(Mis) Understanding Freud With Lacan, Zizek, and Neuroscience
(Mis) Understanding Freud With Lacan, Zizek, and Neuroscience
(Mis) Understanding Freud With Lacan, Zizek, and Neuroscience
(Mis)Understanding
Freud with Lacan, Zizek,
and Neuroscience
RobeRt SamuelS
The Palgrave Lacan Series
Series Editors
Calum Neill
Edinburgh Napier University
Edinburgh, UK
Derek Hook
Duquesne University
Pittsburgh, USA
Jacques Lacan is one of the most important and influential thinkers of
the 20th century. The reach of this influence continues to grow as we
settle into the 21st century, the resonance of Lacan’s thought arguably
only beginning now to be properly felt, both in terms of its application
to clinical matters and in its application to a range of human activities
and interests. The Palgrave Lacan Series is a book series for the best new
writing in the Lacanian field, giving voice to the leading writers of a new
generation of Lacanian thought. The series will comprise original mono-
graphs and thematic, multi-authored collections. The books in the series
will explore aspects of Lacan’s theory from new perspectives and with
original insights. There will be books focused on particular areas of or
issues in clinical work. There will be books focused on applying Lacanian
theory to areas and issues beyond the clinic, to matters of society, politics,
the arts and culture. Each book, whatever its particular concern, will
work to expand our understanding of Lacan’s theory and its value in the
21st century.
Robert Samuels
(Mis)Understanding
Freud with Lacan,
Zizek, and
Neuroscience
Robert Samuels
Writing Program
University of California, Santa Barbara
Goleta, CA, USA
© The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive licence to Springer Nature
Switzerland AG 2022
This work is subject to copyright. All rights are solely and exclusively licensed by the Publisher, whether
the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of
illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and
transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar
or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed.
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication
does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant
protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
The publisher, the authors, and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book
are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or
the editors give a warranty, expressed or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any
errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional
claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
This Palgrave Macmillan imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature Switzerland AG.
The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland
Dedicated to Madeleine and Sophia
Contents
1 I ntroduction 1
2 F
reud’s Project 7
4 Moving
from Freud’s Five Principles to Lacan’s Four
Fundamental Concepts 63
5 The
Desire of the Analyst and the American Repression
of Psychoanalysis105
I ndex191
vii
1
Introduction
The main argument of this book is that psychoanalytic theory and prac-
tice is structured by five threshold concepts, yet these principles are
rarely understood—even by psychoanalysts themselves. In examining
the original meanings of the pleasure principle, the primary processes,
the unconscious, transference, and the reality principle, I hope to pro-
vide a stable and clear ground for this important discipline. I will also
focus on the many ways these core concepts are distorted and repressed.
While the psychoanalyst must remain open and unbiased during treat-
ment in order enable the uncensored free association of the patent, this
analytic position is determined by a clear understanding of the theory’s
key concepts.
I will argue that in his early Project for a Scientific Psychology, Freud
develops a narrative of human development that will continue to shape
his work throughout his life.1 I consider this unpublished text to be the
blueprint and key to psychoanalysis because it presents his five central
concepts in one complete system. Freud’s early work is also important
because it aimed to ground psychoanalysis in neurology; however, Freud
also introduces a vital challenge to the brain sciences.2
Book Outline
Following this introduction, Chap. 2 offers a close reading of Freud’s
Project for a Scientific Psychology in order to define the original meanings
of the pleasure principle, the primary processes, transference, repression,
and the reality principle. One of the main arguments of this chapter is
that Freud’s basic theory is often misunderstood because his central con-
cepts are counter-intuitive and threatening to our own egos and views of
society and the mind.3 Moreover, I stress the close relation between psy-
choanalytic theory and practice as a way of indicating that any misunder-
standing of his original principles results in deviations in treatment.
To help elucidate how these basic psychoanalytic concepts have been
misunderstood, in Chap. 3, I read closely Mark Solm’s The Hidden Spring:
A Journey to the Source of Consciousness.4 With this sustained attempt to
combine psychoanalysis and neuroscience, we see how Freud’s insights
are often distorted and repressed by the new brain sciences. Even though
Freud did begin his work as a neurologist, I posit that his anticipation of
neuroscientific thinking actually goes against the main arguments of con-
temporary brain scientists. Moreover, throughout this book, I will claim
that psychoanalysis provides the most effective and realistic scientific
understanding of the human mind.
Chapter 4 examines Lacan’s The Four Concepts of Psychoanalysis.5
Although Lacan also looks at transference and the unconscious, his con-
ceptions of the drives and repetition distort some of Freud’s central prin-
ciples. Furthermore, he often confuses the pleasure principle with the
primary processes as he replaces the reality principle with the concept of
repetition. Most importantly, Lacan conflates the primary processes with
the unconscious as he downplays repression and focuses on how the
unconscious is structured like a language.
Chapter 5 looks at Mitchell Wilson’s The Analyst’s Desire in order to
show how a contemporary psychoanalyst misunderstands Freud’s and
Lacan’s basic insights.6 In stressing the role played by the analyst’s desire,
Wilson reveals why so many analysts resist the analytic process itself.
What is so instructive about this work is that is demonstrates how psy-
choanalysis can be repressed within psychoanalysis.
1 Introduction 3
Method
This book focuses on close readings of specific primary texts in order to
examine the actual words and ideas of the authors under consideration.9
I do not provide a survey of the field; instead, I concentrate on clarifying
Freud’s key insights, and then I look at some of the ways these concepts
are being misunderstood by influential theorists and practitioners.
Throughout this work, psychoanalysis is seen as a universal discourse that
addresses subjective, cultural, and historical differences. As a product of
the Enlightenment, Freud’s theories apply the scientific method to every-
day experiences and thoughts, and this entails taking an unbiased per-
spective in relation to material evidence.10 Thus, while Freud is often
attacked for being unscientific, I posit that his method is actually more
scientific than many other current approaches to human subjectivity.11
While my book does focus on Freud’s main concepts, the goal is not to
say that Freud is always right or even that he fully understands the impli-
cations of his own theories. Since it took him a long time to discover free
association and analytic neutrality, his practice often lags behind his the-
ory, and yet his central concepts are also shaped by his clinical experi-
ence.12 Moreover, Freud often uses concepts and metaphors borrowed
from biology, chemistry, and physics in order to represent symbolic ideas,
4 R. Samuels
Notes
1. Freud, Sigmund. “Project for a scientific psychology (1950 [1895]).” The
Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud,
Volume I (1886-1899): Pre-Psycho-Analytic Publications and Unpublished
Drafts. 1966. 281–391.
2. Miller, Norman S., and Jack L. Katz. “The neurological legacy of psycho-
analysis: Freud as a neurologist.” Comprehensive psychiatry 30.2 (1989):
128–134.
3. Goldberg, Arnold. Misunderstanding Freud. Other Press, 2004.
4. Solms, Mark. The hidden spring: A journey to the source of consciousness.
WW Norton & Company, 2021.
5. Lacan, Jacques, Jacques-Alain Miller, and Alan Sheridan. The four funda-
mental concepts of psycho-analysis. Routledge, 2018.
6. Wilson, Mitchell. The Analyst’s Desire: The Ethical Foundation of Clinical
Practice. Bloomsbury Publishing USA, 2020.
7. Žižek, Slavoj. The sublime object of ideology. Verso Books, 2019.
8. Belkin, Max, and Cleonie White, eds. Intersectionality and relational psy-
choanalysis: New perspectives on race, gender, and sexuality. Routledge, 2020.
9. Schur, David. “An introduction to close reading.” Harvard University:
Second Version.[Online] (1998).
10. Stockholder, Kay. “Lacan versus Freud: Subverting the enlightenment.”
American Imago 55.3 (1998): 361–422.
1 Introduction 5
11. Von Eckhardt, Barbara. “Why Freud’s research methodology was unsci-
entific.” Psychoanalysis and Contemporary Thought 5.4 (1982): 549–574.
12. Steiner, John. “The aim of psychoanalysis in theory and in practice.”
International Journal of Psycho-Analysis 77 (1996): 1073–1083.
13. Yovell, Yoram. “From mechanism to metaphor—On Freud’s struggle
with the biology of the mind.” Journal of the American Academy of
Psychoanalysis 25.3 (1997): 513–524.
14. Stengel, Erwin. “A Re-Evaluation of Freud’s Book” On Aphasia”. Its
Significance for Psycho-Analysis.” International journal of psycho-analysis
35 (1954): 85–89.
2
Freud’s Project
This chapter argues that Freud’s early Project for a Scientific Psychology
presents the blueprint for psychoanalytic theory and practice.1 By intro-
ducing the core concepts of the pleasure principle, the primary processes,
transference, the unconscious, and the reality principle, Freud’s text lays
the foundations for everything else that would follow in this field. In fact,
one can judge the interpreters of his work based on their (mis)under-
standing of these threshold concepts.2 As we shall see, it is vital to define
each principle separately while one also integrates them into a shared
structure. From this perspective, much of Freud’s later work and the work
of other psychoanalysts is a fleshing out of this unpublished text
from 1895.
From the very first, however, the principle of inertia is upset by another set
of circumstances. As the internal complexity of the organism increases, the
neuronic system receives stimuli from the somatic element itself-
endogenous stimuli, which call equally for discharge. These have their ori-
gin in the cells of the body and give rise to the major needs: hunger,
respiration and sexuality. The organism cannot withdraw itself from them
as it does from external stimuli. (356)
What Is Consciousness?
Freud’s first radical move is to posit that humans have an automatic abil-
ity to satisfy the pleasure principle through hallucination: “I have no
doubt that the wishful activation will in the first instance produce some-
thing similar to a perception-namely, a hallucination” (381). Within the
context of the primary processes, the desire to fulfill the pleasure principle
results in the confusion between the memory of a similar scene of satis-
faction and the perception of the external world.6 According to this logic,
our minds automatically seek to replace unmet needs with the memory
of a past event. It is then this confusion that defines for Freud the origins
of consciousness and thought itself.
10 R. Samuels
The purpose and meaning of dreams (or at least of normal ones) can be
established with certainty. Dreams are the fulfilments of wishes-that is, pri-
2 Freud’s Project 11
In arguing that the fundamental way we satisfy the dictates of the plea-
sure principle is through the hallucination of scenes of satisfaction, Freud
offers a new way of thinking about thought and consciousness. It turns
out that at the foundation of what makes us different from all other ani-
mals is our ability to confuse memories with perceptions.
This fundamental confusion structuring consciousness in the primary
processes is also related by Freud to the essence of human emotions: “In
a word, the affective process approximates to the uninhibited primary
process” (415). The key then to our emotional reactions is that they are
determined by the same processes that we find in dreams and hallucina-
tions, which concerns their ability to suspend reality testing through a
process of unintentional symbolic associations: “The connections in
dreams are partly nonsensical, partly feeble-minded or even meaningless
or strangely demented. The last of these attributes is explained by the fact
that the compulsion to associate prevails in dreams, as no doubt it does
primarily in all psychical life. Two cathexes that are simultaneously pres-
ent must, so it seems, be brought into connection with each other” (400).
This automatic compulsion to associate different representations that
occur at the same time provides the foundations for our access to lan-
guage and symbolic thought.11 As a fundamental mode of rhetoric, meta-
phor, and poetry, the connecting of two separate things through their
shared temporal presence provides the possibility for creative thought
and imagination.12
As Lacan will later claim, what defines the essence of symbolic lan-
guage is that one signifier represents the subject for another signifier, and
we find this same logic in Freud’s theory of associative thinking.13 In fact,
Freud provides a direct example of this structure: “The knight who fights
for a lady’s glove knows, in the first place, that the glove owes its
12 R. Samuels
importance to the lady; and, secondly, his worship of the glove does not
in the least prevent him from thinking of the lady and serving her in
other ways” (407). The core idea here is that the glove acts as a signifier
that is related to the signifier of the lady. Here we find the root of Lacan’s
claim that the unconscious is structured like a language, but in Freud’s
example, it is not a question of the unconscious since there is no repres-
sion. Instead, Freud is pointing to how consciousness itself is structured
like a symbolic language.
This same logic of symbolic association and metaphoric substitution is
used by Freud to define neural structures and the very possibility of mem-
ory itself: “We can then assert that memory is represented by the facilitations
existing between the neurone” (361). By positing that memories are consti-
tuted through the connection between different neurons, he is treating
these memories as if they are signifiers connected in a network of associa-
tions. What most contemporary neuroscientists, however, do not accept
is this idea that neurons as signifiers have no inherent presence because
they are defined in relation to other signifiers; likewise, memories are not
stable representations since their meaning is determined by their relation
to other memories, and the same structure applies to thought itself.14
In an insight that anticipates structural linguistics, Freud affirms that
signifiers are defined by their difference to other signifiers: “It is therefore
more correct to say that memory is represented by the differences in the
facilitations between the neurons” (361). Here we see how memories are
open to constant revision and distortion because they are not self-
contained or permanent, stable representations; as a system of networked
differences and associations, the primary processes function through sub-
stitution and displacement.15 Our minds, then, have an automatic poetic
essence since our memories are structured through metaphor (substitu-
tion) and metonymy (displacement). Freud explains this associative net-
work in the following manner: “Every neuron must in general be
presumed to have several paths of connection with other neurones--that
is, several contact-barriers. It is on this that the possibility depends of the
excitation having a choice of path, determined by facilitation” (363).
Here Freud anticipates the foundations of modern linguistics, computer
science, and neuroscience since he defines the fundamental processes of
differentiation, association, and substitution in a network of connections,
2 Freud’s Project 13
For Freud, then, only psychoanalysis allows us the ability to link subjec-
tive consciousness of the mind to the mechanical structures of the brain.
The paradox of this focus on subjectivity is that Freud also states that we
have no personal awareness of how our own consciousness works.
In examining the hallucinations of psychotics, primitive belief systems,
and dreams, Freud reveals the ways our minds generate a fundamental
confusion between reality and imagination in order to avoid unpleasure.
14 R. Samuels
Experience shows that the first path to be followed is that leading to inter-
nal change (e.g., emotional expression, screaming, or vascular innervation).
But, as we showed at the beginning of the discussion, no discharge of this
kind can bring about any relief of tension, because endogenous stimuli
continue to be received in spite of it and the tension is re-established. Here
a removal of the stimulus can only be effected by an intervention which
will temporarily stop the release of quantity in the interior of the body, and
an intervention of this kind requires an alteration in the external world
(e.g., the supply of nourishment or the proximity of the sexual object), and
this, as a “specific action”, can only be brought about in particular ways. At
early stages the human organism is incapable of achieving this specific
action. It is brought about by extraneous help, when the attention of an
experienced person has been drawn to the child’s condition by a discharge
taking place along the path of internal change [e.g., by the child’s scream-
ing]. This path of discharge thus acquires an extremely important second-
ary function--viz., of bringing about an understanding with other people;
and the original helplessness of human beings is thus the primal source of
all moral motives. (379)
to the task of analysis because analysis starts with a demand for help and
ends with the growing independence of the patient, and it is this goal of
separation that is often refused by contemporary analysts and
therapists.25
As we shall see, Freud develops his theory of analytic treatment by
moving away from his initial practice of hypnosis.26 One reason for this
change in technique is that Freud found that he could get people to
change when they were under hypnosis, but this change would only last
a short amount of time, and many people could not be hypnotized at
all.27 Freud also found that the less he interpreted, the more people were
able to discover on their own the causes for their psychological issues. By
remaining neutral, Freud enabled the process of free association, which in
turn allowed the patient to encounter the reality of their own repressed
thoughts and feelings.28 In placing the onus of responsibility back onto
the patient, Freud was able to reduce the role played by transference as
the patient gained a stronger sense of independence. However, Freud still
had to deal with repression and the various other defenses blocking free
association, and so he had to develop his theory of the unconscious,
which we will see was first produced through his clinical interaction with
hysterical patients.29
The Unconscious
For Freud, hysterics posed a problem for doctors because their symptoms
did not make anatomical or cognitive sense:
Before the analysis, A is an excessively intense idea, which forces its way into
consciousness too often, and each time it does so leads to tears. The subject
does not know why A makes him weep and regards it as absurd--but he
cannot prevent it. After the analysis, it has been discovered that there is an
idea B which rightly leads to tears and which rightly recurs often until a
certain complicated piece of psychical work directed against it has been
completed by the subject. The effect of B is not absurd, is comprehensible
to the subject and can even be fought against by him. (406)
The key move here is to seek out the reason for unreason by returning to
the symbolic network of the primary processes. In treating memories and
thoughts as signifiers, Freud is able to trace the movement of symbolic
substitution and displacement.31
This theory of the formation of neurotic symptoms shows why Lacan
insisted that the unconscious is structured like a language since it is clear
that Freud is using the main principles of modern structural linguistic
before this discipline was developed. In fact, the following passage shows
Freud’s logical and rhetorical approach to the structure of mental repre-
sentations and memories: “B stands in a particular relation to A. For there
has been an event which consisted of B +A. A was a subsidiary circum-
stance, while B was well calculated to produce a lasting effect. The
18 R. Samuels
Symbols are formed in this way normally as well. A soldier will sacrifice
himself for a piece of coloured cloth on a pole, because it has become the
symbol of his native country; and no one considers this neurotic. But a
hysterical symbol behaves differently. The knight who fights for a lady’s
glove knows, in the first place, that the glove owes its importance to the
lady; and, secondly, his worship of the glove does not in the least prevent
him from thinking of the lady and serving her in other ways. But the hys-
teric who is reduced to tears by A is unaware that this is because of the
association A-B, and B itself plays no part whatever in his mental life. In
this case the symbol has taken the place of the thing completely. (407)
2 Freud’s Project 19
In saying that the symbol has taken the place of the thing, Freud is indi-
cating that in the formation of a neurotic symptom, one of the signifiers
in the signifying relationship has been replaced through substitution, and
it is this process that defines repression and the possibility of the uncon-
scious: “We can sum the matter up by saying that A is compulsive and B
repressed (at least from consciousness). Analysis has revealed the surpris-
ing fact that for every compulsion there is a corresponding repression,
that for every excessive irruption into consciousness there is a correspond-
ing amnesia” (407). A key then to understanding the psychoanalytic
theory of the unconscious is to recognize this symbolic structure and the
ways that one memory can substitute for another memory.35
In contrast to neuroscience and other contemporary models of the
human mind, Freud does not define the unconscious by the fact that we
are not aware of how the mind functions or that the content remains
unknown; rather, the unconscious is derived from repression, and so the
central issue is why do we repress certain thoughts and feelings.36 Freud’s
initial response to this question is that symbolic substitution is triggered
by the distressing nature of our own thoughts and feelings: “Repression is
exclusively brought to bear on ideas that, firstly, arouse a distressing affect
(unpleasure) in the ego, and that, secondly, relate to sexual life” (408). In
other words, the reason why we hide things from ourselves is that these
thoughts and feelings make the ego uncomfortable, and one of the things
that causes the most discomfort is the presence of thoughts and memories
of a sexual nature.37 While Freud at this point does not develop his theory
of the moral conscience in the form of the super-ego, it is clear that it is
through the internalization of social norms and laws that sexuality
becomes a source of unpleasure. Since the ego wants to maintain an ideal
self-image, any feelings of guilt and shame have to be repressed through
the creation of a symbolic substitute.38
In order to understand psychoanalytic theory and practice, it is there-
fore necessary to see the relations among symbolism, repression, social
norms, and the super-ego. Furthermore, Freud highlights how what trig-
gers the activation of the primary processes in the unconscious is the
failure of the ego to control our thinking:
20 R. Samuels
Thus it is the business of the ego to permit no release of affect, since this
would at the same time permit a primary process. Its best instrument for
this purpose is the mechanism of attention. If a cathexis which releases
unpleasure were able to escape attention, the ego’s intervention would
come too late. And this is precisely what happens in the case of the hysteri-
cal proton pseudos [first lie]. Attention is focused on perceptions, which
are the normal occasions for the release of unpleasure. But here it is not a
perception but a memory-trace which unexpectedly releases unpleasure,
and the ego discovers this too late. It has permitted a primary process,
because it did not expect one. (415–416)
Freud defines hysteria here as the failure of the ego to block affect, and
this lapse is due to the fact that while the ego is centered on perceiving
the external world, memories of displeasure are allowed to emerge. It is
interesting that he calls this process a lie because it appears to be more of
the ego’s inability to anticipate an upsetting memory.39
Since repression will later be defined as the way people lie to them-
selves in order to avoid thinking about upsetting thoughts, this early
theory of the first lie has to be coupled with what Freud has been saying
about the process of removing particular memory associations from con-
sciousness.40 Moreover, it is important to stress that the unconscious and
the primary processes are two very different concepts. As we have seen,
repression can represent the use of primary processes, but this only occurs
after an act of self-deception, which divides the subject between what has
been conscious and what has replaced the memory of a conscious thought.
Hallucinations, dreams, and delusions are conscious, but they can also be
rendered unconscious through repression.
Since we retain very few memories of our first five years of life, we only
know our infantile experience through a symbolic reconstruction made
mostly out of representations and stories from others.41 From this per-
spective, our past is a black hole filled in by retrospective knowledge. In
fact, Freud insists that one of the important aspects of human sexuality is
that knowledge gained in puberty is used to re-interpret past sexual expe-
riences: “the retardation of puberty makes possible the occurrence of
posthumous primary processes” (416). In other words, childhood sexual-
ity only becomes traumatic after-the-fact when new knowledge is inter-
2 Freud’s Project 21
The first of these arises if, while it is in a wishful state, it freshly cathects the
memory of the object and then sets the process of discharge in motion,
where there can be no satisfaction because the object is not present really
but only as an imaginary idea. At an early stage it is not in a position to
make this distinction, since it can only work on the basis of the sequence
of analogous states between its neurones [i.e. on the basis of its previous
experience that the cathexis of the object was followed by satisfaction]. (386)
The central idea here is that we have to learn how to distinguish between
an image of past satisfaction and reality, but this distinction is at first
impossible because our primary processes confuse past scenes of satisfac-
tion with the perception of the external world.45
In order to establish the reality principle through the separation of
memories from perceptions, Freud claims that it is necessary for the ego
to inhibit the primary processes: “Accordingly, it is the inhibition brought
about by the ego that makes possible a criterion for distinguishing
between a perception and a memory” (388). As we will later see, it is
problematic to locate this form of reality testing in the ego because the
ego itself is a defensive structure guided by the dictates of the pleasure
principle. However, the crucial idea for psychoanalysis is this need to
access reality by countering the primary processes. Freud explains this
conflict between the automatic primary processes and the reality princi-
ple in the following personal example: “For instance, it has happened to
me that in the agitation caused by a great anxiety I have forgotten to
make use of the telephone, which had been introduced into my house a
short time before. The recently established path succumbed to the state
of affect. The facilitation-that is to say, what was old-established won the
day. Such forgetting involves the loss of the power of selection, of effi-
ciency and of logic, just as happens in dreams” (414). Freud posits here
that in the state of anxiety, his mind was taken over by the primary
2 Freud’s Project 23
The education and development of this original ego take place in states in
which there is a repetition of the craving, in states of expectation. The ego
learns first that it must not cathect the motor images (with consequent
discharge), until certain conditions have been fulfilled on the perceptual
side. It learns further that it must not cathect the wishful idea beyond a
certain degree, because, if it does, it will deceive itself in a hallucinatory
manner. If, however, it respects these two restrictions and turns its atten-
tion to the new perceptions, it has a prospect of attaining the desired satis-
faction. (426–427)
As a defense against the primary processes, Freud defines the reality prin-
ciple as a method for avoiding self-deception.48 He adds that in order to
learn to accept reality, we also have to avoid the pleasure principle’s drive
to escape all tension and unpleasure: “Unpleasure remains the sole means
of education” (428). In pitting education against the pleasure principle,
Freud reveals the difficulty in learning anything new or upsetting.
For Freud, the best way to resist the dictates of the primary processes
and the pleasure principle is to transform our thoughts into speech:
24 R. Samuels
Notes
1. Freud, Sigmund. “Project for a scientific psychology (1950 [1895]).” The
Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud,
Volume I (1886-1899): Pre-Psycho-Analytic Publications and Unpublished
Drafts. 1966. 281–391.
2. Meyer, Jan, and Ray Land. Threshold concepts and troublesome knowledge:
Linkages to ways of thinking and practising within the disciplines.
Edinburgh: University of Edinburgh, 2003.
2 Freud’s Project 25
17. Samuels, Robert. Psychoanalyzing the politics of the new brain sciences.
Springer, 2017.
18. Mills, Jon. “Lacan on paranoiac knowledge.” Psychoanalytic Psychology
20.1 (2003): 30.
19. Fink, Bruce. The Lacanian subject: Between language and jouissance.
Princeton University Press, 1997.
20. Riviere, Joan. “On the genesis of psychical conflict in earliest infancy.”
International Journal of Psycho-Analysis 17 (1936): 395–422.
21. Segal, Hanna. “Phantasy and reality.” International Journal of Psycho-
Analysis 75 (1994): 395–401.
22. Benvenuto, Bice. Once upon a Time: The Infant in Lacanian Theory 1.
Routledge, 2018.
23. Lacan, Jacques, Alan Sheridan, and Malcolm Bowie. “The function and
field of speech and language in psychoanalysis.” Écrits. Routledge,
2020. 33–125.
24. Lacan, Jacques. “The seminar of Jacques Lacan: Book VIII: Transference:
1960-1961.” (2011).
25. Benjamin, Jessica. The bonds of love: Psychoanalysis, feminism, and the
problem of domincation. Pantheon, 2013.
26. Makari, George, J. “A history of Freud’s first concept of transference.”
International review of psycho-analysis 19 (1992): 415–432.
27. Freud, Sigmund. “Remembering, repeating and working-through
(Further recommendations on the technique of psycho-analysis II).” The
Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud,
Volume XII (1911-1913): The Case of Schreber, Papers on Technique and
Other Works. 1958. 145–156.
28. Leider, Robert J. “Analytic neutrality—a historical review.” Psychoanalytic
Inquiry 3.4 (1983): 665–674.
29. Freud, Sigmund, and Joseph Breuer. Studies in hysteria. Penguin, 2004.
30. Freud, Sigmund. “Fragment of an analysis of a case of hysteria (1905
[1901]).” The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of
Sigmund Freud, Volume VII (1901-1905): A Case of Hysteria, Three Essays
on Sexuality and Other Works. 1953. 1–122.
31. Dor, Joël. Introduction to the reading of Lacan: The unconscious structured
like a language. Other Press, LLC, 1998.
32. Lacan, Jacques. The other side of psychoanalysis. Vol. 17. WW norton &
Company, 2007.
2 Freud’s Project 27
48. Samuels, Robert. “Science and the reality principle.” Freud for the twenty-
first century. Palgrave Pivot, Cham, 2019. 5–16.
49. Lacan, Jacques, Alan Sheridan, and Malcolm Bowie. “The function and
field of speech and language in psychoanalysis.” Écrits. Routledge,
2020. 33–125.
50. Samuels, Robert. “Logos, global justice, and the reality principle.” Zizek
and the rhetorical unconscious. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham, 2020. 65–86.
3
Neuroscience and the Repression
of Psychoanalysis
Natural Feelings
One of the first moves that Solms makes in his effort to explain human
consciousness and the relation between neuroscience and psychoanalysis
is to argue that feelings are natural and a key aspect of consciousness:
“This requires me to convince you that feelings are part of nature, that
they are not fundamentally different from other natural phenomena, and
that they do something within the causal matrix of things. Consciousness,
I will demonstrate, is about feeling, and feeling, in turn, is about how
well or badly you are doing in life. Consciousness exists to help you do
better” (3–4). In equating consciousness to human emotions, Solms seeks
to prove that the pleasure principle defines our awareness, and since he
wants to derive feelings of pleasure and pain from nature and evolution,
he is able to base human subjectivity on biological determinism.2
The initial problem with this formulation is that as Freud argues in his
Project for a Scientific Psychology, the first way that humans seek to satisfy
the pleasure principle is by hallucinating a previous scene of satisfaction.
Through this act of mental imagination, we are able to break free from
the constraints of reality and biology. Moreover, psychoanalysis explains
the origin of consciousness through a fundamental confusion between
perception and memory coupled with an automatic process of symbolic
association, and it is this human ability to imagine a false reality that
produces a gap between our minds and material reality.
This theory of hallucination through the primary processes, then, pro-
vides the key to answering the fundamental question of how we move
from the physical brain to the mental mind.3 As we shall see, for Solms,
it is the biology of feelings derived from natural selection that provide the
missing link, but this solution goes against both psychoanalysis and our
everyday experience. Since we have the ability to imagine things that do
not exist, we are not tied to the reality principle, evolutionary develop-
ment, or biological determinism. Our minds give us a certain level of
freedom and self-determination, even when we are not in control of our
own thinking.4
One of the results of rejecting the psychoanalytic theory of conscious-
ness is that the human mind can be equated with the brains of other
animals: “Since the cerebral cortex is the seat of intelligence, almost
everybody thinks that it is also the seat of consciousness. I disagree; con-
sciousness is far more primitive than that. It arises from a part of the brain
that humans share with fishes” (4). In equating human consciousness and
feelings with parts of a fish’s brain, Solms makes it easier to combine psy-
choanalysis and neuroscience as he also justifies the use of experiments on
animals in order to explain human psychology.5
From a psychoanalytic perspective, we need to insist that humans and
animals experience feelings in a much different way since as Freud stresses
in his Project, human feelings are always being displaced through
3 Neuroscience and the Repression of Psychoanalysis 31
artificial stimulus, then the artificial stimulus will come to trigger the
same involuntary response as the innate stimulus” (11–12). Just as behav-
ioralists like Skinner sought to shape human reactions by placing thought
in an excluded black box, Solms affirms that like other animals, human
reactions are defined by linking a reflex to particular cue or trigger.16
However, as I pointed out above, humans are able to transcend simple
conditioning because they have mental autonomy and open instincts.
Also, the things that trigger our responses are often indirect, complex,
symbolic, and social.
Because REM sleep arises from the cholinergic brainstem, an ancient and
lowly part of the brain far from the majestic cortex where all the action of
human psychology presumably takes place, he added that dreaming could
not possibly be motivated by wishes; it was ‘motivationally neutral’.
Therefore, according to Hobson, Freud’s view that dreams were driven by
latent desires must be completely wrong. (21)
The argument here is that since the parts of the brain that are activated
during dreaming belong to an early stage of animal evolution, Freud’s
theory that dreams are determined by wishes must be false. In other
words, our primary processes are not driven by the pleasure principle or
our symbolic memory system; instead, dreams are just the random firing
of neurons void of any content or meaning.22 There is thus an underlying
nihilism to this discourse since the main effect is to render meaning and
interpretation irrelevant. We are simply animal-machines programmed
by natural selection and triggered through environmental cues.23
3 Neuroscience and the Repression of Psychoanalysis 35
If there is one part of the brain that might be considered responsible for
‘wishes’, it is the mesocortical-mesolimbic dopamine circuit. It is anything
but motivationally neutral. Edmund Rolls (and many others) calls this cir-
cuit the brain’s ‘reward’ system. Kent Berridge calls it the ‘wanting’ system.
Jaak Panksepp calls it the SEEKING system – and foregrounds its role in
the function of foraging. This is the brain circuit responsible for ‘the most
energised exploratory and search behaviours an animal is capable of exhib-
iting’. It is also the circuit that drives dreaming. (27–28)
This passage is Solms at his most psychoanalytic, but once again, he fails
to separate the theory of the unconscious from the primary processes. By
focusing on the unconscious intentionality derived from the implicit
missing links of associated ideas, he avoids the issue of why these links are
missing in the first place. There is thus an important distinction that has
to be made between the repression of unwanted feelings and thoughts
and the way our stream of consciousness is shaped by the association of
ideas in a network of substitutions and displacements. When you elimi-
nate the causes of repression, you end up with a purely mechanical model
that eliminates human subjectivity.
At one point, Solms does highlight Freud’s theory of repression, but it
is presented in a confused way and then later removed from
consideration:
Feelings, Consciousness,
and the Pleasure Principle
While Solms seeks to base his theory of consciousness on the experience
of feelings, he relates all emotions to the pleasure principle defined by the
quest for self-preservation: “In short, pleasure and unpleasure tell you
how you are doing in relation to your biological needs. Valence reflects
42 R. Samuels
the value system underwriting all biological life, namely that it is ‘good’
to survive and to reproduce and ‘bad’ not to do so” (96–97). This focus
on biological survival and reproduction is in conflict with Freud’s theo-
ries of the pleasure principle and sexuality. Early on in his work, Freud
realized the human sexuality often went beyond the need for reproduc-
tion; in fact, he used the term perversion to point to the many deviations
in the human sexual experience.47 Freud also developed his theory of
masochism to reveal the ways people find pleasure in suffering, and so it
hard to say that psychoanalysis considers the pleasure principle as a drive
for reproduction or self-preservation.48 Furthermore, it is necessary to
distinguish the emotional responses to internal and external stimuli from
the stimuli themselves, and so the question of what it means to feel has to
be examined.
Since Solms wants to equate feelings and consciousness with a biologi-
cal cause shaped by evolution, he has to reduce the complexity of human
drives and emotions: “If you swapped subjective redness with blueness
there would be no consequences, but if you swapped the feeling of fear
with separation distress (or hunger with urinary urgency), it would kill
you” (98–99). A problem with definition of fear as it relates to self-
preservation is that psychoanalysis often highlights how our fears are
often irrational and inconsistent.49 Since we fear things based on our par-
ticular psychopathology, it is incorrect to claim that humans and other
animals experience fear and different emotions in the same way.
As I have been arguing, what allows Solms the ability to equate the
mind with the brain and humans with other animals is his misunder-
standings of the basic concepts of psychoanalysis. We see this problem in
the following passage: “Emotional needs, too, can be managed automati-
cally, by means of behavioural stereotypes such as ‘instincts’ (inborn sur-
vival and reproductive strategies, which Freud placed at the centre of his
conception of the unconscious mind)” (99). In positing that the uncon-
scious is shaped by the instinctual goals of survival and reproduction,
Solms shows how far his discourse is from psychoanalysis. Not only does
Freud’s theory of the drives represent a break with natural instincts, but
his key concept of the unconscious relies on the principle of repression.50
In fact, Lacan claims that the status of the unconscious is ethical because
it is centered on feelings of guilt and shame, which are themselves
3 Neuroscience and the Repression of Psychoanalysis 43
We have started exploring affect via its bodily forms. This is because they
provide the simplest examples, and no doubt they were also the first to
appear in evolution. I think the ‘dawn of consciousness’ involved nothing
more elaborate than valenced somatic sensations. What I want to show you
now is that human emotions are complex versions of the same type of
thing. They, too, are ultimately ‘error’ signals which register deviations
from your biologically preferred states, which tell you whether the steps
you are taking are making things better or worse for you. (102)
It should be clear that psychoanalysis would not exist if people only did
things that were good for their own self-preservation; in fact, the psycho-
analytic clinic proves that we cannot base consciousness or the pleasure
principle on purely biological foundations. Not only do we often find
pleasure in things that are bad for us, but we ignore emotional signals
that seek to warn us against dangerous behaviors and self-destructive
thoughts.60
3 Neuroscience and the Repression of Psychoanalysis 45
In what follows, when I switch back and forth from observations about
animals to observations about humans, I am doing so deliberately. As
Panksepp said when he was accused by colleagues of anthropomorphism
towards animals: he would rather plead guilty to zoomorphism towards
humans. The purpose of his experiments was to determine which brain
structures and circuits reliably arouse the same affective responses, not only
across individuals but also across species. When it comes to emotional
affects, it turned out that seven of them can be reliably reproduced not only
in all primates but also in all mammals, by stimulation of exactly the same
brain structures and chemicals. (Many of them can be evoked in birds, too,
and some in all vertebrates.) Mammals separated from birds about 200
million years ago; that is how old these emotions are. Still, since humans
are mammals, in what follows I am going to focus on these seven types. As
far as we know, these are the basic ingredients of the entire human emo-
tional repertoire. All our myriad joys and sorrows appear to be the outputs
of these seven systems, blending with each other and with higher cognitive
processes. (103–104)
One could interpret this passage as indicating that all of our basic emo-
tions are derived from natural selection and are equivalent to other ani-
mals, yet they become re-interpreted and re-purposed by “higher cognitive
processes.” However, Solms’ goal is to base our understanding of human
consciousness on these emotions, and so he is not just saying that the
origins of our affective responses are biological; rather, he is positing that
human consciousness is a product of natural selection, and in the process,
he is eliminating free will, cultural influence, imagination, and abstract
reason.61
One might ask why would someone who says he is invested in promot-
ing psychoanalysis end up repressing this discipline, and the answer to
this important question revolves around several factors. It is clear that a
driving forces behind his text is that he wants to argue against the notion
46 R. Samuels
The major dissenting voice is that of Lisa Feldman Barrett. Again, the dis-
agreement is attributable mainly to methodological differences. She focuses
on self-reported emotions in humans and, not surprisingly, finds that there
is enormous variability in how different people (and cultures) characterise
and parse feelings. This does not disprove the fact that basic natural kinds
lurk beneath the socially constructed surface. I will soon illustrate the
mechanisms whereby such variability arises, but the short explanation is
this: our reflexes and instincts provide rough-and-ready tools for survival
and reproductive success, but they cannot possibly equip us adequately for
the multiplicity of unpredicted situations and environments that we find
ourselves in. We therefore need to adaptively supplement the innate
responses through learning from experience. The fact that human beings
do so with such ease is the major reason why, for better or worse, we came
to dominate the world to the degree that we now do. (104)
Since we can redirect our drives based on our thoughts, experience, and
culture, we are able to use biological programs in unexpected ways.67 Our
emotional responses, then, may have their roots in evolutionary forces,
48 R. Samuels
Since humans do not primarily use sex for reproduction, the evolutionary
cause is broken, and yet, Solms has to return to biology and evolution to
make psychoanalysis fit his version of science. Once again, by not tying
the unconscious to repression, he displaces the fundamental meaning of
psychoanalysis as he claims he is doing psychoanalytic work.
As Solms rightly points out, a driving force behind our emotions tran-
scending biology is that we have to interact with other people to satisfy
our needs:
The main reason why ‘emotional’ needs are more difficult to meet than
‘bodily’ ones is that they typically involve other sentient agents, who have
needs of their own; they are not mere substances like food and water. To
3 Neuroscience and the Repression of Psychoanalysis 49
This reliance on working with the emotions and needs of others is one of
the main sources for Freud’s theory of transference, and yet Solms turns
to this social factor in order to highlight the inter-subjective nature of
sexuality.68 The problem with this approach is that it rejects Freud’s
insight into how human sexuality is often centered on auto-erotism,
which relies on a denial of the social and the needs of others.69 Although
psychoanalysis also highlights the role that culture plays in reshaping
desire and the drives, the pleasure principle is centered on the release of
tension and not on communication or social interaction.
This distinction between what is social and what is biological has to be
supplemented by the anti-evolutionary aspects of human drives, which
are themselves different from symbolic consciousness and unconscious
repression. When we fail to make these distinctions, we rob psychoanaly-
sis of the very things that make it important and different from other
disciplines. For instance, in the following discussion of reflexes, instincts,
and memories, we encounter a non-psychoanalytic use of psychoanalytic
concepts: “Notice that learning does not erase reflexes and instincts; it
elaborates, supplements and overrules them, but they are still there. Street
lamps illuminate pathways by night, but they cannot get rid of the dark-
ness altogether. The usual mechanism for updating long-term memories,
‘reconsolidation’ (which I’ll describe in Chap. 10), doesn’t apply to
reflexes and instincts. That is because reflexes and instincts are not memo-
ries” (106). Freud would concur that memories and instincts are very
different things, but the key distinction is between the primary processes
and the pleasure principle. A basic Freudian principle is that once drives
(instincts) are repressed into the unconscious, they become restructured
through the primary processes. These symbolic associations, displace-
ments, and substitutions make a break with biology, nature, material real-
ity, and evolution. In turn, on another level, our desires are reshaped by
culture and society through transference, identification, idealization, and
morality. So while it may be true that learning (nurture) does not
50 R. Samuels
Before the 1980s, psychiatric diagnoses were inextricable from the experi-
ences of particular individuals. Clinicians viewed mental problems as being
closely intertwined with people’s psychosocial backgrounds and circum-
stances and therefore impossible to isolate from personal interpretations,
identities, socialization, relationships, and life events. This view of mental
illness sharply divided psychiatry from other medical specialties, which
studied diseases with predictable courses and outcomes that were indepen-
dent of particular individual lives. (2)
What in part allowed for this move away from psychoanalysis in psychia-
try and other forms of therapy was a growing desire to see mental issues
as organic diseases.72
A side-effect, then, of Solms’ discourse is that its focus on biological
determinism feeds the drive to replace social and psychological interpre-
tations with the natural sciences. Likewise, in moving away from the
inner dynamics of individuals and the conflicts between society and the
drives, the standardized diagnostic manual was able to repress psycho-
analysis as it determined the economic and practical future of mental
health treatment:
Since its third edition, many psychiatrists have viewed the DSM as the
product of improving empirical knowledge about mental disorder. They
regard the first two editions as reflecting the unscientific or even anti-
scientific views of eclectic American psychiatrist Adolf Meyer and psycho-
analyst Sigmund Freud. After the DSM-III revolution in 1980, however,
scientific evidence has served as the foundation of psychiatric diagnoses.
