Streminger1 v15n2
Streminger1 v15n2
Streminger1 v15n2
Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME
STUDIES’ Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.humesociety.org/hs/about/terms.html
HUME STUDIES’ Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue
of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and
you may use content in the HUME STUDIES archive only for your personal,
non-commercial use.
Each copy of any part of a HUME STUDIES transmission must contain the
same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such
transmission.
http://www.humestudies.org
Religion a Threat to Morality: An
Attempt to Throw Some New
Light on Hume’s Philosophy of
Religion*
Gerhard Streminger
This preface, however, was not printed in the words quoted above.
Instead i t was reduced by Hume to a footnote at the end of the second
volume of his History of England in a shortened and toned-down
version. Even this footnote was removed in later editions of the History
of England. But in the Dialogues Hume repeated his idea of the effect
of true religion on morality almost verbatim:
History becomes apparent: Hume argues that the clergy has a genuine
interest in setting bounds to human knowledge. He comes to this
conclusion by way of the following steps:
1. Human beings experience the contrariety of life: The sun
destroys what is fostered by the moisture of dews and rains. War may
be favourable to a nation, whom the inclemency of the seasons afflicts
with famine. Sickness and pestilence may depopulate a kingdom,
amidst the most profbe plenty ...Zn short, the conduct of events ... is ...
full of variety and uncertainty (NHR 4:314). Human beings hang in
perpetual suspense between life and death, health and sickness, plenty
and want (NHR 4:316).
2. In order to deal with this situation, human beings, unless they
are enlightened, treat the hidden, unknown causes of these events as
persons, and try to influence them in the same way as is common among
themselves. We represent them to be sensible, intelligent beings, like
mankind; actuated by love and hatred, and flexible by gifrs and
entreaties, by prayers and sacrifwes (NHR 4:335).
3. Although any of the human affections may lead us into the notion
ofinvisible, intelligentpower [hope,fear, but also gratitude] ...men are
much oftener thrown on their knees by melancholy than by theagreeable
passions. Prosperity i s easily received as our due, and few questions are
asked concerning its cause or author. Zt begets cheerfulness andactivity
and alacrity and a lively enjoyment of every social andsensual pleasure:
And during this state of mind, men have little leisure or inclination to
think of the unknown invisible regions. On the other hand, every dis-
astrous accident alarms us, and sets us on enquiries concerning the
principles whence it arose (NHR 4:318-19). Human intentions are
...
usually carried beyond the present course of things by the anxious
concern for happiness, the dread of future misery, the t e r m of death,
the thirst of revenge, the appetite for food and other necessaries (NHR
4:315-16).
4.Theclergy-atleastalarge partofit-isawareofthe fact that
the fear of the unknown is the origin of religion. In order to keep their
flock religious, no topic is more usual with all popular devines than to
display the advantages of aflictwn, in bringing men to a due sense of
religion; by subduing their confidence and sensuality, which, in times
ofprosprity, make them forgetful of a divine providence (NHR 4:319).
In the Dialogues the philosopher repeats this argument: It is allowed,
that men never have recourse to devotion so readily as when dejected
with grief or depressed with sickness. Is not this a proofi that the
religious spirit is not so nearly allied to joy as to sorrow? (D225).
Accordingly, we find the tremendous images to predominate in all
religions ... terror is the primary principle of religion, it is the passion
things, and the God of mercy, but also the God who countenances the
everlasting torments of hell.
5. Theologians and philosophers realised that a God t h a t embodies
discordant elements is no moral authority since moral authorities
behave, at least, consistently. They, therefore, tried to puriify the
popular image ofGod: (a)by deducing the existence of an all-benevolent
God from the world as i t is. Hume discusses this attempt i n Parts X
and XI of his Dialogues. The result is a negative one: EPICURUS'S old
questions areyet unanswered Is he willing toprevent evil, but not able?
