Wiley Wesleyan University
Wiley Wesleyan University
Wiley Wesleyan University
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Wesleyan University and Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to History and Theory.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 193.54.110.35 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 08:28:28 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
THE IRONY OF NIHILISM
EUGENE 0. GOLOB
This content downloaded from 193.54.110.35 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 08:28:28 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
56 EUGENE 0. GOLOB
It will be noted that White's "not proven" verdict on the positivist claim to
history actually incorporates the presuppositions of positivism in suggesting
that history is either nonscientific or unsuccessfully trying to become a science.
Hence his claim that by his approach historians were "freed to conceptualize
2. Although to state it so simply is obviously unjust not only to the principals but
to the many sophisticated,learned participantson both sides.
This content downloaded from 193.54.110.35 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 08:28:28 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
THE IRONY OF NIHILISM 57
history, to perceive its contents" and then to write their narratives according
to their moral and aesthetic "aspirations" (434, my emphasis). Again he
writes, "different historians stress different aspects of the same historical field,
the same set or sequence of events" (274, my emphasis). Now this is the
language of positivism which has the events of history, like the events of
physics, transpiring somehow "out there" and being perceived by the his-
torian-observer. White ignores the counter-argument, that human history
consists of human actions, which are phenomena to be perceived only in their
externals, but which in their inner character, as acts of mind, must be under-
stood. But neither does White urge positivism, for a positivist must observe
phenomena and gauge them according to agreed standards or measures.
White does indeed speak as if the phenomena were "out there" to "observe,"
but, having conceded that positivism had not produced for historical study
the necessary conventions, much less the laws, he turned instead
to construct a verbal model of the historical process, or some part of it, which,
by virtue of its status as a linguistic artifact, can be broken down into the levels
of lexicon, grammar,syntax and semantic.If I proceed in this way, I am permitted
to assert [my emphasis]that differenthistoriansstress differentaspects of the same
historicalfield, the same set or sequence of events, because they actually see dif-
ferent objectsin that field. (274)
It is White's positivist presuppositions, therefore, that allow him to assume a
positivist view of the content of history, to show that history cannot measure
up to the standards of positivist science, and to conclude that the only re-
maining base for history to work from is linguistic. In short, White refused
to give genuine consideration to the argument that history is an autonomous
mode, and he proceeded as if that argument had not been made.3
But the great positivist debate actually went the other way. The autonomy
of history became evident in the very fact of the failure of the positivist
takeover bid.4 There was in fact a slow and quiet convergence among serious
historians, a tacit shedding of preordained causal sequences and ineluctable
regularities, a search in all branches of the discipline for the way people small
and great thought and enacted their thoughts in daily living, in processes of
long duration as well as, in periods of intense crisis; a seeking after con-
sciousness, mentality, or even mentality. The positivist-idealist debate finally
lagged not, as White supposes, because historians could not agree, but be-
cause they began to agree, and the influence of positivism rapidly waned.
But, because he saw things tilting if not proven the other way, he did not
actively consider the position maintained, with differences among them, by
3. Although he cites not only Collingwood's Idea of History but Louis 0. Mink's
"Autonomy of Historical Understanding," by far the most penetrating and effective
explication of the autonomy of history, in History and Theory 5 (1965), 25-47.
4. Lesser takeover bids by Freudians and quantifiers have ended in the partial as-
similation of both within autonomous history.
This content downloaded from 193.54.110.35 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 08:28:28 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
58 EUGENE 0. GOLOB
This content downloaded from 193.54.110.35 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 08:28:28 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
THE IRONY OF NIHILISM 59
no history without an implicit philosophy - a point accepted by all parties
to the great positivist debate - and having gone on to make the very inter-
esting point that there can be no theory of history that does not at least imply
its own narration of history-as-transpired (with which I believe Collingwood
would have agreed) White leaps to the conclusion that we are in a kind of
vicious hermeneutic circle.
White makes much of the fact that history and narrative fiction closely
resemble each other, and that imagination necessarily enters into the forma-
tion of narrative. In making the same points, however, Collingwood showed
with great precision how evidence limited the formation of historical narra-
tive and how it disciplined imagination, so that the historian was constrained
to say only what his evidence obliged him to say. What the particular his-
torian inferred from a batch of evidence, how his a priori imagination worked
with it, depended upon the furniture of that historian's mind. The author of
Speculum Mentis, The Principles of Art, and The New Leviathan would be the
very last to deny the presence and power of moral and aesthetic predisposi-
tions. But for Collingwood all thought was a quest for truth (even if many
conclusions could only be "interim reports"). To think "P is the same as Q"
without thinking that "It is true that P is the same as Q" is impossible.
By contrast, the quest for truth is absent from Metahistory.5 White con-
cedes of course that each of his historians thought he was after the truth and
that he had got it and the others had not. Since they differed, however, they
were all right and all wrong and were merely creating narratives according to
their moral or aesthetic preferences. But the fact that historians differ does
not necessarily mean that some are wrong and others possibly right. It invites,
rather, the question: What is there about historical thinking that produces
this circumstance? This is a simple question for the positivist, for, since his-
torical action is conceived as events (phenomena) which the historian must
observe, it can be understood only by subsumption under proper laws or
by being ranged within less decisive but nonetheless explanatory probabilistic
statements. On this basis, when there are disagreements some judgments are
necessarily wrong, arising from errors in research or evaluation. But this
view has simply not made headway among working historians, and it would
appear that it is this rejection that White has in mind when he cites historians'
failure to agree as one of the reasons for his offering a new way.
But that is not the only way to answer the question. If the stuff of history
consists not of phenomena, as in physics, but of human actions, the his-
torian must consider both the inside and the outside of these actions.
Thought, purpose, motive, customs, conceptual framework -these are the
5. On the face of it, that is. But, of course,Whitethinkshis renderingof the state
of affairsis a true one, and that his renderingof nineteenth-century
historiographyis a
true one.
This content downloaded from 193.54.110.35 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 08:28:28 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
60 EUGENE 0. GOLOB
6. For the present context we may bracket all quarrels over the boundary between
what is psychological and what is not.
7. See The Idea of History, esp. V, 2 "The Historical Imagination" and L. 0. Mink,
Mind, History and Dialectic, The Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood (Bloomington,
Indiana, 1969), esp. ch. 6.
8. Louis 0. Mink, "On the Writing and Rewriting of History," unpublished paper;
cited with the author's kind permission.
This content downloaded from 193.54.110.35 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 08:28:28 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
THE IRONY OF NIHILISM 61
but because it is inferred from real evidence here present, and is bound to
that evidence. Fiction is not so bound.
I do not think it is necessary, in these pages, to offer a detailed argument
for the capacity of history to achieve truth, "that our evidence obliges us to
say that x happened." The presupposition that people acted with each other
on this planet in times past seems a reasonable one. All historians employ it,
and most poets as well. And the pace of evolution is sufficiently slow that we
can assume that they were on the whole physiologically like ourselves
walked upright, talked, and so forth. Beyond this we do have evidence lying
about, a good deal of it, and it is up to us to see what we can make of it by
sound inference. And we undertake this effort not merely for the fun of it,
sometimes with and at times entirely without interest in policy implications
for the future, but always in the belief that we are saying something true
about the past. The fact that we do not always agree, I have argued following
Collingwood, derives from the nature of historical thinking itself, in its as-
pects of question-and-answer and a priori imagination. We justify what we
say by showing it is inferred from the evidence; we explain by constructing
narratives; and the principle of understanding to which we make implicit
appeal is not Humean causality but what Mink calls "synoptic judgment,"9
the kind of understanding we employ when a sequence has been completed,
and when we grasp the interconnectedness among the elements of a picture.
If we historians are wrong in our belief that we have been telling at least
some of the truth, then so is everyone who feels satisfied or clarified, when
he hears a narrative explanation of something that concerns him, why dinner
was not ready, why John Smith came to this university and became a history
major, why our preferred candidate lost the last election. If we are engaged
in self-deception in our work as historians, so are the psychiatrist and the
counselor. And so is Hayden White. The overwhelming part of his large
book is, as he says, an exercise in intellectual history. And the vigor of his
historical argument leaves no doubt concerning his own conviction that he is
telling the truth, telling wie es eigentlich gewesen, correcting the errors of
other historians, bringing out aspects of the past that others had missed,
suggesting new interpretations and offering a new synthesis: all of which he
believes true!
White's honesty does not permit him to exempt himself from his judgments.
His own writing he sees in the ironic mode, and this he confesses to be his
aesthetic and moral choice, while everyone else is free to make his own. The
question therefore is this: Does the mode of emplotment prevent there being
any truth-value? Or, to the contrary, is the truth indifferent to the mode of
emplotment? White argues the former; I shall argue the latter.
This content downloaded from 193.54.110.35 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 08:28:28 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
62 EUGENE 0. GOLOB
Consider the fact that a very large proportion of the cases coming before our
courts are thoroughly historical, in the problems they pose and the questions
they raise. On White's thesis the whole process of the law is at the free
choice of judges and jurors. Whether they found for the plaintiff or the
defendant would rest on the a priori emplotments and tropes the judges and
jurors had happened to adopt. But, as we know, men of contrasting tempera-
ment, tastes, moral outlooks, and even ideologies, regularly reach agreement
on the facts of the case, on what actually happened. And the reason why is
obvious: form constrains content but does not determine or define it. Lan-
guage "contributes to the formation and participates in the constitution of a
fact . . . , this, of course, does not mean that it produces the fact."10 A
hate sonnet is just as much a sonnet as a love sonnet. One wonders if this
must not be at times equally obvious to Hayden White and some of those he
cites in theoretical support. And one is led by this wonder to search out the
steps by which they seek to exorcise the obvious.
One of the principal preparatory steps for White's conclusion is his denial
of apodixis11to any and all theories of history: "Placed before the alternative
visions that history's interpreters offer for our consideration, and without any
apodictically provided theoretical grounds for preferring one over another, we
are driven back to moral and aesthetic reasons for the choice of one vision
over another as the more 'realistic' " (433). In his earliest statement of this
proposition, however, it is made to follow and hang upon the prior assertions
that
1) there can be no "properhistory"which is not at the same time "philosophyof
history";2) the possible modes of historiographyare the same as the possible
modes of speculativephilosophy of history; 3) these modes, in turn, are in reality
formalizationsof poetic insights that analyticallyprecede them and that sanction
the particulartheories used to give historical accounts the aspect of an "explana-
tion." (xi-xii)
But no claim of apodixis can conceivably be made for a proposition based
upon free moral or aesthetic choice, so that the denial of apodixis, while a
tactic necessary to White, is literally without meaning.
10. Friedrich Waismann, How I See Philosophy, ed. R. Harre (New York, 1968),
64, quoted by John S. Nelson, Review Essay on Metahistory, History and Theory 14
(1975), 90. Adrian Kuzminski, "A New Science?" Comparative Studies in Society and
History 18 (1976), 134, quotes Northrop Frye, one of the four pillars of Metahistory:
"it would be silly to use a reductive rhetoric to try to prove that theology, metaphysics,
law, the social sciences, or whichever one or group of these we happen to dislike, are
based on 'nothing but' mere metaphors of myths. Any such proof, if we are right,
would have the same kind of basis itself. [N.B.: White readily concedes this.] Criticisms
of truth or adequacy, then, are mainly criticisms of content, not form."
11. According to the Oxford Universal Dictionary this noun is obsolete, but I find
a noun convenient and this is preferable to the neologism "apodicticity."
This content downloaded from 193.54.110.35 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 08:28:28 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
THE IRONY OF NIHILISM 63
Even if it were not simply a category mistake, it would be without signifi-
cance. Modern philosophy of science has tended increasingly to make the same
denial even for the hard fields such as physics, and such questioning has
actually penetrated into the hitherto sacred precincts of mathematics. And
so we are led to one of the ironies that surrounds White's work. Despite his
Nietzschean desire to liberate the will from the burden of allegedly false his-
torical consciousness, he has clothed himself in the garments of neo-Cartesian
rationalism. The innate ideas of the seventeenth century are replaced with
the machinery of linguistics and rhetoric, and the primacy of language and
its supposed deep structures over thought is clearly asserted.
Fully as much now as then, the static rational systems of Cartesian thought
are hostile to history.12 The reasons stand clear in the contrasts between ra-
tionalistic-formal and historical thought: the former studies structural rela-
tions synchronically, presupposing they are eternal; the latter studies concrete
entities diachronically, presupposing that nothing beneath the sun is eternal.
The former tries to smooth out the roughness of change; the latter makes
change precisely the object of study. And the inevitable consequence of
White's effort to expose the inert gas of rationalism to the flame of history is
to smother the latter into inconsequentiality. After all, if history is merely a
way of letting off moral and aesthetic steam, why bother with all that
research?
It is a fair question to ask what grounds there are for asserting the primacy
of language, and, pursuing the distinction between langue and parole, what
grounds there are for claiming that there are deeper structures of meaning
that generate the changing usage of daily speech. The answer would seem to
be that because we can create systems expressing such structures they must
exist. This is very much the form of St. Anselm's Ontological Argument,
which, as Collingwood shows, proves the real existence, not of "un nomme
Dieu," not of the god of any particular religion, but of the concept of God,
and "that in the special case of metaphysical thinking the distinction between
conceiving something and thinking it to exist is a distinction without a differ-
ence." 13 Now, if White and others make a similar move in respect of "deep
structures of language controlling thought," they have thereby abandoned any
appeal to empirical evidence - inconceivable in any event - and merely
argue that such structures do really exist. But that means that a concept, "deep
structures, etc." exists, controls the language in which it is expressed, which
eo ipse proclaims the very primacy of thought over language which White,
and those with whom he affiliates himself, were striving to deny.
12. See Collingwood's discussion in The Idea of History, 59 ff; Adrian Kuzminski,
"A New Science?", 139-140: "White, the apparent ironist, may be identified as a ra-
tionalist metaphysician in disguise."
13. Essay on Metaphysics, 189; Essay on Philosophical Method, 125.
This content downloaded from 193.54.110.35 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 08:28:28 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
64 EUGENE 0. GOLOB
14. Nelson, Review Essay on Metahistory, 89, is correct in pointing out that White's
affinity with Nietzsche is more transparent in "The Burden of History," History and
Theory 5 (1966), 111-134 than in Metahistory, where, as Nelson remarks, "White often
stops short of spelling out the implications latent in his analysis." But there is no ques-
tion that the 1966 article theoretically prefigures the book. It would be interesting to
inquire whether White's later caution stemmed from a fear of putting his readers off-
which is most unlikely - or from a shift, in which he was by no means alone, from
Nietzschean nihilistic assertivenessto the much more restrained ironic idealism of Croce.
15. This frightening possibility was raised explicitly by Michael Ermarth in his re-
view of Metahistory, American Historical Review 80 (1975), 962-963.
16. White cites the Idea of History and two of Mink's articles, but not his Mind,
History and Dialectic: The Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood. But citation and reading
are not the same as grappling. It is curious that White, who makes Collingwood his
target in his peroration, challenges him specifically only in respect of one point of
interpretingCroce (who had been Collingwood's friend). White may well be correct and
Collingwood wrong on this point (381); but White might well have attacked Colling-
wood's apparently careless dismissal of J. G. Droysen (Idea of History, 165-166). It is
ironic that White's skillful and convincing interpretationof Droysen actually fits Colling-
wood's history of historiographymuch better than did his own.
This content downloaded from 193.54.110.35 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 08:28:28 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
THE IRONY OF NIHILISM 65
song of Nietzsche. White was concerned to lift from our shoulders "the
burden of history," a past that, not without reason, could be viewed as dis-
couraging, and a mode of thought which, beset with irony, could provide
only a sinking foundation for our aspirations for the future. Seeing himself
within what he regarded as a descent of history into irony, he set out to free
us from irony's grasp by showing that the irony of history rested ultimately
not on objective fact but subjective will. But the kind of intellectual liberation
he offers, by destroying any criterion of truth, also destroys personal responsi-
bility and ultimately, freedom itself.
I have put this strongly, because I think the implications that can be drawn
from Metahistory are dangerous and destructive. White's solution to the
alleged burden of history is unlimited relativism. Collingwood controlled the
inevitable relativism of historical thinking by binding it firmly to its evidence,
and warning that we were limited to the certainty of "interim reports." Re-
jecting this in the vain striving for apodixis, White and others fall into the pit
of willing to think just as you choose. Along Collingwood's path there is the
hope of doing better, founded on the workable knowledge of what we have
done and so can do; in short, of progress if we will it. Along White's path
there is the destruction of criteria arising from the past, and in the desperation
born of this certainty of ignorance, a gnashing of the will. Ironically, the
ironist who saw so clearly the pit into which Nietzsche had fallen, followed
in his steps.
Wesleyan University
This content downloaded from 193.54.110.35 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 08:28:28 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions