Next Article in Journal
A Refinement of Recurrence Analysis to Determine the Time Delay of Causality in Presence of External Perturbations
Previous Article in Journal
New Fast ApEn and SampEn Entropy Algorithms Implementation and Their Application to Supercomputer Power Consumption
Previous Article in Special Issue
Quantum Hair on Colliding Black Holes
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Editorial

Some Notes on Quantum Information in Spacetime

1
ISEM, Institute for Scientific Methodology, 90121 Palermo, Italy
2
School of Advanced International Studies on Applied Theoretical and Non-LinearMethodologies in Physics, 70121 Bari, Italy
Entropy 2020, 22(8), 864; https://doi.org/10.3390/e22080864
Submission received: 15 July 2020 / Revised: 27 July 2020 / Accepted: 30 July 2020 / Published: 6 August 2020
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Relativistic Quantum Information)
The results obtained since the 70s with the study of Hawking radiation and the Unruh effect have highlighted a new domain of authority of relativistic principles. Entanglement, the quantum phenomenon par excellence, is in fact observer dependent [1], and the very concept of “particle” does not have the same information content for different observers [2,3]. All this proposes the centrality of the notion of “event” in physics and the meaning of its informational value. It is in this direction that Quantum Relativistic Information (QRI) is defined, which can therefore be defined as the study of quantum states in a relational context.
It must be said that, despite being a prelude to a future quantum gravity, QRI is a largely autonomous field—because it does not imply any specific hypothesis on the Planck scale—and is characterized by some principles that guard an assumption of great epistemological strength. As A. Zeilinger [4] says, it is impossible to distinguish between “reality” and “description of reality”, i.e., information in the study of physics; doing so means jeopardizing the universal value and beauty of physical laws. Both relativity and quantum physics are aspects of a broader information theory that we have been discovering in recent years and within which the foundational debate is renewed with new experimental possibilities. The first principle we need is therefore:
The principle of contextuality [5]: Each description of a class of events must contain, implicitly or explicitly, the reference structure of the observer. In other words, it must be possible for each observer to define assign values for each observable.
A very strong request comes from the principle of equivalence, which, after showing unsuspected resistance to any attempt of de-construction, is now extended to the quantum domain as a request to describe gravitational phenomena in terms of causal networks [6,7,8,9,10,11]. L. Susskind and G. ’t Hooft proposal for the information paradox adds a new element to the picture: the complementarity invoked is in fact a principle of equivalence [12,13]. Although the Black Holes question are still far from being resolved (with particular regard to the core of the BH, with interesting inter-connections between strings, non-commutativity and euclidicity, see for example: [14,15,16,17,18,19,20]), the synthesis of equivalence and complementarity leads to a powerful holographic principle that introduces, according to Bekenstein’s limit [21], a new way of looking at the locality and a different approach to cosmology. The holographic principle feeds on conjectures and is still looking for theories (duality between gravity and quantum field theory: [22,23,24,25,26]), but it is a catalyst for new conceptual suggestions regarding the physical meaning of the cosmological horizon. In particular, considering the four-dimensional dynamics as the explication (in a Bohmian sense) of a De Sitter non-perturbative vacuum offers an improvement of Hartle–Hawking proposal in quantum cosmology and a solution to the informational paradox in the BH [27,28,29]. This line of reasoning is also promising for an event-based reading of Quantum Mechanics [30].
For a long time, holography and emergentism appeared as two styles of explanation irreconcilable with respect to the locality, but an emergency of time could offer new perspectives with a duality between imaginary time and real time, in a diachronic/synchronic complementarity [31,32,33].
It is known that there are well-defined whormhole solutions in General Relativity and Yang Mills Theory, and the recent ER = EPR conjecture proposes the question of the emergence of metric space-time from a non-local background [34,35,36,37,38]. A suggestion in the direction of the laboratory comes from the Bose–Marletto–Vedral conjecture on the possible coalescence of two quantum systems in a non-local phase, which would reveal the limits of the local metric description and the non-classical aspects of space-time [39,40]. A covariant analysis of this situation shows that discrete effects could prove to be an overlap of geometries measurable through entanglement entropy [41,42].
Furthermore, localization appears as the production of a new degree of freedom. We assume, in accordance with a recent proposal [30,43], that the localization R of a process is associated with the genesis of a micro-horizon of de Sitter of center O and radius cθ0 ≈ 10–13 cm (chronon, corresponding to the classical radius of the electron), with O generally delocalized according to the wave function entering/leaving the process. The constant θ0 is independent of cosmic time, so the ratio t0/θ0 ≈ 1041 is also independent of cosmic time, with ct0 ≈ 1028 cm. This ratio expresses the number of totally distinct temporal locations accessible by the R process within the horizon of cosmological de Sitter. In practice, the time line segment on which an observer at the center of the horizon places the process R has length t0, while the duration of the process R is in the order of θ0; the segment is therefore divided into separate t0/θ0 ≈ 1041 “cells”. Each cell can be in two states: “on” or “off”. The temporal localization of a single process R corresponds to the situation in which all the cells are switched off minus one. Configurations with multiple cells on will correspond to the location of multiple distinct R processes on the same time line. If you accept the idea that each cell is independent, you have 2 10 41 distinct configurations in all. The positional information associated with the location of 0, 1, 2, …, 1041 R processes then amounts to 1041 bits, the binary logarithm of the number of configurations. This is a kind of coded information on the time axis contained within the observer’s de Sitter horizon.
The R processes are in fact real interactions between real particles, during which an amount of action is exchanged in the order of the Planck quantum h. Therefore, in terms of phase space, the manifestation of one of these processes is equivalent to the ignition of an elementary cell of volume h3. The number of “switched on” cells in the phase space of a given macroscopic physical system is an estimator of the volume it occupies in this space, and therefore of its entropy. It is therefore conceivable that the location information of the R processes is connected to entropy through the uncertainty principle. This possibility presupposes the “objective” nature of the R processes.
It is therefore natural to ask whether some form of Bekenstein’s limit on entropy applies in some way to the two horizons mentioned. If we assume that the information on the temporal location of the processes R, I = 1041 bits, is connected to the area of the micro-horizon, A = (cθ0) 2 ≈ 10−26 cm2 from the holographic relationship:
A 4 l 2 = I
Then, the spatial extension l of the “cells” associated with an information bit is ≈10−33 cm, the Planck scale! It is necessary to underline that the Planck scale presents itself in this way as a consequence of the holographic conjecture (1), combined with the “two horizons” hypothesis, and therefore of the finiteness of the information I. It in no way represents a limit to the continuity of spacetime, nor to the spatial or temporal distance between two events (which remains a continuous variable). Furthermore, since I = t0/θ0 and t0 is related to the cosmological constant λ by the relation λ = 4/3t02, the (1) is essentially a definition of the Planck scale as a function of the cosmological constant. A global-local relationship is exactly what we expect from a holographic vacuum theory.

