Can There Be Genocide Without The Intent To Commit Genocide
Can There Be Genocide Without The Intent To Commit Genocide
Can There Be Genocide Without The Intent To Commit Genocide
Guenter Lewy
To cite this article: Guenter Lewy (2007) Can there be genocide without the intent to commit
genocide?, Journal of Genocide Research, 9:4, 661-674, DOI: 10.1080/14623520701644457
The question posed in the title of this essay appears to be nonsensical, if not out-
right self-contradictory, but in fact it is not. As we will see below, several well-
known students of genocide have argued that it is possible for genocide to take
place without an intent to cause genocide. Such a view, I submit, would first
have to be squared with the text of the Genocide Convention of 1948. According
to Article II of the convention, the crime of genocide consists of a series of acts
“committed with intent to destroy, in whole or in part, a national, ethnical,
racial or religious group as such [my italics].”1 Since genocide is a legal term in
international criminal law, the definition of the convention establishing the
crime of genocide assumes a prima facie authoritativeness. The issue of the defi-
nition of genocide should not be used to exculpate crimes that do not reach the
threshold of the legal definition of genocide. However, as I will argue in this
essay, the disregard of intentionality can stand in the way of a full understanding
of events that appear to constitute genocide and lead to a distorted finding of
responsibility. The significance of the intent issue goes well beyond the question
of how best to define genocide as a crime under international law.
ISSN 1462-3528 print; ISSN 1469-9494 online/07/040661-14 # 2007 Research Network in Genocide Studies
DOI: 10.1080/14623520701644457
GUENTER LEWY
662
GENOCIDE WITHOUT THE INTENT TO COMMIT
Criminal Court adopted in 1998.10 In its commentary on the 1996 Code of Crimes
Against the Peace and Security of Mankind, the International Law Commission
referred to specific intent as “the distinguishing characteristic of this particular
crime under international law”:
The prohibited acts enumerated [. . .] are by their nature conscious, intentional or volitional
acts which an individual could not usually commit without knowing that certain conse-
quences were likely to result. These are not the types of acts that would normally occur
by accident or even as a result of mere negligence [. . .]. [A] general intent to commit one
of the enumerated acts combined with a general awareness of the probable consequences
of such an act is not sufficient for the crime of genocide. The definition of this crime requires
a particular state of mind or a specific intent with respect to the overall consequences of the
prohibited act.11
Two ad-hoc tribunals established by the United Nations to try violations of inter-
national humanitarian law committed in the former Yugoslavia and Rwanda,
respectively, have addressed the role of intent in the crime of genocide. On
August 2, 2001, General Radislav Krstic, the Serbian commander of the Drina
Corps operating in the Srebrenica area in July 1995, was convicted of genocide
for his role in the massacre of more than 7,000 male Bosnian Muslims. What
had begun as ethnic cleansing, the court ruled, turned into genocide—the deliber-
ate killing of all Muslim men of military age.12 Even though there was no evidence
that Krstic either personally killed anyone or that he had been present at the mass
killings, it was enough that he was held to have had knowledge of the plan to
destroy the Bosnian Muslims of Srebrenica and participated actively in it.
Krstic was given a jail sentence of 46 years, reduced to 35 years on appeal.13
On the other hand, the Serb Goran Jelisic, former commander of a detention
camp in the Brcko region of northwest Bosnia and Herzegovina, was acquitted
in late 1999 of the charge of genocide because he had killed “arbitrarily” and “ran-
domly” rather than with “an affirmed resolve to destroy in whole or in part a group
as such.” The prosecution had argued that it was sufficient if the accused knew the
consequences of his acts—the extermination of a group—though he may not have
sought it, but the court rejected this view. The crime of genocide, the tribunal
declared, required a specific intent, and this meant that a perpetrator, “by one of
the prohibited acts enumerated in Article 4 of the Statute, seeks to achieve the
destruction, in whole or in part, of a national, ethnical, racial or religious group,
as such.”14 Instead, Jelisic was sentenced to 40 years imprisonment for crimes
against humanity, a charge to which he had pleaded guilty.15
The Trial Chamber of the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda, in the
Akayesu case decided on September 2, 1998, also ruled that the crime of genocide
requires a specific intent to commit genocide. Even in the absence of a confession,
the special intent to destroy a protected group as such could be inferred from the
speeches of the accused and the massive nature of the atrocities committed.
