In general topology, a branch of mathematics, a non-empty family A of subsets of a set is said to have the finite intersection property (FIP) if the intersection over any finite subcollection of is non-empty. It has the strong finite intersection property (SFIP) if the intersection over any finite subcollection of is infinite. Sets with the finite intersection property are also called centered systems and filter subbases.[1]
The finite intersection property can be used to reformulate topological compactness in terms of closed sets; this is its most prominent application. Other applications include proving that certain perfect sets are uncountable, and the construction of ultrafilters.
Definition
editLet be a set and a nonempty family of subsets of ; that is, is a subset of the power set of . Then is said to have the finite intersection property if every nonempty finite subfamily has nonempty intersection; it is said to have the strong finite intersection property if that intersection is always infinite.[1]
In symbols, has the FIP if, for any choice of a finite nonempty subset of , there must exist a point Likewise, has the SFIP if, for every choice of such , there are infinitely many such .[1]
In the study of filters, the common intersection of a family of sets is called a kernel, from much the same etymology as the sunflower. Families with empty kernel are called free; those with nonempty kernel, fixed.[2]
Families of examples and non-examples
editThe empty set cannot belong to any collection with the finite intersection property.
A sufficient condition for the FIP intersection property is a nonempty kernel. The converse is generally false, but holds for finite families; that is, if is finite, then has the finite intersection property if and only if it is fixed.
Pairwise intersection
editThe finite intersection property is strictly stronger than pairwise intersection; the family has pairwise intersections, but not the FIP.
More generally, let be a positive integer greater than unity, , and . Then any subset of with fewer than elements has nonempty intersection, but lacks the FIP.
End-type constructions
editIf is a decreasing sequence of non-empty sets, then the family has the finite intersection property (and is even a π–system). If the inclusions are strict, then admits the strong finite intersection property as well.
More generally, any that is totally ordered by inclusion has the FIP.
At the same time, the kernel of may be empty: if , then the kernel of is the empty set. Similarly, the family of intervals also has the (S)FIP, but empty kernel.
"Generic" sets and properties
editThe family of all Borel subsets of with Lebesgue measure has the FIP, as does the family of comeagre sets. If is an infinite set, then the Fréchet filter (the family ) has the FIP. All of these are free filters; they are upwards-closed and have empty infinitary intersection.[3][4]
If and, for each positive integer the subset is precisely all elements of having digit in the th decimal place, then any finite intersection of is non-empty — just take in those finitely many places and in the rest. But the intersection of for all is empty, since no element of has all zero digits.
Extension of the ground set
editThe (strong) finite intersection property is a characteristic of the family , not the ground set . If a family on the set admits the (S)FIP and , then is also a family on the set with the FIP (resp. SFIP).
Generated filters and topologies
editIf are sets with then the family has the FIP; this family is called the principal filter on generated by . The subset has the FIP for much the same reason: the kernels contain the non-empty set . If is an open interval, then the set is in fact equal to the kernels of or , and so is an element of each filter. But in general a filter's kernel need not be an element of the filter.
A proper filter on a set has the finite intersection property. Every neighbourhood subbasis at a point in a topological space has the FIP, and the same is true of every neighbourhood basis and every neighbourhood filter at a point (because each is, in particular, also a neighbourhood subbasis).
Relationship to π-systems and filters
editA π–system is a non-empty family of sets that is closed under finite intersections. The set of all finite intersections of one or more sets from is called the π–system generated by , because it is the smallest π–system having as a subset.
The upward closure of in is the set
For any family , the finite intersection property is equivalent to any of the following:
- The π–system generated by does not have the empty set as an element; that is,
- The set has the finite intersection property.
- The set is a (proper)[note 1] prefilter.
- The family is a subset of some (proper) prefilter.[1]
- The upward closure is a (proper) filter on . In this case, is called the filter on generated by , because it is the minimal (with respect to ) filter on that contains as a subset.
- is a subset of some (proper)[note 1] filter.[1]
Applications
editCompactness
editThe finite intersection property is useful in formulating an alternative definition of compactness:
Theorem — A space is compact if and only if every family of closed subsets having the finite intersection property has non-empty intersection.[5][6]
This formulation of compactness is used in some proofs of Tychonoff's theorem.
Uncountability of perfect spaces
editAnother common application is to prove that the real numbers are uncountable.
Theorem — Let be a non-empty compact Hausdorff space that satisfies the property that no one-point set is open. Then is uncountable.
All the conditions in the statement of the theorem are necessary:
- We cannot eliminate the Hausdorff condition; a countable set (with at least two points) with the indiscrete topology is compact, has more than one point, and satisfies the property that no one point sets are open, but is not uncountable.
- We cannot eliminate the compactness condition, as the set of rational numbers shows.
- We cannot eliminate the condition that one point sets cannot be open, as any finite space with the discrete topology shows.
We will show that if is non-empty and open, and if is a point of then there is a neighbourhood whose closure does not contain ( ' may or may not be in ). Choose different from (if then there must exist such a for otherwise would be an open one point set; if this is possible since is non-empty). Then by the Hausdorff condition, choose disjoint neighbourhoods and of and respectively. Then will be a neighbourhood of contained in whose closure doesn't contain as desired.
Now suppose is a bijection, and let denote the image of Let be the first open set and choose a neighbourhood whose closure does not contain Secondly, choose a neighbourhood whose closure does not contain Continue this process whereby choosing a neighbourhood whose closure does not contain Then the collection satisfies the finite intersection property and hence the intersection of their closures is non-empty by the compactness of Therefore, there is a point in this intersection. No can belong to this intersection because does not belong to the closure of This means that is not equal to for all and is not surjective; a contradiction. Therefore, is uncountable.