Therefore, the evolution of the manual represents the triumph of “science
over ideology”: “The old psychiatry derives from theory, the new psychiatry
from fact.” (5–6)
The desire to increase the profits and prestige of psychiatrists and phar-
maceutical companies helped to motivate this move from psychoanalysis
3 Neuroscience and the Repression of Psychoanalysis 53
There are also clear intra-professional divisions regarding the role of diag-
noses. In particular, researchers and clinicians use the DSM in distinct
ways. Researchers require specific diagnoses to create homogeneous groups
that can reveal the etiology, prognosis, and best treatments for the particu-
lar condition under study. Their definitions must be similar to those of
others who study comparable phenomena. In contrast, clinicians must deal
with the idiosyncrasies of particular clients. For them, diagnoses are practi-
cal tools, not the basis for standardized protocols. (9)
While researchers need clear diagnostic categories, analysts are more con-
cerned about the specificity of each individual case. The way that this
conflict was resolved was to give both sides what they wanted by stan-
dardizing diagnostic categories and multiplying them to such an extent
that every individual could be covered. Moreover, since clinicians wanted
to be re-imbursed by insurance companies that required defined diagno-
sis and treatment plans, they had to conform to a system in which they
did not really believe.76
Horwitz adds that it was often the pharmaceutical industry that was
fueling this drive for more standardized diagnostic categories:
Here we find the core of what I have called the Governmental University
Medical Pharmaceutical Complex (GUMP).77 The government forces
drug companies to cater to particular diagnostic categories, while these
same corporations fund university medical research and required drug
trials. Meanwhile, the professional association that authors the diagnostic
manual is shaped by pharmaceutical interests, and the individual psychia-
trists increase their pay and prestige by invoking a medical and scientific
approach to mental illness.
All of these intertwined incentives are further enabled by the desire of
patients to receive a clear diagnosis that fortifies their identity and pro-
vides access to care and financial support: “Patients and their families
sought them to obtain desired treatments, reimbursement for care, eligi-
bility for government benefits, provision of special education resources,
and explanations for distress” (10). Although it appears that everyone has
a stake in the diagnostic bible, what is still unclear is if this system of
diagnosis has any real validity or scientific value.
In fact, Horwitz reveals how there is little connection between the
development and marketing of psychotropic drugs and a scientific under-
standing of different mental disorders:
What we learn here is that the new brain sciences played a key role in
propping up the pharmaceutical industry’s need to match their medica-
tion with specific diagnostic categories; using the disease model from the
medical sciences, university researchers and pharmaceutical interests pro-
moted the idea that mental problems derived from chemical imbalances.78
In the battle between psychoanalytic treatment and medication, Big
Pharma won by turning to scientific theories bent on discrediting Freud.
Moreover, insurance companies enhanced their influence by dictating
what treatments would be allowed for specific diagnosis:
Between the mid-1960s and 1980, the percentage of patients using insur-
ance to pay for outpatient psychotherapy rose from 38 to 68 percent.
While patients had little concern with particular diagnostic categories, the
third parties that increasingly paid for their treatment were coming to
demand that it involve genuine diseases and not problems in living.
Insurers were willing to fund only a specific number of visits for well-
defined problems and cast an especially sharp eye on what could often be
interminable psychoanalytic sessions. The nebulous DSM-II conditions
poorly fit an insurance logic that would reimburse the treatment of only
discrete diseases. (49–50)
Since the insurance companies would only support payments for specific
diseases, and clinicians relied on insurance payments, the clinicians had
to buy into a system that often went against their own beliefs and prac-
tices. In fact, as Horwitz documents, academic researchers, pharmaceuti-
cal corporations, and psychiatric institutions all dismissed the fundamental
basis of psychoanalytic treatment:
Notes
1. Solms, Mark. The hidden spring: A journey to the source of consciousness.
WW Norton & Company, 2021.
2. Rose, Steven, Richard Charles Lewontin, and L. Kamin. “Not in our
genes: Biology, ideology and human nature.” The Wilson Quarterly
152 (1984).
3. Chalmers, David. “The hard problem of consciousness.” The Blackwell
companion to consciousness (2007): 225–235.
4. Samuels, Robert. “The Backlash Politics of Evolutionary Psychology:
Steven Pinker’s Blank Slate.” Psychoanalyzing the Politics of the New Brain
Sciences. Palgrave Pivot, Cham, 2017. 35–58.
5. Bourtchouladze, Rusiko. Memories are made of this: How memory works
in humans and animals. Columbia University Press, 2002.
6. Żechowski, Cezary. “Theory of drives and emotions-from Sigmund
Freud to Jaak Panksepp.” Psychiatr Pol 51.6 (2017): 1181–1189.
7. Barrett, Lisa Feldman. How emotions are made: The secret life of the brain.
Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 2017.
8. Freud, Sigmund. “Instincts and their vicissitudes.” The Standard Edition
of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, Volume XIV
(1914-1916): On the History of the Psycho-Analytic Movement, Papers on
Metapsychology and Other Works. 1957. 109–140.
9. Freud, Sigmund. Three essays on the theory of sexuality: The 1905 edition.
Verso Books, 2017.
10. Natsoulas, Thomas. “Freud and consciousness: V. Emotions and feel-
ings.” Psychoanalysis and Contemporary Thought14.1 (1991): 69–108.
11. Freud, Sigmund, James Strachey, and Alix Strachey. Inhibitions, symp-
toms and anxiety. New York: Norton, 1977.
12. Freud, Sigmund. “Repression.” The Standard Edition of the Complete
Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, Volume XIV (1914-1916): On the
History of the Psycho-Analytic Movement, Papers on Metapsychology and
Other Works. 1957. 141–158.
13. Samuels, Robert. “Damasio’s Error: The Politics of Biological
Determinism After Freud.” Psychoanalyzing the Politics of the New Brain
Sciences. Palgrave Pivot, Cham, 2017. 9–33.
58 R. Samuels
47. Freud, Sigmund. “Three essays on the theory of sexuality (1905).” The
standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, vol-
ume VII (1901-1905): A case of hysteria, three essays on sexuality and other
works. 1953. 123–246.
48. Freud, Sigmund. “The economic problem of masochism.” The Standard
Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, Volume XIX
(1923-1925): The Ego and the Id and Other Works. 1961. 155–170.
49. Freud, Sigmund. Obsessions and phobias. Read Books Ltd, 2014.
50. Freud, Sigmund. “Instincts and their vicissitudes.” The Standard Edition
of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, Volume XIV
(1914-1916): On the History of the Psycho-Analytic Movement, Papers on
Metapsychology and Other Works. 1957. 109–140.
51. Soler, Colette, Esther Faye, and Susan Schwartz. Lacan—The Unconscious
Reinvented: The Unconscious Reinvented. Routledge, 2018.
52. Sartre, Jean-Paul. Being and nothingness: An essay in phenomenological
ontology. Citadel Press, 2001.
53. Harris, Sam. Free will. Simon and Schuster, 2012.
54. Suttie, Ian D. “Critical Review: METAPSYCHOLOGY AND
BIOLOGY: Some criticisms of Freud’s “Beyond the Pleasure Principle.”.”
Journal of Neurology and Psychopathology 5.17 (1924): 61.
55. Samuels, Robert. “Catharsis: The politics of enjoyment.” Zizek and the
rhetorical unconscious. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham, 2020. 7–31.
56. Rado, Sandor. “The psychoanalysis of pharmacothymia (drug addic-
tion).” The Psychoanalytic Quarterly 2.1 (1933): 1–23.
57. Kim, Eunhyang, and Eunyoung Koh. “Avoidant attachment and smart-
phone addiction in college students: The mediating effects of anxiety
and self-esteem.” Computers in Human Behavior 84 (2018): 264–271.
58. Samuels, Robert. “Drugging Discontent: Psychoanalysis, Drives, and
the Governmental University Medical Pharmaceutical Complex
(GUMP).” Psychoanalyzing the Politics of the New Brain Sciences. Palgrave
Pivot, Cham, 2017. 115–136.
59. Robert, Jason Scott. Embryology, epigenesis and evolution: Taking develop-
ment seriously. Cambridge University Press, 2004.
60. Vazire, Simine, and David C. Funder. “Impulsivity and the self-defeating
behavior of narcissists.” Personality and social psychology review 10.2
(2006): 154–165.
3 Neuroscience and the Repression of Psychoanalysis 61
61. Samuels, Robert. “The Brain Sciences Against the Welfare State.”
Psychoanalyzing the Politics of the New Brain Sciences. Palgrave Pivot,
Cham, 2017. 85–114.
62. Hacker, P. M. S. “Philosophy and scientism: What cognitive neurosci-
ence can, and what it cannot, explain.” Scientism: The new orthodoxy
(2015): 97–115.
63. Samuels, Robert. “Conclusion: Science, Politics, Media, and the Virus.”
Viral Rhetoric. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham, 2021. 109–112.
64. Samuels, Robert. “The Backlash Politics of Evolutionary Psychology:
Steven Pinker’s Blank Slate.” Psychoanalyzing the Politics of the New Brain
Sciences. Palgrave Pivot, Cham, 2017. 35–58.
65. Westen, Drew. “The scientific legacy of Sigmund Freud: Toward a psy-
chodynamically informed psychological science.” Psychological bulletin
124.3 (1998): 333.
66. Westen, Drew. “The scientific legacy of Sigmund Freud: Toward a psy-
chodynamically informed psychological science.” Psychological bulletin
124.3 (1998): 333.
67. Hodgson, Geoffrey M. “Choice, habit and evolution.” Journal of
Evolutionary Economics 20.1 (2010): 1–18.
68. Samuels, Robert. “Transference and Narcissism.” Freud for the Twenty-
First Century. Palgrave Pivot, Cham, 2019. 43–51.
69. Kanzer, Mark. “Freud’s uses of the terms “autoerotism” and “narcis-
sism”.” Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association 12.3 (1964):
529–539.
70. Horwitz, Allan V. DSM: A History of Psychiatry’s Bible. JHU Press, 2021.
71. Lane, Christopher. Shyness: How normal behavior became a sickness. Yale
University Press, 2008.
72. Whitaker, Robert. “Anatomy of an epidemic: Psychiatric drugs and the
astonishing rise of mental illness in America.” Ethical Human Psychology
and Psychiatry 7.1 (2005): 23.
73. Burston, Daniel. “Psychiatry and Anti-psychiatry: History, Rhetoric and
Reality.” Eidos. A Journal for Philosophy of Culture 2.2 (4) (2018).
74. Marquis, Andre, and Kathryn Z. Douthit. “Empiricism in psychiatry’s
post-psychoanalytic era: Contemplating DSM’s” atheoretical” nosol-
ogy.” Constructivism in the Human Sciences 11.1/2 (2006): 32.
75. Goldacre, Ben. Bad science: Quacks, hacks, and big pharma flacks.
McClelland & Stewart, 2010.
62 R. Samuels
76. Cooper, Rachel. “What is wrong with the DSM?.” History of Psychiatry
15.1 (2004): 5–25.
77. Samuels, Robert. “Drugging Discontent: Psychoanalysis, Drives, and
the Governmental University Medical Pharmaceutical Complex
(GUMP).” Psychoanalyzing the Politics of the New Brain Sciences. Palgrave
Pivot, Cham, 2017. 115–136.
78. Moncrieff, Joanna. “The myth of the chemical cure.” The Myth of the
Chemical Cure. Palgrave Macmillan, London, 2008. 217–224.
79. Khoury, Bassam, Ellen J. Langer, and Francesco Pagnini. “The DSM:
Mindful science or mindless power? A critical review.” Frontiers in psy-
chology 5 (2014): 602.
4
Moving from Freud’s Five Principles
to Lacan’s Four Fundamental Concepts
Most of you will have some idea of what I mean when I say--the uncon-
scious is structured like a language. This statement refers to a field that is
much more accessible to us today than at the time of Freud. I will illustrate
it by something that is materialized, at what is certainly a scientific level, by
the field that is explored, structured, elaborated by Claude Levi-Strauss,
and which he has pinpointed in the title of his book, La Pensee Sauvage.
Before any experience, before any individual deduction, even before those
collective experiences that may be related only to social needs are inscribed
in it, something organizes this field, inscribes its initial lines of force. This
is the function that Claude Levi-Strauss shows us to be the truth of the
totemic function, and which reduces its appearance--the primary classifica-
tory function. Before strictly human relations are established, certain rela-
tions have already been determined. They are taken from whatever nature
may offer as supports, supports that are arranged in themes of opposition.
Nature provides-- must use the word--signifiers, and these signifiers orga-
nize human relations in a creative way, providing them with structures and
shaping them. The important thing, for us, is that we are seeking here-
-before any formation of the subject, of a subject who thinks, who situates
himself in it--the level at which there is counting, things are counted, and
in this counting he who counts is already included. It is only later that the
subject has to recognize himself as such, recognize himself as he who
counts. (20)
If you keep hold of this initial structure, you will avoid giving yourself up
to some partial aspect of the question of the unconscious---as, for example,
that it is the subject, qua alienated in his history, at the level at which the
syncope of discourse is joined with his desire. You will see that, more radi-
cally, it is in the dimension of a synchrony that you must situate the uncon-
scious--at the level of a being, but in the sense that it can spread over
everything, that is to say, at the level of the subject of the enunciation, in
so far as, according to the sentences, according to the modes, it loses itself
as much as it finds itself again, and in the sense that, in an interjection, in
an imperative, in an invocation, even in a hesitation, it is always the uncon-
scious that presents you with its enigma, and speaks--in short, at the level
at which everything that blossoms in the unconscious spreads, like myce-
lium, as Freud says about the dream, around a central point. It is always a
question of the subject qua indeterminate … (26)
On one level, Lacan is arguing the subjectivity spreads over the entire
dream because in relation to representation, the ego is absent and the
subject vacillates and is indeterminate; however, on another level, he is
insisting that the subject is present through the emotional relation to the
symbolic representations. In the opposition between the content of the
dream and the subjective response to the content, we find the relation
between the primary processes and the unconscious. Like the final punc-
tuation of a sentence with a question mark or an exclamation point, sub-
jectivity (the enunciation in linguistic terminology) defines the meaning
of a symbolic representation through the attitude of the speaker or writer
in relation to symbolic material.19 In fact, what one often finds in dreams
is an ongoing commentary similar to a voice-over in movies.
The dream then highlights two aspects of the primary processes: the
manifest symbols (signifiers) and the latent thoughts (signifieds). As
Lacan highlights, Freud anticipates Saussure’s theory of linguistics by
68 R. Samuels
To all these forms of unconscious, ever more or less linked to some obscure
will regarded as primordial, to something preconscious, what Freud
opposes is the revelation that at the level of the unconscious there is some-
thing at all points homologous with what occurs at the level of the subject-
-this thing speaks and functions in a way quite as elaborate as at the level
of the conscious, which thus loses what seemed to be its privilege. I am well
aware of the resistances that this simple remark can still provoke, though it
is evident in everything that Freud wrote. (24)
The radical move Lacan makes here is to define consciousness and subjec-
tivity through the psychotic dream state. Since we are not in control of
our dreams, and they do not follow our intentions, we are subjected to
them, and yet, our subjectivity is evident in these formations. Here,
Lacan is close to Sartre’s critique of Freud since one of Sartre’s main criti-
cisms of psychoanalysis was that it tried to divorce subjectivity from con-
sciousness through the concept of the unconscious.22 For Sartre, even
when we try to repress something or avoid a memory, we are conscious of
what we are doing. However, what Sartre refuses to accept is the differ-
ence between consciousness in the primary processes and the way repres-
sion causes a division between the unintentional awareness of
consciousness and the lack of awareness of repressed material.23 Although
Lacan helps to reject Sartre’s criticism by showing how consciousness
4 Moving from Freud’s Five Principles to Lacan’s Four… 69
Let us turn again to an example that has never been sufficiently exploited,
the first used by Freud to demonstrate his theory, namely, his forgetting,
his inability to remember the word Signorelli after his visit to the paintings
at Orvieto. Is it possible not to see emerging from the text itself, and estab-
lishing itself, not metaphor, but the reality of the disappearance, of the
suppression, of the Unterdriickung, the passing underneath? The term
Signor, Herr, passes underneath--the absolute master, I once said, which is
in fact death, has disappeared there. Furthermore, do we not see, behind
this, the emergence of that which forced Freud to find in the myths of the
death of the father the regulation of his desire? After all, it is to be found in
Nietzsche, who declares, in his own myth, that God is dead. And it is
70 R. Samuels
erhaps against the background of the same reasons. For the myth of the
p
God is dead--which, personally, I feel much less sure about, as a myth of
course, than most contemporary intellectuals, which is in no sense a decla-
ration of theism, nor of faith in the resurrection--perhaps this myth is sim-
ply a shelter against the threat of castration. (27)
There is a lot going on in this passage, but what I would like to stress is
Lacan’s emphasis on the notion that Freud cannot remember a name
because part of the signifier reminds him of death and castration. Clearly,
we are on the level of repression and the unconscious here what deter-
mines the self-censorship is the desire to avoid thinking about a threaten-
ing subject matter.25 Lacan adds that we know in analysis when we are
dealing with the unconscious because the subject is surprised by what is
discovered in his or her own discourse: “Thus the unconscious is always
manifested as that which vacillates in a split in the subject, from which
emerges a discovery that Freud compares with desire--a desire that we will
temporarily situate in the denuded metonymy of the discourse in ques-
tion, where the subject surprises himself in some unexpected way” (28).
While the subject of a psychotic hallucination or delusion is certain about
what is being perceived, the subject of the unconscious is surprised by the
automatic return of the repressed.26 It is then a goal of analysis to enable
an encounter with this unexpected material.
Underlying both Freud’s and Lacan’s conceptions of the unconscious is
the notion that whatever is repressed always tries to return.27 In fact,
Lacan uses his theory of desire to show how in contrast to the pleasure
principle, unconscious material resists being subjected to the homeostatic
drive to avoid all tension and conflict: “Pleasure limits the scope of human
possibility--the pleasure principle is a principle of homeostasis. Desire,
on the other hand, finds its boundary, its strict relation, its limit, and it is
in the relation to this limit that it is sustained as such, crossing the thresh-
old imposed by the pleasure principle” (31). From this perspective, what
allows us to move beyond the dictates of the pleasure principle is desire as
a longing for something we do not have that also refuses to be limited by
time or the need to avoid tension:28
4 Moving from Freud’s Five Principles to Lacan’s Four… 71
Lacan reveals here how his method of presentation requires both relating
and distinguishing key concepts. Moreover, he posits that Freud’s theo-
ries can be confusing because they were derived from Freud’s developing
technique. The importance of this latter point is that we see the close
connection between theory and practice, which requires us to constantly
ask how a particular concept helps to shape psychoanalytic technique.
By focusing on analytic treatment, Lacan recenters our understanding
of Freud’s theory of the unconscious:
Lacan thus approaches the reality principle, science, and the ethics of
psychoanalysis through the concept of repetition, which he relates to the
revelation caused by a missed encounter with the real.33
Lacan connects science and the reality principle to the concept of rep-
etition because he sees this notion as highlighting both the impossibility
of fully symbolizing reality and the fact that the real always returns.34
Since we cannot completely escape our own memories, thoughts, fears,
and feelings, psychoanalytic practice is founded on a belief in the power
of repetition. In fact, Lacan points to this role of repetition in psychoana-
lytic technique by making the following argument:
Where it was, the Ich--the subject, not psychology--the subject, must come
into existence. And there is only one method of knowing that one is there,
namely, to map the network. And how is a network mapped? One goes
back and forth over one’s ground, one crosses one’s path, one cross-checks
it always in the same way, and in this seventh chapter of The Interpretation
of Dreams there is no other confirmation for one’s Gewissheit, one’s cer-
tainty, than this--Speak of chance, gentlemen, if you like. In my experience
I have observed nothing arbitrary in this field, for it is crosschecked in such
a way that it escapes chance. (45)
In saying that analysis has to map the network of the subject’s memories,
Lacan is emphasizing how the practice of free association relies on discov-
ering repressed memories by following the path of their associations.
