Democracy, Markets, and The Legal Order: Notes On The Nature of Politics in A Radically Liberal Society
Democracy, Markets, and The Legal Order: Notes On The Nature of Politics in A Radically Liberal Society
Democracy, Markets, and The Legal Order: Notes On The Nature of Politics in A Radically Liberal Society
On the extreme wing of libertarian ideology are the individualist anarchists, who wish to dispense with government altogether. The
quasi-legitimate functions now performed by government, such as
the administration of justice, can, the anarchists claim, be provided
in the marketplace.
George H. Smith1
,
|
103
104
DON LAVOIE
an uncompromising radical who, for example, debated the merits of regicide.2 They aspired to a radicalization of economic and political liberalism, to the principled extension of the ideals of both democracy and
markets.
Just as socialism transformed almost everything else in this century, it
transformed liberalism, but I want to focus on the ideology in what we
might call its pre- and post-socialist forms. The form in which it arose, before the socialist episode, aspired to be a genuine radicalism, and the form
it may now be able to take in the aftermath of socialism will, I think, be
radical again. Pre-socialist liberalism was, like the ideology if not the practice of socialism, highly distrustful of governments in regard to civil liberties and the conduct of war; but unlike socialist ideology, it was also
distrustful of the state in regard to the economy. Many of the intellectual
leaders in the emerging societies of Eastern Europe are unmistakably liberal in this classical, pre-socialist sense.3
Unfortunately, this classical-liberal radicalism failed. Although the original liberalism of Locke, Sidney, et al. was radical in spirit, it failed to
achieve its own ideals. The view among even the most radical liberals was
that democracy is a form of government, and that government is a necessary evil whose scope in society needs to be strictly limited, so that democracy has a necessarily constricted role at best. This essay suggests that
the cost of this position on democracy was the loss of liberalism's radicalism, and that those who would like to re-radicalize the ideology today
should reconsider the role of government and the nature of democracy.
I. DEMOCRACY AND MARKETS
Liberals from the newly liberated countries typically differ from Western liberals on what democracy and markets are, and on whether they
ultimately fit with one another. The Eastern European liberals seem to
idealize democracy and markets, and to think of them as fully complementary. Western liberals, who have experienced "really existing liberalism" in the democratic-capitalist societies, have certainly enjoyed more
democracy and markets than the Eastern European liberals, and seem to
be far less enthused about the ideals, and to think of them as in some sort
of necessary tension with one another. Liberalism in this view is a pragmatic compromise between its own two ideals, neither of which can be
radicalizedthat is, taken to its logical extremewithout endangering the
other. The ideals that won together in Eastern Europe have been having
2
i
I
1
i
!
|
!
|
|
1
j
i
j
I
!
105
A good example of the disillusion with democracy is expressed in Vaclav Havel's article "Paradise Lost," New York Revieiv of Books, April 9,1992.
5
The compromises have divided liberalism into two kinds, each of which bears little
similarity to the original ideal. Some self-styled liberals favor conservative policies such as
aggressive militarism; others favor socialist ones such as intrusive welfare statism. Gone is
the principled opposition to government so characteristic of classical-liberal doctrine.
106
DON LAVOIE
Our Western liberalism is old, tired, worn out, and compromised. Perhaps, then, it is those who have been denied the ideals of liberalism, by
being forced to get by in a system that systematically tried to crush democratic and market processes, who know them in their essence, who
know them as ideals. Maybe out of the newly liberated societies' enthusiasm for liberal values can be forged a more radical sort of liberalism, a
liberalism that is more true to its own ideals.
Liberalism needs to reinterpret its notions of markets and democracy
in such a way that they fundamentally fit with each other. The principles
of political and economic liberalism can be understood in a manner that
makes them essentially complementary, but this will require some profound changes in the way we think about both. Seeing democracy and
markets as essentially complementary suggests the possibility that we do
not need to balance them off one another, and that they can each be taken
considerably further than we have yet taken them.
Liberalism lost in its confrontation with the ideology of socialism because it never really reconciled its own two ideals with one another, or
even came to a very satisfactory understanding of what they are. Socialism arose in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries by taking
the moral high ground away from liberalism, claiming to go radically beyond mere bourgeois democracy and exploitative capitalism. Marxism
saw the conflict between liberalism's two ideals and proposed to radicalize
the one by eliminating the other. It challenged liberalism for not going far
enough with democracy by limiting it to the election of representatives to
run government. Government under capitalism, Marx said, is always in
the pocket of the capitalists. And I would have to admit that there is some
truth to this charge. Any government, no matter how democratically
formed, needs to watch the stock market, and if its policies seem to contradict the /'wishes of Capital," so to speak, they will be revised.
Classical liberalism understood the institutional preconditions of markets better, I think, than it understood the nature of democracy. It accepted too narrow a formulation of democracy as merely a useful form of
government, the very institution that most of its rhetoric criticized. It aspired not to achieve any high ideals with democratic government but
merely to immunize the legal order from democratic government's manipulation. Government, whether democratic or not, needs to have its
hands tied to keep it from undermining markets. The result was that liberalism lost to socialism vthe claim of being democracy's natural ideological home.
Socialism promised to do what liberalism could not: combine and radicalize economics and politics. It would replace a hollow, hypocritical system of votingin which democracy is at the mercy of Capitalwith a
genuine, direct participation in the planning of economic activity. The
economy would no longer be a separate force limiting democracy, but a
direct consequence of conscious, rational, and democratic decision-making
107
I
j
Western ideological socialism was also parasitic on really existing socialism in its notion
of totality, which presumed that the standpoint of the proletariat was a kind of privileged,
totalistic view of history which gave it meaning. The gradual loss of faith in this totality has
meant a loss of historical meaning, and thus a collapse of the whole socialist perspective on
the world. See Martin Jay, Marxism and Totality: Vie Adivnhircs of a Concept from Lukdcs to HaIvrmas (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984).
7
For a concise critique of the decline of radical liberalism, see Albert Jay Nock, "Liberalism, Properly So Called," in 77i<? State of the Union: Essays in Social Criticism (1943; Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1991).
108
DON LAVOIE
the socialist epoch.8 What is needed is a fresh attempt to articulate a radical liberal vision that recovers not the details but the original essence of
classical liberalism: democracy and markets.
Conventional, moderate liberalism advocates the two ideals of democracy and markets, but it does not truly embrace them. It all too quickly
assumes that the existing institutional framework of Western democraticcapitalist societies constitutes a practical realization of liberal ideals. It
defines markets and democracy as completely distinct values, articulated
in the artificially separated domains of economics and political science.
Democracy is a form of government in which citizens can vote for their
leaders. Markets are apolitical forces driven by self-interested activities.
One is in the private sector, the other is in the public sector. One is epitomized by the (impersonal) act of voting, the other is epitomized by the
(impersonal) act of buying and selling. Markets are judged according to
the efficiency of their exchange outcomes in giving consumers what they
want. Democracy is judged according to the efficiency of its electoral outcomes in giving voters what they want.
TJiis conventional understanding takes for granted a meaning of democracy and
markets that does not correspond to the real processes that have made Western
democratic capitalism so much more successful than the Soviet experiment.
Francis Fukuyama makes the dramatic claim that the collapse of the
anti-democratic and anti-market Communist regimes represents the last
gasp of liberalism's opponents. 9 The pattern of history from the turn of
the century to the thirties, when classical liberalism was overcome by the
ideologies of fascism and Communism, has been reversed. Now that liberalism's right- and left-wing challengers have been utterly defeated, he
argues, we have arrived at the End of History, in Hegel's sense. Western
liberalismby which he seems to mean the combination of a relatively
democratic form of government with a relatively market-oriented economyis simply the best possible political-economic system.
Fukuyama is right in seeing the end of Communism as a victory for
economic and political "liberalism," but his vague use of the term conceals the fundamental problem. The manner in which democracy and
markets are generally understood is such as to set them necessarily at odds
with one another. The problem with conventional liberalism's combination of democracy and markets is that, the way they are each understood,
the more one of them advances, the less room there is for the other. Radicalized democracy would seem to imply that decisions that now are left
to the (unconscious) forces of the market, would instead be (consciously)
undertaken by a democratic government. Radicalized free markets would
seem to imply that decisions that are now taken by (persons on behalf of)
8
The next section will briefly summarize the two main correctives I believe a post-socialist
liberalism needs to be built upon, pertaining to the illusions of modernism in philosophy
and social engineering in economics.
9
Francis Fukuyama, "The End of History," Vie Naliotial Interest, Summer 1989, pp. 3-18.
109
democratically legitimated governments, would be left instead to the (impersonal) market. The ideals, as they are understood, cannot be taken too
seriously, or they will collide head-on with one another.
It seems to me that the underlying notions of democracy and markets
have more in common than the fact that totalitarian ideologies hated them
both. The fact that they have been thought to be in fundamental conflict
with one another might be a reflection of the incompleteness of our liberalism. Maybe we in the West have not understood either democracy or
markets well enough. Perhaps the societies we live in are not really the
living embodiments of political and economic liberalism that Fukuyama
seems to imply they are.
As someone who considers our established political-economic system
far from ideal on both political and economic grounds, I find Fukuyama's
complacent attitude about Western systems disturbing. I too consider the
collapse of socialism to signal a triumph of political and economic liberalism, but I want to insist that the liberalism that is triumphant is not
what we in the West already have, but is an incomplete project. Liberalism has not realized its own political and economic aspirations. There is
a great deal of history left to happen in the development of a genuine liberalism, that is, one which truly advances both democratic and market
processes.
A reinterpretation of liberalism might take its cue from the collapse of
the Soviet system, on the hunch that the totalitarians had an insight
about the essence of liberalism from which we can learn: the insight that
the ideals of democracy and markets are essentially complementary. The
defeat of the Soviet system was a victory for both political and economic
liberalism, for both democracy-oriented politics and market-oriented economics.
II. LIBERALISM AS OPENNESS
110
DON LAVOIE
needs to move beyond the model of the atomistic individual and take into
account the cultural underpinnings of markets. Our politics needs to
move beyond the model of the exercise of some kind of unified, conscious
democratic will and understand democratic processes as distributed
throughout the political culture.
The most important lesson to be learned from the experience of socialism is that economic development cannot be engineered but depends
on the decentralized knowledge of market participants. The classic challenge the Austrian economists Ludwig von Mises and F. A. Hayek issued
to socialism some seventy years ago shows why we need open competitive markets in order to marshal knowledge effectively. The price system
involves what one might call a system of distributed intelligence. Market
prices are our "eyes" on the economy, so that attempting to eliminate
them, as traditional Marxism did, or to interfere with them, as all Western democratic-capitalist governments have, blinds or clouds our vision.12 In principle, then, wherever possible, free-market competition
should dictate economic change, and government should get out of the
way.13
I suspect a similar line of argument can be made in regard to politics
and our view of democracy. The force of public opinion, like that of markets, is not best conceived as a concentrated will representing the public, but as the distributed influence of political discourses throughout
society. These open discourses are our eyes on the polity, and the attempt
to resolve their differences into a single political will embodied in a monopoly institution destroys our political vision. We must not reduce our
understanding of democracy to a view of the form of government which
allows periodic elections. We should recognize, rather, that for a society
to be democratic it is neither necessary nor sufficient for it to be ruled by
a particular form of government. More important than whether the government permits regular elections is the issue of whether all the other institutions of human interaction are imbued with a democratic spirit, with
an open political culture.
12
111
What are the qualities of the political culture which characterize liberalism? What I think we should mean by democracy is the distinctive kind
of openness in society which the Soviet system crushed, and which began
to recover under the banner of glasnost.14 Clasnost is the making public of
things. The Russian word translates better into "openness" than it does
into "democracy." Some Western defenders of democratic governments
have complained about the common translation into "democracy" on the
grounds that openness is not the same thing as the holding of periodic
elections, so that the glasnost movement should not be called a democratic
movement at all. I suspect, on the contrary, that the movement captures
the underlying essence of democracy better than our Western democratic
institutions do.
It seems to me that this openness and publicness, not some particular
theory of how to elect the personnel of government, is the essence of democracy. Like the market, a democratic polity exhibits a kind of distributed intelligence, not representable by any single organization which may
claim to act on society's behalf. Democracy is not a quality of the conscious will of a representative organization that has been legitimated by
the public, but a quality of the discursive process of the distributed wills
of the public itself. The Soviet system had no democracy in the liberal
sense, because it had no public opinion.
Traditional thinking about democracy has presupposed the need to assign to one monopoly institution the role of representing the democratic
will, as expressing a boiled-down version of the distributed public opinion. But we can question what happens to democracy in the boiling-down
process. We can question whether the nation-state, historically the most
significant enemy of democratic values, is well-suited to this role as the
primary vehicle for democracy. The force of public opinion is there in a
free society whether or not a single representative body is set up to embody it. Is not the essence of democracy rather a matter of the openness
of the system to bottom-up influence over social rules by the distributed
wills of the public? The state can be undemocratic, in the sense of not
open to electoral politics, as in Hong Kong, and yet the power of democratic forces can be great.
Democracy is all too often identified with a particular democratically legitimated institution, with the narrow idea of a government that risks itself to periodic elections. Radicalizing it is too often imagined as moving
toward "direct democracy," voting directly for social outcomes. But there
14
For a more extensive argument along these lines, see Don Lavoie, "Glasnost and the
Knowledge Problem: Rethinking Economic Democracy," Cato Journal, vol. 2, no. 3 (Winter
1992), pp. 435-55. The idea of openness has been elaborated by hermeneutical philosophy
in its account of the conditions for mutual understanding in everyday life, in the humanities, and in science. See, for example, Richard J. Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hennencutics, and Praxis (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983);
Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, revised translation by J. Weinsheimer and D. Marshall (1960; New York: Crossroad, 1989); and Georgia VVarnke, Gadamer. Hennencutics, Tradition, and Reason (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1987).
112
DON LAVOIE
See Hannah Arendt, Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Tltought (1954;
New York: Penguin, 1977).
16
On the common law, see F. A. Hayek, Law, Legislation, and Liberty: A Neiv Statemctit of
the Liberal Principles of Justice and Political Economy, vol. 1, Rules and Order (London: Routledge
& Kegan Paul, 1973); and Arthur R. Hogue, Origins of the Common Law (Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1966).
113
alienation, between agents that there is no possibility of democratic discourse. This line of critique remains a crucial element of the contemporary
left. The neo-Marxian social theorist Jiirgen Habermas, whose approach
to democratic politics is very much in the spirit of what I have been saying, retains the traditional Marxist's distrust of markets as inherently undemocratic institutions. His worry that markets threaten to/'colonize the
life-world" derives from this widespread interpretation of markets, shared
by their supporters as well as their critics, as essentially impersonalized
mechanisms.17
To be sure, not everyone who advocates the spread of markets really
sees them this way. As one liberal put it, the pro-market philosophy is
frequently attacked with the "tired canard that classically liberal rights
deny the essentially social nature of human beings, that they are crafted
for self-sufficient 'monads' complete unto themselves." 18 But is this
charge really groundless? A significant component of liberal literature
certainly much of its economic analysisprojects exactly this view of individuals as asocial monads, whose preferences confront one another in
impersonal markets.19 Liberalism was born in the Enlightenment, and its
writings often show its modernist pedigree. Only recently have a significant number of liberals begun to take seriously the philosophical critique
of modernism and the social nature of human beings.20
Likewise, seeing markets as driven by narrowly materialistic motivations excludes the realm of democratic politics. Agents in markets are
supposed to be motivated by the narrow pursuit of profit instead of noble
ideals. Marketplaces are understood to be the locus of antisocial conflicts
among bickering traders. People selfishly bickering over price cannot, it
seems, by truly engaged in a democratic discourse over their mutual
rights and responsibilities as citizens.
17
See Jiirgen Habermas, Vie Tlicory of Communicative Action, vol. 1, Reason and the Rationalization of Society (Boston: Beacon Press, 1984), and vol. 2, Lifeuvrld and System: A Critique
of Functionalist Reason (Boston: Beacon Press, 1987). For a particularly stark presentation of
this image of markets as impersonal, see Elizabeth Anderson, "The Ethical Limitations of
the Market," Economics and Philosophy, vol. 6 (1990), pp. 179-205.
18
See Loren E. Lomasky, "Duty Call," Reason, April 1992, p. 51.
19
For examples of analyses of economic phenomena that take culture seriously, see
Mary Douglas and Baron Isherwood, Vie Wbrld of Goods: Tminrds an Anthropology of Consumption (London: Allen Lane, 1979); a n d Georg Simmel, Essays on Interpretation in Social Science,
translated, edited, a n d introduced by G. Oakes (1907; Totowa, NJ: R o w m a n & Littlefield,
1978). Even writings in the Austrian school, although far less guilty of this modernist vice
than neoclassical economics, evidence a n acultural view of h u m a n agents. See, for example, my critique of Israel Kirzner along these lines in "The Discovery a n d Interpretation of
Profit Opportunities: Culture and the Kirznerian Entrepreneur," in Brigitte Berger, ed., Vie
Culture of Entrcprcneurship (San Francisco: Institute for Contemporary Studies, 1991).
20
The postmodern liberalism that is occasionally being presented in t h e pages of t h e
journal Critical Review is beginning to correct for this atomistic element in traditional liberalism. See also G . B. Madison, Vie Logic of Ulvrty (New York: Greenwood Press, 1986),
and Madison, "Getting Beyond Objectivism: The Philosophical Hermeneutics of Gadamer
and Ricoeur," in Don Lavoie, e d . , Economics and Hermeneutics (London: Routledge, 1991),
p p . 34-58.
114
DON LAVOIE
Liberals should not concede so much to the socialist view of the world.
Markets are not essentially impersonal confrontations. Of course, modern markets make possible more distanced interactions with people. But
Marx's claims that markets made people atomistic is on weak empirical
grounds. Inside the firm, in business lunches, at street corners, interpersonal discourses are constantly going on in markets. In all those places
there is a politics going on, a politics that can be more or less democratic.
Nor are markets inherently or typically a matter of crass, merely materialistic motivations. Critics often find repulsive the liberals' ideas of
leaving such services as education or medicine, much less the provision
of legal services, "to the market." The repulsion arises, I think, from the
apolitical notion of individuals and markets. The services we buy and sell
from one another are not necessarily "mere commodities," and our mutual relations are not necessarily distanced. On the contrary, many of the
things we buy and sell are deeply imbued with social meaning. We pay
for services to satisfy our desires for health, companionship, musical pleasure, peace of mind; and these goals are not necessarily cheapened just
because they can be bought. Leaving a service to "the forces of supply
and demand" does not remove it from human decision making, since everything will depend on exactly what it is that the suppliers and demanders are trying to achieve.
If we redefine markets and democracy in terms of the more fundamental value of openness, we may find that the radicalization of these principles poses a challenge to the traditional interpretation of liberalism.
III. POLITICAL CULTURE AND THE LEGAL ORDER
115
These debates may seem a bit arcane and remote from real-world problems, but the free-market anarchist positions represented by Rothbard
and Friedman are not as absurd as they appear, and are worthy of serious attention.25 As Bruce Benson's recent scholarship shows, there are
many cases in history of legal systems working quite effectively without
government.26 The articulation of a Utopian society that claims to eliminate politics altogether highlights the question this essay is raising about
what we ought to mean by politics and by democracy. These debates over
ways of establishing a legal order offer an opportunity to rethink the
relationship between democratic politics and the market economy.
A radically liberal society might be imaginable in which there is nothing left for government, a monopoly of the use of force, to do. The legal
services government now provides could be provided competitively, according to the laws of supply and demand. According to free-market
anarchism, all the fundamental institutions necessary for the market to
functionmoney, police protection, and even justicewould themselves
be "for sale on the market." Of course, to say justice would be "for sale
on the market to the highest bidder" is to invite ridicule. If a court is deciding law according to which party to the dispute can pay better, then
the "service" it is supplying does not deserve the name "justice." But as
with any good, everything depends on what specifically the suppliers
and demanders actually want. It is imaginable that the demand for legal
services could be well-defined, so that competitive pressures could force
suppliers to offer fair adjudication according to widely understood principles of the rule of law.
Nozick's well-known critique of the free-market anarchists was a normative challenge, arguing that a competitive legal system could evolve
step-by-step toward a monopoly government without ever violating in25
1 think that this anarchist policy conclusion is more reasonable than it must appear to
most readers; however, I find the atomistic individualist perspective in which it is couched
by Rothbard and Friedman unacceptable. This notion of free-market anarchism has to be
distinguished, of course, from traditional left-wing anarchism, which does not necessarily
share its hyper-individualism, but which has other serious problems. On left-wing anarchism, see Michael Bakunin, "Statism and Anarchy," in Sam Dolgoff, ed., Bakunin on Anarchy (1873; New York: Vintage, 1971); and Marshall S. Shatz, ed., Vie Essential Works of
Anarchism (New York: Bantam, 1971).
26
The study by Bruce L. Benson, Vie Enterprise of Law: Justice without the Stale (San Fran-
cisco: Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy, 1990), raises the scholarly level of debate
considerably above that of the Rothbard and Friedman polemics. It persuades me that a freemarket anarchist society would be workable, at least under certain plausible cultural conditions; but I think it will convince very few readers, mainly because the cultural
preconditions are not discussed. Free-market anarchism remains unpersuasive to most
people not primarily because of any shortcomings of the arguments its proponents make,
but because of shortcomings of our background notions of markets and democracy. Behind
the objections most people have to the anarchist position is a fear that it would rob us of
a deeply cherished value, democracy. In my own view, a radically market-oriented society
with a severely limited or perhaps even abolished government could turn out to be a more
"democratic" kind of system, properly understood, than the Western-style democracies we
are used to.
116
DON LAVOIE
The term "ideology" is misleading here, since w e are not interested in articulated systems of ideas but rather in the sorts of tacit beliefs that inform concrete practices.
28
Murray Rothbard, "Will Rothbard's Free-Market Justice Suffice? Yes," Reason, May
1973, p p . 19-25.
29
Tyler Cowen, " L a w as a Public Good: T h e Economics of Anarchy," unpublished
manuscript, George Mason University, 1991.
117
118
DON LAVOIE
terfere with) the decentralized market sphere. In the debates over the
supply of justice services, the anarchists have tended to picture the legal
order nonpolitically, and the limited governmentalists to picture it noneconomically. I think both of these ways of thinking about the legal order need to be challenged. Each is a one-sided way of viewing political
economy, which should be seen as an inseparable whole.
Rothbard and Friedman are a case in point. They take the position that
politics (and hence any positive notion of democracy) is by definition a
matter of government, so that the whole topic is, as it were, summarily
dismissed. There is no need for political discourse in the Utopias of these
authors, since agents simply "buy" justice services on an impersonal
competitive market. Friedman's approach leaves the enforcement, interpretation, and definition of rights to be "decided by the market." In Rothbard's case, enforcement and interpretation are left to private police and
courts, but the legal rules are supposed to be derived from natural law,
established once and for all by a deductive science of ethics.
In either case, there is no room in these Utopias for politics. At most,
political discourse is only needed in order to drive the process that brings
about a radically liberal society, but once the free society exists, all the
work of politics is over.30 The definition of rights is decided without the
need for discourse, either by the force of an impersonal market, or by
the force of an unquestionable logic.
Liberals cannot resolve the issue of whether a legal system could be
supplied by a free market because the issue depends on what is happening in the political culture, in the ongoing discourses about mutual rights
and obligations, which individualist liberalism, in both limited-government and anarchist versions, utterly ignores. Radical liberals have been
so intent on establishing a universal system of individual rights that they
have failed to address the cultural conditions in which socialized individuals would demand this or that kind of legal services.
To say we should leave everything to be "decided by markets" does
not, as radical liberals suppose, relieve liberalism of the need to deal with
the whole realm of politics. And to severely limit or even abolish government does not necessarily remove the need for democratic processes in
nongovernmental institutions.
The reason liberals in general have had trouble convincing others of the
desirability of extending marketsand the reason anarchist liberals have
had trouble convincing limited governmentalists to extend them to law
30
Indeed, this may be giving these authors too much credit. Political discourse presupposes an open exploration of issues of mutual concern. It seems that for Rothbard and his
followers, genuine political discourse is not even needed in order to get to the free society.
Instead, it seems there needs to be what is essentially a religious-conversion experience. The
definition of rights is not open to exploratory dialogue but presumed to have been accomplished once and for all in Rothbard's Ethics of Liberty (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities
Press, 1982).
119
is that they have all lacked an adequate theory of politics. Since markets
are assumed to be essentially apolitical, their radicalization seems to imply the end of politics. Extending the market, according to individualist
liberals, seems to mean that we would become the atomistic monads
Marx thought we were becoming.
The weakness of both sides in the debates over anarchism is their neglect of what lies behind the legal order. Why does anybody obey the
law, whether it is conceived as being supplied in a competitive or monopolistic manner? Limited-government advocates assume that it is the ultimate threat of force by a monopoly state that ensures that individuals will
obey the law. Anarchists assume that there is a demand for genuine justice on the part of individual agents, so that competitive courts will profit
most from behaving in a properly liberal manner. Both beg the question
of the political culture. What gives legitimacy to a legal system is neither
the force of threat by the police, nor the force of pure logic, but the force
of public opinion, of the distributed political discourse about rights and
responsibilities.
IV. CONCLUSION
What does all this have to do with contemporary realities of post-socialist societies? Neither limited-government nor anarchist forms of radical
liberalism are likely to carry the day in the near future in places like Russia or Poland. A people so recently recovering from the excesses of a
failed radicalism are apt to resist leaping directly to another utopiansounding idealism.
Moreover, the special challenges of these societies, their severe economic problems, their rising and sometimes strident expressions of nationalism, make experimentation with any ideal policies difficult in the
extreme. The argument could be made that the political culture of these
societies has been systematically shaped in nonliberal ways for decades,
so that neither markets nor democracy have much prospects for survival.
On the other hand, the case could be made that the political culture in
the newly liberated societies is not far from that which would make a radical liberalism an attractive alternative. First of all, the fact that anti-liberal
socialist ideology has been the state religion in those societies for many
years should not be taken to mean that the bulk of the population has
bought into the religion. The severe economic and political problems of
these societies are widely understood to be the legacy of socialism. Nowhere can one find less tolerance for Marxian notions than in this part of
the world. Nowhere are people as deeply and consistently suspicious of
government. Nowhere are the institutions of markets and democracy valued as highly as where their absence is within vivid memory.
The spirit of nationalism that now sees its expression in violent clashes
may yet be transformed into peaceful rivalry. Beneath the nationalism is
120
DON LAVOIE