Corollary — Every closed interval with is uncountable. Therefore, is uncountable.
Corollary — Every perfect, locally compact Hausdorff space is uncountable.
Let be a perfect, compact, Hausdorff space, then the theorem immediately implies that is uncountable. If is a perfect, locally compact Hausdorff space that is not compact, then the one-point compactification of is a perfect, compact Hausdorff space. Therefore, the one point compactification of is uncountable. Since removing a point from an uncountable set still leaves an uncountable set, is uncountable as well.
Ultrafilters
editLet be non-empty, having the finite intersection property. Then there exists an ultrafilter (in ) such that This result is known as the ultrafilter lemma.[7]
See also
edit- Filter (set theory) – Family of sets representing "large" sets
- Filters in topology – Use of filters to describe and characterize all basic topological notions and results.
- Neighbourhood system – (for a point x) collection of all neighborhoods for the point x
- Ultrafilter (set theory) – Maximal proper filter
References
editNotes
editCitations
edit- ^ a b c d e Joshi 1983, pp. 242−248.
- ^ Dolecki & Mynard 2016, pp. 27–29, 33–35.
- ^ Bourbaki 1987, pp. 57–68.
- ^ Wilansky 2013, pp. 44–46.
- ^ Munkres 2000, p. 169.
- ^ A space is compact iff any family of closed sets having fip has non-empty intersection at PlanetMath.
- ^ Csirmaz, László; Hajnal, András (1994), Matematikai logika (In Hungarian), Budapest: Eötvös Loránd University.
General sources
edit- Bourbaki, Nicolas (1989) [1966]. General Topology: Chapters 1–4 [Topologie Générale]. Éléments de mathématique. Berlin New York: Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-3-540-64241-1. OCLC 18588129.
- Bourbaki, Nicolas (1989) [1967]. General Topology 2: Chapters 5–10 [Topologie Générale]. Éléments de mathématique. Vol. 4. Berlin New York: Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-3-540-64563-4. OCLC 246032063.
- Bourbaki, Nicolas (1987) [1981]. Topological Vector Spaces: Chapters 1–5. Éléments de mathématique. Translated by Eggleston, H.G.; Madan, S. Berlin New York: Springer-Verlag. ISBN 3-540-13627-4. OCLC 17499190.
- Comfort, William Wistar; Negrepontis, Stylianos (1974). The Theory of Ultrafilters. Vol. 211. Berlin Heidelberg New York: Springer-Verlag. ISBN 978-0-387-06604-2. OCLC 1205452.
- Császár, Ákos (1978). General topology. Translated by Császár, Klára. Bristol England: Adam Hilger Ltd. ISBN 0-85274-275-4. OCLC 4146011.
- Dolecki, Szymon; Mynard, Frédéric (2016). Convergence Foundations Of Topology. New Jersey: World Scientific Publishing Company. ISBN 978-981-4571-52-4. OCLC 945169917.
- Dugundji, James (1966). Topology. Boston: Allyn and Bacon. ISBN 978-0-697-06889-7. OCLC 395340485.
- Joshi, K. D. (1983). Introduction to General Topology. New York: John Wiley and Sons Ltd. ISBN 978-0-85226-444-7. OCLC 9218750.
- Koutras, Costas D.; Moyzes, Christos; Nomikos, Christos; Tsaprounis, Konstantinos; Zikos, Yorgos (20 October 2021). "On Weak Filters and Ultrafilters: Set Theory From (and for) Knowledge Representation". Logic Journal of the IGPL. 31: 68–95. doi:10.1093/jigpal/jzab030.
- MacIver R., David (1 July 2004). "Filters in Analysis and Topology" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 2007-10-09. (Provides an introductory review of filters in topology and in metric spaces.)
- Munkres, James R. (2000). Topology (Second ed.). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall, Inc. ISBN 978-0-13-181629-9. OCLC 42683260.
- Narici, Lawrence; Beckenstein, Edward (2011). Topological Vector Spaces. Pure and applied mathematics (Second ed.). Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press. ISBN 978-1584888666. OCLC 144216834.
- Wilansky, Albert (2013). Modern Methods in Topological Vector Spaces. Mineola, New York: Dover Publications, Inc. ISBN 978-0-486-49353-4. OCLC 849801114.
- Wilansky, Albert (17 October 2008) [1970]. Topology for Analysis. Mineola, New York: Dover Publications, Inc. ISBN 978-0-486-46903-4. OCLC 227923899.
External links
editFamilies of sets over | ||||||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Is necessarily true of or, is closed under: |
Directed by |
F.I.P. | ||||||||
π-system | ||||||||||
Semiring | Never | |||||||||
Semialgebra (Semifield) | Never | |||||||||
Monotone class | only if | only if | ||||||||
𝜆-system (Dynkin System) | only if |
only if or they are disjoint |
Never | |||||||
Ring (Order theory) | ||||||||||
Ring (Measure theory) | Never | |||||||||
δ-Ring | Never | |||||||||
𝜎-Ring | Never | |||||||||
Algebra (Field) | Never | |||||||||
𝜎-Algebra (𝜎-Field) | Never | |||||||||
Dual ideal | ||||||||||
Filter | Never | Never | ||||||||
Prefilter (Filter base) | Never | Never | ||||||||
Filter subbase | Never | Never | ||||||||
Open Topology | (even arbitrary ) |
Never | ||||||||
Closed Topology | (even arbitrary ) |
Never | ||||||||
Is necessarily true of or, is closed under: |
directed downward |
finite intersections |
finite unions |
relative complements |
complements in |
countable intersections |
countable unions |
contains | contains | Finite Intersection Property |
Additionally, a semiring is a π-system where every complement is equal to a finite disjoint union of sets in |