From this perspective, there is no chance because all connections have
been determined through symbolic relationships that are discovered
through repetition. Since, as Freud insists, no memory can ever be fully
forgotten, these thoughts and feelings are seen as equivalent to a real that
always returns to the same place.35
The practice of free association and the neutrality of the analysis are,
thus, based on a belief in the return and repetition of signifiers. Since all
thoughts and feelings are encoded in memories, and all memories are
signifiers, this theory of the inability to efface signifiers represents the key
to both the theory and technique of psychoanalysis.36 Furthermore,
Lacan shows that in Freud’s work, an important move was made by sepa-
rating these memory signifiers from consciousness and perception:
74 R. Samuels
Just as Freud argued that there is a center to every dream that has no
meaning, Lacan insists that since the symbolic cannot fully represent the
real, every attempt at memory ultimately fails.40 In fact, for Freud, what
defined science was the acceptance of the limits of our knowledge, which
fuels a desire to always try to discover more. Furthermore, Freud sought
to counter what he calls the “omnipotence of thought” in the primary
processes by stressing the limitations of our understanding.41
Lacan’s theory of the real can be seen as representing Freud’s reality
principle because what he seeks to emphasize is the fact that reality always
resists representation: “Where do we meet this real? For what we have in
the discovery of psycho-analysis is an encounter, an essential encounter-
-an appointment to which we are always called with a real that eludes us”
(53). Based on this theory of the real as always being missed, we see how
76 R. Samuels
Lacan asks here how it is possible for people to return in their minds to
traumatic events if our thinking is driven by the pleasure principle’s quest
to avoid all mental tension and unpleasure? In other words, why do we
repeat in our dreams and fantasies the very things we are trying to
escape?44
4 Moving from Freud’s Five Principles to Lacan’s Four… 77
The other day, I was awoken from a short nap by knocking at my door just
before I actually awoke. With this impatient knocking I had already formed
a dream, a dream that manifested to me something other than this knock-
ing. And when I awake, it is in so far as I reconstitute my entire representa-
tion around this knocking--this perception-that I am aware of it. I know
that I am there, at what time I went to sleep, and why I went to sleep.
When the knocking occurs, not in my perception, but in my conscious-
ness, it is because my consciousness reconstitutes itself around this repre-
sentation--that I know that I am waking up, that I am knocked up. (56)
also develop an ego and a holistic body image, the formation of the self
must be based on a virtual mapping of space.53 Our recognition and iden-
tification with an ideal body image, then, relies on our ability to identify
with an external holistic object. Thus, in his theory of the mirror stage,
Lacan highlights how the ideal ego is formed by identifying with the ideal
image in the mirror, and this object can be replaced by the relation to
another person of similar size and age.54
The next move that Lacan makes in relation to this imaginary level of
subjectivity is to oppose the intentionality of the ego to his concept of
the gaze:
You will see that the ways through which he will lead you are not only of
the order of visual phenomenology, since they set out to rediscover--this is
the essential point-the dependence of the visible on that which places us
under the eye of the seer. But this is going too far, for that eye is only the
metaphor of something that I would prefer to call the seer’s ‘shoot’ (pousse)-
-something prior to his eye. What we have to circumscribe, by means of the
path he indicates for us, is the pre-existence of a gaze--I see only from one
point, but in my existence I am looked at from all sides. (72)
Since I see the world from my own perspective, I repress the way I am
seen by others. The gaze, then, represents a reversal of my intentionality
and a threat to my ego.55 Just as in a dream, I am shown something to
look at, which is not controlled by my expectations, with the gaze, I am
looked at from the position of the primary processes.
Lacan ties this theory of the gaze to the production of anxiety in the
face of the threat of castration: “The gaze is presented to us only in the
form of a strange contingency, symbolic of what we find on the horizon,
as the thrust of our experience, namely, the lack that constitutes castra-
tion anxiety” (72–73). From this perspective, what causes anxiety is the
reversal of our intentionality since we can no longer control what we are
experiencing.56 The ego therefore has to repress the primary processes
because these representations are not the products of our intentions: In
the dream, the slip of the tongue, and the symptom, we reveal more than
we want to reveal because we have lost control of our own minds.
Furthermore, free association is predicated on this notion that we need to
4 Moving from Freud’s Five Principles to Lacan’s Four… 81
learn how to speak without intention and control in order to discover the
things we would rather repress.
The theory of the ego is thus equivalent to the concept of repression,
and this equivalence motivates Lacan to posit that the ego is a primarily
a defensive structure, and so it makes no sense to base therapy on trying
to strengthen this agency.57 Once again, we see here how theory matches
practice since the possibility of free association is predicated on the cri-
tique of ego psychology and the Western philosophical tradition.58 In
turn, the concept of the gaze relates to how our visual and virtual relation
to the world and ourselves is always predicated on the repression of the
gaze as a representation of the primary processes: “In our relation to
things, in so far as this relation is constituted by the way of vision, and
ordered in the figures of representation, something slips, passes, is trans-
mitted, from stage to stage, and is always to some degree eluded in it-
-that is what we call the gaze” (73). The gaze presents here the reversal of
our usual form of intentional awareness, and due to its threatening
nature, it must always be repressed by the controlling ego.
The cause of repression is thus centered on the ego’s need to anticipate
what enters consciousness, and this means that the primary processes
have to be repressed because they function beyond the ego’s control.
Lacan’s introduction of the gaze as a primary form of what he calls the
object (a) is shown here to be guided by the need to explain the relation
between repression and the primary processes:
the illusion of ego control, and this loss of control is what causes anxiety.
For instance, many patients do not want to lie on a coach and free associ-
ate because they are afraid of losing control of their own minds. In fact,
one reason why it is not a good practice to have psychotic patients lie
down and just talk is that they might regress to a pure expression of the
primary processes.
In this opposition between the gaze and our usual state of conscious-
ness, we find a central cause for Lacan’s theory of the imaginary order:
Similarly, in that order, which is particularly satisfying for the subject, con-
noted in psycho-analytic experience by the term narcissism-in which I have
striven to reintroduce the essential structure it derives from its reference to
the specular image--in the satisfaction, not to say self-satisfaction, that dif-
fuses from it, which gives the subject a pretext for such a profound mecon-
naissance--and does its empire not extend as far as this reference of the
philosophical tradition represented by plenitude encountered by the sub-
ject in the mode of contemplation--can we not also grasp that which has
been eluded, namely, the function of the gaze? (74)
Although Freud introduces his theory of how the ego is formed by devel-
oping his concept of narcissism, he never fully explores the role played by
the mapping of space in the production of the ideal ego.60 What Lacan
does by turning to the field of philosophy is to show the limits of the
intentionality of consciousness. Instead of privileging the contemplative
ego of visual and cognitive control, Lacan sees the ego as based on a set of
misrecognitions that can be reversed by the presence of the gaze.
As stated above, the concept of the gaze helps us to comprehend the
conflict between the primary processes and the desire for ego control:
“What does this mean, if not that, in the so-called waking state, there is
an elision of the gaze, and an elision of the fact that not only does it look,
it also shows. In the field of the dream, on the other hand, what charac-
terizes the images is that it shows” (74). One has to only think about the
experience of dreaming to realize that on the level of the primary pro-
cesses, we are not in control of what we are perceiving or thinking. The
gaze is a threat to our narcissism and our drive to see only what we want
to see and to think only what we want to think, and the practice of psy-
choanalysis requires a reversal of this narcissism.61
4 Moving from Freud’s Five Principles to Lacan’s Four… 83
It shows--but here, too, some form of ‘sliding away’ of the subject is appar-
ent. Look up some description of a dream, any one--not only the one I
referred to last time, in which, after all, what I am going to say may remain
enigmatic, but any dream--place it in its co-ordinates, and you will see that
this it shows is well to the fore. So much is it to the fore, with the charac-
teristics in which it is co-ordinated-namely, the absence of horizon, the
enclosure, of that which is contemplated in the waking state, and, also, the
character of emergence, of contrast, of stain, of its images, the intensifica-
tion of their colours--that, in the final resort, our position in the dream is
profoundly that of someone who does not see. The subject does not see
where it is leading, he follows. He may even on occasion detach himself,
tell himself that it is a dream, but in no case will he be able to apprehend
himself in the dream in the way in which, in the Cartesian cogito, he
apprehends himself as thought. (75)
Instead of us looking at the dream, we are shown what to see, and this
reversal of intentionality gives us access to unconscious material that has
been transformed by the primary processes. Lacan adds that what
Descartes got wrong in his famous “I think, therefore, I am” is the fact
that in the dream, the ego slips away. In fact, this effacement of the “I” is
similar to the Eastern meditative notion that the self is an illusion.63
In mediation, the dream state, and the hallucination, the primary pro-
cesses think without an ego, as one is forced to see what one may prefer
to repress: “In a dream, he is a butterfly. What does this mean? It means
that he sees the butterfly in his reality as gaze. What are so many figures,
so many shapes, so many colours, if not this gratuitous showing, in which
is marked for us the primal nature of the essence of the gaze” (76). The
dream here presents the reversal of our normal consciousness through the
84 R. Samuels
lack of ego intentionality and the presence of the gaze. From a clinical
perspective, this theory of reversal is so important because it helps to
explain why we need free association to move beyond repression in order
to access unconscious material.
Transference
Following his articulation of the gaze and the reversal of intentionality,
Lacan introduces the concept of transference: “This brings us to the func-
tion of the transference. For this indeterminate of pure being that has no
point of access to determination, this primary position of the uncon-
scious that is articulated as constituted by the indetermination of the
subject--it is to this that the transference gives us access, in an enigmatic
way. It is a Gordian knot that leads us to the following conclusion--the
subject is looking for his certainty” (129). Lacan posits here that since the
subject of the primary processes lacks intentionality and a determinant
status, the patient seeks certainty through transference. In other words,
just as Descartes has to return to the idea of a perfect and all-knowing
god in order to escape from his own feelings of radical doubt, the patient
in analysis idealizes the analyst in order to find a person who knows and
is certain.64
Following Freud, Lacan stresses that in transference, the subject hands
over responsibility over to the Other:
One may go so far as to believe that the opacity of the trauma--as it was
then maintained in its initial function by Freud’s thought, that is to say, in
my terms, its resistance to signification--is then specifically held responsi-
ble for the limits of remembering. And, after all, it is hardly surprising,
given my own theorization, that I should see this as a highly significant
moment in the transfer of powers from the subject to the Other, what I call
the capital Other (le grand Autre), the locus of speech and, potentially, the
locus of truth. (129)
Since the traumatic real resists symbolization, and the gaze of the primary
processes reverses intentional control, the patient in analysis seeks to find
some certainty by seeing the analyst as the One who knows The Truth. In
4 Moving from Freud’s Five Principles to Lacan’s Four… 85
fact, Freud argued that when a patient suddenly stopped free associating,
he was sure that the subject was thinking about the presence of the
analyst.65
Lacan insists that we should see the transference as a necessary obstacle
to free association and the discovery of unconscious material: “The trans-
ference is the means by which the communication of the unconscious is
interrupted, by which the unconscious closes up again. Far from being
the handing over of powers to the unconscious, the transference is, on the
contrary, its closing up” (130). Repressed material and the formations of
the primary processes are thus avoided through the transference, but this
avoidance has to be worked through.66 However, what Lacan finds in
many forms of therapy and analysis is a reinforcing of the transference,
which is caused by a misunderstanding of its essential structure:
argues that the first generation of analysts leaving Europe to set up shop
in America wanted their patients to follow the same path of assimilating
to American culture that they had to follow.71 From this perspective, if
the analyst feeds the transference relationship, the patient will be pushed
to conform to the social ideals of the analyst.
One of Lacan’s important moves is to tie the idealizing transference to
the narcissistic relationship between the ideal ego and the ego ideal: “it is
in the Other that the subject is constituted as ideal, that he has to regulate
the completion of what comes as ego, or ideal ego--which is not the ego
ideal--that is to say, to constitute himself in his imaginary reality” (144).
The idealization of the analyst is thus driven by a desire to idealize the self
since the ego ideal is the place in the Other that subject sees himself as
loveable.72 For instance, in his theory of the mirror stage, Lacan pointed
out how after a child becomes happy by seeing its own completed image
in the mirror, it turns to the caregiver to get a look of approval.73 The
Other, as caregiver, stands here for the social order of cultural ideals, and
so what the subject is looking for is not only the verification of the ideal
ego but also a recognition of his or her conformity to cultural ideals.74
Lacan adds that the ego ideal is the place from which the subject looks
at himself and is also the place from which he speaks: “it is in the space of
the Other that he sees himself and the point from which he looks at him-
self is also in that space. Now, this is also the point from which he
speaks … “(144). Lacan posits that that we see ourselves from the posi-
tion of cultural ideals internalized in the form of the ego ideal; moreover,
our speech is also derived from this idealized cultural Other. This theory
of transference can be considered to be a restating of Freud’s argument
from his Project, where he affirms that the parent’s response to the help-
less child’s cry represents the origins of human communication and
morality.
In this structure, transference presents the fundamental way that we
become social subjects, and it is precisely this mode of alienating confor-
mity that has to be exposed through analysis: “the transference is not the
enactment (mise en acte) of the illusion that seems to drive us to this
alienating identification that any conformity constitutes, even when it is
with an ideal model, of which the analyst, in any case, cannot be the
support--the transference is the enactment of the reality of the
88 R. Samuels
One of the essential ideas behind this description of sexuality is the dia-
lectical relationship between biology and culture.75 Instead of simply
denying the importance of nature or rejecting social mediation, Lacan
centers his theory of sexuality on the combination of nature and cul-
ture.76 In other words, societies use biological sexual differences in order
to structure social relationships through a system of oppositions con-
tained in a combinatory system.77 The signifier plays an important role
because it allows for the translation of natural distinctions into cultural
4 Moving from Freud’s Five Principles to Lacan’s Four… 89
For what Freud intends to make present in the function of this libido is not
some archaic relation, some primitive mode of access of thoughts, some
world that is there like some shade of an ancient world surviving in ours.
The libido is the effective presence, as such, of desire. It is what now remains
to indicate desire--which is not substance, but which is there at the level of
the primary process, and which governs the very mode of our approach. (153)
I maintain that it is at the level of analysis--if we can take a few more steps
forward--that the nodal point by which the pulsation of the unconscious is
linked to sexual reality must be revealed. This nodal point is called desire,
and the theoretical elaboration that I have pursued in recent years will
show you, through each stage of clinical experience, how desire is situated
90 R. Samuels
What Lacan is describing here is that on the most basic level, when the
child asks the caregiver for help, the child is driven by an unconscious
desire for love, knowledge, and recognition, and this desire brings the
reality of unconscious desire into the transference: “it means that in the
transference we must see established the weight of sexual reality. Largely
unknown and, up to a point, masked, it runs beneath what happens at
the level of the analytic discourse, which is well and truly, as it takes form,
that of demand--it is not for nothing that all experience leads us to throw
it on to the side of the terms frustration and gratification” (155). Here we
see how Lacan’s theories have direct implications for the practice of psy-
choanalysis: the reason why the analyst does not satisfy the demands of
the patient is that these demands cannot be fully satiated because they are
supported by an underlying impossible desire for complete love, knowl-
edge, and recognition.81 By not fulfilling the demands of the patient, the
analyst is able to allow these desires to surface for the first time.
It is clear that those with whom we deal, the patients, are not satisfied, as
one says, with what they are. And yet, we know that everything they are,
everything they experience, even their symptoms, involves satisfaction.
They satisfy something that no doubt runs counter to that with which they
might be satisfied, or rather, perhaps, they give satisfaction to something.
They are not content with their state, but all the same, being in a state that
gives so little content, they are content. The whole question boils down to
the following--what is contented here? (166)
One reason why our drives are always partial and limited is that their
fundamental aim is defined by auto-erotism: “If the drive may be satisfied
without attaining what, from the point of view of a biological totalization
of function, would be the satisfaction of its end of reproduction, it is
because it is a partial drive, and its aim is simply this return into cir-
cuit … This theory is present in Freud. He tells us somewhere that the
ideal model for auto-eroticism would be a single mouth kissing itself …
(179). In basing the sex drive on self-satisfaction, Freud reveals the self-
reflexive feedback loop inherent to our drives, which represents a break
with biology and evolution.86
The compulsive circuit of auto-erotism is coupled with the fact that
any object can become a cause of human desire, and yet we become fix-
ated on particular objects.87 Lacan adds that the only thing that pushes us
to move from an oral object to an anal or phallic object is the interven-
tion of an outside social force: “The passage from the oral drive to the
anal drive can be produced not by a process of maturation, but by the
intervention of something that does not belong to the field of the drive-
-by the intervention, the overthrow, of the demand of the Other” (180).
What Lacan is showing here is how human sexuality is so different from
other animals since the object of our desire is arbitrary and the cause of
our development is social. The fundamental concept of the drive there-
fore represents a major challenge for neuroscience, pharmacology, and
evolutionary psychology since human behavior is shown to be motivated
by impulses and demands going against the laws of nature and
evolution.88
From Lacan’s perspective, unlike instincts, drives break with the evolu-
tionary goals of reproduction and self-preservation: “The dialectic of the
drive is profoundly different both from that which belongs to the order
of love and from that which belongs to the well-being of the subject”
(206). In contrast to both narcissistic love and the pursuit of individual
survival, drives represent a compulsive demand for an impossible satisfac-
tion. We see this structure most clearly with addictions where the pursuit
of pleasure can result in self-destruction.89
From a clinical perspective, it is important to understand how Freud’s
diagnostic category of perversion has been mostly replaced by the border-
line personality disorder.90 One reason for this substitution is that the
4 Moving from Freud’s Five Principles to Lacan’s Four… 93
It would be odd all the same if this subject who is supposed to know, sup-
posed to know something about you, and who, in fact, knows nothing,
should be regarded as liquidated, at the very moment when, at the end of
the analysis, he begins at last, about you at least, to know something. It is
therefore at the moment what he takes on most substance, that the subject
who is supposed to know ought to be supposed to have been vaporized. It
can only be a question, then, if the term liquidation has any meaning, of
the permanent liquidation of that deception by which the transference
tends to be exercised in the direction of the closing up of the unconscious.
I have already explained to you how it works, by referring to it the narcis-
sistic relation by which the subject becomes an object worthy of love. From
his reference to him who must love, him, he tries to induce the Other into
a mirage relation in which he convinces him of being worthy of love. (267)
94 R. Samuels
adding that the objet a may be identical with the gaze. Well, Freud pre-
cisely indicates the nodal point of hypnosis when he formulates that the
object is certainly an element that is difficult to grasp in it, but an
incontestable one, namely, the gaze of the hypnotizer. Remember what I
articulated for you about the function of the gaze, of its fundamental rela-
tions to the ink-blot, of the fact that there is already in the world some-
96 R. Samuels
thing that looks before there is a view for it to see, that the ocellus of animal
mimicry is indispensible as a presupposition to the fact that a subject may
see and be fascinated, that the fascination of the ink-blot is anterior to the
view that discovers it. (272–273)
Notes
1. Lacan, Jacques, Jacques-Alain Miller, and Alan Sheridan. The four fun-
damental concepts of psycho-analysis. Routledge, 2018.
2. Julien, Philippe. Jacques Lacan’s Return to Freud: The real, the symbolic,
and the imaginary. Vol. 2. NYU press, 1995.
3. Fink, Bruce. The Lacanian subject: Between language and jouissance.
Princeton University Press, 1997.
4. Leader, Darian. “Lacan’s myths.” The Cambridge Companion to Lacan
(2003): 35–49.
5. Thom, Martin. “The unconscious structured as a language.” The talking
cure. Palgrave Macmillan, London, 1981. 1–44.
6. Verhaeghe, Paul. “Causation and destitution of a pre-ontological non-
entity: On the Lacanian subject.” Key concepts of Lacanian psychoanaly-
sis. Routledge, 2018. 164–189.
7. Lvi-Strauss, Claude. The savage mind. University of Chicago Press, 1966.
8. DiCenso, James J. “Totem and Taboo and the constitutive function of
symbolic forms.” Journal of the American Academy of Religion 64.3
(1996): 557–574.
9. Papapetros, Spyros. “Movements of the soul: traversing animism,
fetishism, and the uncanny.” Discourse 34.2–3 (2012): 185–208.
10. Lacan, Jacques, Alan Sheridan, and Malcolm Bowie. “On a question
preliminary to any possible treatment of psychosis.” Ecrits. Routledge,
2020. 198–249.
11. Grigg, Russell. “From the mechanism of psychosis to the universal con-
dition of the symptom: on foreclosure.” Key concepts of Lacanian psycho-
analysis. Routledge, 2018. 48–74.
12. Freud, Sigmund. Psycho-analytic notes on an autobiographical account of
a case of paranoia (dementia paranoides). Read Books Ltd, 2014.
13. Lacan, Jacques, Jacques-Alain Ed Miller, and Russell Trans Grigg. “The
seminar of Jacques Lacan, Book 3: The psychoses 1955–1956.”
Translation of the seminar that Lacan delivered to the Société Française de
Psychoanalyse over the course of the academic year 1955–1956. WW
Norton & Company, 1993.
14. Freud, Sigmund. Totem And Taboo: Some Points of Agreement between
the Mental Lives of Savages and. Routledge, 2013.
98 R. Samuels
31. Rajchman, John. Truth and Eros: Foucault, Lacan and the question of
ethics. Routledge, 2013.
32. Samuels, Robert. “Science and the reality principle.” Freud for the
twenty-first century. Palgrave Pivot, Cham, 2019. 5–16.
33. Botting, Fred. “Relations of the Real in Lacan, Bataille and Blanchot.”
SubStance 23.1 (1994): 24–40.
34. Zupancic, Alenka. Ethics of the real: Kant and Lacan. Verso Trade, 2011.
35. Kran, Anne. “Comparing causality in Freudian reasoning and critical
realism.” Journal of Critical Realism 9.1 (2010): 5–32.
36. Bistoen, Gregory, Stijn Vanheule, and Stef Craps. “Nachträglichkeit: A
Freudian perspective on delayed traumatic reactions.” Theory &
Psychology 24.5 (2014): 668–687.
37. Cardoso, Mauricio José d’Escragnolle, and Rosane Zétola Lustoza.
“From Freudian representation to Lacanian signifying: the pertinence
of structural interpretation of the unconscious.” Psicologia: Teoria e
Pesquisa 28.2 (2012): 219–226.
38. Plotnitsky, Arkady. “On Lacan and mathematics.” Œuvres & Critiques
34.2 (2009): 143–162.
39. Freud, Sigmund. “Repression.” The Standard Edition of the Complete
Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, Volume XIV (1914-1916): On the
History of the Psycho-Analytic Movement, Papers on Metapsychology and
Other Works. 1957. 141–158.
40. Shepherdson, Charles. Lacan and the Limits of Language. Fordham
University Press, 2009.
41. Freud, Sigmund. Totem And Taboo: Some Points of Agreement between
the Mental Lives of Savages and. Routledge, 2013.
42. Stavrakakis, Yannis. Jacques Lacan. No. IKEEBOOKCH-2020-408.
Aristotle University of Thessaloniki, 2017.
43. Gutiérrez-Peláez, Miguel. “Ferenczi’s anticipation of the traumatic
dimension of language: A meeting with Lacan.” Contemporary
Psychoanalysis 51.1 (2015): 137–154.
44. Gutiérrez-Peláez, Miguel. “Ferenczi’s anticipation of the traumatic
dimension of language: A meeting with Lacan.” Contemporary
Psychoanalysis 51.1 (2015): 137–154.
45. Kesner, Ladislav. “Wandering or unhappy mind?.” American Journal of
Psychiatry 171.9 (2014): 929–930.
46. Bowie, Malcolm. Lacan. Harvard University Press, 1993.
100 R. Samuels
47. Muller, John, P. “Ego and subject in Lacan.” Psychoanalytic review 69.2
(1982): 234–240.
48. McIntosh, Donald. “The ego and the self in the thought of Sigmund
Freud.” International journal of psycho-analysis 67 (1986): 429–448.
49. Rosa, Carmelo Licitra, et al. “From the Imaginary to Theory of the
Gaze in Lacan.” Frontiers in Psychology 12 (2021).
50. Lacan, Jacques. “The mirror stage as formative of the function of the I
as revealed in psychoanalytic experience.” Écrits: a selection (2001):
146–178.
51. Bernet, Rudolf. “The Phenomenon of the Gaze in Merleau-Ponty and
Lacan.” Chiasmi International 1 (1999): 105–118.
52. Barnes, Jenny. “Phenomenological intentionality meets an ego-less
state.” Indo-Pacific Journal of Phenomenology 3.1 (2003): 1–17.
53. Brennan, Teresa, and Martin Jay. Vision in context: historical and con-
temporary perspectives on sight. Routledge, 2013.
54. Lacan, Jacques. The Ego in Freud’s Theory and in the Technique of
Psychoanalysis, 1954-1955. Vol. 2. WW Norton & Company, 1991.
55. Samuels, Robert. “Vertigo: Sexual disorientation and the engendering
of the real.” Gender and Psychoanalysis 5.1 (2000): 81–97.
56. Krips, Henry. “The politics of the gaze: Foucault, Lacan and Žižek.”
Culture Unbound 2.1 (2010): 91–102.
57. Malin, Barnet D. “Kohut and Lacan: mirror opposites.” Psychoanalytic
Inquiry 31.1 (2011): 58–74.
58. Smith, Joseph H. Arguing with Lacan: Ego psychology and language. Yale
University Press, 1991.
59. McGowan, Todd. “Looking for the gaze: Lacanian film theory and its
vicissitudes.” Cinema Journal (2003): 27–47.
60. Samuels, Robert. Between philosophy and psychoanalysis: Lacan’s recon-
struction of Freud. Routledge, 2014.
61. Bonomi, Carlo. “Narcissism as mastered visibility: The evil eye and the
attack of the disembodied gaze.” International Forum of Psychoanalysis.
Vol. 19. No. 2. Taylor & Francis Group, 2010.
62. McGowan, Todd. The real gaze: Film theory after Lacan. SUNY
Press, 2012.
63. Purser, Ronald E. “A Buddhist–Lacanian perspective on lack.” The
Humanistic Psychologist 39.4 (2011): 289.
64. Feldstein, Richard, Bruce Fink, and Maire Jaanus, eds. Reading Seminar
XI: Lacan’s Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis: The Paris
Seminars in English. SUNY Press, 1995.
4 Moving from Freud’s Five Principles to Lacan’s Four… 101
© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2022 105
R. Samuels, (Mis)Understanding Freud with Lacan, Zizek, and Neuroscience, The
Palgrave Lacan Series, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-13327-5_5
106 R. Samuels
follow the fundamental rule, which is free association. Moreover, the ana-
lyst is responsible for suspending judgment so that the patient can also do
the same.7 This is clearly not an everyday relationship, and that is why it
is so important to understand the theory supporting the practice of
psychoanalysis.
Although it is sometimes necessary to deviate from strict analytic neu-
trality, it is vital to realize how the analytic process can be easily subverted
when the analyst refuses to play the required role.8 In fact, Wilson appears
to disregard these foundations of analytic practice in the following pas-
sage: “Over the years I have had occasion to drive patients from my office
to doctors’ offices and emergency rooms. I have made phone calls on
their behalf that they could not. I have had them bring their computers
to the office to do work that had otherwise been languishing for months
or longer. And I have been known to prepare a cup of tea or two” (18).
Instead of performing the optimal frustration of the patient’s drives,
Wilson wants to be experienced as a caring host and helper.9 The major
problem with this approach is that not only does one feed the demands
of the patient, but once one steps away from the position of being an
empty mirror, it is difficult to return to being a blank screen. Since the
analyst wants the content of the transference to come from the patient’s
imagination, any disclosures by the analyst taints the process.10
To be clear, as we shall see, the analyst cannot remain completely silent
or passive, but the interventions have to be directed towards the goal of
free association and the neutralizing of the artificial transference relation-
ship. The trick is how to interpret without being the subject who is sup-
posed to know or the moral authority.11 Unfortunately, the difficulty of
maintaining this analytic position has been increased because theorists
like Wilson want to base their practice of therapy on the model of being
a good mother: “All of these aspects of practice fall under the umbrella of
the matricial. Matricial space is the phrase that to me best captures the
background conditions that facilitate—that hold, flexibly, steadily—the
ongoing conversational engagement that is psychoanalysis” (18). In this
focus on the analyst taking on the attributes of a good mother, Wilson
and others seek to envision analytic treatment as a form of reparative
parenting.12 As Lacan insists, one of the problems with this model is that
it only serves to feed the narcissistic demand for love, understanding, and
108 R. Samuels
recognition.13 Since the ideal ego wants to be recognized by the ego ideal
while repressing the super-ego, the re-enactment of the good mother rela-
tionship functions to strengthen the ego’s defenses.14 In Oedipal terms,
this form of therapy seeks to symbolically kill off the father in order to
maintain the love of the mother. However, what Wilson and others do
not realize is that in order for analysis to progress, the narcissistic transfer-
ence has to be revealed and called into question.15
In a very telling passage, Wilson traces his analytic position to a theory
of maternal care that appears to function to extend the Oedipus complex:
The phrase matricial space, and the theorization of it, comes from Viviane
Chetrit-Vatine. Her book, The Ethical Seduction of the Analytic Situation
(2014), is an extended investigation into the strangeness and risk that
inhere in any meaningful encounter with the other. The foundational
encounter with the other is the mother/caretaker in relation to her/his/
their child; the psychoanalytic encounter evokes and re-figures this original
relational moment. (33–34)
For the patient, the physicianly analyst is a powerful activator of the trans-
ference neurosis and the working alliance. The patient’s image of the doctor
stirs up memories, fantasies, and feelings from childhood of an authorita-
tive, arbitrary, incomprehensible, and magical figure who possessed the
power of the omnipotent, omniscient parents. It is the doctor who takes
over when the parents are sick and afraid. It is the doctor who has the right
to explore the naked body, and who has no fear or disgust of blood, mucus,
vomit, urine, or feces. He is the rescuer from pain and panic, the establisher
of order from chaos, provider of emergency functions performed by the
mother in the first years of life. In addition, the physician inflicts pain,
pierces the flesh, and intrudes into every opening in the body. He is remi-
niscent of the mother of bodily intimacy as well as the representative of the
sadomasochistic fantasies involving both parents. (19–20)
110 R. Samuels
This equation of the analyst with the caring doctor goes against Freud’s
idea that medicine wants nothing to do with the unconscious, hysterical
symptoms, or the unconscious.23 In fact, when the patient places the
analyst in the position of the caring physician, the idealizing transference
is not only activated but it becomes reinforced as one chooses the cure of
love over the cure of analysis.24 Wilson simply resists seeing how his the-
ory and practice end up feeding the transference instead of clearing a
space to work through it.
Although it is very tempting and gratifying for the analyst to feel ideal-
ized by the patient, this type of relationship serves to re-enforce the trans-
ference in an imaginary manner.25 As Lacan has pointed out, when the
patient idealizes the analyst, the patient places the Other in the position
of the ego ideal, which then is manipulated to recognize and verify the
patient’s self-idealization.26 Like someone who is addicted to placing pic-
tures of themselves on the Web so others can “like” their image, the desire
to be recognized by an idealized spectator feeds the unconscious demand
for control and satisfaction.27 Instead of recognizing the pathological
nature of idealization in analysis, Wilson expresses how good it feels to be
admired by his patient: “Relationally, Paul feels relieved that I showed I
had survived his attacks, and did it in a way that reached him, and also in
a way that he could admire” (24). In this representation of the dual rela-
tion between the analyst and the patient, the patient admires the analyst
who is able to tolerate aggression; however, we have to ask if this concep-
tion of analysis enables free association and the discovery of unconscious
content.28 From Lacan’s perspective, it is a mistake to see the analytic
relation in a dualistic manner because this type of structure locks both
subjects into an imaginary world of envy, rivalry, identification, and
idealization.29
To break out from this imaginary dualism, the analyst has to refrain
from feeding the transference by remaining neutral and impersonal.
Clearly, this type of position goes against our natural tendency to care for
the other and make immediate problems go away, and yet, the only way
for someone to discover something new is if they stop acting in a natural
or intuitive manner. The power of psychoanalysis, then, is that is offers a
new type of relationship that is radically different from other forms of
5 The Desire of the Analyst and the American Repression… 111
social interaction, and this means that the patient should always experi-
ence an analytic session as something strange and different.30
One reason for this analytic struggle is that analysts refuse to accept tak-
ing on a position of neutrality, and so they fall into the “normal” way of
relating, knowing, and communicating. As Wilson points out, it is hard
for someone to give up the admiration for being the clever one who can
figure out what others have failed to understand. Furthermore, Wilson is
correct in positing that the narrative form itself pushes analysts to distort
the experience of psychoanalysis: “First, to the extent that the analyst
identifies herself with the hero/detective image she will tend to invest,
and perhaps overly commit to, the explanatory narrative that is being
constructed in the analysis. The second reason has to do with the nature
of narrative itself: narrative explanations tend to create their own demands
for coherence as they get built” (44–45). As a discourse of discovery, psy-
choanalysis does not lend itself to narrative closure or self-satisfied under-
standing. For instance, if the patient is able to speak without censoring or
self-reflection, then the produced discourse will often be fragmented,
incoherent, and de-idealized.38
Wilson himself does recognize that our desire for understanding and
narrative order can serve to undermine the very discourse the analyst is
trying to represent:
direct to tell patients about their defenses, this type of intervention only
serves to heighten the transference and strengthen the resistances of
the ego.42
A frustrating aspect of Wilson’s book is that at times he does seem to
understand the need for analytic neutrality, but at other times, he argues
against it. For example, in the following passage, we see how the desire of
the analyst can result in establishing a dual relationship of opposition
between the patient’s ego and the analyst’s ego: “Here is Friedman again,
in another part of his discussion, more forceful and direct: ‘There’s a
demand for work here … a bending of purpose, a conflict of wills, a ver-
dict of satisfactoriness. The analyst is not just a facilitator; he is a taskmas-
ter and judge’ (1993, 13). Yes, a demand, a conflict, a verdict. That
captures things better. Resistance has no meaning unless there is a force
pushing against it” (52–53). In seeing the analyst as a judge and taskmas-
ter, the neutrality of the position is eliminated as one takes on the role of
super-ego or ego-ideal.43 This type of analytic relationship can only func-
tion to increase the resistances of the ego and reinforce the transference,
and so it is necessary to couple analytic training with a theory devised to
protect against faulty analytic interventions.
In linking bias to the resistances of the narcissistic ego, Wilson reveals the
limits of his own discourse. As much as he would like to maintain the
position of analytic neutrality, he cannot help interpreting his patents’
resistances and substantiating the desire of the analyst.
theoretical persuasion and particular reasons goes against the need for the
analyst to suspend judgment and eliminate all bias. Instead of seeing the
practice of psychoanalysis as shaped by different competing theories, I
have stressed the need to return to Freud’s fundamental concepts as a way
of protecting against misunderstanding the role of the analyst.
Of course, in the age of postmodern relativism, it may appear absurd
to insist that there is a single way to understand Freud and psychoanaly-
sis; however, it is vital to insist on the validity of his initial insights in
relation to the development of his technique.48 In fact, I have been argu-
ing that five key concepts structure the field itself, and any misunder-
standing of these notions results in deviations in the practice of analysis.
Yet, many therapists and analysts will resist this argument because they
simply do not understand these foundational principles and the process
of analysis itself. It is also difficult to critique the analyst as the one who
knows and then present a theory and practice with a strict set of defini-
tions. Just as the Enlightenment seeks to promote a bias against bias, the
privileging of neutrality is itself a value that has to be defended through
the use of non-neutral concepts.49
Returning to Wilson’s discussion of the analyst, we see how psychoana-
lytic theory and practice has been shaped by a continuous resistance to
analytic neutrality:
to satisfy his or her own desire when working with patients: “The analyst
is always, in part, looking for lost objects, trying to refind herself in the
patient and to see herself as an analyst in day-to-day clinical work. The
crucial question is how these desires facilitate or hinder a successful ana-
lytic process” (61). This notion that the analyst is looking for his or her
own lost past objects represents a major deviation from analytic practice
and theory since the neutrality of the analyst requires a suspension of this
self-interest as one takes on the position of being an impersonal, empty
mirror.61 We can, thus consider counter-transference as anything that
prevents the analyst from taking on this position.
As Wilson appears to understand, when the analyst pursues personal
interests, values, and desires, the patient will react with resistances:
What Wilson reveals in this passage is the notion that when an analyst
tries to intervene directly in a patient’s psychopathology, even the most
well-intentioned interpretations can be experienced as direct attacks on
the subject.69 Lacan’s solution to this problem was to claim that the inter-
pretations should always be ambiguous so that they avoid being seen as
judgments or criticisms.70 Of course, this is easier said than done, but the
key is for the analyst to give up the position of being the one who knows
what is the truth or what is morally right. Often, the best way to inter-
vene is to simply ask an open question predicated on the desire to pro-
duce more unknown unconscious material.71
At times, Wilson does show an awareness of the need to interpret from
a position of non-knowledge:
So I pulled back, and not in a “lick my wounds” kind of way. I quite con-
sciously decided not to interpret the defensive aspects of Robert’s pseudo-
nonchalance or his complaints of despair. I simply asked him to tell me
more about these feelings. I let him know through a variety of questions
and an openness in my tone and quality of my presence that I wanted to
hear more, not less. Over the next several weeks, seemingly in direct
response to this shift in my subjectivity—a shift, that is, in the objects of
my analytic desire—Robert gave more full-throated expression to his
124 R. Samuels
In my estimation, there was no other way out of this infinite regress than
for me to stop contributing to it. As I removed myself from the field of
contest, Robert felt much freer to think about himself. This showed in his
ability, perhaps for the first time in our working together, to analyze him-
self. As he talked about the details of how bad he felt at times, he began to
notice he was feeling better. He became more curious about his own
thoughts and spoke more freely. He felt more “in control” and less over-
whelmed. In short, instead of his feeling that I was implicitly telling him
what to do and how to be—forms of ignoring him, as he felt his parents
had done repeatedly— he now felt that I did, really and in fact, want to
listen to how he was feeling. (70–71)
We see here why Lacan argued that every analytic treatment is a training
analysis since what the patient has to learn is how to analyze himself or
herself by taking on the position of non-judgmental neutrality.72 We also
grasp the reason why analysts have to undergo their own analysis so that
they can learn the value of suspending judgment through their own per-
sonal experience.
Notes
1. Wilson, Mitchell. The Analyst’s Desire: The Ethical Foundation of Clinical
Practice. Bloomsbury Publishing USA, 2020.
2. Thompson, M. Guy. The ethic of honesty: The fundamental rule of psycho-
analysis. Vol. 2. Rodopi, 2004.
3. Thompson, M, Guy. “The rule of neutrality.” Psychoanalysis and
Contemporary Thought 19.1 (1996): 57–84.
5 The Desire of the Analyst and the American Repression… 125
52. Samuels, Robert. “Science and the reality principle.” Freud for the twenty-
first century. Palgrave Pivot, Cham, 2019. 5–16.
53. Freud, Sigmund. “Negation.” Organization and pathology of thought:
Selected sources. Columbia University Press, 1951. 338–348.
54. Kerrigan, William. “Psychoanalysis and the Vicissitudes of
Enlightenment.” American Imago 48.2 (1991): 265–278.
55. Lacan, Jacques. “Some reflections on the ego.” International Journal of
Psycho-Analysis 34 (1953): 11–17.
56. Boothby, Richard. Freud as philosopher: Metapsychology after Lacan.
Routledge, 2015.
57. Hole, Richard W., Augustus J. Rush, and Aaron T. Beck. “A cognitive
investigation of schizophrenic delusions.” Psychiatry42.4 (1979):
312–319.
58. Samuels, Robert. “Damasio’s Error: The Politics of Biological
Determinism After Freud.” Psychoanalyzing the Politics of the New Brain
Sciences. Palgrave Pivot, Cham, 2017. 9–33.
59. Poeldinger, W. J. “The psychopathology and psychodynamics of self-
destruction.” Crisis: The Journal of Crisis Intervention and Suicide
Prevention (1989).
60. Palomera, Vicente. “Modalities of the Transference.” Analysis5
(1994): 17–26.
61. Reed, Gail S. “An empty mirror: reflections on nonrepresentation.” The
Psychoanalytic Quarterly 78.1 (2009): 1–26.
62. Van Pelt, Tamise. “Otherness.” Postmodern Culture 10.2 (2000).
63. Lacan, Jacques, Alan Sheridan, and Malcolm Bowie. “The Direction of
the Treatment and the Principles of its Power 1.” Écrits. Routledge, 2020.
250–310.
64. Nobus, Dany. Jacques Lacan and the Freudian practice of psychoanalysis.
Routledge, 2013.
65. Miller, Jacques-Alain, ed. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan: Book 1: Freud’s
Papers on Technique 1953-1954. CUP Archive, 1988.
66. Vanier, Alain. Lacan. Other Press, LLC, 2020.
67. Samuels, Robert. Between philosophy and psychoanalysis: Lacan’s recon-
struction of Freud. Routledge, 2014.
68. Freud, Sigmund. “Analysis Terminable and Interminable.” The
International Journal of Psycho-Analysis 18 (1937): 373.
69. Siebers, Tobin. “7. The Ethical Unconscious: From Freud to Lacan.” The
Ethics of Criticism. Cornell University Press, 2018. 159–185.
5 The Desire of the Analyst and the American Repression… 129
This chapter argues that the work of Slavoj Zizek has been one of the
major causes for the contemporary misunderstanding of psychoanalysis.
Through a close reading of his first major book, The Sublime Object of
Ideology, I will explore how he distorts the meaning of the unconscious,
primary processes, the pleasure principle, the reality principle, and trans-
ference.1 I will also examine the possibility of using psychoanalytic treat-
ment on a social and cultural level. The key question here is how do we
work through the fundamental fantasies shaping our relationship
to others?
© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2022 131
R. Samuels, (Mis)Understanding Freud with Lacan, Zizek, and Neuroscience, The
Palgrave Lacan Series, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-13327-5_6
132 R. Samuels
The famous Lacanian motto not to give way on one’s desire (ne pas cider
sur son desir) - is aimed at the fact that we must not obliterate the distance
separating the Real from its symbolization: it is this surplus of the Real over
every symbolization that functions as the object-cause of desire. To come to
terms with this surplus (or, more. precisely, leftover) means to acknowledge
a fundamental deadlock (‘antagonism’), a kernel resisting symbolic
integration-dissolution. (xxv)
On the hand, Zizek recognizes here the opposition between the social
symbolic and the real, but then on the other hand, he quickly privileges
6 Zizek and the Empty Unconscious 133
Let us take the Freudian notion of the ‘death drive’. of course, we have to
abstract Freud’s biologism: ‘death drive’ is not a biological fact but a notion
indicating that the human psychic apparatus is subordinated to a blind
automatism of repetition beyond pleasure-seeking, self-preservation, accor-
dance between man and his milieu. Man is - Hegel dixit- ‘an animal sick
unto death’, an animal extorted by an insatiable parasite (reason, logos,
language). In this perspective, the ‘death drive’, this dimension of radical
negativity, cannot be reduced to an expression of alienated social condi-
tions, it defines la condition humaine as such: there is no solution, no
escape from it. (xxvii)
6 Zizek and the Empty Unconscious 135
Defining Culture
Not only are we internally divided by our self-destructive urges, but we
are alienated by the social order, which requires us to sacrifice our indi-
vidual impulses.30 Zizek posits that one way that these conflicts are over-
come on an imaginary level is through cultural formations:
Zizek’s important insight here that cultures are often shaped by a utopian
idea to eliminate fundamental conflicts leaves open the question of which
conflict is fundamental. He appears to be arguing that we turn to culture
in order to resolve the tension caused by the death drive and the pleasure
principle. However, Freud’s idea is that we first turn to imagination in the
form of hallucinations in order to satisfy our unmet needs, and then
when this does not work, we turn to others to help us to satisfy our
needs.31 In fact, Freud bases his theory of transference and the social link
on this primary demand for caregivers to satisfy the subject’s pleasure
principle. As he argues in his Project for a Scientific Psychology, morality
and communication have their roots in a primary relation where the
helpless infant cries, and the parents recognize and understand this cry as
a demand for a certain satisfaction. The cry is then turned into a demand
through the recognition of the social Other.32 From this moment on,
when the subject asks for something, there is an underlying desire for the
Other’s love, knowledge, and recognition. Culture then can be under-
stood as the way a society mystifies these relationships by combining the
primary processes of imaginary satisfaction with the requirements of the
social order. Ideological fantasies should therefore be seen as hiding the
fundamental conflict between society and the individual through a solu-
tion that occurs purely on the level of thought.33
We can understand the role of culture as an ideological fantasy by
examining Zizek’s own discourse. In focusing on the death drive, enjoy-
ment, and the inexistence of the social Other, he resolves the conflict
between the social and the individual by indirectly privileging the liber-
tarian subject of freedom and compulsive pleasure.34 While I do not
think that Zizek would approve of this interpretation, this repressed ideo-
logical fantasy continues to return throughout his work. Moreover, one
reason for this symptomatic repetition is that he conflates the five levels
of conflict shaping psychoanalysis and human subjectivity: (1) the con-
flict between stimulation and release (the pleasure principle); (2) the con-
flict between reality and imaginative thought (the primary processes); (3)
the conflict between society and the individual (transference); (4) the
conflict between the ego and the super-ego (the unconscious); and (5) the
conflict between the Symbolic and the Real (the reality principle). We
should therefore think of the misunderstanding of psychoanalysis as gen-
erated from the refusal to accept these foundational antinomies.
6 Zizek and the Empty Unconscious 137
According to Lacan, it was none other than Karl Marx who invented the
notion of symptom. Is this Lacanian thesis just a sally of wit, a vague anal-
ogy, or does it possess a pertinent theoretical foundation? If Marx really
articulated the notion of the symptom as it is also at work in the Freudian
field, then we must ask ourselves the Kantian question, concerning the
epistemological ‘conditions of possibility’ of such an encounter: how was it
possible for Marx, in his analysis of the world of commodities, to produce
a notion which applies also to the analysis of dreams, hysterical phenom-
ena, and so on? (3)
In this privileging of form over content, Zizek makes the important move
of eliminating both social and subjective material from the consideration
of capitalism and subjectivity.38 Thus, instead of looking at the content of
a dream or the material derived from free association, Zizek’s formalism
removes signification and individual experience from psychoanalysis and
Marxism. This emptying out of content to focus on form is odd for some-
one who is known for his insightful political and cultural
interpretations.39
One possible explanation for Zizek’s formalism is his understanding of
the key psychoanalytic concept of the unconscious:
It is also necessary to point out that the formal aspects of the primary
processes—substitution, displacement, association, and projection—do
reshape unconscious thoughts, but these thoughts themselves are derived
from the fundamental conflict between the individual and the social.42
Since one represses feelings of guilt and shame, and these feelings are
derived from the internalization of social norms and morality, the internal
conflict between the super-ego and the ideal ego replicates the larger con-
flict between the self and society.43 When one concentrates on the form
and not the content of this conflict, one loses the important distinction
between the unconscious thoughts and the forms of the primary processes.
Zizek’s misunderstanding of the unconscious is apparent in the follow-
ing passage where he rejects some of the core aspects of unconscious
content:
if we seek the ‘secret of the dream’ in the latent content hidden by the
manifest text, we are doomed to disappointment: all we find is some
entirely ‘normal’ – albeit usually unpleasant - thought, the nature of which
is mostly non-sexual and definitely not ‘unconscious’. This ‘normal’,
conscious/preconscious thought is not drawn towards the unconscious,
repressed simply because of its ‘disagreeable’ character for the conscious,
but because it achieves a kind of ‘short circuit’ between it and another
desire which is already repressed, located in the unconscious, a desire which
has nothing whatsoever to do with the latent dream-thought. (5)
Exchange Value
One reason why Zizek may seek to eliminate the content of the uncon-
scious is that he wants to show that behind modern science and democ-
racy, one finds the formal nihilism of capitalist exchange value: “Before
thought could arrive at the idea of a purely quantitative determination, a
sine qua non of the modern science of nature, pure quantity was already
at work in money, that commodity which renders possible the commen-
surability of the value of all other commodities not withstanding their
particular qualitative determination” (11). The theory here is that under-
lying the modern scientific practice of analyzing nature through the use
of abstract symbols and concepts, we find the abstract quantification
caused by the capitalist exchange value.46 Since any object or act of labor
can be represented by a shared symbolic mediation (money), all other
values and meanings are eliminated.47 Thus, when Marx posits that in
modern capitalism, all past feudal values and relations melt away, he was
pointing to the way exchange value replaces every other value.
It is interesting to note that this nihilism of capitalism dovetails with
Zizek’s own method of emptying out the meaning of key psychoanalytic
concepts: by insisting on form over content, Zizek melts away all of the
meaning and value of Freud’s original theories. We see this move to a
universalized nihilism in his combination of Marx and Hegel:
Cynical Behaviorism
The clearest example of Zizek’s formalism can be seen in his focus on
social practices shaped by exchange value:
we know very well that money, like all other material objects, suffers the
effects of use, that its material body changes through time, but in the social
activity of the market we none the less treat coins as if they consist ‘of an
immutable substance, a substance over which time has no power, and
which stands in antithetic contrast to any matter found in nature’ How
tempting to recall here the formula of fetishistic disavowal: ‘I know very
well, but still … ‘. To the current exemplifications of this formula (‘I know
that Mother has not got a phallus, but still … [I believe she has got one]; ‘I
know that Jews are people like us, but still … [there is something in them,)
142 R. Samuels
we must undoubtedly add also the variant of money: ‘I know that money
is a material object like others, but still … [it is as if it were made of a spe-
cial substance over which time has no power)’. (12)
Similar to Lacan’s notion of the sublime love object in Courtly Love, the
idealized cause of desire embodies a symbolic social value, yet this object-
choice is in direct opposition to the object of the drive.54 As Lacan insists,
when lovers describe their beloved in this tradition, it always sounds like
they are describing the same person, and that is because the object is not
6 Zizek and the Empty Unconscious 143
a real person but a symbolic cultural ideal. Moreover, Freud insists that in
the hypnotic love relation, the lover becomes humble and humiliated as
the ego-ideal is followed with blind obedience.55
It is crucial to contrast the masochistic submission to the idealized
object with the object of the exchange value since it is precisely capitalism
that undermines the feudal discourse of idealization.56 From a historical
and psychological perspective, modern capitalism allows the break from
premodern religion, feudalism, and monarchy through the replacement
of traditional values with the meaningless calculation of market value.57
In terms of psychoanalysis, premodern institutions rely on the transfer-
ence of responsibility from the individual to the transcendent idea, leader,
or love object, while in the perverse realm of the drives, the pursuit of
individual pleasure and self-interest is fueled by a debasement of the
object and denial of the social Other.58 Therefore, when Zizek equates
money with the Sadean victim and the sublime object of desire, he is
conflating the foundation of transference with the pleasure principle.
I have been stressing that is vital to separate the key concepts of trans-
ference, the pleasure principle, the primary processes, and the uncon-
scious because without these differences, one loses the specificity of
psychoanalysis itself. The risk of Zizek’s work, then, is that he tends to
empty the meaning out of these concepts so that he can combine together
different discourses in a unified perspective.59 For instance, the following
passage attempts to equate Marxism and psychoanalysis by conflating
economic exchange value with the unconscious and the primary processes:
“The exchange abstraction is not thought, but it has the form of thought.”
Here we have one of the possible definitions of the unconscious: the form
of thought whose ontological status is not that of thought, that is to say,
the form of thought external to the thought itself - in short, some Other
Scene external to the thought whereby the form of the thought is already
articulated in advance. The symbolic order is precisely such a formal order
which supplements and/or disrupts the dual relationship of ‘external’ fac-
tual reality and ‘internal’ subjective experience. (13)
From this perspective, social practices and individual behaviors are effec-
tive precisely because the people engaged in these activities are not aware
of what is going on.69 For Zizek, the issue is not that we repress our
desires, fears, and primary processes into the unconscious; the real issue
is that the capitalist exchange value and its supporting ideology do not
require subjective knowledge.70 Zizek thus presents a psychoanalysis
without content or subjectivity.
I have been arguing that Zizek’s own discourse partakes in cynical dis-
tance since he empties all terms of their original meaning and context by
creating a psychoanalysis without a psychoanalytic practice.73 In fact, we
shall see that his investment in saving an idealized version of Hegel results
in a reversal of Marx’s own reversal of German Idealism.74
6 Zizek and the Empty Unconscious 147
Even Adorno came to this conclusion, starting from the premise that ideol-
ogy is, strictly speaking, only a system which makes a claim to the truth -
that is, which is not simply a lie but a lie experienced as truth, a lie which
pretends to be taken seriously. Totalitarian ideology no longer has this pre-
tension. It is no longer meant, even by its authors, to be taken seriously - its
status is just that of a means of manipulation, purely external and instru-
mental; its rule is secured not by its truth-value but by simple extra ideo-
logical violence and promise of gain. (27)
This notion that things believe in the place of people believing is a great
example of Freud’s theory of animism, which he defines as the projection
of internal mental thoughts onto external reality.84 However, in contem-
porary culture, these projected thoughts are not coupled with the cer-
tainty of the psychotic subject; instead, projected ideas are experienced
from a position of non-belief. Moreover, while in premodern religion and
feudalism, one submits to the powerful and charismatic leader in a mode
of hypnotic blind obedience, with modernity, this submission to the all-
powerful father-figure is broken or driven into the unconscious.85
In the case of contemporary cynical ideology, Zizek posits that one no
longer has to believe in beliefs since they take on a social life of their own:
150 R. Samuels
They no longer believe, but the things themselves believe for them. This
seems also to be a basic Lacanian proposition, contrary to the usual thesis
that a belief is something interior and knowledge something exterior (in
the sense that it can be verified through an external procedure). Rather, it
is belief which is radically exterior, embodied in the practical, effective pro-
cedure of people. It is similar to Tibetan prayer wheels: you write a prayer
on a paper, put the rolled paper into a wheel, and turn it automatically,
without thinking (or, if you want to proceed according to the Hegelian
‘cunning of reason’, you attach it to a windmill, so that it is moved around
by the wind). In this way, the wheel itself is praying for me, instead of me -
or, more precisely, I myself am praying through the medium of the wheel.
The beauty of it all is that in my psychological inferiority I can think about
whatever I want, I can yield to the most dirty and obscene fantasies, and it
does not matter because - to use a good old Stalinist expression - whatever
I am thinking, objectively I am praying. (31–32)
possible.88 From this perspective, the reason why we are outsourcing our
minds to computer technologies and our labor to automation is that we
are finally able to realize the pleasure principle’s law of inertia.89
Not only do we desire not to think or work, but we also seek to rid
ourselves of the burden of feeling and enjoying: “The only correct answer
would be that the other - embodied in the television set - is relieving us
even of our duty to laugh - is laughing instead of us. So even if, tired from
a hard day’s stupid work, all evening we did nothing but gaze drowsily
into the television screen, we can say afterwards that objectively, through
the medium of the other, we had a really good time” (33). In referring to
the laugh track in television comedies, Zizek affirms that we are driven to
hand over responsibility for feeling, thinking, and enjoying to the other.90
As a form of meaningless enjoyment, popular media gives us the oppor-
tunity to displace our internal lives onto an externalized representation.
Of course, without internal thoughts and feelings, there can be no psy-
choanalysis, and here we see how Zizek’s turn to Lacan results in making
psychoanalysis itself impossible.
While the automatic nature of the signifier in the mind relates to the way
the primary processes structure our thoughts and perceptions, it is repres-
sion that determines the unconscious. Also, the social law is internalized
through the super-ego and the ego-ideal through the process of transfer-
ence and the threat of castration, and so it does not make sense to equate
the automatic nature of the signifier with the law’s authority.92
A possible reason for Zizek’s desire to combine the unconscious, the
primary process, and transference together is that he wants to posit that
our submission to the social order is not based on subjectivity: “The only
real obedience, then, is an ‘external’ one: obedience out of conviction is
not real obedience because it is already ‘mediated’ through our subjectiv-
ity—that is, we are not really obeying the authority but simply following
our judgement, which tells us that the authority deserves to be obeyed in
6 Zizek and the Empty Unconscious 153
Notes
1. Žižek, Slavoj. The sublime object of ideology. Verso Books, 2019.
2. Freud, Sigmund. Civilization and its discontents. Broadview Press, 2015.
3. Lacan, Jacques, and Jacques-Alain Miller. The ethics of psychoanalysis
1959-1960: The seminar of Jacques Lacan. Routledge, 2013.
4. Freud, Sigmund. The future of an illusion. Broadview Press, 2012.
5. Althusser, Louis. “Ideology and ideological state apparatuses (notes
towards an investigation).” The anthropology of the state: A reader 9.1
(2006): 86–98.
6. Reinhard, Kenneth. “Lacan and Monotheism: Psychoanalysis and the
Traversal of Cultural Fantasy.” Jouvert: A Journal of Postcolonial Studies
3.1–2 (1999).
7. Shepherdson, Charles. Lacan and the Limits of Language. Fordham
University Press, 2009.
8. Clemens, Justin, et al. Jacques Lacan and the Other Side of Psychoanalysis:
Reflections on Seminar XVII, Sic Vi. Duke University Press, 2006.
9. Lacan, Jacques, Alan Sheridan, and Malcolm Bowie. “The function and
field of speech and language in psychoanalysis.” Écrits. Routledge,
2020. 33–125.
10. Rieff, Philip. Freud: The mind of the moralist. University of Chicago
Press, 1979.
11. Davis, Robert Con. “Pedagogy, Lacan, and the Freudian subject.” College
English 49.7 (1987): 749–755.
12. Lacan, Jacques, Jacques-Alain Ed Miller, and Bruce Trans Fink. Desire
and its interpretation: The seminar of Jacques Lacan, Book VI. Polity
Press, 2019.
154 R. Samuels
78. Stone, Michael H. “Incest, Freud’s seduction theory, and borderline per-
sonality.” Journal of the American Academy of Psychoanalysis 20.2 (1992):
167–181.
79. Sloterdijk, Peter, Michael Eldred, and Leslie A. Adelson. “Cynicism: the
twilight of false consciousness.” New German Critique 33 (1984):
190–206.
80. Robinson, Andrew, and Simon Tormey. “Zizek’s Marx:’Sublime
Object’or a’Plague of Fantasies’?.” Historical Materialism 14.3
(2007): 145.
81. Samuels, Robert. “Žižek’s Rhetorical Matrix: The Symptomatic
Enjoyment of Postmodern Academic Writing.” JAC (2002): 327–354.
82. Rizvi, Shireen L., and Marsha M. Linehan. “The treatment of maladap-
tive shame in borderline personality disorder: A pilot study of “opposite
action”.” Cognitive and Behavioral Practice 12.4 (2005): 437–447.
83. Reed, James. “Mechanical man: John Broadus Watson and the begin-
nings of behaviorism.” Science 244.4910 (1989): 1386–1388.
84. Hurry, Anne, Jack Novick, and Kerry Kelly Novick. “freud’s concept of
projection.” Journal of Child Psychotherapy 4.2 (1976): 75–88.
85. Weber, Max, and Damion Searls. Charisma and disenchantment: The
vocation lectures. NYRB Classics, 2020.
86. Snell, Robert. “L’Anti-Livre noir de la psychoanalyse. CBT in French/
Lacanian perspective.” (2008).
87. Pfaller, Robert. Interpassivity: The aesthetics of delegated enjoyment.
Edinburgh University Press, 2017.
88. Samuels, Robert. “The pleasure principle and the death drive.” Freud for
the twenty-first century. Palgrave Pivot, Cham, 2019. 17–25.
89. Noble, David F. “Digital diploma mills: The automation of higher edu-
cation.” Science as culture 7.3 (1998): 355–368.
90. Pfaller, Robert. “Interpassivity and misdemeanors. The analysis of ideol-
ogy and the Zizekian toolbox.” Revue internationale de philosophie 3
(2012): 421–438.
91. Samuels, Robert. “Ethos, Transference, and Liberal Cynicism.” Zizek
and the Rhetorical Unconscious. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham, 2020. 49–63.
92. Samuels, Robert. “The unconscious and the primary processes.” Freud
for the twenty-first century. Palgrave Pivot, Cham, 2019. 27–42.
93. Lacan, Jacques, Jacques-Alain Miller, and Alan Sheridan. The four funda-
mental concepts of psycho-analysis. Routledge, 2018.
94. Bracher, Mark, et al., eds. Lacanian theory of discourse: Subject, structure,
and society. NYU Press, 1994.
7
Misunderstanding Psychoanalysis
from the Left
© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2022 159
R. Samuels, (Mis)Understanding Freud with Lacan, Zizek, and Neuroscience, The
Palgrave Lacan Series, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-13327-5_7
160 R. Samuels
the evil Other, any criticism of this discourses can be seen as an effort to
blame the victims of persecution.4 Moreover, the highly emotional way
that the antagonism between the self and the other is represented and
lived, makes it hard to examine this discourse in a scientific or neutral
manner. In fact, as we shall see, a hallmark of this ideology and subjectiv-
ity is the rejection of neutrality itself.5
One of Freud’s most important and controversial ideas was his theory
that people often imagine scenes of victimization.6 However, many peo-
ple inside and outside of psychoanalysis have rejected this theory because
it appears to dismiss the suffering of people who have been truly victim-
ized as it lets the victimizer off the hook.7 Yet, from a psychoanalytic
perspective, we can never know for sure what happened in someone’s life,
but what we do need to consider is how one responds to real and imag-
ined suffering.8 The questions of identity and identification are then key
to the theory of psychoanalysis, but in the actual practice, identity and
identification have to be called into question through the privileging of
analytic neutrality, free association, and unconscious material.9
It is my thesis that these basic aspects of analytic practice are rejected
and repressed through a return to a pre-Freudian understanding of ther-
apy.10 On the most basic level, the therapists and analysts in Intersectionality
and Relational Psychoanalysis see their roles as centered on providing
knowledge, love, and recognition to their patients. In other words, instead
of working through the transference, they aim to strengthen it by respond-
ing to their patients’ fundamental demands. Not only does this mode of
treatment reinforce defensive forms of identity and identification, but it
reduces the analytic relationship to a dualistic structure where the analyst
can be either a source for identification or a cause for frustration.11
As Lacan insists, the dualistic view of the analytic relationship blocks
the emergence of unconscious material as it substantiates primitive fanta-
sies on an imaginary level.12 Since the goal is to expose and move beyond
these limiting mental representations, the analyst has to remain neutral
so that the patient can speak without censorship or thinking about what
the analyst is thinking.13 Of course, this is a very strange type of relation-
ship, and it is perhaps this strangeness that prevents therapists and ana-
lysts from accepting the foundations of psychoanalysis itself.
