Jungsmetaphysics
Jungsmetaphysics
net/publication/239793879
Jung's Metaphysics
CITATIONS READS
17 2,944
1 author:
Jon Mills
The Adler Consortium
71 PUBLICATIONS 779 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
All content following this page was uploaded by Jon Mills on 04 December 2016.
Jung's metaphysics
a
Jon Mills
a
Adler Graduate Professional School, Toronto, Ontario, Canada
Version of record first published: 10 Apr 2012.
To cite this article: Jon Mills (2012): Jung's metaphysics, International Journal of Jungian Studies,
DOI:10.1080/19409052.2012.671182
This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any
substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing,
systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden.
The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation
that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any
instructions, formulae, and drug doses should be independently verified with primary
sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings,
demand, or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or
indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.
International Journal of Jungian Studies
2012, 125, iFirst article
Jung’s metaphysics
Jon Mills*
Despite it being the focal point of his theoretical system, I argue that Jung’s
notion of the archetypes is one of his least understood concepts because it
was nebulous to Jung himself. Jung vacillated between viewing archetypes as
analogous to primordial images and ideas inherited from our ancestral past,
formal a priori categories of mind, cosmic projections, emotional and valuational
agencies, and numinous mystical experience, but the question remains whether
a ‘suprapersonal’ or ‘transubjective’ psyche exists. In what follows, I will be pre-
occupied with tracing the theoretical development of Jung’s thesis on
the collective unconscious, with a special emphasis on the archetypes, and hence
pointing out the metaphysical implications of his thought. It is not possible
to critique his entire body of work in the context of this abbreviated article;
therefore, the reader should be aware that I am limiting myself to a narrow scope
of interest in explicating and analyzing the philosophical viability of his major
concepts. The greater question is whether the archetypes adequately answer to the
question of origins, of an omnipresent and eternal dimension to the nature and
structure of psychic reality.
Keywords: Jung; metaphysics; collective unconscious; archetypes; transcendence
C.G. Jung is one of the most controversial figures in the history of psychoanalysis.
He was a brilliant scholar tenaciously engaged in the human sciences, comparative
religion, philosophy, cultural anthropology, mythology, theosophy, and the mystical
traditions of East and West. He was also purported to suffer from mental illness,
engaged in sexual transgressions with patients, and lived an unorthodox lifestyle for
his era. Despite having achieved notable world fame in his lifetime for his novel
theories and clinical method, including receiving eight honorary doctorates, his most
radical metaphysical theses on the nature of the transpersonal psyche still remain
murky and unsystematized.
Throughout this essay, I attempt to clarify the main theoretical postulates that
constitute Jung’s metaphysics and address to what degree they are philosophically
plausible. In so doing, I shall forgo the typical academic custom of reviewing all the
secondary literature on the subject matter and instead remain focused on what Jung
actually said in his primary texts. In this way, I will spare the reader the redundancy
of offering a banal literature review and approach Jung’s texts in a fresh manner
unencumbered by the imposition of previous interpretations that may color my
analysis of his thought.
*Email: [email protected]
At the heart of his metaphysical system of inquiry lies the premise that all
psychological processes are necessarily conditioned on innate universal structures of
subjectivity that allow for human experience to transpire, and that these processes
participate of a greater cosmic organizing principle that transcends all levels of
particularity or individuality. This is not necessarily an illegitimate claim, for many
philosophical schools have attempted to achieve coherence and explanatory breadth
in forming a conceptual unity between religion, science, and cosmology. What makes
Jung peculiar in the history of metaphysical thought is that he elevates this nexus
or coniunctio to a psychological factor that conditions all metaphysical speculations
on the nature of the universe. For Jung, the nature of reality is psychic process con-
stituted as an impersonal animating force that is superimposed on human experience
Downloaded by [T&F Internal Users], [Laura Huxley] at 00:09 17 January 2013
imply that the collective unconscious was merely a metaphor, social construction, or
linguistic signifier determined by grammatical relativism. On the contrary, he wanted
to delineate its presence as real and elevate it to the proper stature of a metaphysical
category that was operative within all human beings regardless of history, gender,
race, geography, or time. In this sense, Jung was first and foremost an ontologist
interested in defending a universal theory of mind.1
The collective unconscious, what Jung also refers to as the ‘transpersonal un-
conscious’ or ‘objective psyche’ (Jung, 1917, p. 66, fn.4), lies ‘beyond everyday reality,’
yet we are simultaneously ‘in touch with that other reality’ at all times (Kirsh, 2000,
p. 256). Joseph Henderson (1964), one of Jung’s early ‘patrons’ of the C.G. Jung
Institute in Zurich, describes the collective unconscious as ‘the part of the psyche that
Downloaded by [T&F Internal Users], [Laura Huxley] at 00:09 17 January 2013
retains and transmits the common psychological inheritance of mankind’ (p. 107).
In his translation of Jung’s ‘Psychological Commentary’ on the Bardo Thödol, or The
Tibetan Book of the Dead (1957), R.F.C. Hull characterizes the collective unconscious
as ‘the matrix of everything’ (p. xxxvi), hence lending a cosmic animating principle to
the collective psyche, what we may even compare to Plato’s chora, the womb of all
becoming. For Jung, the collective unconscious is the Encompassing, the condition
and ground of existence, the World Soul (anima mundi).2
Jung’s philosophy of the collective unconscious presupposes a psychologism
at the heart of all metaphysical processes, for, in his words, ‘metaphysical as-
sertions . . . are statements of the psyche’ (1957, p. xxxvii) ultimately rooted in the
soul’s (Seele) projections. For Jung, psychic reality and metaphysical reality are
identical:
It is the soul which, by the divine creative power inherent in it, makes the metaphysical
assertion; it posits the distinctions between metaphysical entities. Not only is it the
condition of all metaphysical reality, it is that reality. (ibid., p. xxxviii)
Here Jung joins the ranks of the great German Idealists who view reality as the
product of mind. But he could also be accused of espousing a crass idealism, where
the psyche is believed to think the world into existence. I do not believe Jung makes
this explicit statement anywhere in his Collected Works; however, he does not want to
bifurcate nature from psyche, namely, that which is given, thrown, or predetermined,
and hence psyche and reality are ontologically conjoined.
Throughout his body of writings, Jung refers to the collective unconscious as
comprising both the drives or instincts (Triebe) and the archetypes or primordial
images (1919, pp. 133134, 138), which he equates with a ‘supra-individual psychic
activity’ (1927, p. 148) conditioned by our ancestral heritage and belonging to ‘a
timeless and universal psyche’ (ibid., p. 152). Jung goes so far to say that ‘the whole
of mythology could be taken as a sort of projection of the collective unconscious’
(ibid., p. 152), raising the question and problematic of whether it is an agency in its
own right, what the editors of his Collected Works attribute to an ‘unconscious
entity’ (1919, p. 133, fn.7). This conclusion imports many philosophical conundrums
including: how could separate agencies interact; how could different psychic org-
anizations and productions participate of one another when by definition they would
have incompatible essences; and what or who is the agent or process responsible
for orchestrating psychic activity to begin with? Jung’s whole thesis could be easily
(mis)interpreted to mean that there is an absolute mind, primary source, principle of
the ultimate, or cosmic deity underlying all facets of the universe.
4 Jon Mills
I must content myself with the hypothesis of an omnipresent, but differentiated, psychic
structure which is inherited and which necessarily gives a certain form and direction to
all experience . . . . The archetypes, as organs of the psyche, are dynamic, instinctual
complexes which determine psychic life to an extraordinary degree. That is why I also
call them dominants of the unconscious. The layer of unconscious psyche which is made
up of these universal dynamic forms I have termed the collective unconscious. (Jung,
1957, p. xlv)
The collective unconscious comprises in itself the psychic life of our ancestors right back
to the earliest beginnings. It is the matrix of all conscious psychic occurrences, and hence
it exerts an influence that compromises the freedom of consciousness in the highest
degree (1912, p. 112).
Jung reiterates the notion that the collective psyche is ‘the deposit of all human
experience right back to its remotest beginnings . . . a living system of reactions and
aptitudes that determine the individual’s life in invisible ways’ (1927, p. 157). Here
the collective unconscious is not just confined to primordial images, which are
Downloaded by [T&F Internal Users], [Laura Huxley] at 00:09 17 January 2013
This assessment is not without inherent difficulty, for it leads to several corollary
problems. For one, we need to explain how these processes or mechanisms actually
operate. Even if we come to an agreement about what constitutes human experi-
ence, we need to explicate how a primordial phenomenon was originally retained
within the primitive mind and why it manifests now. How is archaic experience
memorialized? How is it transmitted? It is not enough simply to offer a hypothesis
that these things just happened that way and are currently operative on our present-
day psyches, for we need to theoretically work out all the details in order to avoid an
unsophisticated folk psychology. Perhaps we can justify in some rudimentary fashion
how the earliest experiences of primitive man were genetically encoded and modified
through biological transmutations over time, as this would apply to any organic
developmental, evolutionary process effective within other species. Along these
lines, do we wish to equate prehistoric experience with phylogenetic memories? If
6 Jon Mills
philosophers, cosmologists and physicists we must readily admit the difficulty that
lies before us when positing a suprapersonal entity or Cosmic Being responsible for
all aspects of our mental life.
Here I am concerned with delineating the problem. Of course I cannot offer a
definitive answer of my own, for I am unable to resolve it. But we must attempt to
offer some modicum of an explanation despite it being inherently delinquent or
unsatisfactory. Can we escape the intrinsic mystery of these paradoxes? Can we
broach a plausible hypothesis that lends some sensibility to our dilemma? I am
doubtful, but with a trickle of hope.
If the via mystica leads us to the conclusion that there is a suprapersonal cosmic
mind underlying all productions of psychic life, then Jung’s theories will always
generate incredulity. However, if we ground the transpersonal within a model of
natural psychology, the metaphysical quandaries I am highlighting become less
problematic because they are relegated to the domain of phenomenology rather than
ontology.3 Jung concedes to the limits of reason alone, and hence must resort to the
life of experience, and particularly affect. If the collective unconscious answers to
spiritual questions based on unitive thinking, then they have metaphorical and
phenomenal value. But if mystical moments lead to ontological claims independent
of scientific evidence or logical reason, then they open themselves up to being judged
based on wish fulfillment, emotional prejudice, or subjective intuition imbued with
idiosyncratic meaning. While subjective and objective elements of lived psychic
reality exist simultaneously, we cannot escape the indubitable psychologism that
ultimately grounds Jung’s metaphysics. Whether this psychologism can be extra-
polated to a supernatural metaphysical entity that governs the psyche of all living
individuals is yet another issue.
Here Jung emphasizes imagination and imago and, with his reference to Augustine,
relocates the image within the original form in which it emanates. His lifelong
preoccupation with the medievalists also finds its origin in Plato, where spirit and
imago participate. Jung was attracted to Plato’s notion of forms and Kant’s logical
Downloaded by [T&F Internal Users], [Laura Huxley] at 00:09 17 January 2013
categories, which condition our experiences of both the sensible world and our
conceptual capacity for understanding, because each model serves as a conceptual
scheme on which all experience is based and constructed. In other words, the forms
and the categories become the a priori ground that conditions all experience.
Therefore, form becomes the basic constituent of an archetype.
Jung’s first usage of the term archetype (Archetypus) appears in ‘Instinct and
the Unconscious’ (1919). His previous references to the ‘primordial image’ (Urbild)
are now used almost interchangeably with the word archetype, which the editors of
his Collected Works refer to as ‘an essentially unconscious entity’ (ibid., p. 133, fn.7).
But Jung does not make this claim here explicitly, so it is misleading to refer to the
archetypes as entities, because this implies they have an ontological status apart from
the experiential person. What Jung does say is the following:
We also find in the unconscious qualities that are not individually acquired but are
inherited, e.g., instincts as impulses to carry out actions from necessity, without
conscious motivation. In this ‘deeper’ stratum we also find the a priori, inborn forms of
‘intuition,’ namely the archetypes of perception and apprehension, which are the
necessary a priori determinants of all psychic processes. (ibid., p. 133)
Here Jung refers almost verbatim to Kant’s (1781) intuitive forms of sensibility
(that inform the perceptual apparatus) and the categories for understanding the
sensible world as outlined in his Critique of Pure Reason.4 Jung says they
are necessary, universal and underlie all psychic activity of the mind. Furthermore,
the archetypes ‘force’ themselves on human perception and ‘into specifically human
patterns’ ibid., p.133). He continues to delineate that the instincts and archetypes are
distinct, but together they form the content of the collective unconscious.
Drawing on his historical precursors, from the ancients to scholasticism, modern
philosophy and German idealism, Jung emphasizes how archetypes are ‘natural
images engraved’ on the human psyche that took the form of ‘ideas’ in a Platonic
sense (1947, p. 136). He also equates them with the most ancient of universal
‘‘‘thought-forms’’ of humanity’ which have their own ‘independent life’ (1917, p. 66).
These primordial images are essentially autonomous mental templates that ‘deter-
mine the form and direction of instinct’ (1919, p. 137). Here Jung introduces a causal
impetus as archetype determines how drives will be enacted. He furthermore implies
in this original essay (‘Instinct and the Unconscious’) that archetypes are a type
of perceiving agency, like an ego. In his words: ‘Archetypes are typical modes of
apprehension, and whenever we meet with uniform and regularly recurring modes of
apprehension we are dealing with an archetype’ (ibid., pp. 137138, italics in original).
International Journal of Jungian Studies 9
This suggests that archetypes have an organizational and agentic structure all of
their own. I will return to this notion shortly, but for now, let us continue to examine
the chronological nature of Jung’s thought.
the archetypes, which are pre-existent to consciousness and condition it, appear in the
part they actually play in reality . . . As an attribute of instinct they partake of its
dynamic nature, and consequently possess a specific energy which causes or compels
definite modes of behavior or impulses. (1961, p. 347)
person, themes or motifs represented in the subject’s consciousness still reveal basic
patterns. Jung refers to these as aboriginal shapes or patterns of mind that are both
biological and transpersonal, belonging to the ‘prehistoric and unconscious de-
velopment of the mind in archaic man, whose psyche was still close to that of the
animal . . . . This immensely old psyche forms the basis of our mind’ (Jung, 1964,
p. 67). This is an ontological assertion, but he draws on an evolutionary argument
to support the primacy of archetypes by claiming they are instinctive processes
analogous to those of birds which are hardwired to build nests. Put laconically,
we have evolutionarily developed our minds in this fashion, and have a mental
apparatus that perceives phenomena and structures our personal experience of
reality in this manner.
Downloaded by [T&F Internal Users], [Laura Huxley] at 00:09 17 January 2013
Patterns of Behavior
If instinct, form, image, affect and fantasy are not enough defining attributes, Jung
includes ‘patterns of behavior’ (1947, p. 200) as another characteristic inhering in an
archetype. Here instinct and archetype are conjoined, hence deviating from his
original conception that the collective contained both the instincts and the
archetypes. He states:
There are, in fact, no amorphous instincts, as every instinct bears in itself the pattern of
its situation. Always it fulfills an image, and the image has fixed qualities: . . . it cannot
exist without its total pattern, without its image. Such an image is an a priori type . . . .
