Dorothea Kuhn On Goethe
Dorothea Kuhn On Goethe
Dorothea Kuhn On Goethe
Having to deal with just one problem out of the vast spectrum of
Goethe's works, of which those concerning the natural sciences represent again only a small part, calls for some explanation.
Goethe himself would certainly be pleased with the attention given
to those of his thoughts and works devoted to the natural sciences, for
during his lifetime they did not receive the understanding and respect
for which he had hoped. Indeed, even if one could hope that Goethe
would applaud at least one's good intentions, it is still rather a difficult
task to discuss his scientific studies and ideas.
First of all, there is the purely quantitative problem: his own writings
in the natural sciences are amazingly extensive. The voluminous edition
being published by the German Academy of Natural Scientists
[Deutsche Akademie der Naturforscher], Leopoldina and called, therefore, the Leopoldina edition, contains eleven weighty volumes of texts.
This edition had been planned almost half a century ago. The work was
begun forty years ago by the late Wilhelm Troll and Karl Lothar Wolf
with the assistance of Gunter Schmid and Rupprecht Matthaei. Today,
Wolf von Engelhardt and I, as editors, together with several colleagues,
continue work on the edition. In addition to the eleven volumes of texts
there will now be a number of volumes of commentary, five of which
have already been published. These supplemental volumes will contain
not only commentary but also Goethe's own working notes on which
they are based: notes on books which he read, subjects he had reflected
on, objects he had observed. His outlines for essays are printed there,
as are the drafts to his scientific writings, i.e. material that had remained
among Goethe's papers in the Goethe and Schiller Archives in Weimar.
Additionally, these volumes of commentary in the Leopoldina
edition include Goethe's remarks on scientific topics from his diaries,
letters, and autobiographical writings, as well as the pertinent comments
by Goethe's contemporaries and letters addressed to Goethe: conversations, reviews, and the like.
Endless sources and references are presented. It is not enough that
there is this much material by and addressed to Goethe. In 1940 when
3
F. Amrine, F. 1. Zucker, and H. Wheeler (eds.), Goethe and the Sciences:
ARe-appraisal, 3-15.
DOROTHEA KUHN
Gunter Schmid compiled his bibliography there were already more than
4,500 titles of literature about Goethe as a natural scientist. In the
meantime the 5,000th title has probably long since been passed.
Aside from the sheer quantity, the diversity of its content and its
interpretation is also intimidating. Is there anything left to be said on
this topic? In the 150 years,since Goethe's death one would think that
all of the problems should have been solved long ago. Only the fact that
there are still open questions and controversies, and that the history of
science offers new perspectives for solutions, encourages a contribution
concerning the question of the theories of evolution at the time of
Goethe.
The question of Goethe's position regarding the theories of evolution
in his day is being answered in very different and even controversial
ways. On the one hand, it is said that Goethe had ignored the question
of evolution in so far as it went beyond individual development. His
concept of type had been a rigid idea; the morphological method had
been an idealistic morphology and, therefore, far from evolutionary
concepts of a more general nature. On the other hand, Goethe has
repeatedly been regarded as the precursor of Darwin's theory of
evolution and as the prophet of the notion of actual descent. All
possible variations occur between these extremes.
I would like to try to take a position on this based on my work with
the Leopoldina edition. Working with Goethe's material and with the
references by him and his contemporaries has inspired me to reflect on
the connections between Goethe's perceptions and those current in his
time, and to assess their place in the process of the history of science.
In doing so, I will limit the scope of this paper by choosing examples
only from my field of research; namely, the history of biology. I must
omit the equally interesting problems of development in the geosciences.
I will explore three questions. First, what was the young Goethe's
attitude toward natural history? Then, which theories of evolution did
he encounter? And, finally, how did he perceive them and integrate
them into his own perceptions of the natural sciences?
Quotations and bibliographical references can be found in Volume
9A of the commentary of the Leopoldina edition (Weimar, 1977).
The first question which comes to mind is how did Goethe, the
urbanite, the student of law, the writer, poet, painter, but also the
administrator and minister in Weimar, happen to immerse himself in
research of the natural sciences?
During his childhood he heard very little about the study of nature.
His notebooks list plants and animals by their Latin names. In Latin
and German he wrote that there is nothing more beautiful than nature
with its flowers, herbs, berries, stones, and minerals because the hand
of the Lord, God's hand, had brought it all forth. Even such general
statements appear in the context of vocabulary and translation exercises. They have little to do with 'contemplation' [Anschauung] of
nature. In no way do they deal with scientific concerns.
Yet, the association of nature with God reminds one of an incident
which Goethe related in his autobiography Dichtung und Wahrheit
[Poetry and Truth]. The boy erected an altar to nature on his father's
music stand with pieces from his mineral collection because he wanted
to make an offering to God as the creator of nature by burning incense.
As a student in Leipzig and Strassburg, Goethe had attended
lectures in physics and anatomy. He was also engaged in a discussion
with students of medicine about specific and general questions of
nature. When the students came upon the Systeme de la Nature by
Baron Holbach, they expected a vivid depiction of nature as a whole.
They wanted to know something about its interconnections and were
disappointed by the mechanistic view of nature of this French materialist who described nature as a machine. Goethe spoke in Dichtung und
Wahrheit of Holbach's 'atheistic halfnight' and of the insipid, senile, and
deathlike style and content of the book which aroused his opposition in
every way and which even drove him, so he said, away from French
literature to Shakespeare. In Shakespeare's work, then, Goethe discovered the question of genius and of the creative spirit of man, and
this question guided him back to creation in nature.
He studied the views of nature by the three great natural scientists of
the eighteenth century, Carl von Linne, Georges Buffon, and Albrecht
von Haller, who were all born in the year 1707.
Linne's classification system fascinated Goethe. This great and
consistent system was an ordered depiction of nature, even though, at
first, Goethe could not make it come alive within the conceptualization
and nomenclature employing the criteria of separate parts of natural
objects in their artificial order. Goethe struggled for a time with Linne,
now in acceptance, now in opposition, and he even named Linne's
works, with those of Spinoza and Shakespeare, among the ones that
had the greatest influence and effect on him. Linne's Fundamenta
botanica was among the few books which Goethe took with him to
Italy.
DOROTHEA KUHN
DOROTHEA KUHN
10
DOROTHEA KUHN
roads, in forests and mines, he had dealt more intensively with the
natural sciences. In Jena he attended lectures on anatomy and seminars
on dissection by the anatomist Justus Christian Loder. In the Weimar
school of drawing he gave instruction in anatomy himself in order to
further his knowledge. There, he traced the structure and function of
the intermaxillary bone which in vertebrates holds the incisors in the
upper jaw. Convinced of the existe~ce of a general design, he insisted
on the presence of this bone in man too. Among contemporary
anatomists he encountered the opinion that man differed from the
animals, and especially from the monkey, precisely on account of that
missing intermaxillary bone. He did not rely on the contradictory
literature on anatomy and on its prejudice that man's ability for
language depended on the very absense of just that bone. He dissected
on his own and had prepared specimens sent to him: the skull of a
giraffe from Darmstadt, the skull of an elephant from Kassel; others
were available to him in Jena. He also conducted comparative studies.
After he arrived at the now well-known result, that man "like the other
animals" had an intermaxillary bone, he wrote to Knebel on November
17, 1784 about the conclusion he had drawn from his discovery,
namely that one "cannot find the difference between man and animal in
any specific detail. Rather, man is most closely related to the animals."
That similarity which was consistent throughout the chain of being
confirmed for him the fact of the consistency and harmony of nature,
the accordance of the whole of nature which assigns as identity to every
creature in its place within the whole order, to man as well as to every
other creature.
Goethe expressed his great satisfaction with his discovery even more
vividly when he wrote to Herder on May 24, 1784: "I finally found not gold or silver, but something that gives me boundless pleasure the os intermaxillare in man. It should please you greatly as well,
because it is the final link to man. It is not missing; it is there too!"
With those words, Goethe was referring to Herder's work on the
Ideas Concerning the Philosophy of the History of Mankind [Ideen zur
Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit], which began with a history
of nature, and in which Goethe actively participated. The Ideas offer a
world view [Weltbild] which is based, in every phase of the history of
nature and culture, on a differentiated theory of gradation. Herder's
thought on the 'gradation of organization,' or, as he also put it, the
"series of rising forms and forces," which is developed in the Ideas, led
11
12
DOROTHEA KUHN
mountains, plants, animals, and men. However, it did not develop into a
clearly defined concept. He observed especially the changeability of the
species in the alpine and maritime environments, and in the luxuriousness and multiplicity of the southern flora he searched for his Urp[lanze
[archetypal plant]. But since he only expressed himself regarding the
Urp[lanze in letters and autobiographical writings, and while admitting
that he had not found it, he never described in detail what he had
envisioned by such a plant. The Urp[lanze is often understood as a
simplification which could stand at the beginning of the descent of a
species [Stammesentwicklung].
Analogous to the concept of the intermaxillary bone it can be
assumed, however, that Goethe was looking for a generalization which
could represent the realm of plants in its place in the overall order of
nature. As Goethe later stated, a plant could be seen as a symbol for
the entire plant world. Genetic, even morphogenetic [realgenetisch]
concepts were touched upon when Herder spoke of gradation by steps,
or when Goethe spoke of relationship [Verwandtschaftl and the chain
of being. "If we had a sense to see the primal forms and the first germs
of things, then we could possibly perceive in the smallest point the
whole progression of the entire creation," says Herder in the Ideas. At
the same time, Goethe reflected on creatures which 'develop' from the
primal beginnings of the 'water-earth' [Wassererde] to land and air
inhabitants. A letter by Charlotte von Stein of May 1, 1784 to Knebel
relates to this, wherein she wrote: "Herder's latest writing makes it
probable that we were first plants and animals; what nature will make
of us will remain unknown to us: Goethe expends much profound
thought on these things."
At this point, it is difficult for our later scientific thinking to refrain
from postulating morphogenesis [Realgenese],which seems to be hinted
at everywhere. We find traces of genetic conceptions which were,
already in Buffon's molds, pre-formed to his 'dessin primitif et general'
as the foundations of a primal form, and which Herder used in terms of
the prototype (also used by Robinet) or the main form. In Goethe's
writings, the terms development and relation appear. But nowhere did
he leap into a theory of descent. On the one hand, the barrier of
Christian dogma must have been too prohibitive. Buffon's difficulties
with church censorship when he saw nature and not God as the acting
force are well known. Herder, as a theologian, avoided such difficulties
from the start by emphasizing in his introduction that he always meant
13
14
DOROTHEA KUHN
has been started by nature from the beginning, that is, with an entirely
new plan." Goethe himself took as his point of departure what he found
in nature and in literature. But those names which, for us, are connected with the theories of descent, such as de Maillet, or Robinet, or
Lamarck, do not appear among his extensive writings. It appears as if
after his travels to Italy he. totally abandoned his approach to an actual
concept of descent which he had worked out earlier along with Herder.
In a sketch of 'genetic treatment' in the natural sciences Goethe
noted that he would like to observe the development of an individual in
the smallest possible intervals, in order, finally, to be able to recognize
not just the single phases of development, but, rather, the development
itself, which is a sort of integral method. This means that he could
represent as a whole that which had been developed by steps in time
[das zeitlich nacheinander Entstehende], which he then called the ideal
whole. This kind of genetic observation is connected only to actual
descent in so far as Goethe included in the total picture what he had
found earlier by comparing and observing development and relationship. The type, then, contains the development. With this, however, he
was not pursuing the question of descent, but, rather, the question of
appearance, of the phenomenon.
Goethe. maintained this point of view, which he had already reached
before the turn of the century, even if ~here do exist later remarks by
him, especially in an exchange of ideas with d'Alton, Carus, and Ernst
Meyer, which presuppose polygenesis as being self-evident in terms of
the limited boundaries in the relationships between plants and animals.
Among Goethe's papers there is an article by the Jena botanist,
Friedrich Siegmund Voigt, with whom Goethe had often worked. In
1816 Voigt had written a paper about the colors of plants in connection with Goethe's color theory. In it he included a paragraph in which
he states that plants could not have stemmed from the hand of God as
they appear today, but, rather, that simpler forms had been created and
that then a further development took place up to our current species.
Goethe crossed out this paragraph and took pains to rewrite the
surrounding text so that everything would fit back together. He did this
possibly just because, in his judgment, this excursion did not seem to fit
in with the explanations concerning the colors of plants, or, then again,
possibly because of fundamental disagreement. In any case, Voigt
emphasized in his next work, the Fundamentals of a Natural History
[Grundziige einer Naturgeschichte] of 1817, that those cosmogonies are
15
wrong which are based on the idea that gradual developments create
organisms by descent. He also criticized works from de Maillet to
Lamarck, and took a stand against a continuous change or a gradual
degeneration of organisms.
What speaks even more clearly against Goethe's participation in
phylogenetic thinking is the fact that he, as intensely involved in the
debate of the two French anatomists Cuvier and Geoffroy de SaintHilaire as he was, and to whom he dedicated his last publication in
1832, did not discuss that part of the debate which concerned the
development of the species of animals, but adhered strictly to questions
of structure and type.
For part of the way in his investigative journey in the natural
sciences Goethe had followed the paths of contemporary theorists of
development. He had integrated these thoughts into his own ideas of
type. Therefore, one cannot say that type was a mere idea and
morphology only an idealistic morphology. However, the ideas of actual
descent, as developed by Darwin, were still blocked by barriers which
were difficult to overcome for Goethe and his contemporaries, and
Goethe was not interested in surmounting them. He let this problem
remain an enigma. In 1826 in a letter to Carl Gustav Carus he wrote,
"of a secret, according to which nothing originates except what has
already been announced, and that prediction becomes clear only
through the result, as does prophecy through fulfillment."
NOTE
Translated from the German by Frauke von der Horst, with the financial assistance
of the Goethe Institute, San Francisco. Originally presented at the symposium 'Goethe
as a Scientist' held at the University of California at Los Angeles and the California
Institute of Technology, 12-13 April 1982, and initially published in the Journal of
Social and Biological Structures 7 (1984)307-324; 345-356. It appears with the
kind permission of the editors of JSBS.
Schiller-Nationalmuseum
D-7142 Marbach am Neckar
B.R.D.lFederal Republic of Germany