7 Misunderstanding Psychoanalysis from the Left 161
Another related issue that we find throughout this book is the conflict
between the academic application of psychoanalysis to culture and the
use of theory to shape treatment. Although I do believe that psychoanaly-
sis has many important things to say about race, class, gender, and other
social issues, there is an important difference between examining culture
and psychoanalytic treatment.14 Since the analyst has to remain neutral in
order to enable free association, the analyst cannot be a social critic when
he or she is engaged in the analytic process. It is therefore necessary to
recognize a clear distinction between using analytic concepts to define
the role of the analyst and the employment of these same concepts to
examine social and cultural issues.15 In fact, as we shall see, many prob-
lems arise when we do not make this distinction, and we begin to see the
analyst as playing the role of the political activist.16 However, if the ana-
lyst has to suspend judgment and not feed the patient’s demand for love,
recognition, and knowledge, then the analyst has to also suspend political
analysis and intervention within the clinical relationship.17
Identity in Analysis
In their introduction to their book, Max Belkin and Cleonie White point
out that “the contributing authors explore how similarities and differ-
ences among the patient’s and analyst’s gender, race, and sexual orienta-
tion can be acknowledged, challenged, and negotiated” (iii). In
highlighting the role played by these social categories in the relationship
between the therapist and the patient, the authors take a decisive step
away from both analytic neutrality and free association since they believe
that the analyst must be constantly aware of his or her own identity.18
Moreover, instead of seeing analysis as centered on discovering unknown
unconscious material, there is a tendency to examine fixed identities and
identifications.
One of the main ways that the focus on fixated markers of sexual,
racial, and class identities is evident in this collection of essays is through
the notion that patients want to be analyzed by people who belong to the
same identity group.19 We see this identity-based understanding of the
transference in the following passage:
162 R. Samuels
This notion that the therapist and the patient have to both disclose
what they are thinking at all times perverts the fundamental analytic pro-
cess and feeds a sense of narcissism for both the patent and the analyst.31
Since both want to be seen as the one who knows, the only way to avoid
conflict is through the process of imaginary identification. Belkin reveals
this issue in the following way: “Articulating and exploring the differ-
ences and similarities between me and Ana seemed not only important,
but also fraught. According to Russell Meares (1993), “the therapist’s
state of mind should resemble that to which the patient’s should be mov-
ing” (p. 184)” (10). In this melding of two minds, the goal appears to be
for the patient to identify with the ideal movement of the analyst’s own
mind.32 It is hard to see how this process enables discovery or individual
autonomy.
In light of Belkin’s promotion of an imaginary mode of transference
and identification, it is strange that he still wants to insist that the goal of
analysis is to foster curiosity and personal freedom: “While curious uncer-
tainty never completely supplants defensive not knowing, the goal of psy-
chotherapy is to foster curiosity and expand our relational freedom at the
expense of narrative and interpersonal rigidity (Stern, 2015)” (15). Since
the way to promote independence and open inquiry is through the sus-
pension of identity and identification, the question remains why Belkin
is still focused on the very rigid categories he now sees as stifling the ana-
lytic process.33 In fact, he offers an interesting metaphor for the analytic
process itself: “Thus, psychoanalytic inquiry is akin to driving a car: one
is always wondering where one is headed, while at the same time remem-
bering that one always has blind spots” (15). This notion of wondering
where you are going and recognizing that one has blind spots is an apt
description for what it often feels like to be an analyst and a patient. The
problem is that rigid markers of identity and identification often block
free association, and so in many ways, psychoanalysis is in conflict with
the application of identity politics in the clinic.34
If we want to be open to seeing all people without judgment, then it
makes no sense to focus on race, class, and gender markers. Of course,
this colorblind approach to social categories of discrimination can be
attacked for denying systemic oppression and the suffering of the victims
of prejudice, but my argument here is that for benefit of analytic
7 Misunderstanding Psychoanalysis from the Left 165
treatment, all social and political effects can be voiced and felt through
the speech of the patient; however, the analyst should avoid substantiat-
ing any form of identity and identification.35 From this perspective, the
analytic relation is not symmetrical, and yet Belkin wants to insist on an
imaginary dualism: “From the one-person perspective, the patient is in
the driving seat, while the analyst is a passenger-observer (Wachtel,
2008). However, in the two-person psychology that informs my thinking
about the intersections among ethnicity, gender, and sexual identity, the
“analysis-mobile” comes with two brake pedals and two steering wheels;
both individuals are simultaneously a passenger and a driver; each of
them is an observing participant (Fiscalini, 2004)” (15). The problem
with this symmetrical formulation is that is does not accept the funda-
mental lack of participation of the analyst, while it reinforces the narcis-
sistic relation of identification and rivalry: “Through a joint exploration
of their emotional exchanges in the “here and now,” patient and analyst
can describe both the privileged and marginalized aspects of their identi-
ties” (16). As I have been arguing, the goal of analytic treatment is to use
free association in order to uncover the patient’s repressed unconscious
material. When the analyst openly discusses his or her thoughts and emo-
tions, neutrality is lost, and the patient seeks to transfer responsibility for
knowledge onto the analyst who is idealized as the one who is supposed
to know.36 In fact, Belkin does realize one of the pitfalls of this bonding
over knowledge, identity, and meaning: “From the onset of treatment, as
we now suspect, the two of us had been ensconced in a comfortable illu-
sion that we understood both ourselves and the other person” (17). On a
fundamental level, psychoanalysis tells us that we never fully understand
ourselves or other people, and so our sense of understanding and knowl-
edge always has an imaginary aspect where we fill in the gaps and cover
over the lacks.37
The analyst’s neutrality, then, is in part derived from an acceptance of
the conflict between two consciousness and the need to protect against
the projection of meaning and understanding onto the other in the trans-
ference.38 The analyst has to also refrain from satisfying the drives and
demands of the patient as the psychoanalyst resists seeking narcissistic
gratification from the patient, and yet Belkin shows how hard it can be to
maintain this type of relationship: “Upon arriving to our first meeting,
166 R. Samuels
Ana glanced at the office décor and my clothes and remarked that
aesthetics mean a lot to both of us. I was flattered that this attractive,
sophisticated young woman chose me as her therapist” (18). It is impor-
tant to stress that the analyst seeks to remove himself or herself from this
relation of admiration and aesthetics by sitting behind the patient.39 In
staying out of view, the analyst becomes more of a blank screen, which
enables the suspending of the imaginary mirroring narcissistic structure.
In contrast to Kohut, Lacan emphasizes the need to not feed the patient’s
demand for idealization or mirroring, and so he claims that the analyst
becomes an object lacking a specular image.40
Belkin is aware of the problems contained in a narcissistic transference,
but he appears to be unable to fully commit to the position of the analyst:
“During the first phase of treatment, Ana was open to my questions and
frequently responded to my observations and interpretations with a reas-
suring “Yeah, it’s definitely true.” Although my narcissistic side was bask-
ing in what felt like Ana’s approval, something felt a bit off” (18). As
Belkin indicates, the analyst may desire to be admired for his knowledge,
but even if the patent appears to demand this type of relationship, there
is usually a part of the subject that resists this idealization of the other. In
fact, Lacan stresses that in the imaginary structure of narcissism, we often
resent the person we idealize.41 Moreover, when the patient transfers
responsibility for knowing and care onto the analyst, the patient often
feels ambivalent about handing power over to another person.42
In fact, when working with narcissistic obsessional patients, it is very
apparent that behind the patient’s desire to comply with the analyst, we
find an underlying resistance.43 Since narcissists want their ideal ego to be
recognized by an idealized Other, they become anxious and upset when
this Other fails to fulfill this position:
“Ana,” I offered, trying to sound casual, “I am a bit surprised that you seem
always in agreement with everything that I say. I can’t always be right.” Ana
smiled and admitted that she wanted to please me. Moreover, just as she
does in other social settings, she had compiled a mental list of what makes
me tick, and strategically complimented my plants and my outfits. And
then Ana secretly disdained me (just like she despised others) for being so
vain and gullible. “Why do I need to destroy people?” she later asked both
of us. “I feel bad about being manipulative.” (18)
7 Misunderstanding Psychoanalysis from the Left 167
This conflict between wanting to comply with others and the resentment
of others shows the fundamental ambivalence structuring narcissistic
relationships; on the one hand, the subject wants to be recognized as
being good by conforming to social expectations, but on the other hand,
this conformity requires a sacrifice of the self, which is resented.44
Furthermore, when a demand is made to the Other for love, recognition,
and understanding, what is really desired is for the Other to submit to the
will of the subject.45
The only way to break out of this narcissistic relationship is for the
analyst to refuse to play the part of the one who responds to the demands
of the patient.46 Of course, it can be quite difficult to constantly resist
satisfying the patient, but the only way to allow for a new type of rela-
tionship to emerge is to expose the underlying demands of the subject.47
On a basic level, the analysis must always remain strange and uncomfort-
able because this position suspends the usual ways of communicating and
interacting. The conflict, then, that we find between identity politics and
psychoanalysis is that the analyst has to bracket his or her identity in
order to enable the patient the ability to explore the relation between
social categories and subjectivity in an open and free way.48 However, as
we see from the next passage, Belkin does not trust this process, and so he
returns to an imaginary rivalry between two opposed victim identities: “I
am a marginalized Latina, an underdog with a queer sensibility; you are a
privileged, straight-acting white man,” thought Ana. “No. I am the
underdog here. After all, I am a gay Jewish immigrant, while you are a
straight American woman from a rich family,” protested my inner voice”
(19). In this conflict between social identities, the possibility for analytic
neutrality is lost, and as Belkin adds, the result is a competition for moral
goodness: “In retrospect, it seems that both Ana and I were secretly jos-
tling for some sort of moral superiority” (19). Here, we see the dangers of
maintaining the analytic relationship on the level of narcissistic identifi-
cation and idealization: The analyst cannot help but to feed the underly-
ing negative transference as a constant-sum relationship is established
where one person wins and the other loses.49 The only solution is for the
analyst to simply refuse to play this imaginary game.
Belkin’s text does provide a deep insight into the reasons why most
forms of therapy and analysis that move away from neutrality fail, and
168 R. Samuels
these reasons have a lot to do with inherent tensions within identity poli-
tics. Although this form of political activism does play a vital role in
expanding democratic rights and protections, it often can become
counter-productive when it becomes fixated on a binary battle between
idealized innocent victims and demonized perpetrators.50 Instead of
affirming the fundamental ambivalence of the subject, a splitting occurs
where one is either idealized or debased. Furthermore, as Freud found in
his exploration of masochistic fantasies and psycho-somatic disorders, the
person who is suffering often feels that their aggression towards others is
justified as they feel morally superior due to their victim status.51 Since in
this fantasy structure, the victim is always good and innocent, and you
cannot criticize the victim, revenge is justified, while reality testing and
moral reasoning can be suspended.52
As is evident in Belkin’s discussion of his work with Ana, a focus on
intersectionality in the clinic can result in the formation of defensive
identities and a splitting off of undesired parts of the self and other: “Both
Ana and I seemed married to our narrow and rigid perceptions of our
own selves and of each other. Neither of us wanted to concede that we
might be in any way the more privileged person. Moreover, focusing on
the presumed privileged parts of the other allowed each of us to feel self-
righteous” (19). In this dualistic structure, there is always the calculation
of a moral imbalance that in turn justifies a reductive understanding of
the self and the other. For Belkin, the solution to this imaginary rivalry is
the embracing of a shared process: “Until she and I became curious col-
laborators united by a common project, we kept swapping the roles of the
domineering and the subjugated (Benjamin, 2004)” (19). Once again,
the problem with this formulation is that the analytic relationship is nei-
ther symmetrical nor common.53
As Ana herself discovers, even when people ask for help, they often
resent the helper because it gives the other relational power: “At the same
time, she was reluctant to acknowledge that working with me was helpful
to her. “Telling you about my sadness feels like giving into your expecta-
tions. You’ll have a one up on me,” she mused” (20). The desire for auton-
omy and freedom thus runs into the demand for love, recognition, and
understanding, and so it is important for the analyst to avoid reinforcing
these roles in the transference even though they often represent a key to
7 Misunderstanding Psychoanalysis from the Left 169
the treatment. Since the very act of the patient coming to seek help rep-
resents a fundamental transference demand, they analyst should not have
to feed this imaginary relationship; rather the analyst desires the patient
to free associate, and this requires analytic neutrality and the non-involve-
ment in the inevitable transference.54 Furthermore, since one of the goals
of analysis is to work through the transference, it is necessary to make
sure that it comes from the patient and not the analyst. In other words,
by being a blank screen, the analyst makes it clear that the relationship is
produced through the patient’s imaginary fantasies and unconscious
demands.55
Although it does appear that Belkin was able to make much progress
in uncovering Ana’s underlying subjectivity, his participation in her
imaginary understanding blocked a full working through of the transfer-
ence. As he admits himself, his self-disclosures served to provide a source
of identification for his patient: “I might have inadvertently modeled for
Ana that it was relatively safe to come emotionally undone in our rela-
tionship, to appear unsophisticated, unsure, anxious, and even ashamed.
I shared with Ana the contents of my mind, including my efforts to toler-
ate shame” (25). The problem with this process of modeling thought and
behavior for the patient is that it feeds both the narcissistic idealization of
the analyst and the defensive resistance to analysis itself.56 Belkin expresses
the ambivalence generated by this approach in the following manner: “In
return, Ana explored her ambivalent reaction to my self-disclosure. While
she appreciated my honesty, she was also feeling vindicated, victorious,
superior – and she felt guilty about it” (26). Due to the nature of neurotic
ambivalence, even if the analyst thinks that he or she is doing something
good and helpful for the patient, the subject may resent it, and any self-
disclosure by the analyst will be used by the patient in the private court
of moral judgment.57
From Lacan’s perspective, the analyst must take on the role of being
the object for the patient, and Belkin does seem to concur with this
notion: “Before Ana and I began to play together in a metaphorical space
between fantasy and reality (Winnicott, 1971), Ana tended to use me like
a transitional object, a teddy bear: something to cuddle, hate, and muti-
late, but not destroy. While I did not particularly enjoy being treated that
way, I felt safe enough to continue, and I let Ana know that” (26).
170 R. Samuels
culture: “Benjamin (1988) has noted that the Western assumption of the
primacy of individualism in human development is implicitly gendered.
Rationality and autonomy (qualities attributed to the father in traditional
psychoanalytic frameworks) are celebrated, while empathy, emotion, and
other human capacities deemed feminine are devalued” (66). Since rea-
son and autonomy have often been attached to masculine identity, Pocock
seeks to affirm the opposite traits as essential to a feminist mode of psy-
choanalysis. In this postmodern reversal of premodern hierarchies and
binaries, the same categories of essentialized identity are being used, but
now the debased attributes are idealized, while the former ideals are cri-
tiqued.63 The problem with this strategy is that it remains tied to the same
rigid identity categories as it reinforces a reductive binary logic.
What the postmodern reversal of premodern values refuses to recog-
nize is the importance of the modern effort to suspend these categories
through the affirmation of universality, neutrality, objectivity, and rea-
son.64 At the foundation of modern democratic law is the necessary but
impossible ideal of equal treatment regardless of race, class, gender, or
sexual orientation.65 Of course, the law often fails to live up to these ide-
als, but we judge its failures in relation to this ideal. While it is true that
many postmodern social movements to promote minority rights seek to
expand and correct universal human rights, the central problem occurs
when these movements become so fixated on protecting their particular
identities that they reject the very notions of universality, equality, and
neutrality.66 As we saw in the passage above, this rejection of modern
principles often includes a rejection of reason and individual autonomy
since they are seen as being the products of white European males.
Freud’s conceptions of science, the reality principle, free association,
and analytic neutrality are all being called into question because from the
perspective of postmodern identity politics, these principles are all coded
as masculine, white, and straight.67 Here we witness the ways that politi-
cal ideologies and movements can affect how people practice psycho-
analysis since the rejection of its core concepts and practices is motivated
by a particular political discourse. Instead of seeing neutrality as a bias
against bias, it is interpreted as a masculine value promoted to erase issues
concerning race, class, gender, and sexual orientation.68 As Pocock insists,
analytic neutrality has to be rejected because it is just a cover for
172 R. Samuels
analyst threatens the analyst’s own narcissism, and this is one reason why
therapists and psychoanalysts have such a hard time trusting the process.
Not only does the analyst have to give up on the pleasure of being
admired for being the idealized one who knows and cares, but the temp-
tation to validate the patient also has to be avoided.78 This issue is brought
up in Pratyusha Tummala-Narra’s chapter “Intersectionality in the
Immigrant Context”: “Yet, it is critical for the therapist, when relevant,
to validate that the client’s distress stems from systemic injustice, and that
distress derived from racism, xenophobia, sexism, transphobia, heterosex-
ism, classism, and ableism is an appropriate response to injustice (Greene,
2012)” (136). It is unclear how the analyst can validate a patient’s inter-
pretation without falling into the position of the imaginary ego ideal or
the social super-ego. After all, it is up to the patient to discover their own
truth through the process of speaking without worrying about what the
analyst thinks. Relying on the validation of the therapist functions to feed
the transference and block self-discovery. Moreover, as Tummala-Narra
points out, any response by the analyst could be shaped by the analyst’s
own socialization and rigid identity: “Interestingly, because of shared
socialization experiences of compartmentalizing identity, the therapist
and the client may selectively focus on only certain aspects of the other’s
identity” (135). The best way to avoid this dynamic is for the analyst to
simply stop interpreting from a position of knowledge or identity, and
this is done by basing all interpretations on the desire to promote the free
association of the patient.79 In fact, one reason why Lacan used to end his
sessions early was that he wanted to push his patients to speak without
censoring.80 If you end a session when a patient is not free associating,
you push them to dedicate their time in analysis to this particular practice
instead of wasting their time speaking like they usually speak, which after
all, has not helped them.81
However, the lack of belief in the analytic process comes out in the
following passage: “For instance, a client’s associations to the therapist’s
gender may be a core component of the transference, or a therapist’s
attention to the client’s racial background may dominate the exploration
of conflicts related to social class” (136). The issue here is why is the
therapist paying attention to any particular issue when Freud called for
the “free-floating attention” of the analyst. One answer to this question is
7 Misunderstanding Psychoanalysis from the Left 175
that therapy is not analysis, but then we have to ask why is this chapter in
a collection on psychoanalysis and intersectionality? Since the difference
between therapy and psychoanalysis is never clearly stated, it is hard to
know what actually guides the work of these practitioners.82
It has been one of the main arguments of this book that psychoanalysis
is still guided by Freud’s fundamental concepts, and these concepts con-
tinue to shape both the practice and the theory. This argument may be
hard to accept in a time of moral relativism, but as we have seen, when
people are not guided by a set of core theories, they can rationalize any
practice.83 From this perspective, the problem with incorporating inter-
sectionality and identity politics into psychoanalysis is that it can result in
a complete undermining of the fundamental theory guiding treatment.
On the one hand, we do not need a commitment to identity politics to
transform what is discussed in analysis because anything and everything
should be voiced, yet on the other hand, intersectional theory can serve
to prevent psychoanalytic treatment because it can demonize the prac-
tices of neutrality and free association.
allow the analyst the ability to take on the position of being a blank
screen or empty mirror.
What we often find rejected in post-Freudian forms of psychoanalysis
and therapy is the notion that free association relies on the neutrality of
the analyst, and this neutrality creates an unequal and asymmetrical rela-
tionship.85 Rather than affirming the need for the analyst to suspend his
or her own thought and subjectivity, we are told that the analyst also
undergoes change while helping others to change: “Through this rela-
tionship, the therapist too is transformed as his/her/their own identity
work is re-engaged” (137). At first, it appears that the analyst would have
to change through working with others, but the analyst does not act as a
“normal” person in analysis, and the analytic relationship is not a tradi-
tional relationship. Analytic neutrality requires taking on an artificial
position, which is fortified by a clear understanding of analytic theory.86
What we are seeing today is there is a lack of understanding concerning
both the theory and the practice of psychoanalysis, and the result is that
non-analytic concerns are interjected into the analytic process.
The central problem, then, with intersectionality and identity politics
for psychoanalysis is that the focus on identity undermines the ability of
free association and the free-floating attention of the analyst. Furthermore,
as Freud discovered in his examination of the primary processes, con-
sciousness is not controlled by the intentional ego, and so Lacan is correct
to stress that the subject of psychoanalysis is barred and lacking.87 In
contrast to this lack of identity, Cleonie White focuses on the challenges
posed by imposed identities in the immigrant experience: “My patient,
Trevor, one might say, is “verbed”—that is, projected into performance of
that position as in: “I speak, I think, I dream, I am immigrant.” His posi-
tion in culture is imposed as his defining identity. So, no matter how
sturdy the immigrant’s attempts to “integrate” into the new culture, he is
met with repeated acts of rejection as his difference marks him the imper-
fect Other” (161). While we should not reject the difficulties of immi-
grant identity, it is vital to see that in relation to the unconscious and the
primary processes, we are all immigrants lost in a foreign culture of
strange representations.88 However, the way to access this immigrant sub-
jectivity is through free association and not a relationship of communica-
tion and identification.
7 Misunderstanding Psychoanalysis from the Left 177
Although it would be absurd to claim that culture does not affect what is
said in analysis, the question is whether the analyst or therapist should
direct the patient’s discourse in any particular direction. I have argued
that the analyst still needs to interpret, but these interventions are directed
towards the sole purpose of promoting free association.92 It is therefore
misguided to see analysis as a co-construction equally concerned with the
subjectivity of the analyst and the patient.
Notes
1. Belkin, Max, and Cleonie White, eds. Intersectionality and relational psy-
choanalysis: New perspectives on race, gender, and sexuality. Routledge, 2020.
2. Freud, Sigmund. On the universal tendency to debasement in the sphere of
love. Read Books Ltd, 2014.
3. Samuels, Robert. “Pathos, Hysteria, and the Left.” Zizek and the
Rhetorical Unconscious. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham, 2020. 33–47.
4. Ryan, William. Blaming the victim. Vol. 226. Vintage, 1976.
5. Merrill, Roberto, and Daniel Weinstock. Political Neutrality: A
Re-evaluation. Springer, 2014.
6. Israëls, Han, and Morton Schatzman. “The seduction theory.” History of
Psychiatry 4.13 (1993): 23–59.
7. Esterson, Allen. “Jeffrey Masson and Freud’s seduction theory: a new
fable based on old myths.” History of the Human Sciences 11.1
(1998): 1–21.
8. Ferro, Antonino. Seeds of illness, seeds of recovery: The genesis of suffering
and the role of psychoanalysis. Routledge, 2004.
9. Franklin, Girard. “The multiple meanings of neutrality.” Journal of the
American Psychoanalytic Association 38.1 (1990): 195–220.
10. Boothby, Richard. Death and Desire (RLE: Lacan): Psychoanalytic Theory
in Lacan’s Return to Freud. Routledge, 2014.
7 Misunderstanding Psychoanalysis from the Left 179
11. Smith, Joseph, H. “Ego psychology and the language of Lacan: transfer-
ence and affect.” Psychoanalysis and contemporary thought 14.1 (1991):
143–182.
12. Ian, Marcia. “Freud, Lacan, and imaginary secularity.” American Imago
54.2 (1997): 123–147.
13. Caudill, D. ““Lacan’s social psychoanalysis”.” The Subject of Lacan Eds K
Malone, S Friedlander (State University of New York Press, Albany, NY) pp
(2000): 297–315.
14. Johnson, Barbara. The feminist difference: Literature, psychoanalysis, race,
and gender. Harvard University Press, 1998.
15. Gerson, Samuel. “Neutrality, resistance, and self-disclosure in an inter-
subjective psychoanalysis.” Psychoanalytic Dialogues6.5 (1996): 623–645.
16. Guralnik, Orna. “Sleeping dogs: Psychoanalysis and the socio-political.”
Psychoanalytic Dialogues 26.6 (2016): 655–663.
17. Flax, Jane. Disputed subjects: Essays on psychoanalysis, politics and philoso-
phy. Routledge, 2012.
18. Rozmarin, Eyal. “Better identity politics.” Psychoanalytic Dialogues 20.2
(2010): 181–190.
19. Grinberg, León, and Rebeca Grinberg. “The problem of identity and the
psychoanalytical process.” International Review of Psycho-Analysis 1
(1974): 499–507.
20. Akhtar, Salman. Immigration and identity: Turmoil, treatment, and trans-
formation. Jason Aronson, 1999.
21. Jekels, Ludwig, and Edmund Bergler. “Transference and love.” The
Psychoanalytic Quarterly 18.3 (1949): 325–350.
22. Kohut, Heinz. How does analysis cure?. University of Chicago Press, 2009.
23. Schneider, Stanley. “Transference, counter-transference, projective iden-
tification and role responsiveness in the supervisory process.” The Clinical
Supervisor 10.2 (1993): 71–84.
24. Wilson, Mitchell. “The analyst’s desire and the problem of narcissistic
resistances.” Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association 51.1
(2003): 71–99.
25. Dervin, Daniel. “Where Freud was, there Lacan shall be: Lacan and the
fate of transference.” American Imago 54.4 (1997): 347–375.
26. Rodriguez, Leonardo, and Silvia Rodriguez. “On the transference.”
Analysis 1 (1989): 165–185.
180 R. Samuels
58. Lacan, Jacques, Alan Sheridan, and Malcolm Bowie. “The Direction of
the Treatment and the Principles of its Power 1.” Écrits. Routledge, 2020.
250–310.
59. Freud, Sigmund. “Three essays on the theory of sexuality (1905).” The
standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, vol-
ume VII (1901-1905): A case of hysteria, three essays on sexuality and other
works. 1953. 123–246.
60. Hekman, Susan. “Beyond identity: Feminism, identity and identity pol-
itics.” Feminist Theory 1.3 (2000): 289–308.
61. Bondi, Liz. “Locating identity politics.” Place and the Politics of Identity.
Routledge, 2004. 89–106.
62. Samuels, Robert. “The Resistances to Psychoanalysis and Global
Progress.” Freud for the Twenty-First Century. Palgrave Pivot, Cham,
2019. 53–67.
63. Jarach, Lawrence. “Essentialism and the problem of identity politics.”
The Anarchist Library (2004).
64. Samuels, Robert. “Logos, global justice, and the reality principle.” Zizek
and the rhetorical unconscious. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham, 2020. 65–86.
65. Pagden, Anthony. The Enlightenment: and why it still matters. Oxford
University Press, 2013.
66. Samuels, Robert. “Pathos, Hysteria, and the Left.” Zizek and the
Rhetorical Unconscious. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham, 2020. 33–47.
67. Dimen, Muriel. “The third step: Freud, the feminists, and postmodern-
ism.” The American Journal of Psychoanalysis 55.4 (1995): 303–319.
68. Chatterjee, Angana. “The Plausibility of a Feminist Philosopher’s Take
on Freudian Analysis.” Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research
32.2 (2015): 227–237.
69. Samuels, Robert. “Pathos, Hysteria, and the Left.” Zizek and the
Rhetorical Unconscious. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham, 2020. 33–47.
70. Nock, Christopher John. “Equal freedom and unequal property: a cri-
tique of Nozick’s libertarian case.” Canadian Journal of Political Science/
Revue canadienne de science politique 25.4 (1992): 677–695.
71. Bridge, Gary. “Rationality, ethics, and space: On situated universalism
and the self-interested acknowledgement of ‘difference’.” Environment
and Planning D: Society and Space18.4 (2000): 519–535.
72. Samuels, Robert. “Logos, global justice, and the reality principle.” Zizek
and the rhetorical unconscious. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham, 2020. 65–86.
7 Misunderstanding Psychoanalysis from the Left 183
The main argument of this book has been that psychoanalytic practice
and theory is based primarily on five fundamental concepts, and when
these principles are misunderstood, the specificity of this discourse is lost.
As we have seen, one of the ways that Freud’s original practice is under-
mined is through the refusal to accept the neutrality of the analyst, which
enables the free association of the patient.1 It turns out that many thera-
pists and analysts today simply reject the very idea of suspending judg-
ment and understanding in order to allow patients to say whatever comes
into their minds. Perhaps it is the difficulty in giving up a position of
power that prevents people from assuming the analytic position.2
The resistance to analytic neutrality has also been tied to the political
claim that the concept of neutrality was derived from privileged white
male Europeans, and so it must be a form of oppression and prejudice.3
However, what Freud shows in his use of this notion is the idea that the
reality principle requires a bias against bias, and so even if neutrality is the
product of a particular culture and class, its power undermines all par-
ticular interests.4 In fact, the concept of neutrality is a key aspect of seeing
psychoanalysis as a science. Since the goal in modern science is to judge
evidence from a neutral perspective, the need to suspend self-interest and
© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2022 185
R. Samuels, (Mis)Understanding Freud with Lacan, Zizek, and Neuroscience, The
Palgrave Lacan Series, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-13327-5_8
186 R. Samuels
cultural values in the pursuit of truth and reality requires radical self-
honesty, and we find this same driving force behind psychoanalytic prac-
tice and theory.5
In claiming that psychoanalysis is a science, I am countering the notion
that this discipline has to turn to other fields in order to gain the respect
that is granted to valorized sciences like neuroscience and evolutionary
psychology. In fact, I have argued that these other respected discourses
are often not actually sciences because they rely on a misguided under-
standing of human subjectivity.6 Instead of seeing how humans make a
break with biology and evolution through the open nature of their drives,
many brain scientists seek to equate the human mind with the brains of
other animals and computers.7 Moreover, in the quest to determine the
meaning of consciousness, they fail to see how the human mind is able to
go beyond material reality when internal mental representations are con-
fused with the perception of the external world. In repressing the psycho-
analytic theory of the primary processes, these new disciplines seek to tie
consciousness to inherited mental programs derived from natural
selection.8
There is also the tendency in neuroscience and evolutionary psychol-
ogy to conflate non-conscious mental process with the unconscious. As I
have insisted throughout this book, the problem with this theory is that
it excludes the essential notion of repression.9 Since it is hard to under-
stand how someone can lie to themselves, the splitting of the self between
the truth and the lie is replaced by a simple acknowledgement of a lack of
awareness. As I have shown, even an astute psychoanalyst like Lacan
tends to confuse the unconscious with the primary processes, and one of
the results of this conflation is that the ethical dimension of repression is
lost.10 Since we tend to repress thoughts and feelings that lead to shame
and guilt, our protection of an idealized ego leads to a splitting of the self.
As Freud first found in his work with hysterics, repression entails that not
only do neurotic symptoms not make sense to the medical profession,
but they also do not make sense to the subject.11 In creating a break from
anatomy and cognitive continuity, hysteria reveals the radical nature of
human subjectivity.
Since neurotic symptoms manifest a gap between cause and effect,
they provide a challenge to science and the medical disciplines. However,
8 Conclusion: Still (Mis)Understanding Psychoanalysis 187
from the self, the other, and reality.19 Psychoanalysis is therefore needed
more than ever because it is the only discourse that understands this self-
destructive drive shaping human thought and behavior.
Unfortunately, as this book has documented, psychoanalysis is being
repressed both inside and outside of psychoanalysis. Since its major con-
cepts are easily misunderstood, it has been easy to see Freud’s theory as
being outdated; however, I hope I have shown that this vital discourse is
still guided by a handful of essential concepts. Of course, many people
will reject this argument because it idealizes Freud as the one who already
always knows. Furthermore, if I pose myself as the only one who really
understands Freud, then I only serve to heighten the idealizing transfer-
ence. However, Freud’s work also includes a safe-guard against identifica-
tion and idealization. Since the goal of analysis is to allow for the free
association of the patient, anything that prevents the free discovery of
unconscious material must be considered to be a resistance to the truth
itself. From this perspective, the discourse does not belong to Freud or
any of his followers; rather, the theory provides a space for a practice that
has no limits or inherent content. As a pure practice of radical self-
honesty, psychoanalysis is an open discourse without identity or
identification.
Notes
1. Poland, Warren S. “On the analyst’s neutrality.” Journal of the American
Psychoanalytic Association 32.2 (1984): 283–299.
2. Lacan, Jacques, Alan Sheridan, and Malcolm Bowie. “The Direction of
the Treatment and the Principles of its Power 1.” Écrits. Routledge, 2020.
250–310.
3. Rose, Jeff, and Karen Paisley. “White privilege in experiential education:
A critical reflection.” Leisure Sciences 34.2 (2012): 136–154.
4. Samuels, Robert. “Science and the reality principle.” Freud for the twenty-
first century. Palgrave Pivot, Cham, 2019. 5–16.
5. Samuels, Robert. “Logos, global justice, and the reality principle.” Zizek
and the rhetorical unconscious. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham, 2020. 65–86.
6. Hughes, Austin L. “The folly of scientism.” The New Atlantis(2012): 32–50.
8 Conclusion: Still (Mis)Understanding Psychoanalysis 189
© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2022 191
R. Samuels, (Mis)Understanding Freud with Lacan, Zizek, and Neuroscience, The
Palgrave Lacan Series, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-13327-5
192 Index
Demand, 8, 14–16, 23, 38, 45, 55, Ethics, 72, 73, 105–111
86, 89–94, 106, 107, 110, Evolution, 13, 30, 34, 37, 42–44,
113, 115, 121, 132, 136, 150, 47–49, 52, 90, 92, 93,
160–163, 165–169, 173 120, 186
Democracy, 140 Evolutionary psychology, 44, 47,
Descartes, Rene, 10, 24, 68, 83, 56, 92, 186
84, 86, 118
Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of
Mental Disorders (DSM), F
50–54, 56, 93 Fantasy, 66, 76, 109, 111, 117–119,
Displacement, 12, 17, 31, 32, 34, 131–133, 136, 137, 139, 148,
36, 38, 46, 49, 65, 67, 132, 150, 160, 168, 169
139, 141, 144, 148–151, 163 Fetish, 142
Dreams, 10, 11, 13, 14, 20, 22, 34, Free association, 1, 3, 16, 24, 46,
35, 66–71, 75–78, 80–83, 68, 72–76, 80, 81, 84, 85,
112, 137–139, 141, 144, 176 107, 109, 110, 114, 115,
Drives, 2, 8, 15, 23, 35, 37–39, 42, 118, 119, 138, 139, 160,
43, 47, 49, 51, 53, 56, 63, 70, 161, 164, 165, 170–178,
76, 82, 87, 89–96, 107, 119, 185, 188
120, 131, 134–136, 141–144, Freedom, 14, 30, 43, 136, 147, 152,
147–150, 153, 165, 186–188 164, 168, 172, 187
Drugs, 39, 44, 53, 54 Free will, 43–45, 187
Freud, Sigmund, 1–4, 7–24, 30–38,
40–44, 46, 47, 49, 52, 55, 56,
E 63–96, 105, 108–112, 114,
Ego, 2, 10, 14, 19–24, 38, 40, 66, 117, 118, 120, 122, 131–138,
67, 69, 75, 78–85, 87, 94–96, 140, 142–144, 146, 147, 149,
108, 110–113, 115–121, 136, 152, 159, 160, 162, 163, 168,
139, 162, 166, 176, 186 170, 171, 174–176, 185–188
Ego ideal, 87, 94–96, 108, 110, 112,
115, 143, 152, 162, 174
Emotion, 11, 23, 30–32, 38, 41, 42, G
44–49, 79, 144, 150, 165, 171 Gaze, 80–84, 95, 96, 151
Enjoyment, 133, 134, 136, 151, 187 Guilt, 19, 32, 36, 37, 42–44, 77, 89,
Enlightenment, the, 3, 23, 116–118 138, 139, 149, 152, 186
Index 193
H K
Hallucination, 9–11, 13, 14, 20, 30, Knowledge, 8, 15, 20, 21, 49, 52,
40, 65, 66, 70, 79, 81, 83, 136 75, 78, 90, 94, 114, 116, 118,
Hegel, G. W., 3, 134, 140, 132, 136, 140, 145, 146, 149,
141, 146–148 150, 160, 161, 165, 166, 173,
Horwitz, Allan, 50, 53–56 174, 187
Hypnosis, 16, 86, 95, 96, 114–115
Hysteria, 16, 17, 20, 21, 137, 139,
146, 186, 187 L
Lacan, Jacques, 2, 3, 11, 12, 14, 15,
17, 18, 24, 42, 63–96, 105–107,
I 110, 111, 116, 118, 119,
Id, 38, 147 121–124, 131–134, 137–140,
Ideal ego, 80, 82, 87, 94, 108, 139, 142, 147–148, 151, 153, 160,
162, 166 163, 166, 169, 174, 176, 186
Identification, 49, 75, 78, 80, 87, Language, 2, 11, 12, 17, 46, 64, 65,
94–96, 108, 110, 112, 114, 68, 74, 111, 122, 132–134,
116, 119, 121, 122, 144, 160, 138, 144, 153, 175
161, 164, 165, 167, 169, 172, Left, the, 159–178
173, 176, 177, 188 Linguistics, 4, 12, 13, 17, 35,
Identity politics, 3, 164, 167, 168, 67, 74, 75
170–172, 175–178 Love, 15, 86, 90, 92–96,
Ideology, 3, 52, 109, 145–152, 159, 106–108, 110, 136, 142, 143,
160, 171, 172, 187 150, 160, 161, 163, 167,
Imaginary, 10, 14, 22, 31–33, 66, 168, 173
78–82, 87, 94, 96, 110, 112,
121, 122, 124, 132, 135–137,
142, 160, 163–169, 173, 174 M
Intentionality, 14, 21, 36, 40, 41, Marx, Karl, 3, 137–142,
65, 66, 78–80, 82–84, 146–149
95, 96, 173 Marxism, 137, 138, 143, 146,
Intersectionality, 168, 174–176 148, 149
Memory, 9–13, 17–20, 22, 30, 33,
34, 37, 46, 49, 65, 67, 68,
J 73–77, 109, 118
Jouissance, 133, 134 Metaphor, 3, 4, 11, 12, 18, 32, 33,
Jung, Carl, 89 69, 80, 105, 164
194 Index
Recognition, 15, 80, 86, 87, 90, 94, Self-destruction, 44, 92, 134,
106, 108, 122, 136, 150, 147, 187
160–163, 167, 168, 173 Sexism, 174
Repetition, 2, 10, 23, 63, 71–77, 96, Sexuality, 8, 19, 20, 31, 42, 48, 49,
113, 134–136 88–90, 92, 134, 170, 175
Rhetoric, 4, 11, 32, 35, 46 Shame, 19, 32, 36, 37, 42–44, 77,
Right, the, 3, 10, 109, 111, 112, 89, 138, 139, 149, 152,
123, 142, 166, 168, 171, 172 169, 186
Signifier, 11, 12, 17–19, 64, 65, 67,
69, 70, 73–77, 88, 90, 94,
S 144, 151, 152
Samuels, Robert, 25n5, 26n17, 28n48, Sloterdijk, Peter, 146
28n50, 57n4, 57n13, 58n21, Solms, Mark, 29–49, 51, 52, 56
58n29, 59n38, 60n55, 60n58, Speech, 23, 24, 72, 76, 84, 87, 111,
61n61, 61n63, 61n64, 61n68, 132, 133, 138, 165
62n77, 99n32, 100n55, 100n60, Splitting, 168, 186
102n93, 103n96, 103n97, Subjectivity, 3, 13, 30, 32, 36,
126n19, 126n27, 127n45, 43, 47, 66–68, 80, 123,
127n46, 127n49, 128n52, 136, 138, 144, 145, 147,
128n58, 128n67, 154n13, 148, 150, 152, 153, 159,
154n14, 154n25, 154n27, 160, 163, 167, 169, 172,
155n34, 155n35, 156n48, 173, 176–178, 186
156n59, 157n71, 157n73, Substitution, 12, 17–19, 31, 32, 34,
158n81, 158n88, 158n91, 36, 38, 46, 49, 67, 74, 92,
158n92, 178n35, 181n43, 132, 139, 141, 142, 144
181n44, 181n50, 182n62, Super-ego, 19, 37, 66, 108, 115,
182n64, 182n66, 182n69, 131, 133, 135, 136, 147, 148,
182n72, 183n74, 184n90, 152, 174
188n4, 188n5, 189n13, 189n16 Symbolic, 3, 11, 12, 14, 17–20, 23,
Sartre, Jean Paul, 43, 68, 71 30–35, 39, 46, 49, 63–68, 71,
Saussure, Ferdinand de, 67 73, 75–78, 80, 122, 132–136,
Science, 1, 2, 4, 12, 13, 23, 24, 29, 140–144, 151
31, 37, 46–48, 51–53, 55, 56, Symptom, 16–19, 35, 50–52, 56,
72, 73, 75, 115, 118, 119, 66, 80, 91, 106, 110, 113,
140, 141, 171, 185–187 114, 137, 145, 146, 186
196 Index
T U
Thinking, 2, 10–13, 18–21, 24, 30, Unconscious, 1, 7, 31, 63, 106, 131,
66, 70, 76, 78, 79, 82, 85, 160, 186
119, 120, 144, 150, 151, 160, Universal, 3, 81, 142, 159, 171, 172
163–165, 173
Transference, 1, 2, 7, 9, 14–16, 49,
55, 56, 63, 71, 84–88, 90, W
93–96, 106–112, 114, 115, Wilson, Mitchell, 2, 105–124
119–122, 131, 136, 139, 143,
144, 151–153, 160–170, 173,
174, 188 Z
Trauma, 76–78, 84, 173 Žižek, Slavoj, 3, 131