We may say that the image represents the meaning of the instinct. (1947, p. 201)
Jung speaks from a position of ex cathedra; however, his arguments are convoluted.
Here he deviates radically from Freud’s (1915) definition of Trieb. Jung makes
instinct formless (viz. ‘amorphous’) yet patterned itself a contradiction and
furthermore with the properties of images with ‘fixed qualities’ that are given a
priori, namely, as innate or inborn. This is a radical proposition. Archetypes now
have fixed qualities of images that are instinctually reproduced through patterned
forms of thought, feeling, fantasy, and behavior. What this logically entails is that
we are programmed to reproduce images and behavioral acts that were originally
conditioned by early man and inherited through gradual evolution. That claim is not
necessarily controversial in itself; but what is controversial is the notion that ‘images’
are reproduced from a fund of archaic re-presentations belonging to the ‘collective’.
This intimates a Lamarckian view of a fund of inherent phylogenetic memories
within mind. Moreover, they are ‘fixed’ not malleable; hence they are predetermined
rather than determinate. Here the collective is portrayed as more of a supernatural
mysterium.
Jung furthermore says that the image conveys ‘the meaning of the instinct.’ This
statement can be interpreted as meaning that drives have intentional states expressed
through imagos, but I believe Jung is referring to the notion that they have a purpose
or function for the psyche. He equivocates in separating instinct from archetype,
equating behavior to instinct and image to archetype, yet he also says that the
archetypes ‘act like the instincts’; and he would not ‘refute this possibility’ of their
‘identical’ nature (1947, p. 205).
Jung is attempting to use the hypothesis of archetypes as a heuristic connection
to explain and mediate all aspects of psychic life. By incorporating instinct within
12 Jon Mills
naturally present themselves as ideas and images’ (ibid., p. 227). Like Freudian drive
theory, in principle, the archetype cannot be directly known, for it appears as
modified content and is ‘irrepresentable’ in itself (ibid., p. 214). In this case, only
images, ideas, and so forth are known or experienced as the transmogrification of its
emanating source. But Jung goes on to refute this identity thesis between instinct
and archetype, for he says that: ‘Archetype and instinct are the most polar opposites
imaginable’ because archetype is tantamount to ‘spirit’ or the psychical, while
instinct is tantamount to bodily urge or impulse; yet they have ‘so close a bond’ they
are dialectically inseparable (ibid., p. 206). This is Jung’s attempt to explain the mind/
body problem, yet it reveals the pole of his tacit dualism. Archetype becomes the
ontological bridge to mind and body. But as we will shortly see, he ultimately makes
that bridge a purely psychic process.
Now that Jung has captured the breadth of human psychology within his
metaphysical system, he seeks to offer an integrative paradigm that amplifies his pre-
vious emphasis on imago, fantasy, and affect. He does this by evoking the spiritual
within the aesthetic and emotional life of the collective human subject. Here enters
the numinous.
Archetype as Numinosity
By the time Jung wrote ‘On the Nature of the Psyche’ (1947), the concept of
the archetype had undergone more emendations. This is when Jung introduces
the notion of the archetype as numen. Drawing on medieval astrology and the
alchemists, particularly Paracelsus, he compares the collective archetypes ‘in all their
luminosity and numinosity’ to ‘cosmic projection’ (ibid., p. 195) reflective of a World
Soul: ‘The world-soul is a natural force which is responsible for all the phenomena of
life and the psyche’ (ibid., p. 196). Although Jung is only making comparisons, he is
suggesting that his notion of the archetypes signifies the same phenomena.
Merkur (1996), interpreting Rudolf Otto (1932), describes the sensus numinous as
a category of values that inspires majestic awe and splendor, which at the same time
is clouded in mystery imbued with an emotional sense of urgency. This phenomen-
ological amalgamation of psychic experience nicely captures Jung’s notion of an
archetype. But Jung also takes some supernatural leaps of faith in attributing
spiritual and magical properties to the archetypes:
The archetypes have, when they appear, a distinctly numinous character which can only
be described as ‘spiritual,’ if ‘magical’ is too strong a word . . . . It not infrequently
happens that the archetype appears in the form of a spirit in dreams or fantasy-
International Journal of Jungian Studies 13
products, or even comports itself like a ghost. There is a mystical aura about its
numinosity, and it has a corresponding effect upon the emotions. (1947, pp. 205206)
ethereal realm. Yet it is only poetically suggestive. But when Jung uses language
such as ‘beyond the psychic sphere’, he is clearly evoking transpersonalism.
More specifically, he is referring to the Transcendent, that which lies beyond the
faculties of mind.