Funding

This research received no external funding.

Conflicts of Interest

The author declare no conflict of interest.

References

  1. Alsing, P.M.; Fuentes, I. Observer dependent entanglement, Class. Quantum Grav. 2012, 29, 224001. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  2. Davies, P.C.W. Particles do not exist. In Quantum Theory of Gravity; Essays in Honor of the 60th Birthday of Bryce DeWitt; Christensen, S.M., Ed.; Adam Hilger: Bristol, UK, 1984; pp. 66–77. [Google Scholar]
  3. Colosi, D.; Rovelli, C. What is a particle? Class. Quant. Grav. 2009, 26, 025002. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  4. Zeilinger, A. Dance of the Photons: From Einstein to Quantum Teleportation; Farrar Straus Giroux Publisher: New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
  5. Jaroszkiewicz, G. Observers and Reality, in Beyond Peaceful Coexistence. In The Emergence of Space, Time and Quantum; Licata, I., Ed.; Imperial College Press: London, UK, 2016; pp. 137–151. [Google Scholar]
  6. Licata, I.; Corda, C.; Benedetto, E. A machian request for the equivalence principle in extended gravity and non-geodesic motion. Grav. Cosmol. 2016, 22, 48–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  7. Licata, I.; Benedetto, E. The Charge in a Lift. A Covariance Problem. Gravit. Cosmol. 2018, 24, 173–177. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  8. Candelas, P.; Sciama, D.W. Is there a quantum equivalence principle? Phys. Rev. D 1983, 27, 1715. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Tamburini, F.; de Laurentis, M.F.; Licata, I. Radiation from charged particles due to explicit symmetry breaking in a gravitational field. Int. J. Geom. Methods Mod. Phys. 2018, 15, 1850122. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  10. Zych, M.; Brukner, C. Quantum formulation of the Einstein equivalence principle. Nat. Phys. 2018, 14, 1027–1031. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  11. Hardy, L. Implementation of the Quantum Equivalence Principle. arXiv 2019, arXiv:1903.01289. [Google Scholar]
  12. Hooft, G. Dimensional Reduction in Quantum Gravity. arXiv 1993, arXiv:gr-qc/9310026. [Google Scholar]
  13. Susskind, L. The paradox of quantum black holes. Nat. Phys. 2006, 2, 665–677. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  14. Susskind, L. String Physics and Black Holes. Nucl. Phys. Proc. Suppl. 1995, 45, 115–134. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  15. Strominger, A.; Vafa, C. Microscopic Origin of the Bekenstein-Hawking Entropy. Phys. Lett. 1996, 379, 99–104. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  16. Yogendran, K.P. Horizon strings and interior states of a black hole. Phys. Lett. 2015, 750, 278–281. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  17. Nicolini, P. Noncommutative Black Holes. The Final Appeal to Quantum Gravity: A Review. Int. J. Mod. Phys. 2009, 24, 1229–1308. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  18. Dowker, F.; Gregory, R.; Traschen, J. Euclidean Black Hole Vortices. Phys. Rev. 1992, 45, 2762–2771. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
  19. Hirayama, T.; Holdom, B. Can black holes have Euclidean cores? Phys. Rev. 2003, 68, 044003. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  20. Corda, C. Black hole quantum spectrum. Eur. Phys. J. 2013, 73, 2665. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  21. Bekenstein, J.; Schiffer, M. Quantum Limitations on the Storage and Transmission of Information. Int. J. Mod. Phys. 1990, 1, 355–422. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  22. Bousso, R. The Holographic principle. Rev. Mod. Phys. 2002, 74, 825–874. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  23. Susskind, L. The world as an hologram. J. Math. Phys. 1995, 36, 6377–6396. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  24. Maldacena, J.M. The Large N Limit of Superconformal Field Theories and Supergravity. Adv. Theor. Math. Phys. 1998, 2, 231–252. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  25. Witten, E. Anti De Sitter Space and Holography. Adv. Theor. Math. Phys. 1998, 2, 253–291. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  26. Dong, X.; Silverstein, E.; Torroba, G. De Sitter holography and entanglement entropy. J. High Energy Phys. 2018, 2018, 50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  27. Nikolić, H. Resolving the black-hole information paradox by treating time on an equal footing with space. Phys. Lett. B 2009, 678, 218–221. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  28. Feleppa, F.; Licata, I.; Corda, C. Hartle-Hawking boundary conditions as Nucleation by de Sitter Vacuum. Phys. Dark Universe 2019, 26, 100381. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  29. Licata, I.; Fiscaletti, D.; Chiatti, L.; Tamburini, F.; Davide, F. CPT symmetry in cosmology and the Archaic Universe. Phys. Scr. 2020, 95, 075004. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  30. Licata, I.; Chiatti, L. Event-Based Quantum Mechanics: A Context for the Emergence of Classical Information. Symmetry 2019, 11, 181. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  31. Vistarini, T. Holographic space and time: Emergent in what sense? Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part B: Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 2017, 59, 126–135. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  32. Crowther, K. As below, so before: ‘synchronic’ and ‘diachronic’ conceptions of spacetime emergence. Synthese 2020, 1–29. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  33. Licata, I. In and Out of the Screen. On some new considerations about localization and delocalization in Archaic Theory, in Beyond Peaceful Coexistence. In The Emergence of Space, Time and Quantum; Imperial College Press: London, UK, 2016; pp. 559–577. [Google Scholar]
  34. Kim, H. Classical and quantum wormholes in Einstein-Yang-Mills theory. Nucl. Phys. B 1998, 527, 342–359. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  35. Maldacena, J.; Susskind, L. Cool horizons for entangled black holes. Fortsch. Phys. 2013, 61, 781–811. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  36. Susskind, L. Copenhagen vs Everett, Teleportation, and ER = EPR. Fortschr. Phys. 2016, 64, 551–564. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  37. Cao, C.; Carroll, S.; Michalakis, S. Space from Hilbert Space: Recovering Geometry from Bulk Entanglement. Phys. Rev. 2017, 95, 024031. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  38. Tamburini, F.; Licata, I. General Relativistic Wormhole Connections from Planck-Scales and the ER = EPR Conjecture. Entropy 2019, 22, 3. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  39. Bose, S.; Mazumdar, A.; Morley, G.W.; Ulbricht, H.; Toroš, M.; Paternostro, M.; Geraci, A.A.; Barker, P.F.; Kim, M.S.; Milburn, G. Spin Entanglement Witness for Quantum Gravity. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2017, 119, 240401. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  40. Marletto, C.; Vedral, V. Gravitationally Induced Entanglement between Two Massive Particles is Sufficient Evidence of Quantum Effects in Gravity. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2017, 119, 240402. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  41. Christodoulou, M.; Rovelli, C. On the possibility of laboratory evidence for quantum superposition of geometries. Phys. Lett. B 2019, 792, 64–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  42. Giacomini, F.; Castro-Ruiz, E.; Brukner, C. Quantum mechanics and the covariance of physical laws in quantum reference frames. Nat. Commun. 2019, 10, 494. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  43. Chiatti, L.; Licata, I. Particle model from quantum foundations. Quantum Stud. Math. Found. 2016, 4, 181–204. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Licata, I. Some Notes on Quantum Information in Spacetime. Entropy 2020, 22, 864. https://doi.org/10.3390/e22080864

AMA Style

Licata I. Some Notes on Quantum Information in Spacetime. Entropy. 2020; 22(8):864. https://doi.org/10.3390/e22080864

Chicago/Turabian Style

Licata, Ignazio. 2020. "Some Notes on Quantum Information in Spacetime" Entropy 22, no. 8: 864. https://doi.org/10.3390/e22080864

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop