosophical theorizing. Instead, according to many deflation-
ists, the (non-paradoxical) instances of the disquotational schema (“p” is
true if and only p) or the equivalence schema (it is true that p if and only
if p) exhaust what there is to say about truth.2
The pluralist reaction to the traditional debate is to reject monism and
endorse substantivism. Truth pluralists, encouraged by the seminal work
of Crispin Wright and Michael Lynch, appeal to more than one property
in their account of truth. Propositions from different domains of dis-
course are true in different ways. The truth of propositions concerning
the empirical world (e.g., 〈There are mountains〉) might be accounted
for in terms of correspondence, while the truth of legal propositions (e.g.,
〈Speeding is illegal〉) might be accounted for in terms of coherence with
the body of law.3 This amounts to a rejection of monism. By contrast,
truth pluralists have traditionally endorsed substantivism. They have
appealed to properties or relations that are substantive in nature (where
this means, at least, that they directly explain certain facts entirely in
virtue of characteristics pertaining to their natures).4
The history of logic, like the history of truth, displays little consensus.
Advocates of classical logic, intuitionistic logic, and relevant logic, for
instance, have argued back and forth about the merits and demerits of their
preferred systems. Again, as in the case of truth, this seems to suggest a shared
underlying assumption of monism: there is a uniquely correct logic, and
advocates of different systems are disagreeing about which one it is. The plu-
ralist reaction—notably advocated by Jc Beall and Greg Restall (2006)—is
to reject monism and maintain that there are several equally correct logics.
Speaking more generally, pluralist views are becoming increasingly
prominent in different areas of philosophy. Pluralism about truth has been
extensively developed, defended, and critically discussed. The same goes
Introduction 5

for pluralism about logic.5 Pluralism has also made inroads into ontology
where the idea that there are several ways of being has been defended, sup-
ported, and articulated in various ways. The work of Kris McDaniel is a
particularly rich source.6 In epistemology, a variety of pluralist theses can
likewise be found in the literature. The idea that there are several epistemi-
cally good-making features of belief can be found in different guises, as
pluralism about epistemic justification, warrant, desiderata, and value.
Prominent epistemologists such as Alvin Goldman, Tyler Burge, William
Alston, and Crispin Wright all endorse one of these forms of pluralism.7
These pluralist trends are philosophically significant. They go against a
one-size-fits-all conception of their relevant areas and invite a reconsid-
eration of the nature and character of some of the most fundamental
notions in core areas of philosophy—including truth, validity, being, and
justification. This volume takes as its focus two of kinds of pluralism:
pluralism about truth and pluralism about logic. It brings together 18
original, state-of-the-art essays. The essays are divided into three parts.
Part I is dedicated to truth pluralism, Part II to logical pluralism, and Part
III to the question as to what connections might exist between these two
kinds of pluralism.

2 Truth Pluralism (Part I)


In this section, we will briefly introduce a range of ideas and issues that
have served to shape and define the debate concerning truth pluralism.
We will then introduce the contributions to Part I of the volume.

Background

Truth pluralists are engaged in critical debates on two fronts—one exter-


nal and the other internal. On the external front, we find pluralists debat-
ing monists as to which of these views of truth is superior. The argument
most commonly deployed by pluralists is the scope problem. Pluralists argue
that monist theories do not have a scope that is sufficiently wide to plau-
sibly accommodate all truth-apt discourse. Perhaps the c­orrespondence
6 N. J. L. L. Pedersen et al.

theory can be plausibly applied to empirical discourse, accounting for the


truth of propositions such as 〈Mt. Everest is extended in space〉. However,
it cannot plausibly cover the truth of legal propositions such as 〈Breaking
and entering is illegal〉. Now, maybe coherence with the body of law can
plausibly be applied to legal discourse. However, coherence does not seem
easily extendable to the empirical domain. Pluralists take this point to
generalize and conclude that monism is unsatisfactory. Instead, they let
several theories of truth work in tandem, restricting their range of applica-
bility to certain domains.
In connection with the internal debate, we see advocates of so-called
strong pluralism and moderate pluralism pitched against one another. They
agree that truth pluralism is the right view, but disagree over the details.
According to strong pluralists, there is no single truth property that
applies to all true propositions. Rather, there is a range of properties that
reduce or constitute truth for different propositions belonging to differ-
ent domains. Thus, the truth of 〈There are mountains〉 may reduce to
this proposition’s corresponding to reality while the truth of 〈Speeding is
illegal〉 may reduce to this proposition’s cohering with the body of law.
Crucially, there is no single property that reduces or constitutes the truth
of every true proposition. Moderate pluralists, on the other hand, endorse
a single, generic truth property. This property is possessed by every true
proposition, so that for the moderate pluralist, truth itself is one. However,
moderate pluralists also think that instances of generic truth are grounded
by instances of different truth-relevant properties. In this sense, for the
moderate pluralist, truth is also many. Thus, according to moderate plu-
ralism, truth is both one and many.8
Despite their different views on how to best articulate truth pluralism,
strong and moderate pluralists share significant commitments. One such
commitment is the commitment to domains. Domains are a crucial com-
ponent of the theoretical framework of pluralism, as reflected by the fact
that the core pluralist thesis is that the nature of truth varies across
domains.
Domains also feature prominently in some of the main challenges
faced by truth pluralists. Problems concerning mixed discourse are cases in
point. Mixed discourse is discourse that cuts across domains. Such
­discourse occurs at three different levels: the levels of atomics, com-
pounds, and inferences. Consider the propositions that are expressed in:
Introduction 7

(mix-atom) π is beautiful.

(mix-comp) Mt. Everest is extended in space and Bob’s drunk driving is


illegal.

(mix-inf ) If Mt. Everest is extended in space, then Bob’s drunk driv-


ing is illegal.
Mr. Everest is extended in space.
Bob’s drunk driving is illegal.

〈π is beautiful〉 is a mixed atomic proposition. It features a mathemati-


cal concept (π) and an aesthetic concept (beauty).9 However, in light of
this, should 〈π is beautiful〉 be classified as belonging to the mathemati-
cal domain, the aesthetic domain, both of these domains, or perhaps
some other domain? This question by no means seems to be a straight-
forward one to answer. However, there seems to be considerable pressure
on the pluralist to provide an answer. After all, for atomic propositions
such as 〈π is beautiful〉, the domain membership of the proposition is
meant to determine the property that is relevant to its truth. Hence,
absent a principled story about the domain membership of mixed atom-
ics, there would be a whole cluster of propositions whose truth would
remain unaccounted for. This is the problem of mixed atomics.
〈Mt. Everest is extended in space and Bob’s drunk driving is illegal〉 is
a mixed conjunction. Its first conjunct belongs to the empirical domain,
and its second conjunct to the legal domain. The conjunction is true, as
both of its conjuncts are. However, it is not clear what story the pluralist
is going to tell about this. We can suppose that correspondence to reality
and coherence with the body of law are, respectively, the truth-relevant
properties for the two conjuncts. However, neither correspondence nor
coherence seems like a plausible candidate when we try to account for the
truth of the conjunction itself. Now, if the truth-relevant property of
neither the first nor the second conjunct is the right property, the con-
junction must have some third property. However, what property would
that be? The problem of mixed compounds challenges pluralists to tell a
story about the truth of mixed compounds.
8 N. J. L. L. Pedersen et al.

