Hume's Theory of Time and Trans-Temporal Identity
Hume's Theory of Time and Trans-Temporal Identity
Hume's Theory of Time and Trans-Temporal Identity
Mike Mackus
April 16th, 2009
Professor Bolton
Phil 297
In his science of man Hume holds that there is no rational way to justify the belief that objects, when
unperceived by the senses, continue to exist; and likewise, there is no way to justify the belief that objects have
an existence independent of the mind that perceives them. The proof of each is rather straightforward: the
former is simply unscientific in the sense that it is not falsifiable (the proposition that Object x exists even when
unperceived cannot be verified empirically); and the latter belief turns Hume’s empiricism on its head (that is, it
undermines the basic principle that the mind only has impressions and ideas and that we do not have direct
access to the physical world, thus not enabling us to separate our mind from the impressions and ideas that
occupy it). Hume contends that these two beliefs are necessary consequences of one another such that if and
only if an object exists when it is not present to the senses then the object has an existence independent from the
mind: iff an object has continued existence then it has a distinct existence. While Hume, as a philosopher, rejects
the claim that we can justify our beliefs in continued and distinct bodies, he realizes that one does so only after
sincere, reflective thinking, thinking that takes one out of a normal frame of mind; the fact remains that humans
appear to have a natural inclination to believe that bodies are continued and distinct and this is what is of
importance to Hume: regardless of what can be rationally justified, humans hold these beliefs and thus Hume
Given the relation between the idea of a continued body and the idea of a distinct body, i.e. that they are
necessary consequences of one another, Hume states that if we can identify the source of the one belief then we
can also account for the other as well. He proposes three candidates as the possible source of our (vulgar)
opinions: the senses, reason, and the imagination. Hume quickly dismisses the senses as the source, arguing,
“When the mind looks farther than what immediately appears to it, its conclusions can never be put to the
account of the senses” (T 189). To say that the senses can account for the belief in a continued body is simply a
contradiction in the role of the senses: it is as if we would be saying that the senses are continuing to operate and
2
give us information about an external object even when the external object is not presenting the mind with an
impression. Likewise with the belief of a distinct body, the object provides the mind with an impression and thus
the existence of that impression is contingent on the existence of mind holding it. The senses do not have direct
access to the physical world, hence we cannot argue for a double existence, the existence of a distinct body and
of an impression, from just the fact that there is an impression presented to the mind.
Moving onto reason as a possible source of the (vulgar) belief in continued and distinct bodies, Hume
dismisses this on similar grounds as the senses. As we have already observed, the natural beliefs that Hume
wants to account for are likely to be rationally unjustifiable so it is easy to see why reason would not be the
source of unreasonable ideas. Concluding that it is reason that provides us with beliefs of continued and distinct
bodies undermines the main tenets of Hume’s philosophy, namely his concept empiricism: reason tells us, Hume
would argue, that the only things in the mind are impressions and ideas and thus there is no way to draw
conclusion about continued/distinct bodies from perceptions of broken and interrupted perceptions. So then it is
only the imagination that is left as a source for these conclusions. While the imagination seems like a rather
vague term, that Hume might be using it to just dodge the question, he provides an account that makes the
imagination a functional part of the mind: given certain inputs it will spit out certain outputs according to
general patterns and principles. In this case, the general principles are those of constancy and coherence.
According to Hume’s principle of constancy, objects that we attribute a continued existence to have constancy
that makes the mind distinguish between the impression and the object. For example, each and every time I walk
up to my house it is the same color, size, shape, etc., as it was the last time I perceived it; this constancy of the
impression acts as a repetitive input in the mind, leading to the output that this house is the same house that I
entered the day before; thus, despite the gaps in time, I form the belief that each impression of my house is the
result of the same distinct, external body being presented to my senses. But humans also are naturally inclined to
hold the belief that two impressions presented to the mind at different times may still be caused by the same
individual object even though there may be a difference, say, in color, shape, etc. Hence, Hume argues that the
principle of coherence takes into account the changes in a body’s characteristics: the mind receives the
repetitive inputs of an object at various times but each impression, while maintaining a general resemblance,
3
continues to change in a way that becomes almost predictable; that is, the change in an object is coherent. For
example, as I approach my house, for the most part, the impression maintains a constancy with the impression I
had yesterday; but, through the course of the fall, if no one rakes or cleans up the front yard each succeeding
impression of my house will be one with more litter and leaves across the lawn. The change is a coherent one for
(since no one in my house likes raking) each day the change will be one I have come to expect, i.e. there is more
leaves and litter on the front lawn. Rather than the difference convincing me that this is not the same house I
walked up to yesterday, the constancy and coherence provide me with the belief that this is my home, the same
The functional operations of the imagination, however, only supply Hume with the basis of
understanding the natural human beliefs in continued and distinct bodies. The constancy and coherence of
perceptions leads to the inference of continued existence and thus distinct existence; yet, simply stating the
functional operations of the imagination (i.e. noticing the outputs generated by given inputs) does not explain
why the mind is inclined to make the inference: there is a jump from constancy/coherence of perceptions to
continued/distinct existence of bodies. It cannot be a simple case of cause and effect because, though it may look
that way, the mind moves from sensory information- the image of an impression/idea- to assuming information
about external bodies that it does not have access to: “Any degree, therefore, of regularity in our perceptions,
can never be a foundation for us to infer a greater degree of regularity in some objects which are not perceived”
(T 197). Then in order to justify his account of our natural belief in trans-temporal identity Hume must address
two specific moves implicit within the mind’s inference from broken perceptions to continued bodies: first,
explain what is really meant by identity and where such an idea could be derived from; and secondly, explain
how the mind moves from this idea of identity to a belief in the continued existence of bodies. Hume’s
empiricism and his theory of time lead to an interesting puzzle about identity. It is not the traditional Fregean
puzzle of reference where two different lexical items refer back to the same thing but each item has different
truth-conditions for assertion; rather, Hume’s puzzle is a little simpler in the sense that it asks what is meant by
the proposition Object x is identical with itself. Formulating it this way, Hume shows that uttering an identity
statement is essentially meaningless when in regards to only a single object: Object x is identical with itself
4
contains no additional predicates or subjects aside from x and thus it is only a statement of unity. Yet we can
easily see, just as Hume argues, that a multiplicity of objects does equally as poor of a job of supplying an idea
Hume’s insight into a solution is intriguing: if identity is not compatible with the idea of unity or the
idea of number, he argues that there must be a “medium” between the two. Reintroducing his theory of time,
Hume argues that the idea of identity follows from the conjunction of two impressions: the idea of time passing
which arises from the impression of succeeding perceptions (i.e. changing perceptions, such as a man walking
by) combined with the uninterrupted and unvarying impression of another object. This scenario leads the mind
to believe that the unaltered object is also moving through this duration (of time) and thus we would want to say
that the present unchanging perception is identical with the unchanging perception from a moment ago.
However, for Hume, this identity is only a fiction created by the mind believing that the unchanging object is
also going through a supposed change in time. Moreover, although we recognize the conjunction of time and
unchanging object as the correspondent impression to the idea of identity, this does not explain our inclination to
hold particular metaphysical beliefs. But, as I agree, our understanding of identity seems to be not far from and
closely related to the belief in continued and distinct bodies. Our perceptions are constantly interrupted: to use
Hume’s example, one might close his eyes in the room that he is presently in, cutting off any visual sensory
stimuli, but upon reopening them perceives the room exactly as it was the moment before. These broken
perceptions are associated by what is, Hume argues, the strongest relation, that of resemblance; the strength of
this relationship between the various perceptions leads the mind to connect these broken perceptions as if they
had one single identity, for it appears that they are unchanging through time. The mind now arrives at a
contradiction: “The smooth passage of the imagination along the ideas of the resembling perceptions makes us
ascribe to them a perfect identity. The interrupted manner of their appearance makes us consider them so many
resembling, but still distinct beings, which appear after certain intervals” (T 205). Hume holds that such an inner
contradiction can only be solved by choosing one side over the other and thus, given the strength of the relation
of resemblance between what appears to be a smooth flow of perceptions, we attribute to the objects of our
The interesting part about Hume’s theory is the fact that it is not a metaphysical account of existence
and trans-temporal identity; rather, Hume’s empiricism disregards any possibility of justifying the beliefs that
objects have continued and distinct existence. However, for Hume as a scientist investigating the cognitive
architecture of the human mind he must be able to account for why humans seem predisposed towards certain
metaphysical beliefs about objects and identity. On the other hand, a metaphysician viewing Hume’s explanation
of natural human belief would have little concern for what those beliefs are and why they are held. For the
metaphysician there must be a separation from the way one is naturally inclined to perceive the world, rerouting
the focus to ask what is the actual ontological status of identity. Immediately evident is the fact that this is
incompatible with Hume’s concept empiricism: the only things present to the mind are perceptions and these
perceptions do not provide us with direct access to the external world; the metaphysician, according to Hume, is
speaking improperly any time he speaks of objects in the world when not really meaning perceptions. Since
Hume is skeptical of any metaphysical reasoning, his explanation of man’s inclination towards particular
metaphysical beliefs is greatly contrasted with accounts of identity that try to rationalize our intuitions about
trans-temporal identity. More simply, Hume shows the inconsistency in our beliefs while a metaphysician takes
the conclusions of our beliefs as accurate and then begins to formulate a theory that can rationally justify them.
For example, we might look at the theory of temporal parts as outlined by Theodore Sider. Generally, Sider’s
theory argues that time is like space in the respect that it has parts; just as my body can be spatially divided into
pieces, likewise I can be divided temporally along the lines of my instantaneous temporal parts. This proposes a
new way to think of identity: my identity is not my current temporal part but rather the summation of all my
instantaneous temporal parts; my being, then, is not really an object, but rather it is more like an event with a
beginning, middle and end. This is a simple overview of Sider’s theory but we already see that this is not the
way identity is naturally thought of in the human mind. It appears artificial and slightly ad-hoc because it is: the
theory of temporal parts is designed in response to the problems of defining identity such as temporary intrinsics
and paradoxes of material constitution. The difference between Hume and Sider is really just the simple fact that
they are concerned with different problems: Hume sees no rational way to justify the belief in continued and
distinct bodies so he must find a way to explain why humans still hold these beliefs; and Sider sees no way to
6
accurately ascribe identity to an object through time so he must formulate a theory that rids itself of difficulties
This simple contrast between Hume and Sider, however, directs attention to a much bigger point of
contention between the two: the former holds that trans-temporal identity is a fiction of the imagination while
the latter believes that trans-temporal identity ought to be accurately defined and understood. I believe that this
disagreement is rooted, for the most part, in the contrasting theories of time that each respectively holds. Sider’s
temporal parts theory is founded partly on eternalism; this holds that every moment in time is equally real and
that temporally distant objects are equally as real as ones that are near. Additionally, Sider holds that time is
relative in the sense that words like “now” are indexical and the meaning is contingent on the temporal location
of the speaker. The eternalist in him argues that all moments in time are equally real which consequently
requires him to say that time is relative: a temporal part of myself five years ago says “now” and means April
2004 while the present temporal part of me says “now” and means April 2009. So, for Sider, time is both
absolute and relative: there is a definitive timeline of events throughout the history of time but each event is
relative to observers at different locations in time. This may seem okay at first but we are left entirely clueless
on the question of what exactly time is: where is this master clock that defines the timeline of the universe; and
then what clock determines the accuracy of the first clock? Hume’s theory of time is rather ahead of itself in the
sense that Hume defines time as contingent upon the perception of an observer and closely related to and
determined by the motion of objects. Thus Hume’s idea of time is relative in a different sense, i.e. that time is
entirely in the eye of the beholder, not absolute like Sider’s timeline of history.
Nonetheless, we can still draw a connection between Sider’s and Hume’s theories: Sider understands
identity as a summation of temporal parts and Hume, likewise, understands identity to be a fiction of the mind
that connects spatiotemporally extended objects with one another. That is, both theories take the idea of identity
to be a relationship that bounds together a number of separate and distinct objects: an idea that is somewhere
between unity (a single object) and number (a multiplicity of unrelated objects). But, even if just for a moment,
we assume that Hume doesn’t think of identity as a fiction of the mind, his theory of time is problematic for the
practice of tracing: since time is an abstraction from a succession of perceptions, tracing must always take place
7
relative to another object that is not being traced; however, the perception of time is contingent upon the
observer and what he chooses to use as his “clock”; thus it seems that there are as many ways to trace identity as
there are tracers. Two points come to mind here: first, one might be inclined to argue that Sider is okay with this
because he believes all tracing scenarios have targets; but such is in support of a different argument for Sider
would not want to say that two people can trace, say, the same statue differently (which is possible according to
Hume’s theory of time because I might be seeing a constant, unchanging statue if my “clock” stops moving,
while you might see a number of different instantaneous temporal parts because your “clock” is moving). And
secondly, this sort of tracing leads to an idea of identity that is contradictory to our intuitions: that is, we would
want our tracing of the same objects to yield the same results.
There is an incompatibility between tracing, which figures in largely in Sider’s definition of identity,
and Hume’s theory of time. While Hume’s theory of time does seem somewhat awkward, Sider does not give us
any means by which to understand time within his framework of temporal parts which is obviously problematic:
if we are not given a way to understand this absolute timeline then how does Sider expect us to agree on what is
actually a temporal part and what is not? There are obvious differences that separate Hume’s account of natural
human inclinations towards particular metaphysical beliefs from Sider’s theory of temporal parts (such as
Hume’s commitment to the human mind and empiricism), but at a deeper level it appears that Hume’s theory of
time, which appears more accurate (both to our intuitions and our understanding of post-Newtonian physics),