The psychoid function is also intimately connected to Jung’s thesis on
synchronicity, which is a highly transpersonal phenomenon. Synchronized moments
suspend the phenomenology of spacetime, hence producing numinous affects that
raise the conscious experience of objects to a ‘supernormal degree of luminosity’
(1952, p. 436) due to the intervening elements of the psychoid function. The
synchronicity principle allows for the experiential relativity of ‘causeless order’,
which is marked by simultaneity and meaningful correspondence of events, what
Downloaded by [T&F Internal Users], [Laura Huxley] at 00:09 17 January 2013
They are, at the same time, as both images and emotions. One can speak of an archetype
only when these two aspects are simultaneous. When there is merely the image, then
there is simply a word-picture of little consequence. But by being charged with emotion,
the image gains numinosity (or psychic energy); it becomes dynamic, and consequences
of some kind must flow from it. (p. 96)
through a Jungian lens that translates the language of psychology into ontology;
however, we must take him at face value. Jung makes psychic processes the founda-
tion of all human experience, possessing a transpersonal character, and this by
definition is a metaphysical treatise of mind. It is untenable to separate phe-
nomenological psychology from metaphysics because in making any inquiry or
assertion about experience and reality, the two are ontologically conjoined and
mutually infer each other. Drawing on what he actually says in his written texts, my
conclusion is that Jung believed that the Collective Psyche is real and exists
independently of any individual. This is an ontological claim that surpasses any
methodological agnosticism, phenomenology, or naturalized psychology.
Jung makes contradictory statements throughout his theoretical corpus, at times
averring scientific empiricism, philosophical rationalism and dialectical logic, yet at
the same time he differentiates mind from matter, only then to suggest that matter
is an emergent property of spirit, thus pointing toward a transubjective reality.
Vacillating between viewing an archetype as an inborn idea and the possibility or
potentiality for ideation wed with personal experience, his obscurantism is further
evinced when he says on the one hand that the archetype is ‘pure, unvitiated nature’
(1947, p. 210), but on the other that it is also suprapersonal, transcendent, and
beyond the sensible world. By envisioning the collective psyche as a reservoir of
abstract objects inherent to cosmic process, Jung theoretically evokes a super-
naturalism and aligns with disciplines sympathetic to mysticism, shamanism and
theology.
Jung is very clear in stating that archetypes have a ‘nonpsychic aspect’ or
counterpart to the cosmos connected through synchronicity, or the transcendent
‘psychoid’ function that supposedly mediates the ‘space-time continuum.’ Here he
implies that the collective unconscious is a ‘supernatural faculty’ (ibid., p. 231) full of
psychic dispositions. But how can this be? How does such a faculty exist? How are
psychic forms and contents dispersed into the singular minds of individuals? Why do
they materialize to begin with? How can they be omnipresent and eternal if they
are only capable of being apprehended by finite subjectivity?
Are these aporiai adequately resolved if we translate Jung’s language into the
present-day equivalent of biological heredity, such as genetic attributes inscribed
within DNA? Yet how could images and ideas be encoded and transmitted geneti-
cally when you need to have conscious experience and perception in order to
internalize, memorialize and re-present those images in the mind? Jung wants to fall
back on a priori formalism to explain this conundrum, and in this sense he is no
different from the idealists to certain linguists who endeavor to delineate the formal
structural origins of subjectivity that make conscious experience possible. But when
International Journal of Jungian Studies 17
In the beginning God created one world (unus mundus), . . . the original non-
differentiated unity of the world or of Being, . . . the primordial unconsciousness. While
the concept of the unus mundus is a metaphysical speculation, the unconscious can be
indirectly experienced via its manifestations. (ibid., p. 462)
conjunctions that are generated from this form of philosophy. For example, the
mandala symbolizes the One, which he attributes to ‘the ultimate unity of all
archetypes as well as of the multiplicity of the phenomenal world, and is therefore the
empirical equivalent of the metaphysical concept of a unus mundus’ (ibid., p. 463),
with synchronicity being its ‘parapsychological equivalent’.
What I believe Jung wants to secure is an empirical basis for a justified psycho-
analytic metaphysics grounded through phenomenological psychology. For example,
he explains that ‘insofar as the archetypes act upon me, they are real and actual
to me, even though I do not know what their real nature is’ (1961, p. 352). Here he
uses his subjective felt experience to avouch an ontological commitment despite
conceding to the epistemological limits of his capacities to know. By focusing on the
Downloaded by [T&F Internal Users], [Laura Huxley] at 00:09 17 January 2013
for the numinous phenomena that the experiential subject encounters. He further-
more attributes this numinosity to the ‘psychoid aura that surrounds conscious-
ness’ (1955, p. 551), a concept that remains nebulous and ill-defined, something of a
mysterium coniunctionis in itself. But what Jung is clear about is that ‘when we talk of
God or gods we are speaking of debatable images from the psychoid realm. The
existence of a transcendental reality is indeed evident in itself’ (ibid., p. 551). Here I
interpret Jung as first acknowledging the agnosticism of the origin of the image,
which is dubious, yet it is mediated through some unarticulated transcendental
faculty that gives it organizational clarity, order, and meaning. At best we can
attribute this function to fantasy. But Jung makes this a ‘transcendental reality.’ He
goes on to say:
That the world inside and outside ourselves rests on a transcendental background is as
certain as our own existence, but it is equally certain that the direct perception of the
archetypal world inside us is just as doubtfully correct as that of the physical world
outside us’ (ibid., p. 551).
the cosmos rather than a psychic faculty that allows for experience to materialize,
such as Kant’s categories, Fichte’s principles (Grundsät) as transcendental acts of
mind, or Hegel’s dialectic (Aufhebung). In this way, Jung deviates from primordial
form and gives archetypes a transpersonal organizational ontology that conditions
the quality of experience for individuals and cultures, and hence he elevates the
archetype to a majestic or divine provenance.
Is Jung committing a genetic fallacy? Does he presuppose that all internal
experiences and contents can be traced back to their most basal roots, which are
held to be the causal determinants of all present experiences that furthermore retain
their original attributes and properties, constituted long ago? Is he drawing an
inappropriate conclusion that the reconstructed trace or path back to origins
Downloaded by [T&F Internal Users], [Laura Huxley] at 00:09 17 January 2013
presumes that present experience contains the same properties as it may have held at
one time in the archaic past? When Jung says that psychic energy ‘follows its own
gradient down into the depths of the unconscious, and there activates what has lain
slumbering from the beginning’ (1917, pp. 6667), he is presuming that prehistoric
mind would be preserved in its original manner. This assumes that psychic contents
would not undergo transmogrification and, like an artefact, can be unearthed and
discovered as they once existed. But this notion is highly suspicious. Because we
do not have direct access to things in themselves, especially the mental contents
of primitive man; we can only speculate, interpret and creatively construct meaning
based on our plausible inferences. We make reasonable comparisons between
particulars and universals, but are we philosophically justified to equate the concrete
present with the abstract past as being identical in composition? To assume that these
ancient forces and contents would be perfectly preserved within an archaic
transpersonal psyche and transmitted in any form seems to imply that everything
is a reproduction from an antecedent stage in the history of the human race rather
than the cognitive modification of one’s own personal life history that is mistaken for
prehistory.
Critics pose the question: Do we need the collective unconscious hypothesis
to explain archetypal phenomena? For example, it may be argued that human
experience becomes memorialized as communal knowledge that gives rise to social
practices, symbols, rituals and linguistic orders that inform cultural anthropology,
and that these historical remembrances become transgenerationally and transcultu-
rally transmitted over the millennia. You do not need to appeal to a collective
transcendent psyche to explain these universal phenomena save only in the formal
sense that there must be a collection of individual subjects that form the greater
collective consciousness that is part of our objective social existence. Appealing to
a supernatural entity that becomes the ontological ground for human experience is
unnecessary and introduces a whole host of philosophical conundrums.
As Dan Merkur points out,7 one could object to the use of my term ‘super-
natural’ because this presupposes an inherent duality between nature and spirit or
psyche. Jung’s unique brand of Naturphilosophie is indeed an attempt to dialectically
bridge that dichotomy; however, he does not conceptualize the natural as meta-
physical. Rather, he makes the archetypal collective something that stands above or
beyond the mere natural as Transcendent; hence he reinstates oppositionality and
difference despite their underlying monistic order. Although psyche is naturalized, it
is Something More than its corporeal embodiment. When Jung introduces the notion
of synchronicity, the archetype now fully acquires the status of an independent being
that simultaneously is experienced within the psyche, but it still lies beyond
International Journal of Jungian Studies 21
individual agency. Although archetypes are the locus classicus, synchronicty becomes
the causus belli. For example, Jung wants to reclaim the spiritual function of what
religion has typically addressed under the guise of the supernatural by making it
an aspect of the psyche. Here religion itself becomes transformed into ontological
psychology as a naturalized psychic system, but this system is ultimately informed by
a suprapersonal netherworld.
Jung would likely challenge this by replying that although images, symbols,
ritualistic behaviors and so forth developed throughout the slow progression of
human civilization, they could not have been simply transmitted cross-generationally
or transculturally because they happen everywhere in every society. Cultures that
were geographically and temporally segregated from one another, and hence had no
Downloaded by [T&F Internal Users], [Laura Huxley] at 00:09 17 January 2013
communication with each other whatsoever on the human history timeline, never-
theless experienced psychic phenomena that were universal to all people at all times
and places, personified by primordial images. But images are ubiquitous and
empirical. There is nothing supernatural or mystical about them in themselves, for
they are common to all of us. This is part of our natural thrownness, namely, that
which is given. There is no magic to them, because this is how we perceive and think
as human beings. They are simply part of our a priori nature, not a supernatural
agency. Common experiences happen throughout the world regardless of culture,
time and history. An emotion is a specific affective experience regardless of who is
having it, or when and where. Could it be plausible that instead of summoning a
magical sea of transcendent objects derived from an anthropic psyche, we may more
humbly conceive of archetypes as psychic contents derived from internalized
personal experience of images embedded within our culture and the environs that
penetrate our minds from birth onward?
Jung’s doctrine of the archetypes becomes an all-encompassing psychic category
that potentially explains every facet of human psychology. Whether Jung is suc-
cessful in achieving this goal is disputable. Jung has been accused of espousing
and living his life based on a psychomythology as a substitute for religion (Wehr,
1985). Is the belief in an archetypal collective merely a fiction or illusion, an exalted
anthropomorphic projection, or perhaps a deposit from omnipotent infantile fanta-
sies still clamouring for wish fulfillment? We have good reason to suspect that Jung’s
longing for wholeness is the passion behind his philosophy, and that the sober logic
of reason or antiseptic science could not answer or fulfill the greater metaphysical
questions and spiritual quandaries we perennially face. Jung found some consolation
in the via mystica. This is his answer to the question of complexification. I think a
more generous reading of Jung, and in the spirit of his life project, is that the pursuit
of the numinosum is what brings a qualitative exuberance and existential purpose to
life that grounds our own personally created metaphysics of experience. Whether this
applies to an objectivist epistemology or to social or scientific consensus is not the
issue. We define our reality through our experience of the world mediated through
mind. In this way, Jung’s metaphysics shares intimate affinities with the Idealist
tradition of philosophy.8
One conundrum Jung perpetually faces is that he is begging the question of
human spirituality as a transcendent eternity, when it can be persuasively argued that
one does not need a transpersonal psyche or metaphysical divinity to explain the
numinous. This conclusion, of course, meets with little emotional satisfaction, for
man is a wishing animal. It is all too human to attempt to find a rational system that
fulfills our wishes, but in the end, we cannot simply dismiss our fundamental desires
22 Jon Mills
descriptor we call bliss is guaranteed to be our granting salivation. And for Jung,
God is synonymous with the unconscious.10 The truth of our pathos is that we can
never know what lies beyond.11 But what we do know is that we are all headed for a
pine box. Here our Being-toward-death becomes the primal ground (Bythos)
underlying our spiritual anxieties, perhaps even the impetus fueling our unitive
wish to return to a collective origin, what we might call home.
Notes
1. Because the term ‘metaphysics’ was such an explosive issue for Jung, and remains so today
for his apologists, it becomes important to offer an adumbrated explanation of its
philosophical usage. Metaphysics signifies Being, existence and reality, that which is. It is
often contrasted with empiricism as a scientific endeavor and phenomenology as an
experiential factor, when metaphysics subsumes these categories within a unifying
perspective that accounts for all facets of human subjectivity including the nature of
the psychological or spiritual, as well as religion as a naturalized human inquiry.
Therefore, when we speak of metaphysics, we do not need to bifurcate the empirical from
the phenomenological, for speculative propositions about psychic reality are simulta-
neously metaphysical phenomena.
2. In many ways the collective unconscious is anticipated by Hegel’s conception of Absolute
Spirit (Geist) as the sum totality or self-articulated complex holism that defines psychic
process (see Kelly, 1993; Mills, 2002). Specifically, refer to Hegel’s (1807) discussion of
‘unconscious universality’ within the context of collective spirit in the Phenomenology of
Spirit (PS §§ 460462, 474).
3. Although ontologists from Heidegger to Sartre wish to make phenomenology the ground
of Being, here I wish to retain their categorical distinction, for Jung was attempting to
highlight lived experience while privileging the greater metaphysical conditions that make
experience possible.
4. Particularly see I. Part 1, Sec. 12; Part 2, Bk 1, Sec. 3.
5. Freud’s notion of Trieb is usually interpreted as a ‘borderline concept’ between the
somatic and the psychical, which, it could be argued, Jung substituted for archetype, with
the psychoid further being an intervening animating principle that straddles the two
spheres and institutes a unifying function. This is particularly relevant to the nature of
synchronicity, where the psychoid function gathers the material world into the psychic
domain and forms a meaningful unity.
6. Hegel (1807) is concerned not only about explaining individual psychology, but also about
providing a universal, anthropological account of humankind. For Hegel, individuality is
ultimately subordinated to higher social orders constituted in society by participating in
the ethical life (Sittlichkeit) of a collective community. This participation rests on the
development of a continuous psychosocial matrix of relations that has its origin in the
family. The communal spirit and the ethical law embodied within the family of communal
consciousness arises from ‘the power of the nether world’ (PS § 462) what one might not
inappropriately call the collective unconscious. For Hegel, collective spirit ‘binds all into
International Journal of Jungian Studies 23
one, solely in the mute unconscious substance of all’ (PS § 474). This ‘unconscious
universality’ contains the ethical order as divine law as well as the ‘pathos’ of humanity,
the ‘darkness’ of the ‘underworld’ (PS § 474).
7. Personal communication (2010).
8. In his memoir, Jung (1961) expresses the idealist pole of his thinking this way: ‘Human
consciousness created objective existence and meaning, and man found his indispensable
place in the great process of being’ (p. 256).
9. John Freeman, the BBC reporter and deputy editor of the New Statesman, recorded an
interview with Jung in March 1959 that was first broadcast on the radio later that year and
afterwards as a film. Jung’s biographer, Gerhard Wehr (1985), tells us:
The interview contained the remarkable passage in which the reporter swung from
Jung’s childhood experiences and religious upbringing in the Jung family parsonage to
the present, posing the direct question of whether he believed in God now. ‘Now?’
Downloaded by [T&F Internal Users], [Laura Huxley] at 00:09 17 January 2013
Jung replied, and paused for a moment like a subject in one of his association
experiments on the hot seat. Then he admitted that it was really quite a difficult
question. And to the surprise of his listeners he added very definitely: ‘I know. I don’t
need to believe. I know.’ (p. 440)
This sentiment echoes Jung’s earlier view in ‘Spirit and Life’ where he says that ‘God is a
psychic fact of immediate experience, otherwise there would never have been any talk of
God’ (1926, p. 328).
10. ‘I prefer the term ‘‘the unconscious’’, knowing that I might equally well speak of ‘‘God’’ or
‘‘daimon’’ if I wished to express myself in mythic language. When I do use such mythic
language, I am aware that ‘‘mana’’, ‘‘daimon’’ and ‘‘God’’ are synonyms for the
unconscious’ (Jung, 1961, pp. 336337).
11. Contra Kant, who believed that there was always a firm epistemological limit to pure
reason or absolute knowing, Hegel believed that mind readily grasps the Ding un sich by
virtue of the fact that we posit it. In the act of positing, we have already breached the limit.
Here he employs an argument similar to Anselm’s ontological proof for the existence of
God; however, just because we can conceive of an idea does not mean that we can think
something into existence.
Notes on contributor
Jon Mills, Psy.D., Ph.D., is a philosopher, psychologist, and psychoanalyst. He is Professor of
Psychology & Psychoanalysis at the Adler Graduate Professional School in Toronto and runs
a mental health corporation in Ontario. He is the author of numerous works in philosophy
and psychoanalysis including Conundrums: A Critique of Contemporary Psychoanalysis;
Origins: On the Genesis of Psychic Reality; Treating Attachment Pathology; The Unconscious
Abyss: Hegel’s Anticipation of Psychoanalysis; and an existential novel, When God Wept. He
received a Gradiva Award in 2006 and 2011 for his scholarship.
References
Adams, M.V. (1997). The archetypal school. In P. Young-Eisendrath & T. Dawson (Eds.), The
Cambridge companion to Jung (pp. 101118). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Freud, S. (1915). Instincts and their vicissitudes. In The standard edition of the complete
psychological works of Sigmund Freud, vol. 14 (J. Strachey, Trans. & Gen. Ed., in
collaboration with A. Freud, assisted by A. Strachey & A. Tyson). London: Hogarth
Press, 19661995 (pp. 111140).
Hegel, G.W.F. (1807). Phenomenology of spirit (A.V. Miller, Trans., 1977). Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Henderson, J.L. (1964). Ancient myths and modern man. In C.G. Jung (Ed.), Man and his
symbols (pp. 104157). New York: Doubleday.
Hillman, J. (1975). Loose ends. Dallas: Spring Publications.
24 Jon Mills
Jung, C.G (191112). Symbols of transformation. In Collected works, vol. 5 (H. Read,
M. Fordham & G. Adler, Eds.; R.F.C. Hull, Trans.). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul;
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
_____ (1912). The significance of constitution and heredity in psychology. In Collected works,
vol. 8. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul; Princeton: Princeton University Press (pp. 107
113).
_____ (1916). The relations between the ego and the unconscious. In Collected works, vol. 7.
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul; Princeton: Princeton University Press (pp. 121241).
_____ (1917). On the psychology of the unconscious. In Collected works, vol. 7. London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul; Princeton: Princeton University Press (pp. 1119).
_____ (1919). Instinct and the unconscious. In Collected works, vol. 8. London: Routledge &
Kegan Paul; Princeton: Princeton University Press (pp. 129138).
_____ (1926). Spirit and life. In Collected works, vol. 8. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul;
Downloaded by [T&F Internal Users], [Laura Huxley] at 00:09 17 January 2013
Merkur, D. (1996). The numinous as a category of values. In The Sacred and its Scholars.
Leiden: E.J. Brill (pp. 104123).
_____ (1999). Mystical Moments and Unitive Thinking. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Mills, J. (2002). The unconscious abyss: Hegel’s anticipation of psychoanalysis. Albany, NY:
SUNY Press.
_____ (2010). Origins: On the genesis of psychic reality. Montreal: McGill-Queens University
Press.
Otto, R. (1932). The sensus numinis as the historical basis of religion. Hibbert Journal, 30,
283297, 415430.
Salman, S. (1997). The creative psyche: Jung’s major contributions. In P. Young-Eisendrath &
T. Dawson (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Jung (pp. 5270). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Samuels, A. (1997). Introduction: Jung and the post-Jungians. In P. Young-Eisendrath &
Downloaded by [T&F Internal Users], [Laura Huxley] at 00:09 17 January 2013
T. Dawson (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Jung (pp. 113). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Wehr, G. (1985). Jung: A biography. Boston, MA: Shambhala.
Whitehead, A.N. (1929). Process and reality (Corrected Edition) (D.R. Griffin &
D.W. Sherburne, Eds.). New York: Free Press, 1978.