The inference from 〈If Mt. Everest is extended in space, then Bob’s
drunk driving is illegal〉 and 〈Mr. Everest is extended in space〉 to 〈Bob’s
drunk driving is illegal〉 is a mixed inference. It is also a valid inference—
that is, necessarily, if the premises are true, then so is the conclusion. In
order to account for the validity of the inference, it would seem that there
must be some truth-relevant property that the premises and conclusion
all share which ensures that truth is preserved from premises to conclu-
sion. However, the pluralist seems to be unable to point to a property
that satisfies this constraint. For, as before, we can suppose that corre-
spondence to reality is the truth-relevant property for 〈Mr. Everest is
extended in space〉 and coherence with the body of law for 〈Bob’s drunk
driving is illegal〉. This means that one of the premises and the conclu-
sion have different truth-relevant properties. The problem of mixed infer-
ences challenges the pluralist to tell a story about the validity of mixed
inferences.10
Another fundamental problem confronting pluralists is what is some-
times called the “double-counting objection.” In essence, the objection is
that pluralists count two differences where only one is needed. They
endorse significant metaphysical differences regarding the nature of vari-
ous subject matters and, in addition, they endorse differences in the
nature of truth. However, in order to accommodate wide-ranging truth-­
aptitude, differences need only be countenanced at one level—at the level
of the things themselves (numbers, trees, moral properties, laws, etc.) or
at the level of the content associated with different domains (expressivist
content vs. representational content). Drawing distinctions at the level of
truth, the objection goes, is superfluous.11

The Contributions

Dorit Bar-On and Keith Simmons’ contribution “Truth: One or


Many?” runs a version of the double-counting objection. Prominent
pluralists such as Wright and Lynch claim that one motivation for
adopting truth pluralism is that it puts one in a position to make
sense of disputes between realists and anti-realists. Adopting the the-
sis that the nature of truth varies across domains, it is possible for the
Introduction 9

pluralist to account for the “differential appeal of realist and anti-


realist intuitions” about them.12 Bar-On and Simmons counter by
arguing that truth pluralism offers no distinctive explanatory power
vis-à-vis the realism/anti-realism debate. Rather, all that is needed is a
plurality of kinds of worldly conditions that track metaphysical differ-
ences. Bar-On and Simmons’ version of the double-counting objec-
tion targets not only truth pluralists but also certain kinds of truth
monists—namely, those who think that a distinction between differ-
ent kinds of content or meaning offers explanatory power vis-à-vis the
realism/anti-realism debate. Bar-On and Simmons spell out in con-
siderable detail how their proposal differs from those of truth monists
who seek to accommodate realism/anti-realism disputes by appealing
to semantic differences.
Michael P. Lynch’s contribution “Truth Pluralism, Quasi-Realism and
the Problem of Double-Counting” offers a pluralist response to the dou-
ble-counting objection—in particular, as it might be pressed by quasi-
realists such as Simon Blackburn and global expressivists such as Huw
Price. Lynch argues that semantic diversity and cognitive unity are theses
that quasi-realists, global expressivists, and truth pluralists all seek to
accommodate and explain:

(SD) There are real differences in kind between the contents of our
beliefs and indicative statements.

(CU) All beliefs and indicative statements are subject to a single


type of cognitive normative assessment of correctness.

Blackburn proposes to accommodate semantic diversity by appealing to


two sorts of propositions or two sorts of truth-aptitude. Price proposes to
accommodate semantic diversity by appealing to two kinds of representa-
tion: i-representation and e-representation. A proposition i-represents in
virtue of its inferential or functional role, while e-representation is cashed
out in terms of co-variance with the environment. Lynch argues that, in
effect, both Blackburn’s proposal and Price’s proposal result in a form of
truth pluralism. Hence, when it comes to double-counting, truth plural-
ists turn out to be no worse off than quasi-realists or global expressivists.
10 N. J. L. L. Pedersen et al.

Douglas Edwards’ contribution “The Metaphysics of Domains” pro-


vides a systematic account of domains and thus addresses a major lacuna
in the theoretical framework of truth pluralism. Edwards distinguishes
between a semantic and a metaphysical aspect of domains. He accounts
for these via a discussion of, respectively, singular terms and predicates
and their metaphysical counterparts, objects and properties. Edwards
argues that his proposed notion of domain is not a commitment of
pluralists only—it is implicit in a number of philosophical views.
Edwards demonstrates the significance of his account of domains by
arguing that it delivers a solution to two major challenges to truth plu-
ralism: the problem of mixed atomics and the problem of mixed
compounds.
Seahwa Kim and Nikolaj Jang Lee Linding Pedersen’s contribution
“Strong Truth Pluralism” provides a pluralist solution to the problem of
mixed compounds. Kim and Pedersen offer their solution against the
background of a certain form of strong pluralism. They thus deny that
there is any generic truth property that applies across all domains.
Instead they think that an atomic proposition’s being true reduces to its
corresponding to reality, cohering, or having some other “base-level
truth property.” The truth of a compound reduces to its having a com-
pound-specific truth-reducing property. For example, the truth of the
mixed conjunction 〈Mt. Everest is extended in space and Bob’s drunk
driving is illegal〉 reduces to its being a conjunction with conjuncts that
have their respective truth-reducing properties. Note that in this regard
mixed conjunctions are no different from pure conjunctions. Hence,
Kim and Pedersen’s response to the problem of mixed compounds is
that there is nothing special or problematic about them. They are true
in the same way that their pure counterparts are.
The contributions by Nathan Kellen, Filippo Ferrari, and Jeremy
Wyatt explore different ways to reconfigure or add a new dimension to
the debate concerning truth pluralism.
Kellen’s contribution “Methodological Pluralism About Truth” introduces
a meta-­perspective on the truth pluralism debate. According to Kellen,
Wright takes anti-realism to be methodologically fundamental. He does so
in the sense that anti-realist truth is taken to be the default for all domains.
Introduction 11

This is not to say that Wright is opposed to giving truth a “non-default”


treatment within some domains. However, in order for truth to receive
this kind of treatment, there must be reasons why, within that particular
domain, the default should be abandoned. Kellen likewise attributes a
thesis of methodological fundamentality to Edwards although, in con-
trast to Wright, the default is realist truth. Kellen proposes methodological
pluralism as an alternative to anti-realist and realist default forms of plu-
ralism. According to this methodological doctrine, the pluralist should
have no default for any domain but should remain neutral until reasons
have been given one way or the other.
Filippo Ferrari’s contribution “Normative Alethic Pluralism” articu-
lates a novel view concerning the normativity of truth—what he calls
“normative alethic pluralism.” He articulates this view against the back-
ground of a rejection of normative alethic monism, the view that truth’s
normative profile is uniform across all domains, and can be captured by
a single principle that connects truth and judgment. Ferrari targets nor-
mative alethic monism by employing a normative analogue of the scope
problem. By appealing to disagreements pertaining to different domains,
Ferrari argues that the normative profile of truth varies across domains. If
people disagree over whether, for example, oysters are tasty, there is no
strong sense of fault in play. On the other hand, if two parties disagree as
to whether abortion is a morally acceptable practice, there is a strong
sense of fault in play. This is reflected by each party’s tendency toward
condemnation of the other party. This normative variability cannot satis-
factorily be accommodated within the framework of normative alethic
monism. Hence, according to Ferrari, there is reason to adopt normative
alethic pluralism. There are several ways for truth to normatively regulate
judgment. Having motivated and articulated normative alethic plural-
ism, Ferrari discusses the issue of whether it might bear significant con-
nections to pluralism about truth. He concludes that the two kinds of
pluralism are compatible and may nicely complement one another. Yet,
one does not imply the other.
Jeremy Wyatt’s contribution “Truth in English and Elsewhere: An
Empirically-Informed Functionalism” presents a refined framework that
should help to shape future work on both pluralism and functionalism
12 N. J. L. L. Pedersen et al.

about truth. Wyatt argues that a proper defense of alethic functional-


ism—a view that was pioneered by Lynch—must be informed by empiri-
cal data. The alethic functionalist puts forward an account of the folk
theory of truth, which is meant to consist of the propositions about truth
that those who possess the folk concept of truth are ipso facto disposed to
believe upon reflection. The functionalist’s view on the folk theory of
truth is thus empirical in nature and should be evaluated using empirical
data. Wyatt discusses two kinds of existing data: data pertaining to alethic
vocabulary in English and preliminary data pertaining to the Ghanaian
language Akan. The English-related data suggest variation in the use of
alethic vocabulary among male and female English speakers. The prelimi-
nary data concerning Akan suggest that there are significant differences in
the alethic vocabulary that is used, respectively, by native Akan and native
English speakers. Wyatt argues that these lines of data lend support to
two kinds of pluralism regarding ordinary thought about truth—what he
calls intralinguistic and interlinguistic conceptual pluralism. In addition to
motivating these two sorts of pluralism, Wyatt shows how the functional-
ist, by adopting a more nuanced version of Lynch’s framework, can nicely
accommodate these pluralistic hypotheses.

3 Logical Pluralism (Part II)


Over the past decade, there has been a surge of interest in logical plural-
ism, one major factor being the publication of JC Beall and Greg Restall’s
Logical Pluralism.13 In this section, we will briefly introduce Beall and
Restall’s logical pluralism and the contributions to Part II of the volume.
In one way or another, most of these contributions engage with promi-
nent themes from Beall and Restall’s work.

Background

According to Beall and Restall, logic is plural in the sense that there are
several equally legitimate instances of what they call Generalized Tarski’s
Thesis (GTT):
Introduction 13

(GTT) An argument is validx if and only if in every casex in which


the premises are true, so is the conclusion.

Beall and Restall argue that there are at least three equally legitimate ways
to construe casex in GTT: cases as (consistent and complete) possible
worlds, cases as (possibly incomplete) constructions, and cases as (possibly
inconsistent) situations. These three notions of case deliver different log-
ics—respectively classical logic, intuitionistic logic, and relevant logic.
To shed further light on the nature of Beall and Restall’s logical plural-
ism, let us highlight a number of key features of their view: legitimacy,
logical functionalism, logical generalism, logical relativism, meaning con-
stancy, and structural rules and properties.

Legitimacy The standard of legitimacy for cases is given by three features


that Beall and Restall call “necessity”, “formality”, and “normativity.”
Roughly stated, necessity is the idea that valid arguments must be neces-
sarily truth-preserving; formality is the idea that validity is neutral with
respect to content; and normativity is the idea that invalid arguments
must involve a kind of mistake or fault.

Logical Functionalism The network approach to conceptual analysis can


be regarded as a form of conceptual functionalism. A target concept C is
characterized by a set of principles that connect C to other concepts. In
this way, C is characterized through its role or function within a larger
conceptual network. Beall and Restall’s view can be regarded as an
instance of the network approach. Generalized Tarski’s Thesis and the
three constraints of necessity, formality, and normativity characterize the
concept of validity via its connection to other concepts such as case,
truth, necessity, formality, and normativity. In this way, validity
is characterized through its function or role within a larger conceptual
network, and for this reason Beall and Restall’s logical pluralism involves
a form of functionalism.

Logical Generalism To borrow a phrase from Hartry Field, Beall and


Restall’s logical pluralism is a pluralism about all-purpose logics.14 Their
view is not that classical logic, intuitionistic logic, and relevant logic are
14 N. J. L. L. Pedersen et al.

legitimate only when restricted to certain domains or when used for certain
purposes. Rather, their view is that classical logic, intuitionistic logic, and
relevant logic are equally legitimate across the board. This idea can be
regarded as a form of logical generalism. The legitimacy of the logics admit-
ted by (GTT) and the three constraints is meant to be completely general.

Logical Relativism Beall and Restall’s logical pluralism involves a form of


logical relativism: statements concerning the validity of arguments only
have a truth-value relative to a particular system.15 Thus, for example, as
far as logic is concerned, there is no absolute fact of the matter as to
whether double negation elimination is valid. Instead there are logic-­
relative facts: in classical logic, double negation elimination is valid while
in intuitionistic logic, it is not.16

Meaning Constancy Beall and Restall are pluralists about validity and
logical consequence. However, they maintain that the meaning of the
logical connectives is constant across the various logics that qualify as
legitimate. This view contrasts with a view often attributed to Carnap—
namely, that different logics have different connectives.17 According to
the latter view, the meaning of “and”, “not”, “or”, etc. changes from one
logic to another. By contrast, on Beall and Restall’s view, logical expres-
sions share the same—but incomplete—meaning across logics. However,
clauses that govern the connectives in different logics capture different
aspects of that shared meaning.

Structural Rules and Properties It is common to distinguish between the


operational rules and the structural rules of a system. Operational rules
and properties concern specific logical operations (e.g., negation).
Structural rules and properties of a logic capture general features that
hold purely in virtue of premises and conclusions being structures of
unstructured objects that can be manipulated in certain ways. The fol-
lowing list specifies five well-known structural rules:

(Reflexivity) ϕ⊨ϕ

(Monotonicity) If Γ ⊨ ϕ, then Γ, Δ ⊨ ϕ
Introduction 15

(Transitivity) If Γ ⊨ ϕ and Δ, ϕ ⊨ ψ, then Δ, Γ ⊨ ψ

(Contraction) If Γ, ϕ, ϕ ⊨ ψ, then Γ, ϕ ⊨ ψ

(Commutativity) If Γ, ϕ, ψ, Δ ⊨ χ, then Γ, ψ, ϕ, Δ ⊨ χ

Reflexivity says that anything is a logical consequence of itself.


Monotonicity says that, if ϕ is a logical consequence of Γ, adding more
premises Δ does not change anything (i.e., ϕ is also logical of a conse-
quence of Γ, Δ). Transitivity says that, if ϕ is a logical consequence of Γ
and ψ is a logical consequence of Δ, ϕ, then ψ is a logical consequence of
just Δ, Γ. Contraction says that multiple occurrences of the same premise
can be cut to a single occurrence without impacting consequence.
Commutativity says that the order of premises does not matter: it can be
switched without impacting consequence. Any system that fails to accom-
modate any of the five structural rules listed above is a substructural logic.18

The Contributions

Neil Tennant’s contribution “Core Logic: A Conspectus” presents an


“absolutist pluralist” view on logic. It is absolutist in the sense that there is
a core to logic or deductive reasoning—core logic in Tennant’s terminology.
However, Tennant’s view is pluralist in that there are several legitimate
extensions of the core. Tennant is particularly interested in providing an
account of logic for mathematics. He wants to accommodate both con-
structive and non-constructive (or classical) mathematics, but argues that
all proofs should be “relevantized.” For this reason, core logic is relevant.
Thus, Tennant’s view is revisionist, as he thinks that the logics of construc-
tive and classical mathematics should be revised along relevantist lines.
The logic suitable for c­ onstructive mathematics is relevantized intuitionis-
tic logic (the core logic C) while the logic suitable for non-constructive (or
classical) mathematics is relevantized classical logic (the core logic C+).
Teresa Kouri Kissel’s contribution “Connective Meanings in Beall and
Restall’s Logical Pluralism” contests Beall and Restall’s meaning con-
stancy thesis, that is, their claim that logical expressions have the same
16 N. J. L. L. Pedersen et al.

meaning across logics. She argues that this cannot be the case for intu-
itionistic negation and relevant negation. Thus, contrary to their own
claims, Beall and Restall’s logical pluralism ends up having a Carnapian
flavor.
Elia Zardini’s contribution “Generalised Tarski’s Thesis Hits
Substructure” offers an extended argument to the effect that Beall and
Restall’s logical pluralism is overly restrictive. He shows that (GTT)
implies that logical consequence has the structural features mentioned
above, that is, reflexivity, monotonicity, transitivity, contraction, and
commutativity. For instance, in every casex in which ϕ is true, ϕ is true—
thus (GTT) implies reflexivity. By the lights of Beall-Restall logical plu-
ralism, then, any system that fails to satisfy reflexivity cannot qualify as
logic properly so-­called. Similarly, for any system that fails to satisfy
monotonicity, transitivity, contraction, or commutativity. In general,
Beall-Restall logical pluralism disqualifies any substructural logic from
qualifying as logic proper. Zardini argues that there are philosophical rea-
sons to doubt each of reflexivity, monotonicity, transitivity, contraction,
and commutativity. For instance, one might wish to abandon transitivity
in order to give an account of vagueness, and one might wish to abandon
contraction in order to address the semantic paradoxes. In light of these
considerations, Zardini deems Beall-Restall pluralism unacceptably
restrictive.
Gillman Payette and Nicole Wyatt’s contribution “Logical
Particularism” introduces and spells out a particularist view on logic.
According to logical particularism, there are no completely general
principles concerning validity. Rather, validity is a property of particu-
lar arguments or inferences. Since Payette and Wyatt think that differ-
ent, specific arguments call for different treatments vis-à-­vis validity,
their logical particularism goes hand in hand with a ­particularist ver-
sion of logical pluralism. This particularist pluralism is at odds with the
kind of logical pluralism endorsed by Beall and Restall—which, as seen
above, involves a commitment to logical generalism. Logics on the
Beall-Restall view are all-purpose logics, which means that their rules
are completely general principles concerning validity. Payette and
Wyatt’s particularist pluralism is also at odds with domain-based forms
Introduction 17

of logical pluralism. Unlike logical generalists, domain-based logical


pluralists do not think that there are completely general logical prin-
ciples. However, they do think that there are somewhat general prin-
ciples, as the rules of a domain-specific logic hold for all arguments or
inferences within the specific domain to which the logic applies. This
commitment, although weaker than generalism, is likewise at odds
with logical particularism.
Aaron Cotnoir’s contribution “Logical Nihilism” makes a case for a
species of logical nihilism. According to this view, there is no logical
consequence relation that correctly represents natural language infer-
ence; formal logics are inadequate to capture informal inference.
Cotnoir gives two clusters of arguments that lend support to logical
nihilism. The first cluster consists of arguments from diversity, the sec-
ond of arguments from expressive limitations. Arguments from diver-
sity contain two steps. The first step is an argument to the effect that no
single logic can provide an adequate account of natural language infer-
ence. The second step is an argument to the effect that at most one logic
can provide an adequate account of natural language inference.
However, nothing satisfies both of these requirements—so, no formal
logic can provide an adequate account of natural language inference.
Arguments from expressive limitations also consist of two steps. The
first is an observation to the effect that natural language contains infer-
ences involving a certain phenomenon. The second step is an argument
to the effect that no formal logic has the expressive resources to capture
inferences of that kind. Hence, due to the expressive limitations of for-
mal logics, no formal logic can provide an adequate account of natural
language inference.
Gillian Russell’s contribution “Varieties of Logical Consequence by
Their Resistance to Logical Nihilism” also speaks to the theme of logi-
cal nihilism, although a different variety than the one d ­ iscussed by
Cotnoir. Logical nihilism, as Russell approaches the view, has it that
there are no valid arguments. This view has emerged as a discussion
point in the logical pluralism debate. A criticism of Beall and Restall
is that validity should be conceived as truth-preservation across all
cases, in contrast to Beall and Restall’s strategy of pairing each type of
18 N. J. L. L. Pedersen et al.