Killings had been carried out in a planned and concerted manner. The fact that
the accused had deliberately and systematically targeted victims on account of
their membership in a particular group (the Tutsis), while excluding the
663
GUENTER LEWY
members of other groups, enabled the Chamber to infer the genocidal intent of a
particular act.16
Critics of the Genocide Convention have taken exception to the limited scope of
the convention’s definition of protected entities, especially the exclusion of politi-
cal groups, as well as the ambiguity of the requirement that a group be destroyed
“in whole or in part.” Such criticism has also targeted the intent provision.
664
GENOCIDE WITHOUT THE INTENT TO COMMIT
In a critique of Barta, the sociologist Frank Chalk has argued against the down-
playing of the role of individuals in the occurrence of genocide. “Systemic vari-
ables facilitate genocide, but it is people who kill.” The same structures of
society do not always lead to the same consequences. States eschewing capitalism
such as China and Cambodia have perpetrated huge massacres of ethnic groups
and social classes. Arguments which minimize the importance of intentionality,
Chalk points out, “also distract our attention from the role of absolutist or
utopian or uncompromisingly idealistic doctrines or ideologies in the great mass
killings of the twentieth century.” The search for the perfect society became the
recipe for the most horrible bloodshed in which millions lost their lives.21
The abandonment of the criterion of intentionality, I would add, also makes
it difficult to assign guilt. Who is to be held responsible for structural violence?
Guilt is individual; one cannot punish a social system, violent and unjust as it
may be. The principle of individual responsibility for international crimes was
affirmed by the International Military Tribunal that tried the German major war
criminals. Crimes against international law, declared the Nuremberg Court in its
judgment delivered on September 30– October 1, 1946, “are committed by men,
not by abstract entities, and only by punishing individuals who commit such
crimes can the provisions of international law be enforced.”22 According to the
judgment of the International Court of Justice rendered in the case of Bosnia
and Herzegovina v. Serbia and Montenegro on February 26, 2007, “states can
be held responsible for genocide,” but proof has to be established that the acts
of genocide were committed by “persons or entities ranking as organs of the
respondent.”23 This is in line with Article IV of the Genocide Convention
which provides punishment for “persons committing genocide,” irrespective of
“whether they are constitutionally responsible rulers, public officials or private
individuals.”
665
GUENTER LEWY
666
GENOCIDE WITHOUT THE INTENT TO COMMIT
eyes of Jehuda Bauer the destruction of the Indian people by Anglo-Saxon settlers
was “clearly genocide.”31 In this country few professional students of American
history share this view, but many others in the academic community and
beyond have accepted the charge of genocide. The argument became popular at
the time of the Vietnam War when historians opposed to the conflict drew parallels
between our actions in Southeast Asia and earlier examples of supposedly
ingrained American viciousness toward non-white people. The author of a book
entitled The American Indian: The First Victim called America’s white civiliza-
tion as originating in “theft and murder” and the wars against the natives
“efforts towards the genocide of the Indian people.”32 The troops under the
command of the famous Indian scout Kit Carson, wrote the historian Richard
Drinnon in 1980, were “forerunners of the Burning Fifth Marines” who set fire
to Vietnamese villages, and the Puritans at Fort Mystic in 1637 piled up a body
count “that equaled or exceeded that at My Lai in 1968.”33 By the end of the
1970s, a study of the changes in high school American history textbooks con-
cludes, Christopher Columbus had ceased to be a hero and instead had become
“a genocidal criminal, responsible for the wreckage of the unspoiled civilizations
that preceded the European arrival.”34
The 1992 quincentenary of the landing of Columbus brought to the fore more
accusations of genocide and revealed the rampant guilty conscience. The National
Council of Churches adopted a resolution that called Columbus’ landfall “an inva-
sion” resulting in the “slavery and genocide of native people.”35 In a widely read
book entitled The Conquest of Paradise, Kirkpatrick Sale charged the English
“and their United States successors” with following a policy of extermination
that lasted four centuries.36 An Encyclopedia of Genocide, published in 1999
and edited by the genocide scholar Israel Charny, includes an article on genocide
against the American Indians authored by Ward Churchill which argues that the
“express objective” of the Indian wars waged by the United States was “extermi-
nation.”37 The “only appropriate way” to describe the way white settlers treated
the Indians, the Cambodia expert Ben Kiernan has written, is “genocide.”38
A demographic disaster
It is a firmly established fact that a mere 250,000 Native Americans were still alive
in the territory of United States at the end of the nineteenth century. Still in scho-
larly contention, however, is the number of Indians at the time of first contact with
the Europeans. Some students of the subject speak of a “numbers game.”39 Since
the 1960s, in particular, observes the anthropologist Shepard Krech, population
estimates have become “sharply politicized.” Indian scholars have accused non-
Indian demographers of minimizing the size of the aboriginal Indian population
in order to make the decline less severe than it was.40
The disparity in estimates is enormous. In 1928 the ethnologist James Mooney
arrived at a count of 1,152,950 Indians in all tribal areas north of Mexico at the
time of initial contact with Europeans.41 By 1987, in American Indian Holocaust
and Survival, Russell Thornton gave the figure of five-plus million Indians in the
667
GUENTER LEWY
coterminous United States area in 1492.42 Considering this estimate as far too low,
Lenore Stiffarm and Phil Lane, Jr. called Thornton “a somewhat confused Cherokee
demographer” who seeks academic respectability by aligning himself with the low-
counters, and they proposed the number of 12 million native inhabitants within the
present borders of the United States.43 This figure is indebted to the anthropologist
Henry Dobyns, who in 1983 estimated the aboriginal population of North America
as 18 million and that in today’s United States as about 10 million.44
From one perspective, these differences, however startling, may seem beside
the point; there is ample evidence, after all, that the arrival of the white man trig-
gered a drastic reduction in the number of Native Americans. Nevertheless, even if
the higher figures are credited, they alone do not prove the occurrence of genocide.
To address this issue properly we must begin with the most important reason for
the Indians’ catastrophic decline—namely, the spread of highly contagious dis-
eases to which they had no immunity. This phenomenon is known as a “virgin
soil epidemic”; in North America it was the norm and it resulted in staggering
death rates. The most lethal of the pathogens introduced into the New World by
the Europeans was smallpox. Sometimes this disease incapacitated so many
adults, including hunters, at the same time that as many tribesmen died of
hunger and starvation as of the disease itself. In several cases entire tribes
became extinct. Other killers included measles, influenza, whooping cough,
diphtheria, typhus, bubonic plague, cholera and scarlet fever. Although syphilis
was apparently native to parts of the western hemisphere, it, too, was probably
introduced into North America by Europeans.45
There is some disagreement about the number of the various epidemics that
decimated the Indian populations, about the timing of their impact, and the
extent of their spread. Population declines varied in different regions.46
However, the basic facts about the mortality caused by disease are unquestioned.
The most hideous enemy of Native Americans was not the white man and his
weaponry, concludes Alfred Crosby, “but the invisible killers which those men
brought in their blood and breath.”47 It is estimated that between 75% and 90%
of all Indian deaths were the result of epidemic disease.48 Ann Ramenofsky
speaks of “a minimal population loss of 90% from all introduced disease.”49
To some this is enough in itself to warrant the term genocide. David Stannard
has insisted that the Indians who died of introduced disease “were as much the
victims of the Euro-American genocidal war as were those burned or stabbed or
hacked or shot to death, or devoured by hungry dogs.” The Jews who died of
disease and starvation in the ghettos, he argues, are counted among the victims
of the Holocaust. In the same way, the native people of the Americas died “in
vastly higher numbers and proportions, directly as a result of the larger genocidal
conditions created by violent European invasions of their communities.” As an
example of such genocidal conditions Stannard refers to the Franciscan missions
in California which he calls “furnaces of death.”50
There are several problems with this argument. It is true that the cramped quar-
ters of the missions, with their poor ventilation and bad sanitation, encouraged
the spread of disease, but unlike the Nazis, whose intentions were anything but
668
GENOCIDE WITHOUT THE INTENT TO COMMIT
benevolent, the missionaries were sincerely concerned for the welfare of their
native converts. Labour was obligatory, food and medical care were often
inadequate, and, in conformity with prevailing norms, there was corporal punish-
ment.51 However, none of this can compare with the fate of the Jews in the ghettos.
