Figures
Abstract
Adaptive plasticity allows organisms to cope with environmental change, thereby increasing the population’s long-term fitness. However, individual selection can only compare the fitness of individuals within each generation: if the environment changes more slowly than the generation time (i.e., a coarse-grained environment) a population will not experience selection for plasticity even if it is adaptive in the long-term. How does adaptive plasticity then evolve? One explanation is that, if competing alleles conferring different degrees of plasticity persist across multiple environments, natural selection between genetic lineages could select for adaptive plasticity (lineage selection). We show that adaptive plasticity can evolve even in the absence of such lineage selection. Instead, we propose that adaptive plasticity in coarse-grained environments evolves as a by-product of inefficient short-term natural selection: populations that rapidly evolve their phenotypes in response to selective pressures follow short-term optima, with the result that they have reduced long-term fitness across environments. Conversely, populations that accumulate limited genetic change within each environment evolve long-term adaptive plasticity even when plasticity incurs short-term costs. These results remain qualitatively similar regardless of whether we decrease the efficiency of natural selection by increasing the rate of environmental change or decreasing mutation rate, demonstrating that both factors act via the same mechanism. We demonstrate how this mechanism can be understood through the concept of learning rate. Our work shows how plastic responses that are costly in the short term, yet adaptive in the long term, can evolve as a by-product of inefficient short-term selection, without selection for plasticity at either the individual or lineage level.
Author summary
Organisms respond to different environments by changing how they act, look or function. When these responses improve the chances of survival, we call them adaptive plasticity. But observing adaptive plasticity does not prove that the response evolved because it improved survival. Being plastic is only selected for if individuals experience environmental variation, so that in slow changing environments plasticity may be selected against even if it is adaptive in the long term. Can adaptive plastic responses still evolve under these conditions? Yes. We use learning theory to describe how genetic changes accumulate when individual lifespan is shorter than the time between environmental changes, and show that adaptively plastic responses can evolve even when they are selected against. This is because adaptive plastic responses can evolve as the by-product of selection for different functions in different environments, as long as organisms retain some plasticity until the next environmental change. Our work demonstrates that evolution can reach general solutions even when each individual is only presented with a simple fraction of a more complex problem. This intuition could explain why plastic responses to past environments can be adaptive even to environments the entire lineage has never seen before.
Citation: Rago A, Kouvaris K, Uller T, Watson R (2019) How adaptive plasticity evolves when selected against. PLoS Comput Biol 15(3): e1006260. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1006260
Editor: Jessica C. Flack, Santa Fe Institute, UNITED STATES
Received: June 1, 2018; Accepted: January 18, 2019; Published: March 8, 2019
Copyright: © 2019 Rago et al. This is an open access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited.
Data Availability: All relevant data are within the paper and its Supporting Information files.
Funding: This work was supported by a research grant from the John Templeton Foundations (60501) and a Wallenberg Academy Fellowship from the Knut and Alice Wallenberg Foundations to TU. KK was supported by the DSTLX-1000074615 from Defence Science and Technology Laboratory (DSTL). The funders had no role in study design, data collection and analysis, decision to publish, or preparation of the manuscript.
Competing interests: The authors have declared that no competing interests exist.
Introduction
Organisms that live in variable environments are often subject to opposing selective pressures, either temporal or spatial, such that intermediate generalist phenotypes have decreased fitness across all environments. Rather than evolving a generalist phenotype, populations can keep adapting to each environmental condition as they encounter them, a process known as adaptive tracking [1, 2]. Populations that evolve via adaptive tracking need time to adapt to each new environment. As a result of this adaptation, the population experiences reduced fitness after each environmental change. Both populations that evolve a generalist phenotype and those that evolve by adaptive tracking thus have reduced fitness in the long term. By contrast, adaptive phenotypic plasticity allows individuals to maintain an adaptive fit between phenotype and environment: plastic individuals produce only high fitness phenotypes by responding appropriately to environmental cues. Populations evolving adaptive plasticity thus avoid both the fitness loss arising from trade-offs of generalist phenotypes and the fitness loss that tracking populations suffer after environmental change. Within this framework, the question of whether plasticity evolves can be interpreted as the comparison between the average fitness across all environments for populations which evolve plastic responses, evolve generalist phenotypes or evolve via tracking [3, 4]. As such, a considerable amount of effort has been invested in characterizing the conditions that determine the fitness of plastic rather than non-plastic solutions, and to document if plasticity itself incurs a fitness cost [5–7].
While adaptive plasticity is common in nature and demonstrably superior to non-plastic solutions for a wide range of conditions, the process by which it evolves remains a matter of debate. The standard assumption that natural selection favours the best available solution is problematic, since natural selection only discriminates between phenotypes that are expressed. Natural selection is thus unable to detect that a plastic organism is adapted to more environments than a non-plastic one unless individuals encounter multiple environments within their life spans, a condition known as environmental fine-grain [8]. Even when individuals experience more than one environment per lifetime, each individual may express only a single phenotype if plastic responses are irreversible [9–11], too slow (e.g [12]) or too costly (e.g. [5]) relative to the fitness advantage of producing the right phenotype for the current conditions [2, 7].
This creates an evolutionary dilemma: adaptive plasticity maximizes fitness in the long-term, but natural selection favours non-plastic phenotypes in each short-term environment. In other words, experiencing one environment per lifetime (environmental coarse grain) does not allow individual selection for plasticity, so that if plastic responses incur any cost compared to non-plastic phenotypes they will be selected against in the short-term. Since costly plastic responses in coarse-grained environments provide fitness benefits only when individuals are selected over multiple generations, we refer to those responses as long-term adaptive plasticity. While long-term adaptive plasticity is selected against in the short-term, adaptive responses to coarse-grained environments commonly evolve, and include environmental determination of resistance and dispersal phenotypes [13, 14] and seasonal morphs of short-lived species [9, 15].
How can we explain the process by which costly adaptive plasticity evolves in such coarse-grained environments? While individual-level selection does not favour plasticity in coarse-grained environments, alleles that determine an organism’s plasticity are transmitted between generations, and their fixation or loss will depend on their fitness across the set of environments they encounter [16, 17]. Natural selection may therefore discriminate between plastic and non-plastic alleles if both are maintained long enough to be selected across multiple environments, even if each individual organism experiences only a single environment. Plastic adaptations to coarse-grained environments could therefore evolve if multiple alleles (genetic lineages) persist long enough to be subject to natural selection across multiple generations and environments, a process known as lineage selection [4, 18, 19]. More precisely, we define lineage selection as a specific type of natural selection acting on multiple alleles which persist for multiple generations (see [20]). This is in contrast with Strong Selection and Weak Mutation regimes (SSWM) in which each new allele is either lost or fixed before more genetic variation can arise. Under SSWM genetic variation is provided only by new mutations (rather than standing genetic variation), so that repeatedly comparing multiple alleles is impossible.
