Studies in Brain and Mind
Volume 13
Editor-in-Chief
Gualtiero Piccinini, University of Missouri - St. Louis, U.S.A.
Editorial Board
Berit Brogaard, University of Missouri - St. Louis, U.S.A.
Carl Craver, Washington University, U.S.A.
Edouard Machery, University of Pittsburgh, U.S.A.
Oron Shagrir, Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Israel
Mark Sprevak, University of Edinburgh, Scotland, U.K.
More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/6540
Beate Krickel
The Mechanical World
The Metaphysical Commitments of the New
Mechanistic Approach
Beate Krickel
Department of Philosophy II
Ruhr-University Bochum
Bochum, Germany
ISSN 1573-4536
ISSN 2468-399X (electronic)
Studies in Brain and Mind
ISBN 978-3-030-03628-7
ISBN 978-3-030-03629-4 (eBook)
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-03629-4
Library of Congress Control Number: 2018961738
© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2018
This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of
the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation,
broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information
storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology
now known or hereafter developed.
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication
does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant
protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book
are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the
editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any errors
or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims
in published maps and institutional affiliations.
This Springer imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature Switzerland AG
The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland
Acknowledgments
This book began as my PhD thesis, submitted in June 2014 at the HumboldtUniversität zu Berlin, Germany. I thank my supervisors, Geert Keil and Andreas
Hüttemann, for their support and feedback. I also thank my former colleagues from
Humboldt University for their helpful discussions and the good times we had
together in Berlin. In particular, I want to thank Alexander Dinges, Julia Zakkou,
Thomas Krödel, Sanja Dembic, Sebastian Bender, and the participants of Prof.
Keil’s colloquium. I also profited from discussions with Marie Kaiser, Lena Kästner,
Dan Brooks, the LeRM group, Michael Baumgartner, Lorenzo Casini, Jens
Harbecke, Stuart Glennan, Felipe Romero, Florian Fischer, Sven Walter, and Achim
Stephan. I had the honor of being a member of an annual meeting of philosophers
which included such figures as Carl Gillett, Carrie Figdor, Christian Sachse, Fred
Adams, Larry Shapiro, Rob Rupert, Tom Polger, and Zoe Drayson, all of whom
provided helpful feedback on the presentations of my PhD thesis. I am also grateful
to Kelley Schiffmann for proofreading an earlier version of the manuscript. Finally,
I benefitted a lot from my stay at Washington University in St. Louis; the discussions I had there with Carl Craver were deeply intellectually stimulating, and he
later helped me finish the book while also providing challenging feedback that
greatly improved the arguments therein.
I started writing this book in 2016 while working in Albert Newen’s research
group at Ruhr University Bochum. This provided the perfect environment for my
project, and I want to thank my colleagues, especially Albert Newen, Alfredo
Vernazzani, Francesco Marchi, Judith Martens, Krys Dolega, Pascale Willemsen,
Peter Brössel, Sabrina Coninx, and Tobias Starzak, for their feedback and helpful
discussions. Also, I gained a great deal from discussions with Frances Egan, Michael
Kirchhoff, and Rob Rupert, who visited the research group at different times in
2016/2017. Furthermore, I want to thank the DFG-Graduiertenkolleg “Situated
Cognition” (GRK-2185/1) for supporting the completion of this book.
Finally, I want to thank my friends and family for their support over the last few
years. I am especially grateful to my uncle, who was the first philosopher in my
family and taught me how to write philosophical texts; my high school teachers
v
vi
Acknowledgments
Mr. Leubner and Mrs. Dittforth, who awakened my interest in philosophy; my
twin sister, without whom I would not have survived my time as a PhD student;
my partner, my mother, my father, my grandparents, and my sisters for always
supporting me.
Contents
1
Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
1.1 The New Mechanistic Approach: Core Ideas . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
1.2 Why the Metaphysics of Mechanisms Matters . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
1.3 Consequences for the Philosophy of Mind . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
1.4 Goals and Overview . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
1
2
7
9
11
13
2
Theories of Mechanism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
2.1 Wesley Salmon’s Approach, the Ontic View, and the CausalConstitutive Distinction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
2.2 Complex System Mechanisms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
2.3 The Acting Entities Approach. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
2.4 Acting Entities Mechanisms and the Etiological/Constitutive
Distinction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
2.5 Comparing Complex System Mechanisms and Acting
Entities Mechanisms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
2.6 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
17
18
22
25
30
32
35
36
3
Types of Mechanisms: Ephemeral, Regular, Functional . . . . . . . . . .
3.1 Functional Mechanisms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
3.2 Regular Mechanisms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
3.3 Reversely Regular Mechanisms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
3.4 Individuating Mechanism Types . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
3.5 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
39
41
47
58
61
64
66
4
Entity–Activity Dualism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
4.1 What Are Entities? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
4.2 What Are Activities? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
4.3 Entity–Occurrent Dualism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
4.4 Activity Causation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
69
70
72
79
81
vii
viii
Contents
4.5 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
90
92
5
Mechanistic Componency, Relevance, and Levels . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
5.1 Causal Relevance . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
5.2 Constitutive Relevance . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
5.3 Organization and Levels of Mechanisms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
5.4 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
95
95
98
102
107
108
6
Mechanistic Phenomena . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
6.1 Mechanisms Do Not Explain Capacities . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
6.2 The Functionalist View of Constitutive Mechanistic
Phenomena . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
6.3 The Behaving Entity View of Constitutive Mechanistic
Phenomena . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
6.4 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
111
113
7
Causation and Constitution . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
7.1 Two Notions of Causation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
7.2 Constitution: Connecting the Dots . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
7.3 A New Interventionist Approach to Constitutive Relevance . . . . . .
7.4 Interlevel Causation and Exclusion Worries . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
7.5 Mechanistic Constitution . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
7.6 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
129
130
135
137
146
149
150
151
8
Autonomy, Laws of Nature, and the Mind–Body Problem . . . . . . . .
8.1 Summary: The Metaphysics of Mechanisms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
8.2 The Autonomy of the Special Sciences . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
8.3 Mechanisms vs. Laws—Is the New Mechanistic Approach
Original? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
8.4 Non-reductive Physicalism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
155
155
159
114
120
124
125
160
162
163
List of Figures
Fig. 2.1
Fig. 2.2
Fig. 2.3
Fig. 3.1
Fig. 3.2
Fig. 3.3
Fig. 3.4
Illustration of a mechanism and its relation to the phenomenon
in etiological mechanistic explanation ............................................
Illustration of a complex system mechanism. The larger box
is an entity/object that is the mechanism (e.g., a heart); the smaller
boxes are the parts (e.g., the right atrium, the right ventricle)
of the larger entity that have the relevant dispositions that,
if manifested, would create interactions such that the larger
entity shows the behavior with regard to which the larger entity
is a mechanism (e.g., pumping blood). The empty spaces between
the parts are also occupied by parts of the complex system
mechanism; but these parts are not included in the relevant
decomposition of the complex system mechanism .........................
Illustration of the etiological mechanism
(i.e., the EA-mechanism causing the phenomenon)
and the constitutive mechanism (i.e., the EA-mechanism
constituting the phenomenon) of a given phenomenon ..................
Factual regularity: The relationship between types A and B
is factually regular since A has multiple instances a1–a4
that bring about (cause or constitute) instances of B b1–b4 .............
Stochastic regularity: The relationship between type A and type B
is stochastically regular since some but not all instances of A
a1–a7 bring about (cause or constitute) instances of B ....................
High-failure mechanism: Type A has a high failure rate with
respect to bringing about instances of type B since most of its
instances a1–a11 do not bring about (cause or constitute)
an instance of B...............................................................................
Illustration of the cancer mechanism. (Illustration inspired by
Grundmann 2000, Chap. 8).............................................................
22
24
31
49
51
52
53
ix
x
Fig. 3.5
Fig. 3.6
Fig. 3.7
Fig. 4.1
Fig. 5.1
Fig. 5.2
Fig. 5.3
Fig. 5.4
Fig. 5.5
Fig. 7.1
Fig. 7.2
Fig. 7.3
Fig. 7.4
Fig. 7.5
List of Figures
Comparative regularity: The relationship between types A and B
is comparatively regular since there are more instances of A a1–a9
that bring about an instance of B than instances of A that bring
about a particular other type—the instances that do not bring
about an instance of B bring about tokens that are instances
of various different types C, D, E, F, G...........................................
Reverse regularity: The relationship between types A and B
is reversely regular since all instances of B b1–b4
are caused/constituted by instances of A ........................................
Comparative reverse regularity: The relationship between types
A and B is comparatively reversely regular since more instances
of B are brought about by an instance of A than by any other
type—the instances of B that are not brought about by
an instance of A are due to instances of various different
types J, K, L, M, N ..........................................................................
Illustration of (a) a spatial EIO-part of an EIO,
and (b) a temporal EIO-part of an EIO ..........................................
Causal graph of a common cause structure.....................................
Mutual manipulability in terms of interventions: the
phenomenon (represented by variable Ψ) and a component
(Φi ∈ Φ1–Φ3) are mutually manipulable iff there is an ideal
intervention IΨ on Ψ with respect to Φi that changes Φi,
and there is an ideal intervention IΦi on Φi with respect
to Ψ that changes Ψ. (Adapted from Baumgartner
and Gebharter 2015) .......................................................................
Example of different level of mechanisms. (Krickel 2017, 2018;
loosely adapted from Craver 2007a, 166) .......................................
Verticality of mechanistic levels: Craver’s notion of levels
of mechanisms implies that levels are relative to phenomena
at a specific point in time ................................................................
Mechanistic levels with horizontal extension .................................
The Craver diagram. (Adapted from Craver 2007, 7) .....................
Illustration of a constitutive mechanism: modification
of the Craver-diagram based on the metaphysical considerations
from the previous chapters ..............................................................
Mutual manipulability as a relation between a component
and temporal EIO-parts of the phenomenon ...................................
Constitutive relevance in terms of interventionism requires
two ideal* interventions (a) (bottom-up intervention)
and (b) (top-down intervention) ......................................................
Interlevel causation between temporal EIO-parts
of phenomena (transparent slices) and components
of mechanisms (grey tubes) ............................................................
56
58
61
80
96
100
103
104
107
136
137
140
140
147