case with a corresponding, case-specific type of validity. If validity is


thus conceived, logical nihilism (or “minimalism”) threatens—maybe
no (or only very few) arguments are truth-preserving across all cases.
Russell investigates what resources different accounts of logical conse-
quence offer when it comes to resisting the threat of nihilism. She con-
siders Etchemendy’s interpretational and representational accounts,
Quine’s substitutional account, and Williamson’s universalist account.
Williamson’s account is found to be the one that offers the strongest
path of resistance to the threat of logical nihilism. However, Russell sug-
gests that the universalist path of resistance may come at a high cost. It
may only work because the universalist account operates at a level that
does not fully engage with the problematic phenomena that fuel the
move toward nihilism (such as empty names, vagueness and incomplete
predicates, and self-reference and overdetermination).

4 Connections (Part III)


Parts I and II of the volume respectively concern truth pluralism and logi-
cal pluralism, considered and discussed (mostly) in isolation from one
another. The contributions in Part III explore potential connections
between these two kinds of pluralism.

Background

The most widely explored form of truth pluralism is domain-based. The


core idea, as we have seen, is that the nature of truth varies across domains.
Several authors have connected domain-based truth pluralism and logic,
arguing that pluralism in the case of truth supports pluralism about logic.
The target kind of logical pluralism inherits a crucial feature from its
alethic counterpart: it is domain-based. Different domains have different
logics.
The kind of argument that truth pluralists have given to support
domain-based logical pluralism can be presented as follows19:
Introduction 19

(1) If truth is epistemically constrained in one domain and epistemically


unconstrained in another domain, then different logics govern these
domains.
(2) Truth is epistemically constrained in one domain and epistemically
unconstrained in another domain.
(3) So, there are domains that are governed by different logics.

(2) is accepted by most (domain-based) truth pluralists. Many of them take


the realism/anti-realism debate as background for their truth pluralism.
They want to accommodate the appeal of realism and anti-realism with
respect to different domains. It is an integral part of the realism/anti-realism
debate that anti-realist truth is epistemically constrained while realist truth
is epistemically unconstrained. It is with this in mind that many domain-
based truth pluralists go in for (2). The idea behind (1) is that the logic of
epistemically constrained truth is intuitionistic while the logic of epistemi-
cally unconstrained truth is classical. Both (1) and (2) can be regarded as
reflections of Dummett’s influence on the realism/anti-realism debate, as it
figures in the theoretical foundations of the pluralist program.20
Domain-based logical pluralism raises some tough questions. The view
pairs individual domains with logics. However, what is to be said about
the logic of mixed inferences (sec. 2.1)? What logic governs inferences
that cut across domains with different logics? Lynch has proposed the
following principle of modesty:

(mod) The logic of a mixed compound or inference that involves


propositions from domains with distinct logics L1, …, Ln is
the intersection of L1, …, Ln.

The logic of a given mixed compound or inference is thus minimal—it is


the core shared by all the logics of the domains involved in the com-
pound or inference. Lynch himself officially endorses two logics within
his domain-based pluralist framework, viz. intuitionistic and classical
logic. This means that there is only one way for a compound or inference
to be “logically mixed”—namely, by involving those two logics. The
modesty principle tells us, then, that the logic of mixed compounds and
inferences is always intuitionistic logic.21
20 N. J. L. L. Pedersen et al.

We have just reflected on the potential connections between domain-­


based pluralisms about truth and logic. However, what other paths into
pluralist territory might there be? There are several, it would seem. For
Beall and Restall, it is cases, rather than domains, that play an integral
role in delivering pluralism about logic. One might also think that logical
pluralism can be supported by appealing to considerations regarding con-
text. Different contexts might be governed by different logics, even if the
domain at issue is the same. Consider two contexts that both involve
mathematics. It may be that in one context, proofs are subject to the
standards of intuitionistic logic because informativeness matters and con-
structive proofs are more informative. In that context, for instance, indi-
rect proofs would not be counted as valid. However, in a different context,
proofs may be subject to the standards of classical logic, so that in that
context, indirect proofs are counted as valid.22
How about truth? Here, too, there are several paths into pluralist ter-
ritory. Let us mention three. On the basis of empirical data, Robert
Barnard and Joseph Ulatowski have suggested that there are significant
differences in ordinary people’s thought and talk about truth along vari-
ous dimensions. One such dimension is gender. In connection with cer-
tain statements, male subjects’ thought and talk about truth look to align
with a correspondence conception of truth. By contrast, female subjects’
thought and talk about truth seem to not align with a correspondence
conception in these cases. At the very least, then, these data suggest that
two different notions of truth are in play.23
John MacFarlane is well-known for advocating an assessment-sensitive
brand of relativism about truth, according to which the truth of some
statements is relative to a context of assessment. However, MacFarlane
also wants to leave room for truth simpliciter. The combination of these
two commitments suggests a form of truth pluralism, which has it that
there are two basic ways of being true: being true relative to a context of
assessment and being true simpliciter.24
Several authors have argued that the semantic paradoxes—including,
famously, the liar paradox—motivate a pluralistic account of truth. One
such author is Kevin Scharp, who has recently proposed a novel approach
to the semantic paradoxes.25 Classical logic and the unrestricted
T-schema (T(ϕ) ⟷ ϕ) generate the liar paradox.26 According to Scharp,
Introduction 21

the ordinary concept of truth is characterized by the unrestricted


T-schema. This concept is rendered inconsistent by the liar paradox and
other paradoxes. Scharp’s solution is to adopt a replacement theory. The
ordinary concept of truth should be replaced by two new concepts,
descending truth and ascending truth. The axiomatic theory that goes
with Scharp’s proposal includes the following two conditionals (but
excludes the converse conditionals):

(TD) TD(ϕ) → ϕ
(TA) ϕ → TA(ϕ)

The combination of (TD) and (TA) looks superficially like the T-schema,
but it is not. The subscripts make all the difference in the world. They
indicate that the two conditionals involve different concepts—the con-
cepts that, on Scharp’s view, should replace the inconsistent, ordinary
concept of truth. Hence, the two conditionals cannot be combined into
a biconditional to yield the T-schema. Rather, according to Scharp, truth
theorists should rest content with (TD) and (TA) and the concepts of
descending and ascending truth that they respectively concern. It is in
this sense that Scharp puts forward a pluralistic account of truth—
whereas we might have thought that we could get along with a single
truth concept, Scharp’s contention is that we actually need a pair of
replacement concepts to adequately resolve the semantic paradoxes.
Insofar as Scharp’s views are motivated by the semantic paradoxes, they
represent yet another path into pluralist territory.27

The Contributions

Roy T. Cook’s contribution “Pluralism About Pluralisms” investigates


the issue of what connections, if any, there might be between truth
pluralism and logical pluralism. His investigation focuses on domain-
based versions of both views, according to which different domains
involve respectively different ways of being true and different logics. As
seen earlier, some pluralists (e.g., Lynch and Pedersen) have argued that
domain-based truth pluralism supports domain-based logical plural-
22 N. J. L. L. Pedersen et al.

ism. Cook contests this claim by constructing a formal model in which


domain-based truth pluralism holds, but domain-based logical plural-
ism fails. He also constructs a model in which domain-based logical
pluralism holds, but domain-based truth pluralism fails. On the basis
of these two models, he concludes that domain-based truth pluralism
and domain-based logical pluralism are independent. Neither entails
the other.
Lynch has two key commitments regarding logic. First, he is a
domain-­based logical pluralist. Different domains have different log-
ics. Second, he endorses (mod) for mixed inferences: the logic of a
mixed inference is the intersection of the logics of the domains
involved in the inference. Chase Wrenn’s contribution “A Plea for
Immodesty: Alethic Pluralism, Logical Pluralism, and Mixed
Inferences” critically discusses Lynch’s commitments vis-à-vis logic.
Wrenn argues that (mod) renders intuitively valid inferences invalid
and also renders intuitively invalid inferences valid. Furthermore, he
argues that it seems natural to combine (mod) with virtual logic plu-
ralism. Virtual logic pluralism is the thesis that there is just one proper
logic, but that domains may have certain features that make them
appear to be governed by a stronger logic. Thus, for example, while
logic proper may be intuitionistic, reasoning within some domains
may conform to classical logic (for non-logical reasons). As Wrenn
notes, virtual logical pluralism goes against domain-­based logical plu-
ralism. These considerations leave someone like Lynch in a tough
spot. He wants to be a domain-based logical pluralist, but domain-
based logical pluralism will not do on its own. It remains silent on
mixed inferences, so in order to deal with such inferences, (mod) is
adopted. Unfortunately, however, (mod) seems to get both certain
validity verdicts and certain invalidity verdicts wrong. Crucially, once
(mod) is adopted, virtual logical pluralism strongly suggests itself to
the ­self-­professed domain-based logical pluralist—undermining, it
would seem, their domain-based logical pluralism.
Andy Yu’s contribution “Logic for Alethic, Logical, and Ontological
Pluralists” is primarily concerned with the issue of how truth pluralists
can provide an account of logic. Yu sets himself the task of responding to
Introduction 23

the challenges of providing a uniform, standard account of the truth of


atomics, compounds, and quantified statements, as well as a standard
account of logical consequence as necessary truth-preservation. One might
expect this to be a tall order, especially bearing in mind that mixed dis-
course has traditionally been a major obstacle for truth pluralists. Yu pres-
ents a formal framework that he takes to capture the commitments of
truth pluralists. The proposed framework behaves like classical first-order
logic and has a logical consequence relation that behaves like classical
consequence. In light of this, Yu takes his account to provide an adequate
response to the challenge of providing a pluralist account of logic that is
both uniform and standard. At the end of his contribution, Yu extends
the framework so that it can accommodate logical pluralism and sketches
how to accommodate ontological pluralism as well. He does the former
by defining a domain-specific notion of validity that allows different
domains to traffic in different kinds of validity. This amounts to a formal
model of what we have called “domain-based logical pluralism” above.
Ontological pluralism is often taken to be the view that there are several
equally fundamental existential quantifiers. Yu proposes to accommodate
this view as well by introducing domain-specific quantifiers. Following
our earlier labeling conventions, the resulting view would be a form of
domain-based ontological pluralism.
Rosanna Keefe’s contribution “Pluralisms: Logic, Truth and
DomainSpecificity” also explores domain-based logical pluralism. She criti-
cally discusses two attempts by domain-based truth pluralists to give an
account of logic: Cotnoir’s algebraic account and domain-based logical plu-
ralism. Cotnoir’s account treats semantic values as n-tuples where n is the
number of domains. Each position in an n-tuple is 1 or 0. If a proposition
belongs to the i-th domain and is true, it has 1 in the i-th position of the
n-tuple and 0 in all other places. The framework incorporates classical clauses
for the connectives and sustains a classical consequence relation, although
Cotnoir also presents a modified framework meant to allow for other log-
ics. Keefe argues that Cotnoir’s account fails. The adoption of n-tuples as
semantic values forces each sentence to have a (“sub”)semantic value in each
place of its n-tuple, and that brings about odd results. Keefe likewise
presses several objections against domain-based logical pluralism. First,
24 N. J. L. L. Pedersen et al.

she observes that the view clashes with the widely held view that logic is
topic neutral. Second, like others, she observes that (mod)—a natural candi-
date for addressing the issue of mixed inferences—threatens to undermine
domain-based logical pluralism. Third, building on the two first points,
Keefe offers the following collapse argument: mixed inferences can cut across
all domains. By (mod), the logic of this inference would be the intersection
of all logics that hold for some domain. However, since this logic is topic
neutral, this is what logic proper is—and hence, logical monism is correct.
Fourth, Keefe questions an implicit assumption behind domain-based logi-
cal pluralism, viz. that domain membership suffices to fix the logic of infer-
ences. She points to vagueness as a phenomenon that tells against this
assumption, as this phenomenon that cuts across domains and has tradition-
ally been thought to be of relevance to logic. Lastly, Keefe presents a positive
proposal: validity is assessed relative to context. This allows for logical plural-
ism because the rules or assumptions justified in different contexts may vali-
date different arguments. Keefe observes that (1) her context-based
framework can accommodate domain-based logical pluralism in the sense
that different context-domain pairs may validate different inferences, and (2)
the context-­based approach allows for logical pluralism with respect to a
single domain since different contexts may validate different inferences per-
taining to the same domain. Furthermore, Keefe suggests that the context-
based approach is also better suited to deal with vagueness.
Kevin Scharp’s contribution “Aletheic and Logical Pluralism” explores
what he calls coordinated pluralism and compares it to his own replace-
ment theory. Coordinated pluralism is the combination of context-based
truth pluralism and context-based logical pluralism. Coordinated plural-
ism is motivated by considerations related to the semantic paradoxes. As
observed earlier, if truth is characterized by the unrestricted T-schema
and classical logic or certain other logics hold, you end up with paradox.
The double-barreled pluralism that coordinated pluralism offers is meant
to block paradox by letting the nature of truth and the nature of logic
vary across contexts in such a way that there is no context in which truth
and logic have natures that generate paradox. This is meant to happen in
virtue of their natures being coordinated in any given context. If, in a
given context, truth is strong, logic is weak and vice versa. This coordi-
nated pluralism seems like a promising approach to paradox. Might it be
Introduction 25

better than Scharp’s replacement theory? Scharp shows that coordinated


pluralism falls prey to a revenge paradox, that is, a paradox generated
using the very resources that were supposed to block paradox. In light of
this, Scharp concludes that his replacement theory is in fact superior to
coordinated pluralism.

Acknowledgements Nikolaj J. L. L. Pedersen and Jeremy Wyatt have both ben-


efited from support from the National Research Foundation of Korea (grants
no. 2013S1A2A2035514 and 2016S1A2A2911800). This support is gratefully
acknowledged.

Notes
1. David 1994; Devitt 1984; Newman 2007; Rasmussen 2014; Russell
1912; Vision 2004; and Wittgenstein 1921 all endorse versions of the
correspondence theory. Coherence theorists include Blanshard 1939;
Joachim 1906; and Young 2001. (Neo-)pragmatists include James 1907,
1909; Peirce 1878; and Putnam 1981.
2. Deflationists of various stripes include Field 1986, 1994a, b; Grover
1992; Horwich 1998; Quine 1970; Ramsey 1927; Strawson 1950. For a
systematic treatment of deflationary metaphysics of truth, see Wyatt
2016.
3. We use angle brackets to represent propositions.
4. See Wright 1992, 2001; Lynch 2001, 2004b, 2009.
5. Works on pluralism about truth include Asay 2018; Beall 2000, 2013;
Cook 2011; Cotnoir 2009, 2013a, b; Edwards 2008, 2009, 2011,
2012a, b, 2013a, b, 2018; Engel 2013; David 2013; Dodd 2013; Kölbel
2008, 2013; Lynch 2000, 2001, 2004a, b, 2005a, b, 2006, 2008, 2009,
2013; Newhard 2013, 2017; Pedersen 2006, 2010, 2012a, b, 2014;
Pedersen and Edwards 2011; Pedersen and Wright 2010, 2012, 2013a,
b; Shapiro 2011; Sher 1998, 2005, 2013, 2016; Stewart-Wallace 2016;
Tappolet 1997, 2000, 2010; Williamson 1994; (C.D.) Wright 2005,
2010, 2012; Wright 1992, 1996a, b, 1998, 2001, 2013; Wyatt 2013;
Wyatt and Lynch 2016; and Yu 2017a, b. Works on logical pluralism
include Beall 2014; Beall and Restall 2000, 2001, 2006; Bueno and
Shalkowski 2009; Carnielli and Coniglio 2016; Ciprotti and Moretti
2009; Cook 2010, 2014; Eklund 2012; Field 2009; Goddu 2002;
Hjortland 2013; Humberstone 2009; Keefe 2014; Kouri 2016; Kouri
26 N. J. L. L. Pedersen et al.

and Shapiro forthcoming; Payette and Wyatt 2018; Priest 2001, 2008,
2014; Read 2006a, b; Restall 2001, 2002, 2012, 2014; Russell 2008,
2014; Shapiro 2014; Sher forthcoming; Terrés forthcoming; van
Benthem 2008; Varzi 2002; and Wyatt 2004.
6. MacDaniel’s work on ontological pluralism spans about a decade. His
book The Fragmentation of Being (2017) brings together much of his
earlier work on the topic. See also. Turner 2010, 2012; Eklund 2009.
7. Alston 2005; Burge 2003; Goldman 1988; Wright 2004. Pedersen 2017
formulates and defends pluralism about fundamental or non-derivative
epistemic goods.
8. This slogan is the title of Lynch 2009. Having advocated moderate plu-
ralism for nearly two decades in a wide range of works, Lynch is the most
prominent advocate of the view. The distinction between these two
forms of pluralism is due to Pedersen 2006.
9. We will use small caps to denote concepts.
10. Sher 2005 raises the problem of mixed atomics. For the problems of
mixed compounds and inferences, see respectively Tappolet 2000 and
Tappolet 1997.
11. Versions of the double-counting objection have been presented by Asay
2018; Blackburn 1998, 2013; Dodd 2013, Horwich 1996; Pettit 1996;
Quine 1960; and Sainsbury 1996.
12. Wright 1998. See also Wright 1992 (Chap. 1, II) and Lynch 2004b: 386.
13. Beall and Restall 2006.
14. Field 2009.
15. In attributing a logical relativist view to Beall and Restall, we follow
Shapiro 2014.
16. It may seem odd to attribute both logical generalism and logical relativ-
ism to Beall and Restall. For, isn’t the idea that logic is general in tension
with the idea that it is relative? No. Logical generalism, as we have char-
acterized it, concerns whether a given logic legitimately issues (in)valid-
ity verdicts across the board (in the technical sense of legitimacy tied to
Generalized Tarski’s Thesis and the constraints of necessity, formality,
and normativity). For logics that are general in this sense, there is a fur-
ther issue as to the semantic status of their (in)validity verdicts—in par-
ticular, whether those verdicts have absolute or relativized truth-values.
17. Carnap 1937, 1950.
18. For a comprehensive introduction to substructural logics, see Restall
2000.
19. Lynch 2009, Pedersen 2014. The version of logical pluralism presented
in Shapiro 2014 can also be regarded as a kind of domain-based logical
Introduction 27

pluralism, although the various domains that Shapiro considers are all
mathematical.
20. The realism/anti-realism debate is, of course, one of the major themes in
Dummett’s corpus of work. See e.g., the essays in Dummett 1978.
21. See Lynch 2009 for details. The set of intuitionistic validities is a proper
subset of the set of classical validities, and hence, (mod) delivers the ver-
dict that the logic of any mixed compound or inference is intuitionistic
logic. In cases where there is overlap between two logics but no subset
relation, the intersection is identical to neither of the domain-specific
logics. This applies in the case of intuitionistic logic and relevant logic.
22. Smith forthcoming supports logical pluralism via logical contextualism.
While Beall and Restall never themselves present their logical pluralism
as a form of logical contextualism, Caret 2017 offers a contextualist read-
ing of their view and argues that it can be used to block a certain funda-
mental objection.
23. Barnard and Ulatowski 2013, Ulatowski 2017. See Kölbel 2008, 2013
for another empirically-based form of truth pluralism.
24. For details concerning MacFarlane’s assessment-sensitive relativism, see
MacFarlane 2014. Wyatt and Lynch 2016 suggest that MacFarlane is
committed to the kind of truth pluralism described.
25. Scharp 2013.
26. We’re blurring the line between use and mention here, but we trust that
the idea is clear.
27. See Wyatt and Lynch 2016 for further discussion of the relations between
truth pluralism and Scharp’s replacement theory. See also Beall 2013 and
Cotnoir 2013b for paradox-based motivations for truth pluralism.

References
Alston, W. 2005. Beyond ‘Justification’: Dimensions of Epistemic Evaluation.
Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Asay, J. 2018. Putting Pluralism in Its Place. Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research 96 (1): 175–191.
Barnard, R., and J. Ulatowski. 2013. Truth, Correspondence, and Gender.
Review of Philosophy and Psychology 4: 621–638.
Beall, J.C. 2000. On Mixed Inferences and Pluralism About Truth Predicates.
The Philosophical Quarterly 50: 380–382.
———. 2013. Deflated Truth Pluralism. In Pedersen & Wright 2013a,
323–338. New York: Oxford University Press.
28 N. J. L. L. Pedersen et al.

———. 2014. Strict-Choice Validities: A Note on a Familiar Pluralism.


Erkenntnis 79: 301–307.
Beall, J.C., and G. Restall. 2000. Logical Pluralism. Australasian Journal of
Philosophy 78: 475–493.
———. 2001. Defending Logical Pluralism. In Logical Consequence: Rival
Approaches Proceedings of the 1999 Conference of the Society of Exact Philosophy,
ed. J. Woods and B. Brown, 1–22. Stanmore: Hermes.
———. 2006. Logical Pluralism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Blackburn, S. 1998. Wittgenstein, Wright, Rorty and Minimalism. Mind 107:
157–181.
———. 2013. Deflationism, Pluralism, Expressivism, Pragmatism. In Pedersen
& Wright 2013a, 263–277. New York: Oxford University Press.
Blanshard, B. 1939. The Nature of Thought. London: George Allen and Unwin.
Bueno, O., and S.A. Shalkowski. 2009. Modalism and Logical Pluralism. Mind
118: 295–321.
Burge, T. 2003. Perceptual Entitlement. Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research 67: 503–548.
Caret, C. 2017. The Collapse of Logical Pluralism Has Been Greatly Exaggerated.
Erkenntnis 82: 739–760.
Carnap, R. 1937. The Logical Syntax of Language. New York: Harcourt, Brace
and Company.
———. 1950. Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology. Revue Internationale de
Philosophie 4: 20–40.
Carnielli, W., and M.E. Coniglio. 2016. Combining Logics. In The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/
archives/win2016/entries/logic-combining/.
Ciprotti, N., and L. Moretti. 2009. Logical Pluralism Is Compatible with
Monism About Metaphysical Modality. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 87:
275–284.
Cook, R.T. 2010. Let a Thousand Flowers Bloom: A Tour of Logical Pluralism.
Philosophy Compass 5: 492–504.
———. 2011. Alethic Pluralism, Generic Truth and Mixed Conjunctions. The
Philosophical Quarterly 61: 624–629.
———. 2014. Should Anti-Realists Be Anti-Realists About Anti-Realism?
Erkenntnis 79: 233–258.
Cotnoir, A. 2009. Generic Truth and Mixed Conjunctions: Some Alternatives.
Analysis 69: 473–479.
———. 2013a. Validity for Strong Pluralists. Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research 86: 563–579.
Introduction 29

———. 2013b. Pluralism and Paradox. In Pedersen & Wright 2013a, 339–350.
New York: Oxford University Press.
David, M. 1994. Correspondence and Disquotation: An Essay on the Nature of
Truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
———. 2005. On Truth Is Good. Philosophical Books 46: 292–301.
———. 2013. Lynch’s Functionalist Theory of Truth. In Pedersen & Wright
2013a, 42–68. New York: Oxford University Press.
Devitt, M. 1984. Realism and Truth. Oxford: Blackwell.
Dodd, J. 2013. Deflationism Trumps Pluralism! In Pedersen & Wright 2013a,
298–322. New York: Oxford University Press.
Dummett, M. 1978. Truth and Other Enigmas. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Edwards, D. 2008. How to Solve the Problem of Mixed Conjunctions. Analysis
68: 143–149.
———. 2009. Truth Conditions and the Nature of Truth: Resolving Mixed
Conjunctions. Analysis 69: 684–688.
———. 2011. Simplifying Alethic Pluralism. The Southern Journal of Philosophy
49: 28–48.
———. 2012a. On Alethic Disjunctivism. Dialectica 66: 200–214.
———. 2012b. Alethic vs. Deflationary Functionalism. International Journal of
Philosophical Studies 20: 115–124.
———. 2013a. Truth, Winning, and Simple Determination Pluralism. In
Pedersen & Wright 2013a, 113–122. New York: Oxford University Press.
———. 2013b. Truth as a Substantive Property. Australasian Journal of
Philosophy 91: 279–294.
———. 2018. The Metaphysics of Truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Eklund, M. 2009. Carnap and Ontological Pluralism. In Metametaphysics, ed.
D. Chalmers, D. Manley, and R. Wasserman, 130–156. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
———. 2012. Multitude, Tolerance and Language-Transcendence. Synthese
187: 833–847.
Engel, P. 2013. Alethic Functionalism and the Norm of Belief. In Pedersen &
Wright 2013a, 69–86. New York: Oxford University Press.
———. 1986. The Deflationary Conception of Truth. In Fact, Science and
Morality, ed. G. MacDonald and C. Wright, 55–117. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
———. 1994a. Deflationist Views of Meaning and Content. Mind 103:
249–285.
———. 1994b. Disquotational Truth and Factually Defective Discourse.
Philosophical Review 103: 405–452.
30 N. J. L. L. Pedersen et al.