The availability and persistence of standing genetic variation on plastic responses is thus a key requirement for the evolution of adaptive plasticity in coarse grained environments (e.g. [4, 17, 19]). This implies that plasticity will not evolve in populations that are small or under strong selection, since these conditions remove the genetic variation lineage selection requires to operate (e.g. [21]). Because small population size and strong selection are representative for populations experiencing rapid environmental change, evolution of plasticity appears unlikely to play a role in evolutionary rescue or successful colonization [22, 23]. The evolution of costly adaptive plasticity will only be possible if genetic diversity is available, but high genetic diversity will also cause rapid removal of costly plastic variants in favour of non-plastic short-term solutions, so that costly adaptive plasticity should only evolve as an intermediate step towards non-plastic solutions.
We apply a core concept of learning theory—learning rate—to propose an alternative mechanism for the evolution and maintenance of costly adaptive plasticity without lineage selection. In machine learning, learning rate measures the amount of change a system accumulates with each example shown. Existing literature demonstrates that the process of learning by trial and error is mechanistically analogous to evolution by natural selection [24]. In the context of adaptation, genetic learning rate measures the ability of a population to change in response to new environments by accumulating adaptive mutations. More specifically, we can define genetic learning rates as the amount of genetic change fixed by a population in each new environment. Genetic learning rate (henceforth just learning rate) depends both on the ability to generate variation (mutation rate and effect size, population size) and to fix particular variants (strength of selection). Since both the processes that produce and fix variants require time to operate, increasing the time spent in each environment will allow populations to accumulate more adaptive change. Thus, the more generations a population spends in a single environment the higher its learning rate will be.
As we show in our simulations, populations initially produce phenotypes matching their current environment by accumulating both mutations that change the mean phenotypic value and mutations that change plasticity. Populations with high learning rates find optimal phenotypes for the current environment and remove costly plasticity before each new environmental shift: When populations can quickly reach current optima in each current environment, plastic adaptations to past environments cannot evolve. Populations with low learning rates cannot reach current optima before the next environmental shift, and pass on to the next environment all genetic changes which brought them closer to the previous phenotypic optimum, whether or not these genetic changes cause phenotypes to be plastic. Selection in the new environment thus starts from a population which already accumulated adaptively plastic changes, so that the overall plastic responses can be further refined over time.
In evolutionary terms, low learning rates maintain directional selection for plastic development, with the end result of directing evolution towards the production of long-term adaptive plastic responses. Unlike the lineage selection explanation, the learning theory explanation does not require the prolonged co-existence of alleles with different effects on plasticity: adaptive plastic responses will evolve even in populations which exhibit only a single reaction norm at any given time. Rather, learning theory only requires that the population accumulates limited genetic change per environment, so that the average genotype retains some of the adaptive plasticity accumulated in past environments. Learning theory thus predicts that, as long as natural selection is inefficient in bringing about genetic change, long-term adaptive plasticity should evolve even in the extreme case when only one lineage is present in the population at any given time (strong selection weak mutation) and plasticity is selected against in each current environment.
In this paper, we provide a first exploration of the evolution of adaptive plasticity from a learning theory perspective. To do so, we employ a classic linear reaction norm model [25, 26] to simulate the evolution of costly adaptive plasticity in temporally coarse-grained scenarios. This allows us to contrast the predictions made by learning theory and lineage selection regarding when and how plasticity should evolve. First, we demonstrate that plasticity can evolve in coarse-grained environments, showing that individual-level selection for plasticity is not necessary to evolve adaptive plasticity. Second, we demonstrate that adaptive plasticity evolves in coarse-grained environments even in the absence of multiple lineages, counter to the predictions of lineage selection. Third, we show that limiting mutation rates biases populations towards adaptive plasticity rather than adaptive tracking, in accordance with the predictions of learning theory. These results reveal that long-term adaptations can evolve even when each current environment selects against them, as long as natural selection is inefficient.
Results and discussion
Simulation set-up
We simulate a population that experiences temporal environmental heterogeneity. Each individual receives information from the environment and develops into an adult phenotype, upon which selection can act. We follow standard approaches for the evolution of plasticity [18, 27, 28] and model development as a linear reaction norm, whose intercept a represents the mean genetic trait value across environments (also known as G, e.g. [17]) and slope b the degree of plasticity, or genotype by environment interaction (GxE, see Reaction norm model). The developed phenotype P is thus where C is the univariate environmental cue.
We model a heterogeneous varying environment with 10 environmental states, so that each environmental state, Ei produces a single, unique value of the cue and requires a single specific univariate phenotype . We model the matching between cues and trait optima as a linear function (see Environmental variability). This implies that a linear reaction norm with appropriate slope and intercept can achieve perfect fit for all environments in our set. We assume non-overlapping generations of individuals with a constant fixed lifespan. This assumption allows us to control the granularity of environmental variability with a single parameter, K. If K ≥ 1 the environment changes every K generations, indicating coarse-grained (K = 1) or slow coarse-grained (K > 1) environmental variability. If instead K < 1 the population encounters on average 1/K environments per generation, indicating fine-grained environmental variability.
We evaluate the fitness of each individual based on the distance of its developed phenotype from the optimal target phenotype in the current environment. In case the individuals experience more than one environment, we calculate their fitness as the mean match between the developed phenotypes and the selective environments experienced. We further impose a fitness penalty proportional to the individual’s responsiveness to its environment (absolute reaction norm slope b, see above). This cost of plasticity ensures that plastic individuals will have lower fitness than non-plastic ones regardless of their phenotypes, and effectively represents a trade-off incurred by plastic organisms (see Evaluation of fitness). While few empirical studies have found evidence for costs of plasticity (see Conclusion), including a cost means that plasticity is selected against, and thus serves as a form of conservative bias against plasticity. Since we measure fitness as relative to a pre-specified optimal phenotype, we express it as phenotypic mismatch or lack-of-fit: a measure which decreases quadratically from zero as the phenotype diverges from the optimum (see section Evaluation of reaction norms).
Organisms reproduce asexually with a probability proportional to their relative fitness within the population (see Evolutionary process). Every individual inherits the same slope and intercept as their parents, which are then mutated by adding a random value selected from a normal distribution with mean 0 and standard deviation equal to the mutation size (0.01 unless otherwise specified). Thus, both intercept and slope mutate every generation (effective mutation rate = 1), but most mutations have small effects. Unless otherwise stated, we set a population of 1000 individuals and choose strength of selection ω of 0.2. In addition, we set the associated cost of plasticity, λ, to be 0.1.