then is he impotent. Is he able, but not willing? then he is malevolent. Is
he both able and willing? whence then is evil? (D198);(b) b y enlarging
and emphasizing God's positive properties. According to Hume, how-
ever, this attempt fails, since the extension of God's power and the
extension of God's benevolence conflict with each other. The reason i s
that human fear increases with the extension of God's power and
knowledge, because no secrecy is to be kept out of his reach. An
omnipotent and omniscient God is not an all-benevolent one, but rather
a new source of fear. Thus it may safely be afirmed, that popular
religions are really, in the conceptwn of their more vulgar votaries, a
species of &monism; and the higher the deity is exalted i n power and
knowledge, the lower of course is he depressed in goodness and
benevolence;whatever epithets ofpraise may be bestowed on him by his
amazed adorers (NHR 4:354). Human beings have tried to overcome
their fears by feigning a saviour God; but this God turned out to be a
demon. According to Humean standards, such a creature is no moral
authority.
I summarize this point: The God of false religion is thought to be
the source of commands and of our moral actions, According to Hume,
this God is the product of human projections. The imagination,
motivated by weakness, fear, melancholy, together with ignorance is the
truesourc[el OfSUPERSTITION, the human imagination set in motion
by Hope, pride, presumption ... together with ignomnce is the true
sourc[e] of ENTHUSLASM (Works 3:145).'* The God of false religion is
no moral authority: He either embodies discordant elements, due to the
different motivesin human nature that activate theimagination, or he
is a demon, insofar as the extension of the so-called positive properties
(knowledge, power, benevolence, presence) turn God into a new source
of fear. Nothing can be hidden from this demon's all-seeing eyes. The
God of popular religion contradicts our natural ideas of generosity,
lenity, impartiality, and justice (NHR 4:355). LUCLAN observes that a
young man, who reads the history of thegods i n HOMER or HESIOD,
and finds their factions, wars, injustice, incest, adultery, and other
immoralities so highly celebrated, is much surprised afierwards, when
hecomes into the world, toobserve thatpunishments are by law inflicted
Heaven and hell suppose two distinct species of men, the good
and the bad. But thegreatestpartof mankindfloat betwixt vice
and virtue ...Punishment, according to our conception, should
bear some proportion to the offence. Why then eternal punish-
ment for the temporary offences of so fmil a creature as man?
Can any one approve of Akxander’e mge, who intended to
exterminate a whole nation because they had seized his
famurite horse. Bucephahs? (Works 4402)
Thus, Hume did not accept the doctrine of original sin and he did
not think that human nature is depraved. In the essay “Of the Dignity
and Meanness of Human Nature” and, in particular, i n the second
Enquiry, Hume defends a very positive, almost Hutchesonian view of
human nature. He believed that he had proven that there is in human
nature a tendency to increase the happiness ... o f m u n k i n d that there
is ageneral concernfw society; that we are compelled by ... instances ...
[to] renounce the theory, which accounts for every moral sentiment by
the principle of self-love. We must adopt a more public affection, and
allow, that the interests of society are not, even on their o w n account,
entirely indifferent to w (E 218-19). Hume thought that there is a
spontaneous sympathy with the unhappy that the very aspect ofhappi-
ness, joy, prosperity, gives pleasure; that of pain, suffering, sorrow,
communicates uneasiness (E 220).A11 mankind sofar resemble thegood
principle, that, where interest or revenge or envy perverts not our
disposition, we are always inclined, from our natural philanthropy, to
give thepreference to the happiness ofsociety, and consequently to virtue
above its opposite (E227). The most impressive illustration of Hume’s
positive view of human nature is, I think, to be found in the Treatise of
Human Nature. According to orthodox Calvinisticthinking, not to help
the crew of a ship that hadruninto danger on the Sabbath was a special
sign of piety. Now, Hume writes:
have a tendency to accept the most absurd and nonsensical for two
reasons:
The first is that to believe in absurdities, improbabilities and
incredibilities opens an opportunity to triumph in one's belief. Since
those who believe in absurdities will be confronted with opposition,
even abuse; and because of this opposition they can value highly their
service to the deity. Nay, the baser the materials are, of which the
divinity is composed, the greater devotion is he likely to excite in the
breasts of his deluded votaries. They exult in their shame, and make a
merit with their deity, i n braving, for his sake, all the ridicule and
contumely of his enemies. Ten thousand Crusaders inlist themselves
under the holy banners; and even openly triumph in thoseparts of their
religion, which their adversaries regard as the most reproachful (NHR
4:346). The effect of this mechanism on the moral sentiments is fatal:
The believers become obstinate and dogmatical. Men dare not avow,
even to their own hearts, the doubts which they entertain on s w h
subjects: They make a merit of implicit faith;and disguise to themselves
their real infidelity, by the strongest asseverations and most positive
bigotry (NHR 4:348). Is it strange, when mistakes are so common, to find
every one positive and dogmatical? And that the zeal ofren rises in
proportion to the error? (NHR 4347).
The second reason why the faithful believe in absurdities i s that
they feel that ordinary moralityis just somethingnatural. Humecomes
to this conclusion by way of the following steps:
(i) It is afact that manyofthe votaries,perhapsthegreatest number,
will still seek the divine favour, not by virtue and good momls, which
alone can be acceptable to a perfect being, but either by frivolous
observances, by intemperate zeal, by mpturous extasies, or by the belief
...
of mysterious and absurd opinions. The least part ofthe Pentateuch,
consists i n precepts of morality; and we may also be assured, that that
part was always the least observed and regarded (NHR 4:357). Even if
a popular religion were found, i n which it was expressly declared, that
nothing but morality could gain the divine favour; i f an order ofpriests
were instituted to inculcate this opinion, in daily sermons, and with all
the arts ofpersuusion;yet so inveterate are the people's prejudices, that,
for want ofsomeother superstition, they would make the very attendance
on these sermons the essentials of religion, rather than place them in
virtue and good morals (NHR 4:357-8).
(ii) This phenomenon, Hume goes one, is very odd for two reasons:
(1)Nobody is so stupid, as that,judging by his natuml reason, he would
not esteem virtue and honesty the most valuable qualities, which any
person could possess. Why not ascribe the same sentiment to his deity?
(NHR 4:358); and, (2) To practice superstition is very often far more
difficult than to practice morality. It is certain, that the Rhamadan of
the TURKS, during which the poor wretches, for many &ys, often i n
the hottest months of theyear, and i n some of the hottest climates of the
world, remain without eating or drinkingfrom the rising to the setting
sun; this Rhamadan, I say. must be more severe than the practice of any
moral duty, even to the most vicious and depraved of mankind ... The
austerities of some Roman Catholics, appear more disagreeable than
meekness and benevolence. I n short, a11 virtue, when men are reconciled
to it by ever so little practice, is agreeable: All superstition is for ever
odious and burthensome (NHR 4358).
(iii)Moralityisnot amatter ofcourse, butitis anatural behaviour.
This Humean (and classical) idea is very nicely summed u p by J. C. A.
Gaskin: Moral behaviour "is not difficult or disagreeable or in any way
contrary to our nature as normal people. It is an 'interested obligation'
and we are inclined to observe it by a combination of many factors: our
participation in the feelings of others through sympathy or fellow
feeling, our concern to be well thought of in society and live at peace
with ourselves and others, our aversion to criminal punishment and
disgrace, our calculation of our own greatest happiness etc. In brief,
happiness for people and usefulness for society, are the criteria for the
morality of an action, and action in accordance with these criteria is
both in a man's best interest and in harmony with his normal per-
sonality. Morality is social, utilitarian and secular. The will of god and
the rewards and punishment of an afterlife play no part in Hume's
scheme of morals.""
(iv) Believers feel this. They know that moral behaviour is nothing,
which they have properly performed for the sake of God, or which can
peculiarly recommend [them] to the divine favour andprotection (NHR
4:359). They get into conflicts, and the consequence is that they turn to
absurdities, rites, ceremonies, etc. - not although these are absurd
and unnatural, but because they are. Since they are absurd the
believer has the certainty that they are done for God's sake.