Mathematical analysis of discontinuous points From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
"Jump point" redirects here. For the science-fiction concept, see Hyperspace.
Continuous functions are of utmost importance in mathematics, functions and applications. However, not all functions are continuous. If a function is not continuous at a limit point (also called "accumulation point" or "cluster point") of its domain, one says that it has a discontinuity there. The set of all points of discontinuity of a function may be a discrete set, a dense set, or even the entire domain of the function.
The oscillation of a function at a point quantifies these discontinuities as follows:
in a removable discontinuity, the distance that the value of the function is off by is the oscillation;
in a jump discontinuity, the size of the jump is the oscillation (assuming that the value at the point lies between these limits of the two sides);
in an essential discontinuity, oscillation measures the failure of a limit to exist.
The point is a removable discontinuity. For this kind of discontinuity:
The one-sided limit from the negative direction:
and the one-sided limit from the positive direction:
at both exist, are finite, and are equal to In other words, since the two one-sided limits exist and are equal, the limit of as approaches exists and is equal to this same value. If the actual value of is not equal to then is called a removable discontinuity. This discontinuity can be removed to make continuous at or more precisely, the function
is continuous at
The term removable discontinuity is sometimes broadened to include a removable singularity, in which the limits in both directions exist and are equal, while the function is undefined at the point [a] This use is an abuse of terminology because continuity and discontinuity of a function are concepts defined only for points in the function's domain.
Jump discontinuity
Consider the function
Then, the point is a jump discontinuity.
In this case, a single limit does not exist because the one-sided limits, and exist and are finite, but are not equal: since, the limit does not exist. Then, is called a jump discontinuity, step discontinuity, or discontinuity of the first kind. For this type of discontinuity, the function may have any value at
Essential discontinuity
For an essential discontinuity, at least one of the two one-sided limits does not exist in . (Notice that one or both one-sided limits can be ).
Consider the function
Then, the point is an essential discontinuity.
In this example, both and do not exist in , thus satisfying the condition of essential discontinuity. So is an essential discontinuity, infinite discontinuity, or discontinuity of the second kind. (This is distinct from an essential singularity, which is often used when studying functions of complex variables).
Supposing that is a function defined on an interval we will denote by the set of all discontinuities of on By we will mean the set of all such that has a removable discontinuity at Analogously by we denote the set constituted by all such that has a jump discontinuity at The set of all such that has an essential discontinuity at will be denoted by Of course then
The two following properties of the set are relevant in the literature.
The set of is an set. The set of points at which a function is continuous is always a set (see[2]).
Tom Apostol[3] follows partially the classification above by considering only removable and jump discontinuities. His objective is to study the discontinuities of monotone functions, mainly to prove Froda’s theorem. With the same purpose, Walter Rudin[4] and Karl R. Stromberg[5] study also removable and jump discontinuities by using different terminologies. However, furtherly, both authors state that is always a countable set (see[6][7]).
The term essential discontinuity has evidence of use in mathematical context as early as 1889.[8] However, the earliest use of the term alongside a mathematical definition seems to have been given in the work by John Klippert.[9] Therein, Klippert also classified essential discontinuities themselves by subdividing the set into the three following sets:
Of course Whenever is called an essential discontinuity of first kind. Any is said an essential discontinuity of second kind. Hence he enlarges the set without losing its characteristic of being countable, by stating the following:
The set is countable.
When and is a bounded function, it is well-known of the importance of the set in the regard of the Riemann integrability of In fact, Lebesgue's Theorem (also named Lebesgue-Vitali) theorem) states that is Riemann integrable on if and only if is a set with Lebesgue's measure zero.
In this theorem seems that all type of discontinuities have the same weight on the obstruction that a bounded function be Riemann integrable on Since countable sets are sets of Lebesgue's measure zero and a countable union of sets with Lebesgue's measure zero is still a set of Lebesgue's mesure zero, we are seeing now that this is not the case. In fact, the discontinuities in the set are absolutely neutral in the regard of the Riemann integrability of The main discontinuities for that purpose are the essential discontinuities of first kind and consequently the Lebesgue-Vitali theorem can be rewritten as follows:
A bounded function, is Riemann integrable on if and only if the correspondent set of all essential discontinuities of first kind of has Lebesgue's measure zero.
The case where correspond to the following well-known classical complementary situations of Riemann integrability of a bounded function :
If has right-hand limit at each point of then is Riemann integrable on (see[10])
If has left-hand limit at each point of then is Riemann integrable on
Thomae's function is discontinuous at every non-zero rational point, but continuous at every irrational point. One easily sees that those discontinuities are all removable. By the first paragraph, there does not exist a function that is continuous at every rational point, but discontinuous at every irrational point.
Consider now the ternary Cantor set and its indicator (or characteristic) function
One way to construct the Cantor set is given by where the sets are obtained by recurrence according to
In view of the discontinuities of the function let's assume a point
Therefore there exists a set used in the formulation of , which does not contain That is, belongs to one of the open intervals which were removed in the construction of This way, has a neighbourhood with no points of (In another way, the same conclusion follows taking into account that is a closed set and so its complementary with respect to is open). Therefore only assumes the value zero in some neighbourhood of Hence is continuous at
More precisely one has In fact, since is a nonwhere dense set, if then no neighbourhood of can be contained in This way, any neighbourhood of contains points of and points which are not of In terms of the function this means that both and do not exist. That is, where by as before, we denote the set of all essential discontinuities of first kind of the function Clearly
Let an open interval, let be differentiable on and let be the derivative of That is, for every .
According to Darboux's theorem, the derivative function satisfies the intermediate value property.
The function can, of course, be continuous on the interval in which case Bolzano's Theorem also applies. Recall that Bolzano's Theorem asserts that every continuous function satisfies the intermediate value property.
On the other hand, the converse is false: Darboux's Theorem does not assume to be continuous and the intermediate value property does not imply is continuous on
Darboux's Theorem does, however, have an immediate consequence on the type of discontinuities that can have. In fact, if is a point of discontinuity of , then necessarily is an essential discontinuity of .[11]
This means in particular that the following two situations cannot occur:
is a removable discontinuity of .
is a jump discontinuity of .
Furthermore, two other situations have to be excluded (see John Klippert[12]):
Observe that whenever one of the conditions (i), (ii), (iii), or (iv) is fulfilled for some one can conclude that fails to possess an antiderivative, , on the interval .
On the other hand, a new type of discontinuity with respect to any function can be introduced: an essential discontinuity, , of the function , is said to be a fundamental essential discontinuity of if
and
Therefore if is a discontinuity of a derivative function , then necessarily is a fundamental essential discontinuity of .
Notice also that when and is a bounded function, as in the assumptions of Lebesgue's Theorem, we have for all :
and
Therefore any essential discontinuity of is a fundamental one.
Removable singularity– Undefined point on a holomorphic function which can be made regular
Mathematical singularity– Point where a function, a curve or another mathematical object does not behave regularlyPages displaying short descriptions of redirect targets