While we assume that the cost of plasticity is a property of the genotype, the fitness losses caused by adaptive tracking depend on both the frequency of environmental changes and the amount of time required to reach new short-term optima after each environmental change. Thus, if environmental changes are rare or if the population can quickly reach new optima, the cost of adaptive tracking can be lower than the cost of adaptive plasticity. To verify whether or not adaptive plasticity is the optimal long-term strategy, we analytically tested all parameter combinations used in our simulations (see S1 Appendix). Our analysis confirmed that the fitness cost of adaptive tracking is greater than the cost of adaptive plasticity for all parameter combinations used in this paper. Since adaptive plasticity is the optimal strategy across all our simulations, we can rule out that the eventual evolution of adaptive tracking is because of its greater long-term fitness. In other words, lineage selection should select for adaptive plasticity across all our simulations, since adaptive plasticity incurs lower fitness costs compared to adaptive tracking.
Individual-level selection is not necessary for the evolution of adaptive plasticity
In this section, we compare the evolution of plasticity in fine-grained environments, which allow individual-level selection for plasticity, with coarse-grained ones, which do not. We initially assess the evolution of phenotypic plasticity when individuals encounter multiple environmental states per life-time (i.e., a fine-grained environment; here 10, K = 0.1). We further assume that the phenotype can change during individuals’ lifespan (reversible plasticity), and this change is both immediate and incurs in no fitness costs.
In fine grained environments, the evolved reaction norms converge the optimal intercept and slope in less than 3000 generations (Fig 1A, inset). This means that individuals produce trait values that perfectly match the optimal trait value of all environmental states they encountered during their lifetime, as we can see from the fact that the distance between realised and optimal phenotypes decreases to zero for all environments in our set (Fig 1A). We find minimal residual genetic variation on both the slope and intercept terms of the reaction norm (Fig 1B). This is reflected in the limited differences between the reaction norms of top and mean performing individuals (Fig 1A). Note that the reaction of the average (yellow dots) and best individual (green dots) are perfectly aligned and match the optimal reaction norm (red crosses).
(A) Average plasticity (orange line) and lack of fit (blue line) of the population over time, relative to the optimal adaptive reaction norm, see Evaluation of reaction norms. The dashed orange line indicates optimal long-term adaptive plasticity (B) Evolved reaction norms (grey lines) compared to optimal reaction norm (dashed line) at the end of the evolutionary period. Crosses indicate optima corresponding to environmental values used in the simulation. Dots indicate the phenotypes expressed for environmental values used in the simulation. The population evolves optimal adaptive plasticity.
We contrast the previous fine-grained scenario with a slow coarse-grained environment in which conditions change every 4000 generations on average (K = 4000). As such, each individual experiences only one environment, and environmental change between generations is also slow. In this coarse-grained environment, the population fails to evolve adaptive long-term plasticity (Fig 2). After each environmental change we observe a drop in fitness to the current environment, followed by a distinctive two-step pattern in their adaptive paths. During the first phase, organisms evolve towards the new target phenotype, as indicated by the steep increase in current fitness (Fig 2A, inset, green line). Crucially, the increase in current fitness during this phase is accompanied by a corresponding increase in fitness to past environments (Fig 2A, blue line), which indicates evolution of adaptive plasticity. During this phase, mutations which increase plasticity can be selected for if they cause the production of fitter phenotypes, offsetting the cost of plasticity (see S1 Appendix). After organisms are able to produce phenotypes which match the current phenotypic optima, we observe a decrease in their fitness to past environments (Fig 2A, blue curve). This indicates that the same organisms would no longer be able to produce adaptive phenotypes when exposed to past environments, consistent with a decrease in costly adaptive plasticity. During this phase plasticity is directly selected against in order to decrease its fitness costs.
(A) Lack of fit (see Evaluation of reaction norms) in current (green lines) and past (blue lines) environments. Orange line indicates average plasticity in the population, dashed orange line optimal long-term plasticity. (B) Evolved reaction norms (grey lines) compared to optimal reaction norm (dashed line) at the end of the evolutionary period. Crosses indicate optima corresponding to environmental values used in the simulation. Dots indicate the phenotypes expressed for those values. The population re-adapts to the current environment after each environmental change (adaptive tracking).
In other words, the population reaches the optimal phenotype using a combination of slope and intercept (phenotypic adaptation) and then minimizes the slope (plasticity minimization). From a fitness perspective, selection during the phenotypic adaptation phase increases fitness by producing the current target phenotype, whereas selection in the plasticity minimization phase increases fitness by maintaining the current target phenotype while removing costly plasticity. It is worth noting that these two phases match those described in the analogous model presented in [17]. After the plasticity minimization phase we still observe some genetic variation in reaction norm slope (grey lines in Fig 2B), but the average slope is 0: adaptive plastic responses are approximately as likely as maladaptive ones. Populations evolving under slow, coarse-grained environments thus fail to evolve adaptive plasticity and instead re-adapt upon each environmental change, consistently with adaptive tracking.
Next, we test whether or not direct selection for plasticity is required for its evolution. To do so, we set the environment to change every generation (K = 1), which is the fastest rate we can set under a coarse-grain scenario: every individual experiences only a single environment, but every generation experiences a different one. Since each individual only experiences one environment, we can rule out direct selection for adaptive plasticity. Furthermore, costly plasticity is selected against within each short-term environment.
In this fast coarse-grained environment, populations evolved adaptive plasticity (Fig 3). We observe that the deviation from the optimal phenotype for both current and past environments decreased to zero, indicating optimal fit to all environments within the range experienced (Fig 3A). In addition, we observe less residual genetic variation compared to the case of slow coarse-grained environmental variability (Fig 3B). This is also indicated by the narrow gap between the top and the mean performance curve in Fig 3A.
(A) Lack of fit (see Evaluation of reaction norms) in the current (green line) and past (blue line) environments. Orange line indicates the average slope of plasticity in the population, dashed orange line indicates optimal long-term adaptive plasticity. (B) Evolved reaction norms (grey lines) compared to optimal reaction norm (dashed line) at the end of the evolutionary period. Crosses indicate optima corresponding to environmental values used in the simulation. Dots indicate the phenotypes expressed for those values. The population evolves optimal adaptive plasticity.
Looking at the evolutionary trajectory of the population, we can see that while fitness to the current environment (green line) fluctuates, fitness to the whole environment set (past environment; blue line) gradually increases over time. Moreover, we see no gap between performance in current and past environments. This indicates that increasing fitness to the current environments does not cause loss of fitness in past environments. Instead, the population accumulates responses that are adaptive for all previously experienced environments. These results demonstrate that populations evolving in fast-changing environments produce adaptive plastic responses even when plasticity is costly and environmental change only occurs between generations.
At this stage, we have merely confirmed well-known results (e.g., [17]). We now consider two explanations for the evolution of adaptive plasticity in coarse-grained environments. The standard interpretation is based on a lineage selection model, where faster environmental change will increase the odds that each allele is tested in more than one environment. Adaptive plasticity can evolve since plastic alleles have greater mean fitness than non-plastic alleles when compared across multiple environments, even though the latter have higher fitness within each current environment. The learning theory interpretation instead is based on the prediction that decreasing the number of generations in each environment will decrease the genetic change accumulated within each environment (i.e., the learning rate), ensuring that the changes accumulated during the phenotypic adaptation phase are not lost because of optimization to current environments. While both mechanisms cause a shift from short to long-term adaptation, each has distinct requirements: lineage selection relies on the transmission of genetic variants in order to compare the fitness of multiple alleles; learning theory requires that populations accumulate little genetic change in each environment, so that the system retains some information from the past. In contrast with lineage selection, learning theory does not require that past information is stored in separate lineages. Rather, past information can also be stored in developmental parameters, such as the slope of plasticity. As long as plasticity does not revert to zero, the system retains some information about past adaptive plasticity and can be progressively improved after each environmental change, regardless of the presence of trans-generational genetic variation. In the next two sections, we make use of this key difference to determine which of the two processes can better explain the evolution of plasticity in coarse environments.
Lineage selection is not necessary for the evolution of adaptive plasticity
To test the need for lineage selection, we repeat the scenarios for the evolution of plasticity in fine-grained (K = 0.1), coarse-grained (K = 1) and slow coarse-grained (K = 40000) environments enforcing strong selection and weak mutation (SSWM). Under SSWM, the speed at which mutations arise is much slower compared to the speed at which they are fixed or lost, driving standing genetic variation to zero. Comparing the fitness of alleles across different environments is therefore impossible. We model SSWM using a hill-climber algorithm: each evolutionary step produces only one mutation. If the new mutation is fitter than the previous one it is fixed, otherwise it is lost (see Hill-climbing model). SSWM leads to a constant effective population size of 1 and makes lineage selection impossible. Therefore, if the lineage selection hypothesis is correct, we expect that adaptive plasticity will fail to evolve in all coarse-grained environments. To rule out that the potential failure to evolve plasticity is due to insufficient time, we verify the results under an extended simulation time of 2*107 generations.
Contrary to the predictions of the lineage selection explanation, we find that the results from the above simulations are qualitatively and quantitatively similar to those obtained using a population size of 1000, despite the SSWM selection regime (Fig 4). That is, populations fail to evolve plasticity when environments change every 40000 generations (Fig 4A), and succeed in doing so when provided with either fine environmental grain (Fig 4B) or a rapid coarse-grained (i.e., trans-generational) change (Fig 4C).
Panels to the left show population performance (see section Evaluation of reaction norms) over time in current (green line) and past (blue line) environments. Panels to the right show the evolved reaction norm (solid line) compared to optimal reaction norm (dashed line) at the end of the evolutionary period. Crosses indicate optima corresponding to environmental values used in the simulation. Dots indicate the phenotypes expressed for those values. (A) Slow coarse-grained environments (K = 40000) (B) Fine-grained environments (K = 0.1) (C) Fast coarse-grained environments (K = 1). Performance over time and evolved reaction norms are identical to weak selection scenarios.
The evolutionary trajectory of populations under SSWM also remains remarkably similar to that of populations with standing genetic variation (compare Fig 4 with Figs 1, 2 and 3). Populations evolving in fine-grained and fast coarse-grained environments both show a gradual increase in fitness to past environments, which remains comparable to fitness in the current environment. This indicates that they adapt to all previously seen environments rather than just the current one. Populations in slow coarse-grained environments instead perform consistently better in current environments compared to past ones, showing the repeated evolution of phenotypes adapted to current conditions, or adaptive tracking. Their evolutionary trajectory also displays the same two-step cycle after each environmental change: fitness increase in both current and past environments (phenotypic adaptation) followed by fitness decrease in past environments only (plasticity minimization) (Fig 4A).
Taken together, these findings demonstrate that both the final results and the evolutionary trajectories of our simulations are largely unaffected by the lack of standing genetic variation. Since standing genetic variation is required for adaptation via lineage selection, these results falsify the hypothesis that plasticity needs to evolve by averaging the fitness benefits of alternative variants across multiple environments. In the next section, we make further predictions based on the learning theory explanation and try to falsify them.
Low mutation rates are analogous to fast environmental change
Using a learning theory framework, we can define the conditions that allow evolution in coarse-grained environments to approximate evolution in fine-grained ones. The two scenarios will produce the same outcome only as long as the average of evolutionary changes in coarse-grained environments is the same as the evolutionary changes that would happen in fine grained environments.
In our specific example, individuals selected in slow coarse-grained environments evolve non-plastic solutions after each environmental change. On average, evolutionary changes in slow coarse-grained environments decrease plasticity until it reaches zero. This is in contrast with fine-grained environments, which evolve plasticity towards the optimal adaptive slope. Since the average change in plasticity in coarse-grained environments is different from the change in plasticity under fine-grained environments, the two scenarios have different outcomes. Conversely, individuals selected in fast coarse-grained environments retain some plasticity between environments. Furthermore, on average, the change in plasticity induced by each new environment points towards optimal adaptive plasticity: inherited maladaptive plasticity will be selected against, and inherited adaptive plasticity will be conserved. Therefore, as long as plasticity does not reach zero before the environment changes, evolution in coarse-grained environments will follow the same direction as evolution in fine-grained environments. This is the reason why we expect lower learning rates to cause the evolution of adaptive plasticity in coarse-grained environments: lower learning rates ensure that the population does not find short-term, non-plastic optima before the next environmental change, which allows the averaging of plasticity across environments.
Since we define learning rates in biological systems as the amount of genetic change accumulated by the population in each new environment, they can be affected by several parameters other than rate of environmental change. Population size, mutation size and mutation frequency will all increase the amount of genetic change produced within each environment and thus increase the population’s learning rates. Stronger selective pressure will speed up the fixation of beneficial variants, and therefore also increase learning rates. If the learning rate explanation for the evolution of adaptive plasticity in coarse-grained environments is correct, these factors should be interchangeable with the rate of environmental change.
For example, small populations or populations with low mutation frequency should be able to find long-term plastic solutions even when environmental change is rare. It is important to point out that decreasing population size or mutation frequency would instead hinder the action of lineage selection, which benefits from the maintenance of a large pool of genetic variants to select from.
While a full exploration of all possible parameter space is beyond on the scope of this paper, we evaluate the learning theory explanation by testing the specific prediction that adaptively plastic responses can evolve even when environmental changes are slow, provided that mutation sizes are sufficiently small (and hence learning rate is low). This question can be answered using the same model, and in particular the case of slow coarse-grained environments (environments change every 4000 generations) with a population size of 1000 individuals. As shown above, adaptive plasticity fails to evolve under these conditions. Learning theory explains this failure with the high learning rates in this population. Rather than decreasing the learning rate by decreasing the number of generation spent in each environment, we lower the standard deviation of mutation sizes from 10−2 to 10−4.
As we can see in Fig 5B, the population eventually evolves an optimally adaptive plastic reaction norm, with negligible amounts of variation around both slope and intercept. Their evolutionary trajectories (Fig 5A) are also qualitatively similar to those of populations evolving in fast, coarse-grained environments. In both scenarios, fitness to the current environment (green) fluctuates around average fitness to past environments (blue), indicating that the populations are not evolving phenotypes that increase current fitness at the expense of past adaptation. The steady increase in average fitness to past environments instead indicates the evolution and retention of more general, plastic solutions.
(A) Lack of fit (see Evaluation of reaction norms) in current (green lines) and past (blue lines) environments. Orange lines indicate realized (solid lines) and optimal (dashed lines) adaptive plasticity. (B) Evolved reaction norms (grey lines) compared to optimal reaction norm (dashed line) at the end of the evolutionary period. Crosses indicate optima corresponding to environmental values used in the simulation. Dots indicate the phenotypes expressed for those values. The population slowly evolves optimal adaptive plasticity.
While the two trajectories are similar in shape, the population experiencing slower environmental changes and smaller mutation rates takes a significantly longer to reach optimal plasticity. An increase in the number of generations required to find solutions is a known consequence of lower learning rates. Intuitively, we can explain the longer time required to adapt as a consequence of the slower rate at which variants become available.
While lineage selection is technically viable in this simulation, decreasing mutation sizes would also decrease the amount of available genetic variation, making it even less effective. A potential alternative explanation to our findings is that the reduced amount of genetic change per generation would enable multiple lineages to persist for longer, thus enabling the action of lineage selection. To test for this alternative explanation we run a simulation with K = 40000 and σμ = 10−5 using a hill-climber to model SSWM. The results are both qualitatively and quantitatively similar to those obtained in the previous simulation (see Fig 6). Since our results are unaffected by the absence of lineages, we can rule out that the observed evolution of plasticity with smaller mutation rates is due to the longer persistence of multiple lineages. Taken together, our simulations provide falsifying evidence for a number of frequent assumptions on the requirements for the evolution of costly adaptive plasticity in coarse-grained environments, which we summarize in Table 1.
The solid orange lines indicates average population plalsticity, the dashed orange line optimal adaptive plasticity (B) Evolved reaction norms (grey lines) compared to optimal reaction norm (dashed line) at the end of the evolutionary period. Crosses indicate optima corresponding to environmental values used in the simulation. Dots indicate the phenotypes expressed for those values. The population slowly evolves optimal adaptive plasticity.
Conclusion
The evolution of costly adaptive plasticity has often been framed as a necessity caused by environmental change outpacing the ability of natural selection to generate new adaptations [2, 3, 29, 30], but the process by which organisms achieve plasticity in these conditions have seldom been clarified.
We demonstrate that neither individual nor lineage-level selection for adaptive plasticity are necessary for the evolution of adaptive plasticity. Rather, the speed of adaptation relative to environmental change (modelled as learning rates) is by itself a causal factor in the evolution of plastic responses that are adaptive across a range of coarse-grained environments. High learning rates allow optimization of phenotypes in each current environment, at the expense of more general solutions that improve their fitness across all environments experienced. Low learning rates instead make it impossible for phenotypes to chase short-term optima, yet allow individuals to reach long-term optimal plasticity despite the presence of short-term trade-offs.
If approached from a purely adaptationist perspective, these results seem counter-intuitive: the conditions which allow natural selection to work most effectively (high population sizes, high mutation rates, strong selective pressure and rare changes in the environment) result in an evolutionary outcome (adaptive tracking) which has lower fitness than adaptive plasticity across all of our simulations (see S1 Appendix). Conversely, changes in the same parameters that decrease the ability of natural selection to effectively cause phenotypic change result in an evolutionary outcome (adaptive plasticity) which maximizes fitness of the population in the long-term. We explain these counter-intuitive findings by using learning rates, a core concept of learning theory. Specifically, we demonstrate that low learning rates prevent populations from reaching short-term optima before a new environmental change occurs. This in turn allows evolved plastic reaction norms to be transferred across environments, so that they are effectively selected across multiple environments. The end result is that, as long as learning rates are sufficiently low, selection in coarse-grain environments converges on the same outcome as selection in fine-grained ones: adaptive plasticity. In learning theory terms, the cumulative effect of testing models sequentially on each individual example (online learning) will be the same as testing them on the entire set at once (batch learning) only if learning rates are low enough to prevent overfitting to the last example seen [31].
While low learning rates are necessary to evolve general solutions in the presence of trade-offs in performance, none of the factors that affect learning rates is necessary by itself. This is because learning rate is a composite measure, so any given factor may be offset by the others. We demonstrate this by showing that low mutation rate is sufficient to evolve costly adaptive plasticity even in slow, coarse-grained environments. Increasing population size and selection strength should instead decrease the odds of evolving costly adaptive plasticity, as both factors increase learning rates. As a consequence, even populations with no measurable genetic variation in plasticity could evolve adaptive plastic responses as long as (1) new genetic variation can be produced over time and (2) short-term optima change before natural selection can reduce plasticity to zero.
This observation reverses the suggested causal link between plasticity and the rate of genetic evolution. Current theory proposes that plastic individuals experience weaker selection because they are able to cope with a wider range of environments [4]. Because of the reduced selective pressure, the amount of genetic change that accumulates in the population (learning rate) is also reduced. We instead suggest a low learning rate itself may skew populations towards evolving more general solutions, including plastic responses that are costly in current conditions but optimal across the entire set of previously experienced environments. As such, weak selection could facilitate the evolution of plasticity.
Since low learning rates promote the evolution of adaptive plastic responses by reducing the relative importance of minimizing plasticity costs, they are irrelevant to the evolution of inexpensive plastic responses. When there are no costs of plasticity, every combination of slope and intercept that generates the optimal short-term phenotype is fitness equivalent within each environment. Because plastic and non-plastic solutions have the same short-term fitness, adaptive plasticity is selected for when the population moves towards the current phenotypic optimum and randomly drift after the optimal phenotype has been reached. The population will thus inevitably find the optimum for all past environments, and learning rates will only determine the speed at which the population reaches the optimum.
Learning rates are likewise irrelevant for the evolution of costly adaptive plasticity in fine-grained environments, which are sufficient (but not necessary) for the evolution of adaptive plasticity across all our simulations (see S1 Fig). Fine-grained environments allow natural selection to directly compare the fitness of phenotypes across multiple environments at the individual-level within each generation, so that adaptive plasticity is optimal even in the short-term. Direct selection for plasticity is unsurprisingly sufficient to ensure the evolution of adaptive plasticity. Under those conditions, learning rates can only determine the speed of selective process rather than its outcome.
Our simulations consider the specific case of maintenance costs for plasticity. That is, we assume that plasticity directly decreases fitness, regardless of whether it is expressed. This assumption has a long history in modelling the evolution of plastic responses, but has been largely unsupported by empirical data which does not find costs of plasticity for the vast majority of traits analysed [32, 33]. However, several alternative scenarios can create mathematically equivalent trade-offs between selection in current and past environments. A well-studied example is that of inaccurate cues, either due to imperfect perception or noise in the cues themselves [3, 22, 34]. Alternatively, the target phenotypes may not perfectly match with the best possible reaction norm. This scenario can happen for any reaction norm which is selected on a set of environments larger than its degrees of freedom (3 in the case of linear reaction norms) [35] or if there are limits to the maximum amount of plastic changes that an organism can evolve [27, 32, 33, 36]. In all of the above mentioned cases, optimal long-term plasticity would cause loss of fitness across current environments and consequently be selected against. Learning rates will thus be relevant for the evolution of plastic responses across all of them.
In our simulations, mutations that lead to adaptive plasticity are selected since they increase phenotypic fitness within current environments, eventually causing the evolution of adaptive long-term plasticity. This is in contrast with lineage selection models, in which mutations that cause adaptive plasticity are selected because of their long-term benefits, but are (at best) selectively neutral in current environments. Since the evolution of plasticity in our model is driven by a short-term (rather than lineage) selection process, we predict it to be both faster and more robust to the presence of trade-offs. Similar dynamics apply to the evolution of modularity as a by-product of short-term phenotypic selection, and are proven to be scalable to arbitrarily complex systems [37].
From a learning theory perspective, low learning rates cause the evolution of adaptive plasticity because they constrain populations to evolve new adaptive solutions starting from previous genetic adaptations of the reaction norm rather than ‘from scratch’. As a result, evolved reaction norms do more than just ‘remember’ which specific phenotype associated with each specific environment: they capture the logic that connects all cues to all phenotypes. In learning theory terms, organisms learn the regularities of the (evolutionary) problem, a process also known as generalization [31]. Therefore, as long as regularities remain the same, each individual will be able to produce adaptive phenotypes even in environments it has never experienced in its evolutionary history (extrapolation), without the need for further adaptation. Conversely, several studies show that systems that learn a problem’s regularities are also able to quickly adapt to new problems which share a similar logic [38, 39]. This ability to more rapidly evolve new adaptive phenotypes in response to new environments can instead considered as an increase in their evolvability. Our demonstration that organisms can learn regularities between environments even when each organism only ever experiences a single environment opens up the possibility that evolved plastic responses may both prepare organisms for future, more extreme, environments (via extrapolation) and enable them to more rapidly evolve new adaptive solutions (via evolvability). This demonstrates that past evolution can shape evolutionary trajectories by biasing the phenotypic variants that are exposed to selection [24, 40].
In summary, we use a simple reaction norm model to demonstrate that costly adaptive plasticity can evolve even when natural selection is unable to compare competing alleles over multiple environments (i.e., lineage selection). A learning theory framework helps us interpret this finding: Populations evolving in coarse-grained environments can evolve adaptive plasticity if the amount of adaptive change accumulated per environment—the learning rate—is low. Populations with high learning rates evolve via repeated short-term adaptation even if this pattern is maladaptive in the long term. Low learning rates facilitate adaptation to the entire set of environments experienced over adaptation to just the current environment, favouring adaptive plasticity even in the presence of short-term functional trade-offs. Thus, long-term adaptive plasticity can evolve even when it is not selected for at either the individual nor lineage level. Whether a population evolves phenotypes that optimize fitness in the short or long term instead depends on the amount of adaptive changes it accumulates within each environment.
Methods
Environmental variability
For plasticity to evolve, the environment needs to fulfill two roles: determining the selective conditions (selective role) and providing information about those conditions (constructive role) [41]. We simulate the selective role by assigning each environmental state (current or short-term environment) a target single trait optimum ϕ, represented by a single real number. We simulate the constructive role by assigning each target optima an environmental cue represented by a real number C sampled from a normal distribution with mean 1 and standard deviation 1. Each of our simulations cycles between 10 short-term environments, which make up the long-term environment. For simplicity, we consider a linear relationship between phenotypic targets and environmental cues, so that ϕ = g(C) = g1 * e + g0. Hence, the targets are directly proportional to the respective cue. We choose g1 = −2 and g0 = 6. This ensures that the relationship between selective environment and cues remains constant across environmental states.
We assume that the lifespan of the individuals is fixed and the same for all. As a result, environmental grain is solely determined by the parameter K. K < 1 indicates fine-grained environmental variability, where the population encounters an average of 1/K environments per generation. On the other hand, K >= 1 indicates coarse-grained (K = 1) or slow coarse-grained (K > 1) environmental variability where the population encounters a new environment every K generations on average. We choose small K values compared with the total number of generations in our simulations so that each population is able to evolve for multiple environmental cycles.
Our simulations were designed with temporal variation in mind, but the conclusions should be applicable to spatial variation as well. In fact, the environmental fluctuations described within our model match those experienced by a population in which all individuals migrate after fitness evaluation and before reproduction, or in which all propagules are dispersed to the same new environment. In this scenario environmental change rates are effectively interchangeable with migration rates, with other findings remaining unchanged.
Reaction norm model
We model plastic responses using a univariate linear reaction norm model [42]. A reaction norm can be defined as the set of phenotypes that would be expressed if the given individual would be exposed to the respective set of environments. Since we consider univariate and linear reaction norms, we can describe the development of an organism’s phenotype as P = a + b * C. Each organism’s genotype can thus be described by the factors a and b. Of those, a determines the organism’s breeding value and b the direction and magnitude of its plasticity.
Evolutionary process
We model the evolution of a population of asexual individuals as follows. First, we select a parent using a fitness proportional criterion [43, 44]. Each individual can be selected with a probability of , where corresponds to mean fitness in the current population and f to the parent’s own fitness (see section Evaluation of fitness for details on how we calculate f). Then, we generate a new individual with the same genotype (reaction norm intercept a and slope b) as the parent. Finally, we independently mutate both the offspring’s intercept and slope by adding a random value sampled from a normal distribution with mean μ = 0 and standard deviation equal to mutation size (σμ = 0.01 unless otherwise specified). We repeat this process until we generate a number of offspring equal to the set population size. The parameters a and b are initialized at zero.
Evaluation of fitness
Following previous work [35, 37, 38], we define an organism’s overall fitness f in terms of a benefit-minus-cost function, which allows us to consider both positive (benefits) and negative (costs) contributions to its fitness. The benefit of a given genotype, , for each environment, Ei, is determined based on how close the developed adult phenotype, Pa, is to the target phenotype, , of the given selective environment, Ei. Since we deal with an univariate phenotype, we can calculate this amount as (1) where |*| corresponds to the absolute distance between the two phenotypes. Note that the selective advantage of respective genotypes is solely determined by its immediate fitness benefits on the currently encountered selective environment(s). We consider that individuals experience a distribution of selective environments during their lifetime with occurring probabilities, . Each environment contributes to the selection process in proportion to its occurrence [45]. The overall fitness benefits of an individual over all experienced environments in its lifetime, bE is determined by the arithmetic mean of the fitness benefits in each environment, , weighted by the occurrence, , of each environment: (2)
In cases of coarse-grained environmental variability, where each individual encounters a single environment in its lifespan, for the respective environment, i = j, and for i ≠ j. On the other hand, in cases of fine-grained environmental variability, we assume a uniform distribution of environments experienced during individual’s lifespan, that is, . The cost represents how maintaining plasticity reduces the organism’s fitness. Unlike the benefit, the cost of plasticity is a property of the genotype and does not change in different environments. Thus, we can calculate the overall performance, d, of a genotype over a range of selective environments as (3) where parameter λ indicates how steeply fitness decreases in proportion to the reaction norm slope b. The final fitness score is calculated with the following formula: (4) which penalizes lower performances exponentially and re-scales them to a 0-1 range. ω is a scaling factor on the relation between f and d. Lower ω values cause greater loss of fitness per loss of performance, and correspond to steeper selection gradients. We choose ω = 0.2, which corresponds to a scenario of strong selection (see [38]).
Evaluation of reaction norms
We evaluate the adaptive potential of the population due to plasticity by estimating how close the reaction norm of each individual in the population is to the (theoretical) optimal reaction norm. The optimal reaction norm here corresponds the function that given any environmental cue, , produces the appropriate target phenotype, , which best matches the current selective environment, Ei (Evaluation of fitness). We evaluate the performance of reaction norms based on how different they are from the optimal reaction norm. The lack of fit, LackD of a given reaction norm, D, is estimated as a function of the phenotypic trait values in each of the past selective environments (here 10), Ei, whose magnitude increases quadratically with the distance from each phenotypic optimum, : (5)
Where NE stands for the number of past selective environments. The evaluation of lack of fit is performed for each individual at the end of each environmental period. We report the average and best performance in the population.
Hill-climbing model
A hill-climbing evolutionary model simulates a scenario of strong selection and weak mutation, where each new mutation is either fixed or lost before a new one can arise. Therefore, the entire population shares the same values of a and b. Each evolutionary step introduces a single mutant genotype with parameters a′ and b′ equal to a and b plus a random value sampled from a normal distribution with mean 0 and standard deviation equal to mutation size. We develop both the reference and mutant phenotypes P and P′ (section Reaction norm model) and compare their fitness values f and f′ (section Evaluation of fitness). If f′ > f, the mutation is beneficial and therefore adopted so that at+1 = a′ and bt+1 = b′. Otherwise, the mutation is deleterious and a and b remain unchanged.
Supporting information
S1 Appendix. Fitness cost of plasticity and tracking.
Numerical calculations of the expected long-term fitness costs of adaptively plastic and adaptive tracking populations.
https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1006260.s001
(PDF)
S1 Fig. Additional simulation results.
Evolutionary trajectories and evolved plasticity in the absence of cost of plasticity for SSWM (A and B) and population models (C and D).
https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1006260.s002
(TIF)
S1 File. Simulation code.
Code used to generate all results shown in the paper.
https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1006260.s003
(RAR)
References
- 1. Simons AM. Modes of response to environmental change and the elusive empirical evidence for bet hedging. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 2011;278(1712):1601–1609. pmid:21411456
- 2. Botero Ca, Weissing FJ, Wright J, Rubenstein DR. Evolutionary tipping points in the capacity to adapt to environmental change. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 2015;112(1):184–189.
- 3. Moran NA. The Evolutionary Maintenance of Alternative Phenotypes. The American Naturalist. 1992;139(5):971–989.
- 4. Ghalambor CK, McKay JK, Carroll SP, Reznick DN. Adaptive versus non-adaptive phenotypic plasticity and the potential for contemporary adaptation in new environments. Functional Ecology. 2007;21(3):394–407.
- 5. Hoverman JT, Relyea RA. How flexible is phenotypic plasticity? Developmental windows for trait induction and reversal. Ecology. 2007;88(3):693–705. pmid:17503597
- 6. Van Buskirk J, Steiner UK. The fitness costs of developmental canalization and plasticity. Journal of Evolutionary Biology. 2009;22(4):852–860. pmid:19226418
- 7. Auld JR, Agrawal AA, Relyea RA. Re-evaluating the costs and limits of adaptive phenotypic plasticity. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 2010;277(1681):503–511. pmid:19846457
- 8.
Levins R. Evolution in changing environments: some theoretical explorations. 2. Princeton University Press; 1968.
- 9. Rountree DB, Nijhout HF. Hormonal control of a seasonal polyphenism in Precis coenia (Lepidoptera: Nymphalidae). Journal of Insect Physiology. 1995;41(11):987–992.
- 10. Moczek AP. Pupal remodeling and the evolution and development of alternative male morphologies in horned beetles. BMC evolutionary biology. 2007;7:151. pmid:17727716
- 11. Michie LJ, Masson A, Ware RL, Jiggins FM. Seasonal phenotypic plasticity: Wild ladybirds are darker at cold temperatures. Evolutionary Ecology. 2011;25(6):1259–1268.
- 12. Kaji T, Palmer AR. How reversible is development? Contrast between developmentally plastic gain and loss of segments in barnacle feeding legs. Evolution. 2017;71(3):756–765. pmid:28012177
- 13. van Gestel J, Weissing FJ. Regulatory mechanisms link phenotypic plasticity to evolvability. Scientific Reports. 2016;6(1):24524. pmid:27087393
- 14. Gerber N, Kokko H, Ebert D, Booksmythe I. Daphnia invest in sexual reproduction when its relative costs are reduced. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 2018;285:20172176. pmid:29343596
- 15. BRAKEFIELD PM, REITSMA N. Phenotypic plasticity, seasonal climate and the population biology of Bicyclus butterflies (Satyridae) in Malawi. Ecological Entomology. 1991;16(3):291–303.
- 16. Via S, Gomulkiewicz R, De Jong G, Scheiner SM, Schlichting CD, Van Tienderen PH. Adaptive phenotypic plasticity: consensus and controversy. Trends in Ecology and Evolution. 1995;10(5):212–217. pmid:21237012
- 17. Lande R. Adaptation to an extraordinary environment by evolution of phenotypic plasticity and genetic assimilation. Journal of Evolutionary Biology. 2009;22(7):1435–1446. pmid:19467134
- 18. Gomulkiewicz R, Kirkpatrick M. Quantitative Genetics and the Evolution of Reaction Norms. Evolution. 1992;46(2):390–411. pmid:28564020
- 19. Siljestam M, Östman . The combined effects of temporal autocorrelation and the costs of plasticity on the evolution of plasticity. Journal of Evolutionary Biology. 2017;30(7):1361–1371. pmid:28485061
- 20. Palmer ME, Feldman MW. Survivability is more fundamental than evolvability. PLoS ONE. 2012;7(6).
- 21. Volis S, Ormanbekova D, Yermekbayev K, Song M, Shulgina I. Introduction beyond a species range: A relationship between population origin, adaptive potential and plant performance. Heredity. 2014;113(3):268–276. pmid:24690758
- 22. Reed TE, Waples RS, Schindler DE, Hard JJ, Kinnison MT. Phenotypic plasticity and population viability: the importance of environmental predictability. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 2010;277(1699):3391–3400. pmid:20554553
- 23. Chevin LM, Lande R. When do adaptive plasticity and genetic evolution prevent extinction of a density regulated population? Evolution. 2010;64(4):1143–1150. pmid:19863583
- 24. Watson RA, Szathmáry E. How Can Evolution Learn? Trends in Ecology & Evolution. 2016;31(2):147–157.
- 25.
Schmalhauzen II. Factors of Evolution: The Theory of Stabilizing Selection. Blakiston; 1949.
- 26. de Jong G. Phenotypic Plasticity as a Product of Selection in a Variable Environment. The American Naturalist. 1995;145(4):493–512.
- 27. Via S, Lande R, May N. Genotype-Environment Interaction and the Evolution of Phenotypic Plasticity. Evolution. 1985;39(3):505–522. pmid:28561964
- 28. de Jong G. Quantitative Genetics of reaction norms. Journal of Evolutionary Biology. 1990;3(5-6):447–468.
- 29. Fischer B, Taborsky B, Kokko H. How to balance the offspring quality-quantity tradeoff when environmental cues are unreliable. Oikos. 2011;120(2):258–270.
- 30. Gomez-Mestre I, Jovani R. A heuristic model on the role of plasticity in adaptive evolution: plasticity increases adaptation, population viability and genetic variation. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 2013;280(1771):20131869–20131869. pmid:24068357
- 31. Kouvaris K, Clune J, Kounios L, Brede M, Watson RA. How evolution learns to generalise: Using the principles of learning theory to understand the evolution of developmental organisation. PLOS Computational Biology. 2017;13(4):e1005358. pmid:28384156
- 32. Murren CJ, Auld JR, Callahan H, Ghalambor CK, Handelsman CA, Heskel MA, et al. Constraints on the evolution of phenotypic plasticity: limits and costs of phenotype and plasticity. Heredity. 2015;115(July 2014):293–301. pmid:25690179
- 33. Auld JR, Agrawal AA, Relyea RA. Re-evaluating the costs and limits of adaptive phenotypic plasticity. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 2010;277(1681):503–511. pmid:19846457
- 34. Panchanathan K, Frankenhuis WE. The evolution of sensitive periods in a model of incremental development. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 2016;283(1823):20152439. pmid:26817766
- 35. De Jong G. Evolution of phenotypic plasticity: patters of plasticity and the emergence of ecotypes. New Phytologist. 2005;166(2003):101–118. pmid:15760355
- 36. de Jong G. Quantitative Genetics of reaction norms. Journal of Evolutionary Biology. 1990;3(5-6):447–468.
- 37. Kashtan N, Mayo AE, Kalisky T, Alon U. An Analytically Solvable Model for Rapid Evolution of Modular Structure. PLoS Computational Biology. 2009;5(4). pmid:19360090
- 38. Draghi JA, Whitlock MC. Phenotypic plasticity facilitates mutational variance, genetic variance, and evolvability along the major axis of environmental variation. Evolution. 2012;66(9):2891–2902. pmid:22946810
- 39. Watson RA, Wagner GP, Pavlicev M, Weinreich DM, Mills R. The evolution of phenotypic correlations and “developmental memory”. Evolution. 2014;68(4):1124–1138. pmid:24351058
- 40. Uller T, Moczek AP, Watson RA, Brakefield PM, Laland KN. Developmental bias and evolution: A regulatory network perspective. Genetics. 2018;209(4):949–966. pmid:30049818
- 41.
West-Eberhard MJ. Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford University Press; 2003.
- 42.
Scheiner SM, DeWitt TJ. Phenotypic plasticity: functional and conceptual approaches; 2004.
- 43.
Hancock PJB. An empirical comparison of selection methods in evolutionary algorithms. In: AISB Workshop on Evolutionary Computing. Springer; 1994. p. 80–94.
- 44. Lipson H, Pollack JB. Automatic design and manufacture of robotic lifeforms. Nature. 2000;406(6799):974–978. pmid:10984047
- 45. De Jong G, Bijma P. Selection and phenotypic plasticity in evolutionary biology and animal breeding. Livestock production science. 2002;78(3):195–214.