———. 2009. Pluralism in Logic. The Review of Symbolic Logic 2: 342–359.


Goddu, G.C. 2002. What Exactly Is Logical Pluralism? Australasian Journal of
Philosophy 80: 218–230.
Goldman, A. 1988. Strong and Weak Justification. Philosophical Perspectives 2:
51–69.
Grover, D. 1992. A Prosentential Theory of Truth. Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
Hjortland, O.T. 2013. Logical Pluralism, MeaningVariance, and Verbal
Disputes. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91: 355–373.
Horwich, P. 1996. Realism Minus Truth. Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research 56: 877–881.
———. 1998. Truth. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Humberstone, L. 2009. Logical Pluralism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 87:
162–168.
James, W. 1907. Pragmatism: A New Name for some Old Ways of Thinking.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
———. 1909. The Meaning of Truth. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Joachim, H. 1906. The Nature of Truth. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Keefe, R. 2014. What Logical Pluralism Cannot Be. Synthese 191: 1375–1390.
Kölbel, M. 2008. ‘True’ as Ambiguous. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
77: 359–384.
———. 2013. Should We Be Pluralists About Truth? In Pedersen & Wright
2013a, 278–297. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kouri, T. 2016. Restall’s Proof-Theoretic Pluralism and Relevance Logic.
Erkenntnis 81: 1243–1252.
Kouri, T., and S. Shapiro. Forthcoming. Logical Pluralism and Normativity. To
appear in Inquiry.
Lynch, M.P. 2000. Alethic Pluralism and the Functionalist Theory of Truth.
Acta Analytica 15: 195–204.
———. 2001. A Functionalist Theory of Truth. In The Nature of Truth, ed.
M. Lynch, 723–749. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
———. 2004a. Minimalism and the Value of Truth. The Philosophical Quarterly
54: 497–517.
———. 2004b. Truth and Multiple Realizability. Australasian Journal of
Philosophy 82: 384–408.
———. 2005a. True to Life. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
———. 2005b. Reply to Critics. Philosophical Books 46: 331–342.
———. 2006. ReWrighting Pluralism. The Monist 89: 63–84.
Introduction 31

———. 2008. Alethic Pluralism, Logical Consequence, and the Universality of


Reason. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 32: 122–140.
———. 2009. Truth as One and Many. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
———. 2013. Three Questions for Truth Pluralism. In Pedersen & Wright
2013a, 21–41. New York: Oxford University Press.
MacFarlane, J. 2014. Assessment Sensitivity: Relative Truth and its Applications.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
McDaniel, K. 2017. The Fragmentation of Being. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Newhard, J. 2013. Four Objections to Alethic Functionalism. Journal of
Philosophical Research 38: 69–87.
———. 2017. Plain Truth and the Incoherence of Alethic Functionalism.
Synthese 194: 1591–1611.
Newman, A. 2007. The Correspondence Theory of Truth: An Essay on the
Metaphysics of Predication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Payette, G., and N. Wyatt. 2018. Logical Pluralism and Logical Form. Logique
et Analyse 61: 25–42.
Pedersen, Nikolaj J.L.L. 2006. What Can the Problem of Mixed Inferences
Teach Us About Alethic Pluralism? The Monist 89: 103–117.
———. 2010. Stabilizing Alethic Pluralism. The Philosophical Quarterly 60:
92–108.
———. 2012a. True Alethic Functionalism? International Journal of Philosophical
Studies 20: 125–133.
———. 2012b. Recent Work on Alethic Pluralism. Analysis 72: 588–607.
———. 2014. Pluralism × 3: Truth, Logic, Metaphysics. Erkenntnis 79:
259–277.
———. 2017. Pure Epistemic Pluralism. In Epistemic Pluralism, ed. A. Coliva
and Nikolaj J.L.L. Pedersen, 47–92. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Pedersen, Nikolaj J.L.L., and D. Edwards. 2011. Truth as One(s) and Many: On
Lynch’s Alethic Functionalism. Analytic Philosophy 52: 213–230.
Pedersen, Nikolaj J.L.L., and C.D. Wright. 2010. Truth, Pluralism, Monism,
Correspondence. In New Waves in Truth, ed. Nikolaj J.L.L. Pedersen and
C.D. Wright, 205–217. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
——— 2012. Pluralist Theories of Truth. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/
entriesruthpluralist/.
———, eds. 2013a. Truth and Pluralism: Current Debates. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
Clarification of Vinegar.

For those who desire an extra fancy product of extraordinary brightness,


suitable for bottling, it will be necessary to subject the vinegar to a special
process of clarification known as fining. According to Bioletti[*], the best
results are obtained by using isinglass. This is employed at the rate of from
one-half to three-fourths of an ounce of isinglass to each one hundred
gallons of vinegar.
[*] Bioletti, Frederic T., Grape Vinegar, Bull. 227, California Exp. Sta.,
1912.

"The isinglass is cut into small pieces and soaked for twelve to twenty-
four hours in a little water containing acetic or tartaric acid equal in weight
to the isinglass used. When thoroughly soft it is then rubbed several times
through a fine sieve, gradually adding a little more water until a perfectly
fluid liquid is obtained. This fluid is then well mixed with a little vinegar
and thoroughly stirred into the cask. With some vinegars it is necessary to
add a little tannin, from one-half to one-seventh the amount of the isinglass
used. This tannin should be added at least twenty-four hours before the
finings.

When the finings have settled and the vinegar is perfectly bright it is
ready for bottling."

Pure Cultures for Vinegar Making.


Reference has been made above to the use of pure cultures, both yeast
and acetic acid bacteria, for vinegar making. For a little more than one year,
the Bacteriological Laboratory of the Colorado Experiment Station has been
supplying these at fifty cents (50c) per set, post paid, sufficient for one
barrel, to those who care to give them a trial. Full printed directions for
their use are included. These cultures have been selected because of certain
properties which they possess which make them especially suited to the
vinegar industry. No guarantee, either expressed or [Page 14] implied, goes
with the cultures, since it is not the purpose of the Experiment Station to
exploit these products, but rather to distribute them at the cost of production
for experimental purposes. Inasmuch as one of the cultures is to be added to
the sweet cider, the set should be obtained a few days, not longer, before the
cider is to be made.

Requests for cultures should be addressed to the Bacteriological


Laboratory, Colorado Experiment Station, Fort Collins, Colorado, and
should be accompanied by a remittance of fifty cents (50c).

Directions For Using Pure Cultures in Making Vinegar


Preparation of Yeast Culture.

1. For each barrel of sweet cider, sterilize one two-quart Mason jar by
washing thoroughly and boiling for five minutes in clean water.

2. Cover the top of the jar with a single layer of clean muslin or cheese
cloth just removed from boiling water and secure it in place by a string tied
about the neck of the can.

3. Select 6 or 8 medium sized ripe apples; pare and quarter or slice


them; add one quart of water and boil till soft; strain liquid through clean
cloth while hot into Mason jar, first removing the cloth covering from the
top.

4. Make up the volume of liquid to approximately one quart with


boiling water; add 4 tablespoonfuls of sugar and replace the cloth
immediately.

5. When the liquid has cooled thoroughly, partly remove the cloth
covering and add the contents of the culture bottle marked "Yeast." Replace
the cloth. Just previous to opening the culture bottle, shake thoroughly and
immerse the lip and cork only, ten second in boiling water. Do not touch the
lip while removing cork.

6. Keep the jar in subdued light at a temperature of 75 degrees F. to 90


degrees F. After two to four days the foaming characteristic of alcoholic
fermentation should appear.
7. After four to six days, add the entire contents of the yeast jar to the
barrel of freshly made sweet cider. The barrel must not be more than two-
thirds full; it should be placed on its side, and the bung-hole be left open, or,
better, plugged loosely with a tuft of clean cotton batting.

8. Keep the barrel at 75 degrees F. to 85 degrees F.

[Page 15]

Preparation of Acetic Culture.

1. Three to four weeks after the yeast culture has been added to the cider
prepare the Acetic Culture in precisely the same manner as described for
the yeast in paragraphs 1 to 6 above. See that all of the culture is removed
from the bottle; rinse with a little cooled boiled water if necessary. Do not
shake the jar while the culture is developing.

2. By the end of one to two weeks, a white, gelatinous film or


membrane should be visible on the surface of the liquid. This is a growth of
acetic acid bacteria and constitutes the "Mother of Vinegar."

3. When this acetic membrane is well formed, which will require about
two weeks, with a clean sliver of wood, previously dipped into boiling
water, remove the membrane from the jar, but do not lay it down; pour the
contents of the jar into the barrel of cider, now fermented, to which the
yeast was added some five or six weeks before; next drop the sliver with the
attached acetic film into the barrel through the bung-hole. The wood will
serve to float the acetic membrane on the surface of the hard cider and
thereby hasten its development by keeping it in contact with the air.

4. Keep the barrel at 65 degrees F. to 75 degrees F. till the vinegar has


formed.

5. When vinegar of satisfactory quality has been obtained, in three to six


months, draw off and store at a cool, even temperature in casks which are
kept full and tightly bunged.
6. Both of these cultures can be propagated indefinitely by employing a
small portion of the jar cultures in the same manner as the original bottle
starters.
*** END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK HOME-MADE
CIDER VINEGAR ***

Updated editions will replace the previous one—the old editions will
be renamed.

Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S.


copyright law means that no one owns a United States copyright in
these works, so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it
in the United States without permission and without paying copyright
royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part of
this license, apply to copying and distributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG™ concept
and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and
may not be used if you charge for an eBook, except by following the
terms of the trademark license, including paying royalties for use of
the Project Gutenberg trademark. If you do not charge anything for
copies of this eBook, complying with the trademark license is very
easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such as
creation of derivative works, reports, performances and research.
Project Gutenberg eBooks may be modified and printed and given
away—you may do practically ANYTHING in the United States with
eBooks not protected by U.S. copyright law. Redistribution is subject
to the trademark license, especially commercial redistribution.

START: FULL LICENSE


THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK

To protect the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting the free


distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work (or
any other work associated in any way with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg”), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full
Project Gutenberg™ License available with this file or online at
www.gutenberg.org/license.

Section 1. General Terms of Use and


Redistributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works
1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg™
electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree
to and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
(trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or
destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in your
possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a
Project Gutenberg™ electronic work and you do not agree to be
bound by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from
the person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in
paragraph 1.E.8.

1.B. “Project Gutenberg” is a registered trademark. It may only be


used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people
who agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a
few things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg™ electronic
works even without complying with the full terms of this agreement.
See paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with
Project Gutenberg™ electronic works if you follow the terms of this
agreement and help preserve free future access to Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below.
1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the
Foundation” or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the
collection of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the
individual works in the collection are in the public domain in the
United States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright law in
the United States and you are located in the United States, we do
not claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing,
performing, displaying or creating derivative works based on the
work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of
course, we hope that you will support the Project Gutenberg™
mission of promoting free access to electronic works by freely
sharing Project Gutenberg™ works in compliance with the terms of
this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg™ name
associated with the work. You can easily comply with the terms of
this agreement by keeping this work in the same format with its
attached full Project Gutenberg™ License when you share it without
charge with others.

1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also
govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most
countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside the
United States, check the laws of your country in addition to the terms
of this agreement before downloading, copying, displaying,
performing, distributing or creating derivative works based on this
work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The Foundation makes
no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in
any country other than the United States.

1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:

1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other


immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg™ License must
appear prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg™
work (any work on which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” appears, or
with which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” is associated) is
accessed, displayed, performed, viewed, copied or distributed:
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United
States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away
or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License
included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you
are not located in the United States, you will have to check the
laws of the country where you are located before using this
eBook.

1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is derived


from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not contain a
notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the copyright
holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in the
United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are
redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg” associated with or appearing on the work, you must
comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through
1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project
Gutenberg™ trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is posted


with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any
additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms
will be linked to the Project Gutenberg™ License for all works posted
with the permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of
this work.

1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project


Gutenberg™ License terms from this work, or any files containing a
part of this work or any other work associated with Project
Gutenberg™.

1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this


electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
Gutenberg™ License.
1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form,
including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you
provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work
in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in
the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg™ website
(www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense
to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means
of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original “Plain
Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate format must include the
full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.

1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,


performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg™ works
unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing


access to or distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works
provided that:

• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”

• You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who


notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that
s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™
License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and
discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of Project
Gutenberg™ works.

• You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of


any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in
the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90
days of receipt of the work.

• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.

1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg™


electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set
forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the manager of
the Project Gutenberg™ trademark. Contact the Foundation as set
forth in Section 3 below.

1.F.

1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend


considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe
and proofread works not protected by U.S. copyright law in creating
the Project Gutenberg™ collection. Despite these efforts, Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works, and the medium on which they may
be stored, may contain “Defects,” such as, but not limited to,
incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt data, transcription errors, a
copyright or other intellectual property infringement, a defective or
damaged disk or other medium, a computer virus, or computer
codes that damage or cannot be read by your equipment.

1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except


for the “Right of Replacement or Refund” described in paragraph
1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner
of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark, and any other party
distributing a Project Gutenberg™ electronic work under this
agreement, disclaim all liability to you for damages, costs and
expenses, including legal fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO
REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF
WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE
FOUNDATION, THE TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY
DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE LIABLE
TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL,
PUNITIVE OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE
NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE.

1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you


discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it,
you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by
sending a written explanation to the person you received the work
from. If you received the work on a physical medium, you must
return the medium with your written explanation. The person or entity
that provided you with the defective work may elect to provide a
replacement copy in lieu of a refund. If you received the work
electronically, the person or entity providing it to you may choose to
give you a second opportunity to receive the work electronically in
lieu of a refund. If the second copy is also defective, you may
demand a refund in writing without further opportunities to fix the
problem.

1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth in
paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO
OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED,
INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF
MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.

1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied


warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages.
If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the
law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be
interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted
by the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any
provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.
1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the
Foundation, the trademark owner, any agent or employee of the
Foundation, anyone providing copies of Project Gutenberg™
electronic works in accordance with this agreement, and any
volunteers associated with the production, promotion and distribution
of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, harmless from all liability,
costs and expenses, including legal fees, that arise directly or
indirectly from any of the following which you do or cause to occur:
(a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg™ work, (b)
alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any Project
Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any Defect you cause.

Section 2. Information about the Mission of


Project Gutenberg™
Project Gutenberg™ is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers.
It exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and
donations from people in all walks of life.

Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the


assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg™’s
goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg™ collection will
remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a
secure and permanent future for Project Gutenberg™ and future
generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help,
see Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at
www.gutenberg.org.

Section 3. Information about the Project


Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non-profit
501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
Revenue Service. The Foundation’s EIN or federal tax identification
number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent
permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state’s laws.

The Foundation’s business office is located at 809 North 1500 West,


Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up
to date contact information can be found at the Foundation’s website
and official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact

Section 4. Information about Donations to


the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation
Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without
widespread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can
be freely distributed in machine-readable form accessible by the
widest array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small
donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax
exempt status with the IRS.

The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating


charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and
keep up with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in
locations where we have not received written confirmation of
compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of
compliance for any particular state visit www.gutenberg.org/donate.

While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where


we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no
prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in
such states who approach us with offers to donate.

International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make


any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.

Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of
other ways including checks, online payments and credit card
donations. To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate.

Section 5. General Information About Project


Gutenberg™ electronic works
Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
Gutenberg™ concept of a library of electronic works that could be
freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
distributed Project Gutenberg™ eBooks with only a loose network of
volunteer support.

Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several printed


editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by copyright in
the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not
necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper
edition.

Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.

This website includes information about Project Gutenberg™,


including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how
to subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.

You might also like