E.T. Gendlin - The New Phenomenology of Carrying Forward
E.T. Gendlin - The New Phenomenology of Carrying Forward
E.T. Gendlin - The New Phenomenology of Carrying Forward
forward
E.T. Gendlin
To speak with and from what is more than the categories, we employ
the capacity of language for new sentences. This capacity of language
is rooted in the human body as reflexively sensed from inside. The
reflexivity is currently being missed, because attention is understood
along the lines of perception, as if a neutral and unexamined person
over here directs a neutral beam at some already separate object
over there. If we attend to experiencing directly we find[Page
129]that we live with situational bodies which always sense
themselves in sensing anything else. So the first half of my paper
concerns the functions of what is more than categories, especially the
inherent interrelations of language, situations, and the human body.
The second half of my paper concerns the reflexivity of attention,
self-consciousness and first-person process.
1.
A philosophy that can think with more does not assume the science
picture. It does not assume, in Russell's words, that logic is the
"furniture of the world." We want to derive and understand the great
power of logic and science, and grasp how these are embedded in
more than themselves. We badly need to add a new and different
kind of science to augment that world-picture. Husserl's refusal to
assume the reductive ontology was sound, and we can go much
further in the direction he opened. We can derive this and also other
ontologies in and from phenomenology.
In use, all concepts involve more than their clean logical patterns. But
if we do not pay more attention to this, then we seem to have
nothing left, when the concepts fail. There is no new road, only
arbitrariness where the concepts break. We find ourselves in a welter
of conceptual possibilities, a mix of all the concepts and theories we
have read and thought. We can move in all sorts of possible
directions, old and new. Many analytic distinctions can always be
made, and need not be foolish. In this plethora what we choose to
say is arbitrary.
What you find is not disorder, not limbo, not just flow, not some
concept together with the opposite of that concept. Rather, you find
an intricacy, pregnant, implicitly ordered, perhaps partly opaque.
From this intricacy you may at times be unable to go on, at least for
a while. This implicit intricacy is quite different than the welter of
analytic concepts and possibilities.
I have been speaking about concepts breaking down, but even when
they work well, we can always go to the implicit intricacy. It is a
more organic order, a more precise and more demanding kind of
order, a very finely determined order, very different from logic, yet
responsive to logic. It contains a great many implicit distinctions and
entities, but you can easily assure yourself that it has much more
order than these, and an order of a different kind.
Now I must point to the mode of language I have already used here.
Can I really use words such as "organic," "order," "precise," "kind,"
"determined," and "different," to speak of more than conceptual
distinctions? These words seem to mean certain conceptual
distinctions. Does not "order" always consist of discrete entities and
patterns? Does not "organic" refer to certain defined entities? But in
my sentences the words have not remained within their old
meanings. When we speak from the intricacy, the sentences can add
to the meanings of the words. We notice this especially when we
have trouble finding words. Then we can sense the physical strain as
the implicit words rearrange themselves in our bodies, so that when
they come, they arrive newly arranged. Words can acquire more
meaning when they come in sentences that come freshly at the edge
of the implicit intricacy.
You need not be a philosopher to find yourself at such an edge. You
might be tracking a half-formed new observation in any field. Or, you
might be in midst of writing a poem. Or, you might find yourself in a
troubling situation which no obvious action can resolve. With the
usual view of the body as a machine, it may seem surprising that the
body can feel a situation, and what[Page 131]is more, can imply and
demand a next step of speech or action that has never been seen
before. But we are familiar with this bodily "knowledge" from many
practical situations. We know that we cannot base our actions just on
what we can conceptualize. We have to use our implicit bodily sense
of the whole situation. We may find a way that resolves our bodily
unease, or not. We decide when we must, but perhaps a large
discomfort remains hanging there. This bodily discomfort "knows"
some of the intricacy which the decision did not take account of. But
when a decision does sit right in our bodies, how well we sleep that
night!
Right now, for example, where do you sense your reaction to what I
am saying? If you have not stopped to articulate it, then it is still only
a physical sense of implicit meaning, perhaps excitement, perhaps
discomfort, at any rate a bodily sense which only a philosophical body
could create. It is not an emotion, not a mere feeling about this
discussion, but an implicit intricacy, a cluster of implicit philosophical
thoughts.
But I am getting too far ahead. Let me choose one example and go
into some detail. I hope the example will let me point to the close
relation between language and the body. In my example you will note
the physical "coming" of words. The example should also show how
we can find where the implicit intricacy opens. Thirdly it should show
how we recognize when we did not speak from the implicit intricacy,
and when we did.
Say you are writing a poem. You have six or eight lines but the poem
is not finished. It wants to go on. In an implicit way you feel (sense,
have, live, are ...) what should be said next, but you do not know
what to say. The phrases that come do not precisely say it. You reject
one phrase after another. How are you able to do this? You do not
know what to say, but you recognize that these phrases do not say it.
Something implicit is functioning in your rejection of them. Lovely
phrases come. Some are so good, you save them for another poem.
But THIS demanding implicit sense still hangs there.
Your hand rotates in midair, your body knows what needs to be said
and has never as yet been said in the history of the world (if it is a
good poem).
What does the word "come" say here? How do words come to us?
This "coming" needs to be studied. How do the right phrases come
and how are they recognized?
[Page 132]
As a poet you need not worry over these questions. Poets work in
what Husserl called the "natural attitude." But as philosophers and
phenomenologists we want to think with, from, and into this unclear
but more precise demanding edge, and think into this coming of
words. When we then speak from there, these three words
"language," "concept," and "body" will have acquired more meanings.
The body physically rearranges the same old words, so that they
come to us already arranged in new phrases and sentences. This is so
in all ordinary speech, not only in fresh thinking. We do not look up
single words and paste them together. If we hear ourselves saying
the wrong thing, we can only stop, regain the implicit sense of what
we were about to say, and wait for another set of words to come.
The "coming" of words is bodily, like the coming of tears, sleep,
orgasm, improvisation, and how the muse comes. But here we have
to be careful. The higher animals also sleep and have orgasms, and
very complex lives even without language. But language is implicit in
the whole human body (not only in our brains). Language is implicit
in our muscular movements and in every organ. It is implicit in what
rouses or spoils our appetites, and in what disturbs our sleep. The
language is part of culture and history, but the body is always freshly
here again, and can say "no," even when culture and reason say
"yes." If you enter there, you find a finely ordered cluster of strands,
far more intricate than culture. The body can insist on some new and
more sophisticated way that has never as yet been found, and may
never be found. We often need to find our way beyond the cultural
forms. Similarly, improvisation and the muse come in a bodily way
beyond the already existing forms.
Although what we called "you" does not control what comes, the
implying is not an otherness (not an "alterity"), not another self, not
unreachable. Rather, what comes in this way feels more deeply and
uncensoredly from yourself,[Page 133]than anything that you could
construct. Now the words "you" and "self" tell of degrees of selfness,
since we are most ourselves when there is a fresh and surprising
coming through the body.
There has been no established word for this kind of bodily datum. The
words "perception," "idea," "emotion," "feeling," "affective,"
"kinesthetic," "proprioceptive" all mean something else. Do not call it
by an old word; people will not be able to find it. Let it generate an
odd fresh phrase. It is a felt meaning, a felt sense, the direct
referent, the implicit demanding.
All known concepts are available, but their patterns are not what we
find here. If we had nothing else, we would be in limbo. But we have
much more than the concepts – we have language forming freshly
and oddly to say all this. And we have what language can freshly
speak from, which is anything but indeterminate. What comes in this
way from the intricacy is more finely organized, usually on a new
plane, skew and around the corner from the common meanings. Now
let me consider the great question which must obviously be asked
here: How are we able to recognize when we are speaking from the
implicit intricacy, and when not? We want to grasp how. The fact that
objective observers can reliably distinguish it is now well established.
We have a good deal of research to support this claim. [3]
But can we say what does happen? Or can we only negate the old
notion of representation? Do we have more here than the old
concepts? Of course we have more here. We have what happens, and
also the power of language which can speak freshly from what
happens. Let us permit the language to do this, and also observe how
it does this.
Was the new line already hidden in the implying? No, the line came
from, but was not in the implying. The pattern we spoke of as: "came
from but was[Page 134]not in" is more complex than representation.
We are speaking from it; we are taking it along.
Does the implying become explicit? No, not at all! The implying does
not become words, even after the newly-phrased words arrive. The
implying never turns into something explicit, as if now it is no longer
there. If the implying were no longer there, the poet would not know
to prefer just these words. Rather, these words carry the implying
along with it. They bring it. They carry it forward. They take it along.
They bring this implying with them, which is how the poet knows to
keep just this line.
At last the poet knows what the implying "was," but is this quite the
same implying that was there before? We cannot say yes because the
poet didn't quite know what was implied. We cannot say no because
then there would be no connection and no reason to keep these lines.
Here again the old concepts break, and again I point to the more
intricate pattern we find, and to the power of fresh language to speak
from it. We can do much more than deny that the implying is the
same or different. As philosophers we recognize the "same and
different" as the arch principles of the logical use of concepts.
But is not something a "concept" only because its pattern goes free
from the juncture at which it first arises, so that it is applicable
elsewhere? But the pattern of this concept is not only a separable
spatial diagram. The pattern is also its relation to the carried-forward
intricacy. When we apply "carrying[Page 135]forward" elsewhere, we
apply this juncture. Let me explain how such a concept is applicable
at other junctures.
Concepts that carry their implicit junctures with them are much more
precise. They mean what they do at that juncture in that situation.
When applied elsewhere they bring their first implicit
juncture into the new implicit juncture. So they do not have the same
effect there, nor just a different effect, but again more than same or
different. Can language say what we do find? The concept's first
implicit juncture "crosses" with the new juncture, to produce just this
next change at this new juncture. We can enter into its effect. Then
we find that crossing opens every concept so that it can do more than
before. We also find that it opens each new juncture so that there is
more there than before. The crossing of two junctures does not bring
the lowest common denominator but rather a great deal that is new
to both of the two that cross.
When two patterns function only logically, they do limit each other
down to their lowest commonality. Our capacity for logical patterns is
an enormously valuable human power, but we do not lose it if we also
use the kind of pattern which happens with intricacy. "Carrying
forward" and "crossing" are two more-than-logical concepts I have
introduced. In the crossing of two intricacies, each becomes implicit
in the other insofar as it can. This is an extremely precise implicit
process. When we enter into this implicit effect, we find that the new
possibilities are much more precisely differentiated than what we had
before.
It has long been known that concepts bring their implicit junctures
and are not the same in different contexts, but this was always
considered a terrible limitation which has to be ignored if we want to
make sense. Concepts were therefore said to "drop out" all their
intricacy, as if the actual intricacy consisted only of "particulars"
subsumed under them. But concepts do not drop out their intricacy,
and the intricacy does not consist only of subsumed detail. When
concepts are treated as empty patterns, they seem to close the
intricacy which is always there and can always be entered. Although
this closing is vital for logic, it has given concepts a bad reputation as
if they must always close us to more. This is not so.
In contrast to spatial patterns which have no inherent value-direction,
we find that experiential implying has a life-enhancing, forward-
moving character. The implied new steps (of language or action) are
in a life-forwarding direction. What we usually call the "direction" is
defined by some external aim or mark. The externally-defined
"direction" can change at each step, but in its implicit intricate
meaning we say, looking back, that the surprising steps of carrying
forward were in "the same" direction all along. The body's organic
direction is prior to the externally defined "direction." As a society we
must be careful that the great progress of the logically reductive
sciences does not lead us to lose this little-understood characteristic
of body process.
[Page 137]
My point here is: You need not wait till you get home, and either
deplore speaking prematurely, or happily laud the power of dialogue.
If you keep returning to the implicit, you can check step by step
whether the implicit is being carried forward. If it shrivels, quickly
discard the statement. Better words will come.
[Page 138]
I could show only a little here. We have become able to employ and
(by means of the employment also characterize) many of the ways in
which the intricacy functions in thinking, in language, and in action,
as well as in logic and science.
2.
Husserl discovered what I call "the intricacy." And then he did not
stop short of it, as so many others did. He entered it and classified a
thousand or so facets, like Adam in Paradise naming all the animals.
In his way, Husserl already found that the present occurs into the
previous implying and brings it forward as the new implying. He
denied that time consists only of pure presents. He found that there
is always also a protention of the not-yet. For example, as I now
begin this very sentence, you are already ... Yes. And, if I stop, you
feel as if we had stopped in midst of a broad jump. Phrased in my
terms, he found that the present happens into a previous protention,
and is also a new protention. If we enter further into the intricacy
here, we find carrying forward.
[Page 139]
that every manifold of experience, however far extended, leaves open still
closer and new determinations of things and so ad infinitum.
Der Ausdruck ist nicht so etwas wie . . . ein darübergezogenes Kleid; er ist
eine geistige Formung, die an der intentionalen Unterschicht neue intentionale
Funktionen übt, und von ihr korrelativ intentionale Funktionen erfahrt. Was
dieses neue Bild wieder besagt, das muss an den Phänomenen selbst . . .
studiert werden (Ideen I, para 124, p. 307).
Here I find in the margin my own note from when I first read this text
many years ago. It says: "Is there an 'all'?"
Even in regard to any one concern, the intricacy can always lead
further, and can enrich and complicate the earlier findings. But that
never makes them wrong or useless. Unless one finds an error (which
is something distinctly different, but this demands another intricate
and unfinishable discussion), one retains the earlier steps, although
the further intricacy becomes implicit in them.
[Page 140]
With old habits we might wrongly assume that such a spot is entirely
the result of his categories, so that it would disappear if we question
them. But this is not so. As Experiencing and the Creation of
Meaning shows, the intricacy we find by means of concepts and
categories is not controlled by the concepts and categories. In the
intricacy they do not act as if they were logical premises which
control what we will find. What we find with them does not need to
remain consistent with them. What we directly find at any juncture
where we apply concepts, can immediately require a further
differentiation in the very concepts which led to it. The intricacy is not
determined by any hierarchy of concepts. Even the smallest detail,
seemingly subsumed under a lower concept, can lead to an
experiential differentiation which reformulates the top categories. I
showed this "reversal" in Experiencing and the Creation of
Meaning and in a new procedure, "thinking at the edge" (TAE). [8]
[Page 141]
This is the central meaning, not the edge. Words mean the change
they make when they are said. The change happens implicitly in the
situation. If we examine what it is that functions as the statement's
meaning, what difference it makes to say it, what the point of it is,
we discover that the implicit intricacy is what actually functions when
a statement functions. When we say "I understand it," the
understanding is an implicit intricacy. When we do not understand a
statement, we can only repeat the statement. We repeat its form of
words. But when we understand the statement, we can speak from it
in many ways.
For philosophy the model of clear perceptual objects found over there
and capable of being formulated alone, utterly breaks down. We
cannot use perception as the model for language or most everything
else. An implicit intricacy functions centrally, and we have to study
how speech, thought, and action function in relation to it. Philosophy
cannot model itself on the reception of "external" perceptual objects.
It has to study the process by which the external/internal distinction
comes about (A Process Model, VIIB).
Husserl knew not to attempt one logically coherent system from his
many independent articulations from intricacy. Each of these provides
access to reenter the intricacy. It is because Husserl enters the
experienced intricacy that he can generate so many new terms and
distinctions at points where there had been only a supposedly simple
pattern before. But it is also for this reason that he does not make
analytically desirable distinctions when he does not directly find them.
For example, among the many questions Zahavi very justly raises, it
seems true to me that Husserl does not make the following
distinctions. Zahavi says:
The phrase "tends to equate" says a little too much, but I think
Zahavi is right that Husserl does not make the distinction which
would set apart how the ego's self-awareness is a structural
characteristic inherent in all experience. Zahavi[Page 142]is also right
to argue that this is Husserl's view. Self-awareness is structurally
inherent, not merely the perceiving of, or the "presence" to
experiences. Zahavi is pursuing a cogent line of argument against
Pothast, who seems to reduce Husserl's account just to the I's
perception and ownership of experiences. Zahavi writes:
I think Zahavi is right, that Husserl did not construe the "I" only as a
presence over against experiences. But given the juncture at which
Husserl describes what is directly experienced, and given Husserl's
logical categories, I think that Husserl is right not to make the
distinctions which Zahavi makes in (1)-(4) above. As Zahavi says,
Husserl finds and says that self-experience is inherent in the very
structure of any experience. There are many places where Husserl
obviously speaks-from more than mere ownership. But I think one
cannot distinguish the inherent self-consciousness with the language
and kind of concepts Husserl had available.
Let me first cite the evidence to support Zahavi's reading, and then
show what would be needed to provide phenomenologically the
distinction which Zahavi proposes.
Husserl says:
Auch mein Leib ist mir gegenüber als Körper, aber nicht als Leib; der Stoss,
der . . . meinen Leib trifft, trifft "mich." (Beilage VI of Ideen II)
Also my body is over against me as Körper but not as Leib. The blow which hits
. . . my Leib hits 'me.' A stab into my hand: I am stabbed.
It is interesting here to compare Wittgenstein on the relation of
person and pain in the body. [10]
We easily find the "I" which issues our "ray" of attention. And as
Husserl says, we can indeed shift this attentional "viewing beam"
(Blickstrahl). We just did this by shifting our attention to the body
from inside. But do we find these many "experiences" there? For
example, take "yesterday." Is yesterday an experience, or
is an experience rather that moment yesterday when . . ., or perhaps
just only one of the many strands of relevances and consequences
which went into that moment? Now we can say that experiences are
not waiting there, in advance of our attention. They are not pre-cut.
Of course the categories and concerns we bring are not just arbitrary
either. We respond within an ongoing continuity, or to an implicit
demand. We can evaluate this by entering into the implicit sense of
it. Or, if such a demand is not already there we attend with the
project of letting such a demand form so that we might know what to
do next. No attention operates alone. It always comes from and with
a mesh of physically sensed relevance just as any other kind of
symbolizing does, and it is therefore questionable, relative, and
various, and yet also always in a precise and demanding relation to
the implicit intricacy which motivates it.
More often our attention is not a peaceful neutral just being and
looking. Rather, we attend in order to search for something or keep
track of something. We attend only in a certain relevance, which is
part of our situation and which we "know" and feel without going into
it. Recall Sartre in a restaurant looking everywhere for the absent
Pierre, thereby seeing none of the people who were there.
[Page 146]
Now we can enter directly into our experiencing of what we call "mere
attention," to see if we have spoken from it, and if it responds with
more. Is this intricacy carried forward if we say that attention is also
a self-reception? "Of course," I find myself saying, "I always felt
implicitly that I was meant by "pay attention!" If I was "not paying
attention," it meant thatI myself had wandered away inside, and was
not there with the event. So, of course.
I must point out the sharp difference between this reflexive re-
reception internal to experiencing, on the one hand, and what we call
"reflection" on the other hand. The reflexive re-reception generates
the process. It generates each next bit of process. A first-person
process happens through this reflexive re-reception. On the other
hand, when we reflect, we take a separate stand in relation to the
past. The reflexivity of carrying forward is not the past,[Page 147]not
reflection. It is the self-generating of the present. "Reflexivity" is a
more complex concept of the present.