The missionaries had an inadequate understanding of the causes of the diseases
that afflicted their charges, and, given the state of medical knowledge, there was
little they could do for them. By contrast the Nazis knew exactly what was happen-
ing in the ghettos, but quite deliberately deprived the Jewish inmates of both food
and medicine. Unlike in Stannard’s “furnaces of death,” the deaths that occurred
there were meant to occur.
The larger picture also does not conform to Stannard’s idea of disease as
an expression of “genocidal conditions.” True, the forced relocations of
Indian tribes was often accompanied by great hardship and harsh treatment;
the removal of the Cherokee from their homelands to territories west of the
Mississippi in 1818 took the lives of thousands and has entered history as the
“Trail of Tears.” However, the largest loss of life occurred well before the creation
of the reservations, and some of the most severe epidemics hit the Indians after
minimal contact with European traders. Later, some colonists welcomed the
large number of deaths and saw them as a sign of divine blessing that made the
land of the natives available to them, but this does not change the basic fact
that the Europeans did not come to the New World in order to infect the
Indians with deadly diseases.
Ward Churchill not only agrees with Stannnard that the deaths from alleged
“natural causes” must be considered part of the overall pattern of genocide
against the Indians, but takes the argument a step further by charging a policy
of biological warfare. The waves of epidemic disease that afflicted the indigenous
populations during several centuries, he writes, “were deliberately induced, or at
least facilitated, by the European invaders.” There was nothing unwitting or unin-
tentional about the way the great bulk of North America’s native population
disappeared. “It was precisely malice, not nature, that did the deed.”52
We do know of one instance of biological warfare against the Indians. In
1763, a particularly serious Indian uprising threatened the British garrisons
west of the Allegheny Mountains. Sir Jeffrey Amherst, commander-in-chief of
British forces in North America, concerned about his limited resources to put
down the rebellion and disgusted by what he saw as the Indians’ treacherous
and savage mode of warfare, wrote to Colonel Henry Bouquet at Fort Pitt:
“You will do well to try to inoculate the Indians [with smallpox] by means of
blankets, as well as to try every other method, that can serve to extirpate this
execrable race.” It is not clear whether Bouquet carried out Amherst’s sugges-
tion, though we know that he approved of it. It is documented that on or
around June 24, 1763, two traders at Fort Pitt gave two visiting Delaware
Indians two blankets and a handkerchief from the fort’s quarantined hospital.
One of the traders, William Trent, noted in his journal: “Out of regard we
gave them two blankets and a handkerchief out of the smallpox hospital.
I hope it will have the desired effect.” Smallpox was already present among
669
GUENTER LEWY
the tribes of Ohio, but some time after this episode there was another outbreak
and hundreds of Indians died.53
During the Yorktown campaign of 1781, a British officer sent 300 smallpox-
infected blacks to the rebel plantations, and there may have been other instances
where the British deliberately used smallpox as a weapon of war.54 However, apart
from Fort Pitt in 1763, no other cases of the deliberate use of smallpox against
Indians have been recorded. The allegation of Ward Churchill that the US
Army deliberately distributed smallpox-infected blankets to Mandan Indians in
183755 is a fabrication, unsubstantiated by any evidence. This instance of aca-
demic fraud was one of several cited by the Standing Committee on Research
Misconduct at the University of Colorado, and led the Interim Chancellor of the
University to announce on June 26, 2006 the initiation of dismissal proceedings
against Churchill.56
The allegation that agents of the US government intentionally infected Indian
tribes with smallpox is also at odds with the attempts of the federal government
to vaccinate the Indian population. Vaccination against smallpox was developed
by the English country doctor Edward Jenner in 1796, and in 1801 President
Jefferson ordered the first Indians to be vaccinated. During the following three
decades, this programme continued, though implementation was slowed by the
resistance of the Indians, who suspected a trick, and by the lack of interest on
the part of some officials. Still, as Thornton writes: “Vaccination of American
Indians did eventually succeed in reducing mortality from smallpox.”57
The charge that the US government should be held responsible for the demo-
graphic disaster that overtook the American Indian population as a result of
various deadly epidemics is thus unsupported by any valid argument or evidence.
The United States did not wage biological warfare against the Indians; neither can
the large number of deaths experienced by Native Americans as a result of disease
be considered the result of a genocidal design. European settlers came to the New
World for a variety of reasons, but the idea of infecting the Indians with deadly
pathogens was not one of them. The experience of the American Indians thus
calls into question the notion that it is possible to determine the occurrence of gen-
ocide by looking at results and consequences. The crucial role of disease in the
decimation of the Indian population drives home the point that a huge death toll
in and by itself is not proof of malfeasance or genocide. The stress of the Genocide
Convention on intentionality is not a mere legalism.
Is there other evidence to support the charge that American Indians were the
victims of genocide? Perhaps there is, though this evidence does not implicate
the national government and involves massacres of small groups of Indians
rather than the Indian people as such. The treatment of Native Americans by
European settlers was often callous and brutal. Settlers on the expanding frontier
treated the Indians with contempt, often robbing and killing them at will. In
California especially, volunteer militias and vigilante groups at times displayed
a flagrantly exterminatory mentality and murdered large numbers of Indians.
The Genocide Convention outlaws the destruction of a group “in whole or in
part,” but does not address the question of what percentage of a group must be
670
GENOCIDE WITHOUT THE INTENT TO COMMIT
affected by the destructive acts enumerated in the convention to trigger the crime
of genocide. The prosecutor of the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former
Yugoslavia has declared that the definition requires “a reasonably significant
number, relative to the total of the group as a whole,” though he added that the
actual or attempted destruction should relate to “the factual opportunity of the
accused to destroy a group in a specific geographic area within the sphere of his
control, and not in relation to the entire population of the group in a wider geo-
graphic sense.”58 The trial chamber in the Krstic case, involving the wholesale
killing of Bosnian Muslims in Srebrenica, ruled that “although the perpetrators
of genocide need not seek to destroy the entire group protected by the Convention,
they must view the part of the group they wish to destroy as a distinct entity which
must be eliminated as such.”59 If this principle is adopted, an atrocity such as the
Sand Creek massacre of November 29, 1864 during which a volunteer regiment of
Western settlers attacked an Indian village and killed large numbers of women and
children, even though limited to one group in a specific single locality, could be
considered an act of genocide. Still, it is well to remember that a far larger
number of Indians died from the epidemic diseases unintentionally introduced
and spread by the white man than from outright violence. As the historian
Francis Jennings has observed: “Not even the most brutally depraved of the con-
quistadores was able purposely to slaughter Indians on the scale that the gentle
priest unwittingly accomplished by going from his sickbed ministrations to lay
his hands in blessing on his Indian converts.”60
Conclusion
Intentionality is an important element in domestic law. The difference between
homicide and murder, for example, turns on the degree of intent that is present
in the act of taking life. The negligent killing of a pedestrian by a motorist is
not the same as a deliberate assault that aims at the death of the victim. In the
same way, I have argued in this essay, there is every reason not to ignore the
role of intent in what is often called “the crime of crimes”—the destruction of
an entire group of people or genocide. Proof of specific intent is necessary to
find an individual guilty of genocide, and the role of intent is similarly crucial
when the historian assesses an episode of mass death that occurred in the past.
A large loss of life should be the point of departure for a searching investigation
to determine responsibility, but in and by itself it should never be sufficient for a
finding of genocide. The disregard of intentionality will create an incomplete or
distorted picture and lead to false conclusions.
In the absence of a confession, the establishment of intent in mass deaths that
occurred in the past is often difficult. Yet many times genocidal intent can be
inferred from factors such as the scale of the atrocities committed or the deliberate
targeting of victims on account of their membership in a particular group. “The
emphasis on intent is important,” Kurt Jonassohn has correctly noted, “because
it removes from consideration not only natural disasters but also those man-
made disasters that took place without explicit planning. Many of the epidemics
671
GUENTER LEWY
672
GENOCIDE WITHOUT THE INTENT TO COMMIT
24 Henry R. Huttenbach, “Locating the Holocaust on the genocide spectrum: towards a methodology of
definition and categorization,” Holocaust and Genocide Studies, Vol 3, No 3, 1988, pp 294, 297.
25 John Collier, Annual Report of the Secretary of the Interior (Washington, DC: GPO 1938), p 209, quoted in
Wilcomb E. Washburn, ed., The Indian and the White Man (Garden City, NY: Anchor Books, 1964), p 393.
26 Helen Hunt Jackson, A Century of Dishonor: A Sketch of the United States Government’s Dealings with Some
of the Indian Tribes (Boston: Roberts Brothers, 1888).
27 Ward Churchill, Indians are Us? Culture and Genocide in Native North America (Monroe, ME: Common
Courage Press, 1994), p 38; Ward Churchill, A Little Matter of Genocide: Holocaust and Denial in the
Americas, 1492 to the Present (San Francisco, CA: City Lights Books, 1997), p 4.
28 David E. Stannard, American Holocaust: The Conquest of the New World (New York: Oxford University
Press, 1992), p 146.
29 Lenore A. Stiffarm and Phil Lane, Jr., “The demography of Native North America: a question of Indian sur-
vival,” in M. Annette Jaimes, ed., The State of Native America: Genocide, Colonization, and Resistance
(Boston: South End Press, 1992), p 37.
30 Pap Ndiaye, “L’extermination des Indes d’Amérique du Nord,” in M. Ferro, ed., La livre noir du colonialisme
(Paris: Robert Laffon, 2003), p 57.
31 Yehuda Bauer, “Comparison of genocide,” in Levon Chorbajian and George Shirinian, eds, Studies in Com-
parative Genocide (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1999), p 38.
32 Jay David, The American Indian: The First Victim (New York: William Morrow, 1972), p 89.
33 Richard Drinnon, Facing West: The Metaphysics of Indian-Hating and Empire-Building (Minneapolis, MN:
University of Minnesota Press, 1980), p 459.
34 Robert Lerner et al., Molding the Good Citizen: The Politics of High School History Texts (Westport, CT:
Praeger, 1995), p 152.
35 Quoted in José Barreiro, “View from the shore: toward an Indian voice in 1992,” Northeast Indian Quarterly,
Vol 7, No 3, 1990, p 16.
36 Kirkpatrick Sale, The Conquest of Paradise: Christopher Columbus and the Columbian Legacy (New York:
Alfred A. Knopf, 1990), pp 281–282.
37 Churchill, “Genocide of native populations in the United States,” in Israel W. Charny, ed., Encyclopedia of
Genocide (Santa Barbara, CA: ABC-Clio, 1999, Vol 2), p 436.
38 Ben Kiernan, “The genocide of Native Americans,” Bangkok Post, July 29, 2001.
39 Brian W. Dippie, The Vanishing American: White Attitudes and U.S. Indian Policy (Middletown, CT:
Wesleyan University Press, 1982), p xv.
40 Shepard Krech, The Ecological Indian: Myth and History (New York: W. W. Norton, 1999), pp 83 –84.
41 James Mooney, The Aboriginal Population of America North of Mexico (Washington, DC: Smithsonian Insti-
tution, 1928), p 2.
42 Russell Thornton, American Indian Holocaust: A Population History since 1492 (Norman, OK: University of
Oklahoma Press, 1987), p 43.
43 Stiffarm and Lane, Jr., “The demography of Native North America,” pp 27–28.
44 Henry F. Dobyns, Native American Historical Demography: A Critical Bibliography (Bloomington, IN:
Indiana University Press, 1976), p 1. See also his Their Numbers Became Thinned: Native American Popu-
lation Dynamics in Eastern North America (Knoxville, TN: University of Tennessee Press, 1983).
45 Krech, The Ecological Indian, p 91; E. Wagner and Allen E. Stearn, The Effect of Smallpox on the Destiny of
the Amerindian (Boston: B. Humphries, 1945), p 94; Karen Ordahl Kupperman, Settling with the Indians: The
Meeting of England and Indian Cultures in America, 1580– 1640 (Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield,
1980), p 5.
46 Dean R. Snow and Kim M. Lanphear, “European contact and Indian depopulation in the northeast: the timing
of the first epidemics,” Ethnohistory, Vol 35, No 1, 1988, pp 15–33.
47 Alfred W. Crosby, Jr., The Columbian Exchange: Biological and Cultural Consequences of 1492 (Westport,
CT: Greenwood Press, 1972), p 31.
48 Brenda Baker gives this figure for southern New England in “Pilgrim’s progress and praying Indians: the
biocultural consequences of contact in southern New England,” in Clark Spencer Larsen and George
R. Milner, eds, In the Wake of Contact: Biological Responses to Conquest (New York: Wiley-Liss, 1994),
p 36. Estimates for other regions of the country yield a similar ratio. See e.g. the case of the Kalapuya
tribe on the northwest coast in James L. Ratcliff, “What happened to the Kalapuya? A study of the depletion
of their economic base,” The Indian Historian, Vol 6, No 3, 1973, p 27.
49 Ann F. Ramenofsky, Vectors of Death: The Archaeology of European Contact (Albuquerque, NM: University
of New Mexico Press, 1987), p 171.
50 Stannard, American Holocaust, pp 137, 255, and “Uniqueness as denial: the politics of genocide scholarship,”
in Alan S. Rosenbaum, ed., Is The Holocaust Unique? Perspectives on Comparative Genocide (Boulder, CO:
Westview Press, 1996), p 179.
673
GUENTER LEWY
51 The standard work on the subject is Sherburne F. Cook, The Conflict between the California Indians and
White Civilization (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976). See also: James J. Rawls, Indians of
California: The Changing Image (Norman, OK: University of Oklahoma Press, 1984).
52 Churchill, A Little Matter of Genocide, pp 2, 156, 151.
53 A. T. Volviler, “William Trent’s journal at Fort Pitt, 1763,” Mississippi Valley Historical Review, Vol 11, No
4, 1924, p 400; Elizabeth Fenn, “Biological warfare in eighteenth-century North America: beyond Jeffery
Amherst,” Journal of American History, Vol 86, No 4, 2000, pp 1554– 1558; Gregory Evans Dowd, War
under Heaven: Pontiac, the Indian Nations and the British Empire (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Univer-
sity Press, 2002), p 190.
54 Fenn, “Biological warfare in eighteenth-century North America,” pp 1572– 1573, 1580.
55 Churchill, A Little Matter of Genocide, p 155. The story of the “distribution of smallpox-infected blankets by
the U.S. Army to Mandans at Fort Clark” also appears in Stiffarm and Lane, Jr., “The demography of Native
North America,” p 32, and in Jaimes, State of Native America, p 7.
56 http://www.colorado.edu/news/reports/churchill/distefano062606.html.
57 Thornton, American Indian Holocaust, p 101.
58 Quoted in Schabas, Genocide, p 237.
59 Krstic (IT-98-33-T), Judgment, August 2, 2001, para. 590, www.un.org/icty/cases-e/index-e.htm. See also:
William A. Schabas, The UN International Criminal Tribunal: The Former Yugoslavia, Rwanda, and Sierra
Leone (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), p 169.
60 Francis Jennings, The Invasion of America: Indians, Colonialism and the Cant of Conquest (Chapel Hill, NC:
University of North Carolina Press, 1975), p 22.
61 Kurt Jonassohn, “What is genocide?,” in Helen Fein, ed., Genocide Watch (New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press, 1992), p 21.
674