Levinas said that another person is not just your other, not alive to fit
you or to frustrate you by being other than you need. The other
person is not your other. Another person is alive in different
dimensions, another life with its own issues, and not what the issues
seem to you to be, not how they seem to be other-than yours.
Levinas is right about this. But this does not mean that you are not
connected. The other person is already inherent in your bodily
carrying forward of your situation. How you are a self remains
mysterious; how you are the other people and the things is obvious.
The reality of the other person who keeps me company is not based
on "same" or "other." Implicit intricacy gets past the old notions.
Another person keeps me the most company when we touch or look
at each other silently and implicitly. Each of us is a thick implicit
process. If we relate to each other from there, then we can be very
close with very little content shared. Or, we can share a lot but the
company is thick only if we relate from there. Of course another
person may not choose to interact from the implicit level. Then we
are at a distance. Even so I can relate to that implicit level, since it is
there.
From this philosophy of the implicit have come two practices. Yes,
philosophy now comes with practices, just as philosophy did in
ancient times. What is now called "Focusing" consists of simple steps
to attend in the body where the implying can come. We have a lot of
phenomenology on how this is done. Focusing is useful in many ways,
and has now generated a world-wide network of trained teachers and
focusing partners. Focusing is often done alone, but is also practiced
regularly with a listening partner. One need not understand the
philosophy to do this practice. It enables one to find and enter the
intricacy.
In your professional field or in your life, what do you 'know' and cannot yet
say, that wants to be said?
NOTES
[1] "The Responsive Order: A New Empiricism," Man and World 30/3
(1997): 383-411.
[2] Experiencing and the Creation of Meaning (New York: Free Press,
Macmillan, 1962); 2nd paperback edition (Evanston: Northwestern
University Press, 1997).
[3] See www.focusing.org for an overview of the research. Twenty-seven
successive studies have shown that higher levels on the Experiencing
Scale (applied to the tape-recorded interviews) correlate with more
successful outcome in therapy. The philosophy has led to wide
applications in psychotherapy and other fields.
[4] "Reply to Mohanty," in Language Beyond Postmodernism: Saying and
Thinking in Gendlin's Philosophy, ed. David M. Levin (Evanston:
Northwestern University Press, 1997). See also "Crossing and
Dipping: Some Terms for Approaching the Interface Between Natural
Understanding and Logical Formation," Minds and Machines 5/4
(1995): 547-560; and "Thinking Beyond Patterns: Body, Language
and Situations, in "The Presence of Feeling in Thought, ed. B. den
Ouden and M. Moen (New York: Peter Lang, 1992), pp. 25-151, also
at www.focusing.org.
[5] For the new time model, see A Process Model, IV, V (available
at www.focusing.org,[Page 151]printed from Focusing Institute,
1997), here, IVB.
[6] Much of the philosophy is available at www.focusing.org, click
philosophy.
[7] Edmund Husserl, Ideen I and II (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1950 and
1952), Ideen I, para 3.
[8] "Introduction to Thinking At The Edge" (TAE), The Focusing Folio, 2004.
[9] Dan Zahavi, Self-Awareness and Alterity (Evanston: Northwestern
University Press, Evanston, 1999).
[10] "If someone has a pain in his hand . . . one does not comfort the hand,
but the sufferer: One looks into his face" (Philosophical
Investigations 286). See also my "What Happens When Wittgenstein
Asks: 'What Happens When ...?"' in "Zur Sprache Kommen: Die
Ordnung und das Offene nach Wittgenstein," [conference paper,
University of Potsdam, 1996] Philosophical Forum 28/3 (1997), also
at www.focusing.org.
[11] Pierre Vermersch, Carbondale Conference, Southern Illinois University,
2001.
[12] See the power of patterns, derived in A Process Model, VIIA.
[13] See First-Person Science, www.focusing.org.
Note to Readers: