Science of Logic
Science of Logic
1 Brief history
Hegel wrote Science of Logic after he had completed his
Phenomenology of Spirit and while he was in Nuremberg
working at a secondary school and courting his ance.
It was published in a number of volumes. The rst, The
Objective Logic, has two parts (the Doctrines of Being
and Essence) and each part was published in 1812 and
1813 respectively. The second volume, The Subjective
Logic was published in 1816 the same year he became a
professor of philosophy at Heidelberg. Science of Logic is
too advanced for undergraduate students so Hegel wrote
an Encyclopaedic version of the logic which was published in 1817.
In 1826, the book went out of stock. Instead of reprinting, as requested, Hegel undertook some revisions. By
1831, Hegel completed a greatly revised and expanded
version of the Doctrine of Being, but had no time to revise the rest of the book. The Preface to the second edition is dated 7 November 1831, just before his death on
14 November 1831. This edition appeared in 1832, and
again in 18345 in the posthumous Works. Only the second edition of Science of Logic is translated into English.
2 Introduction
2.1 Hegels General Concept of Logic
According to Hegel, logic is the form taken by the science
of thinking in general. He thought that, as it had hitherto
been practiced, this science demanded a total and radical reformulation from a higher standpoint. His stated
goal with The Science of Logic was to overcome what he
perceived to be a common aw running through all other
former systems of logic, namely that they all presupposed
a complete separation between the content of cognition
(the world of objects, held to be entirely independent of
thought for their existence), and the form of cognition
(the thoughts about these objects, which by themselves
1
2.2
The self-exposition of this unied consciousness, or Notion, follows a series of necessary, self-determined stages
in an inherently logical, dialectical progression. Its course
is from the objective to the subjective sides (or judgements as Hegel calls them) of the Notion. The objective
side, its Being, is the Notion as it is in itself [an sich],
its reection in nature being found in anything inorganic
such as water or a rock. This is the subject of Book One:
The Doctrine of Being. Book Three: The Doctrine of
the Notion outlines the subjective side of the Notion as
Notion, or, the Notion as it is for itself [fr sich]; human
beings, animals and plants being some of the shapes it
takes in nature. The process of Beings transition to the
Notion as fully aware of itself is outlined in Book Two:
The Doctrine of Essence, which is included in the Objective division of the Logic.[4] The Science of Logic is thus
divided like this:
Volume One: The Objective Logic
Book One: The Doctrine of Being
Book Two: The Doctrine of
Essence
Volume Two: The Subjective Logic
Book Three: The Doctrine of the
Notion
This division, however, does not represent a strictly linear progression. At the end of the book Hegel wraps all
of the preceding logical development into a single Absolute Idea. Hegel then links this nal absolute idea with
the simple concept of Being which he introduced at the
start of the book. Hence the Science of Logic is actually
a circle and there is no starting point or end, but rather a
totality. This totality is itself, however, but a link in the
chain of the three sciences of Logic, Nature and Spirit,
as developed by Hegel in his Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1817), that, when taken as a whole,
comprise a circle of circles.[5]
3.1
3.1.2
Determinate Being
A. Determinate Being as Such The transition between Becoming and (a) Determinate Being as Such is
accomplished by means of sublation. This term, the traditional English translation of the German word aufheben,
means to preserve, to maintain, but also to cease, to put
an end to. Hegel claims that it is one of the most important notions in philosophy. Being and Nothing were
complete opposites whose inner unity needed to be expressed, or mediated, by a third term: Becoming. Once
having been accomplished through mediation, their unity
then becomes immediate. Their opposition, still extant in
Becoming, has been put an end to. From the newly acquired standpoint of immediacy, Becoming becomes Determinate Being as Such, within which Being and Nothing are no longer discrete terms, but necessarily linked
moments that it has preserved within itself. Sublation,
then, is the ending of a logical process, yet at the same
time it is its beginning again from a new point of view.[12]
So, as moments of Determinate Being, Being and Nothing take on new characteristics as aspects of (b) Quality. Being becomes emphasized, and, as Quality, is Reality; Nothing, or Non-Being, is concealed in Beings background serving only delimit it as a specic Quality distinct from others, and, in so doing, is Negation in General, i.e., Quality in the form of a deciency. Quality,
then, comprises both what a Determinate Being is and
is not, viz., that which makes it determinate in the rst
place.[13] Within Quality, however, Reality and Negation
are still distinct from one another, are still mediated, just
like Being and Nothing were in Becoming. Taken in their
unity, that is, in their immediacy as, again, sublated, they
are now only moments of (c) Something.[14]
EXAMPLE: Hegel contrasts his logically derived notion of Reality from the earlier metaphysical one present in the ontological proof
of Gods existence, specically Leibnizs formulation of it. In this theory, God was held
to be the sum-total of all realities. These realities are taken to be perfections, their total-
3
ity therefore comprising the most perfect being imaginable: God. Speculative logic, however, shows that Reality is inextricably bound
up with its own negation, and so any grand total of these realities would not result in something strictly positive, e.g., God, but would inevitably retain, to an equal degree, the negation of all these realities. The mere addition
of realities to each other, then, would not in
any way alter their principle, and so the sum
of all realities would be no more or less than
what each of them already was: a Reality and
its Negation.[15]
Something is the rst instance in The Science of Logic of
the negation of the negation. The rst negation, Negation in General, is simply what a Determinate Being is
not. Hegel calls this abstract negation. When this negation itself is negated, which is called absolute negation,
what a Determinate Being is, is no longer dependent on
what it is not for its own determination, but becomes an
actual particular Something in its own right: a BeingWithin-Self. Its negation, what it is not, is now cut o
from it and becomes another Something, which, from the
rst Somethings point of view, is an Other in general.
Finally, just as Becoming mediated between Being and
Nothing, Alteration is now the mediator between Something and Other.[16]
B. Finitude (a) Something and Other are separate
from each other, but each still contains within itself,
as moments, their former unity in Determinate Being.
These moments now re-emerge as Being-in-Itself, i.e.,
Something as Something only insofar as it is in opposition to the Other; and Being-for-Other, i.e., Something as Something only insofar as it is in relation to
the Other.[17] (Hegels view is in this way contrasted
with Kants noumenon, the unknowable thing in itself:
Being-in-itself taken in isolation from Being-for-Other is
nothing but an empty abstraction and to ask what it is
is to ask a question made impossible to answer.)[18]
Something is now no longer only an isolated something,
but is in both positive and negative relationship to the
Other. This relationship, however, is then reected back
into the Something as isolated, i.e., in-itself, and bestows
upon it further determinations. What a Something is in
opposition to an Other is its (b) Determination;[19] what
it is in relation to an Other is its Constitution.[20]
EXAMPLE: A human beings Determination
is thinking reason, since that is what she unalterably is in opposition to her Other: nature.
However, humans are entangled in nature in
myriad other ways than just thinking rationally
about it, and how humans react to this external inuence also tells us about what they are.
This is their Constitution, the part of their be-
3.1
in nothing else than in recognizing that the nite has no Constitution, etc. It is therefore indeterminate and unalveritable being.[33]
terable. There is Nothing in it.[39] Just as there is no criAs having been sublated, the mediation which was per- terion to distinguish Being and Nothing despite the fact
formed by the True Innite between the Finite and the that they are opposites, the One is also identical with its
The Void can be said to be the
Innite now has resulted in their immediate unity. This opposite, (b) the Void.
[40]
Quality
of
the
One.
[34]
unity is called Being-for-Self.
3.1.3
Being-For-Self
A. Being-for-Self as Such At this point we have arrived back at simple Being from which all the previous developments had initially proceeded. This Being, though,
is now in the standpoint of Innity from which these developments can be seen as moments of itself and so it
is (a) Being-for-Self as Such. Until this point Determinate Being was burdened with Finitude, depended on the
Other for its own determination, and so was only relatively
determined Being. From the Ideal standpoint of Innity,
Being-for-Self has become free from this burden and so
is absolutely determined Being.[35]
As a consequence of having overcome this relativity,
however, both sides of the relationship between Something and Other are now also in equal relation to the Innite Being that they have become Ideal moments of. So,
although through their relationship Something and Other
mutually determine each others inner Qualities, they do
not have the same eect on the Innite Beingbe it God,
spirit or ego (in the Fichtean sense)to which they are
now objects. This Being is not just another Finite Other,
but is the One for which they are and of which they are
a part. The Being-for-Other of Finitude has become the
(b) Being-for-One of Innity.[36]
EXAMPLE: This Being-for-One recalls
Leibnizs monad because it involves a simple
oneness that maintains itself throughout the
various determinations that might take place
within it. Hegel, however, is critical of Leibnizs construction because, since these monads
are indierent to each other and, strictly
speaking, are not Others to one another, they
cannot determine each other and so no origin
can be found for the harmony that is claimed to
exist between them. Being-for-One, containing as it does the moments of determination
within it, avoids this contradiction.[37]
If we now take in isolation that to which all the preceding
moments refer, i.e., that which we now have immediately
before us, we end up with (c) the One.[38]
B. The One and the Many This (a) One in its Own
Self, standing in negative relation to all its preceding moments, is entirely dierentiated from each of them. It
is neither a Determinate Being, nor a Something, nor a
EXAMPLE: At this stage, the Logic has incorporated the ancient atomism of Leucippus and
Democritus. Hegel actually held the ancient
philosophical notion of atomism in higher esteem than the scientic one of modern physics
because the former understood the void not
just as the empty space between atoms, but
as the atoms own inherent principle of unrest and self-movement. Physics with its
molecules and particles suers from the atom
... just as much as does that theory of the
State which starts from the particular will of
individuals.[41]
The original transition of Being and Nothing to Determinate Being is again echoed here in the sphere of Beingfor-Self. The One, though, as negatively related to all
aspects of Quality excepting its own Quality of being the
Void, cannot take on a Qualitative determinateness like
Determinate Being did. In its own self-dierentiation, it
can only relate to itself as another self identical to it, that
is, as another One. Since no new Quality has been taken
on, we cannot call this transition a Becoming, but rather
a Repulsion, i.e., the positing of (c) Many Ones.[42]
C. Repulsion and Attraction Once these many Ones
have been posited, the nature of their relationship begins
to unfold. Because it is the nature of the One to be purely
self-related, their relation to one another is in fact a nonrelation, i.e., takes place externally in the Void. From
the standpoint of the one One, then, there are no other
Ones, that is, its relation to them is one of (a) Exclusion.
Seen from within the One there is only one One, but at the
same time the One only exists in the rst place through
its negative external relation to other Ones, i.e., for there
to be the one One there must be Many Ones that mutually
Exclude one another.[43]
EXAMPLE: The idea that the One is entirely
self-subsistent and can exist without the Many
is, according to Hegel, the supreme, most
stubborn error, which takes itself for the highest truth, manifesting in more concrete forms
as abstract freedom, pure ego and, further, as
Evil.[44]
Now that Many Ones have been posited out of their Repulsion from the One, their original Oneness reasserts itself and their Repulsion passes over to (b) Attraction. Attraction presupposes Repulsion: for the Many to be At-
6
tracted by the One, they must have at rst been Repulsed
by it.[45]
3.2
Magnitude (Quantity)
external to it because there is no inner necessity in the various arrangements imposed
on them by arithmetical procedure. With the
expression 7 + 5 = 12, although 5 added to 7
necessarily equals 12, there is nothing internal
to the 7 or the 5 themselves that indicates that
they should be brought in any sort of relation
with one another in the rst place.[55] For this
reason, number cannot be relied upon to shed
any light on strictly philosophical notions,
despite the ancient attempt by Pythagoras to
do so. It can however be used to symbolize
certain philosophical ideas. As for math as
a pedagogical tool, Hegel presciently had
this to say: Calculation being so much an
external and therefore mechanical process, it
has been possible to construct machines which
perform arithmetical operations with complete
accuracy. A knowledge of just this one fact
about the nature of calculation is sucient for
an appraisal of the idea of making calculation
the principal means for educating the mind
and stretching it on the rack in order to perfect
it as a machine.[56]
B. Extensive and Intensive Quantum Taken in its immediacy, a Number is an Extensive Magnitude, that is, a
collection of a certain Amount of self-same Units. These
Units, say ten or twenty of them, are the sublated moments of the Extensive Magnitudes ten or twenty. However, the Number ten or twenty, though made up of
Many, is also a self-determining One, independent of
other Numbers for its determination. Taken in this way,
ten or twenty (a) dierentiates itself from Extensive
Magnitude and becomes an Intensive Magnitude, which
is expressed as the tenth or twentieth Degree. Just as the
One was completely indierent to the other Ones of the
Many yet depended on them for its existence, each Degree is indierent to every other Degree, yet they are externally related to one another in ascending or descending
ow through a scale of Degrees.[57]
Although thus dierentiated from each other, Extensive
and Intensive magnitude are essentially (b) the same.
[T]hey are only distinguished by the one having amount
within itself and the other having amount outside itself.
It is at this point that the moment of the Something reasserts itself having remained implicit over the course of
the development of Quantity. This Something, which
reappears when the negation between Extensive and Intensive Magnitude is itself negated, is the re-emergence
of Quality within the dialectic of Quantity.[58]
EXAMPLE: Weight exerts a certain pressure
which is its Intensive Magnitude. This pressure, however, can be measured Extensively,
in pounds, kilograms, etc. Heat or cold can be
Qualitatively experienced as dierent Degrees
7
of temperature, but can also be Extensively
measured in a thermometer. High and low Intensities of notes are the results of a greater or
smaller Amount of vibrations per unit of time.
Finally, in the spiritual sphere, high intensity
of character, of talent or genius, is bound up
with a correspondingly far-reaching reality in
the outer world, is of widespread inuence,
touching the real world at many points.[59]
In the realm of Quantity, the relationship between Something and Other lacked any mutual Qualitative Determinateness. A One could only relate to another One identical to itself. Now, however, that Qualitative Determinateness has returned, the Quantum loses its simple selfrelation and can relate to itself only through a Qualitative
Other that is beyond itself. This Other is another Quantum, of a greater or lesser Amount, which, in turn, immediately points beyond itself to yet an Other Quantum
ad innitum. This is what constitutes the self-propelled
(c) Alteration of Quantum.[60]
C. Quantitative Innity Although a particular Quantum, of its own inner necessity, points beyond itself,
this beyond is necessarily an Other Quantum. This fact,
that Quantum eternally repulses itself, yet equally eternally remains Quantum, demonstrates the (a) Notion of
Quantitative Innity, which is the self-related, armative opposition between Finitude and Innity that lies
within it.[61] This irresolvable self-contradiction within
Quantum yields (b) the Quantitative Innite Progress.
This progress can take place in one of two directions, the
greater or the smaller, giving us the so-called innitely
great or innitely small. That these innites are each
the Spurious Quantitative Innite is evident in the fact that
great and small designate Quanta, whereas the Innite
by denition is not a Quantum.[62]
EXAMPLE: Hegel here gives several examples
of the appearance of the Spurious Quantitative
Innite in philosophy, namely in Kants notion
of the sublime and his categorical imperative,
as well as Fichtes innite ego as outlined in his
Theory of Science (1810). At bottom of all
these ideas, says Hegel, is an absolute opposition that is held to exist between the ego and
its other, this latter taking the form, respectively, of art, nature and the non-ego in general.
The opposition is supposed to be overcome by
the positing of an innite relation between the
two sides, the egos level of morality, for example, ever increasing in proportion to a decrease
in the power of the senses over it. According
with the nature of the Spurious Quantitative Innite, however, it does not matter how great a
level the ego raises itself to, the absolute opposition between it and its other is there and everywhere reasserted and the whole process can
3
have no other outcome than a desperate and futile longing.[63]
x = y/k.
As in themselves incomplete in this way, these Quanta
serve only as the Qualitative moments of one another.[66]
B. Inverse Ratio
The Inverse Ratio is a ratio, x:y, in which the relation between both sides is expressed in a constant which is their
product, i.e.,
k = xy
or
y=
k
.
x
Whereas formerly with the Direct Ratio, the quotient between the two terms was xed, in the Inverse Ratio it
becomes alterable. Because the Inverse Ratio connes
within itself many Direct Ratios, the constant of the former displays itself not merely as a Quantitative, but also
3.2.3 The Quantitative Relation
as a Qualitative Limit. It is therefore a Qualitative Quantum. The Spurious Innity/True Innity dialectic again
A. The Direct Ratio
makes an appearance here as either term of the ratio is
A ratio, such as x:y, is a Direct Ratio if both terms of only capable of innitely approximating the ratios conthe ratio are delimited by a single Quantum, a constant, stant, the one increasing in proportion to a decrease in
k (what Hegel calls in the language of his day the expo- the other, but never actually reaching it (neither x nor y
nent of the ratio),
may equal zero). The constant is nonetheless present as
a simple Quantum, and is not an eternal beyond, making
its self-mediation through the two terms of the ratio an
y
k= .
example of True Innity.[67]
x
3.3
Measure
y = kx .
It is in this form of the Ratio, says Hegel, that quantum has reached its Notion and has completely realized
it. In the Direct and Inverse Ratios, the relation between
the constant and its variables was not continuous, the former only being a xed proportionality between them, and
the latter relating itself to them only negatively. With the
Ratio of Powers, however, this relationship is not simply one of external limitation, but, as a Quantum brought
into relationship with itself through the power, it is selfdetermining Limit. This self-determination constitutes
the Quality of the Quantum, and nally demonstrates the
full signicance of the essential identity of Quality and
Quantity. Originally, Quantity dierentiated itself from
Quality in that it was indierent to what was external to
it, that which it quantied. Now however, in the Ratio of
Powers, what it relates itself to externally is determined
by its own self, and that which relates externally to its own
self has long since been dened as Quality. But quantity is not only a quality; it is the truth of quality itself.
Quantum, having sublated the moment of Quantity that
originally dened it and returned to Quality, is now what
it is in its truth: Measure.[68]
3.3
3.3.1
Measure
Specic Quantity
A. The Specic Quantum Measure is the simple relation of the quantum to itself ... ; the quantum is thus
qualitative. Previously, Quantum was held to be indifferent to the Quality of that which it quantied. Now, as
Measure, Quality and Quantity though still distinct from
one another are inseparable and in their unity comprise a
specic Determinate Being: Everything that exists has
a magnitude and this magnitude belongs to the nature of
the something itself. The indierence of Quantum is retained in Measure insofar as the magnitude of things can
increase or decrease without fundamentally altering their
Quality, and yet their essential unity nevertheless manifests at the Limit where an alteration in Quantity will
bring about a change in Quality.[69]
EXAMPLE: Aristotle gives the example of a
head from which hairs are plucked one by one.
Its Quality of being a head of hair remains if
only a few hairs are gone, but at a certain point,
it undergoes Qualitative Alteration and become
a bald head. Although the Quantitative change
is gradual, the Qualitative one, oftentimes, is
unexpected. It is the cunning of the Notion to seize on this aspect of a reality where
9
its quality does not seem to come into play; and
such is its cunning that the aggrandizement of
a State or of a fortune, etc., which leads nally
to disaster for the state or for the owner, even
appears at rst to be their good fortune.[70]
B. Specifying Measure Insofar as Quantity describes
the upper and lower Limits between which a specic
Quality can maintain itself, it serves as a (a) Rule. The
Rule is an arbitrary external standard or Amount that
measures something other than itself. Although it is often
tempting to assume so, there is in actuality no object that
can serve as a completely universal standard of measurement, i.e., be pure Quantity. Rather, what is involved in
measurement is a ratio between two Qualities and their
inherent Quantities, the one made to act as the (b) Specifying Measure of the other, this other, however, being
itself just as capable of measuring that which it is being
measured by.[71]
EXAMPLE: In the measure of temperature,
we take the expansion and contraction of
mercury relative to the heat it contains as
a Quantitative Rule for the increase or decrease of temperature in general by dividing
the range of its change in magnitude into a
scale of arithmetical progression. Tempting
though it is to believe, this is not the measure
of temperature as such, but only the measure
of how Quantitative change specically affects the Quality of mercury. The water or air
the mercury thermometer measures has a very
dierent Qualitative relationship to changes
in the Quantity of heat which do not necessarily bear any direct relation to mercurys.
Thus, what is actually going on when we take
a temperature is a relationship of comparison between two Qualities and their respective natures when exposed to a Quantitative increase or decrease in heat, and not a universal
determination by some disembodied, abstract
thing that is temperature itself.[72]
So long as we arbitrarily use the Quantitative properties
of some Quality or other as a Rule to Measure the magnitude of other Qualities, we abstract from it its Qualitative
nature. However, once we have established a Quantitative ratio between two or more Qualities, we can give this
ratio an independent existence that Quantitatively unites
things that are Qualitatively distinct. We can thus take
the Qualities of both sides into account, the independent,
or Realized, Measure serving as their (c) Relation. This
Measure necessarily involves variable magnitudes since
the Qualitatively distinct ways in which dierent things
relate to Quantity can only be registered in their respective rates of increase or decrease relative to each other.
Further, in order for each side of the ratio to fully reect
10
d
.
t
Real Measure
3.3
Measure
EXAMPLE: Hegel makes it clear that the
above analysis applies to the system of chemical anities and that of musical harmony. In
the case of the latter, for example, each individual note is a Real, self-subsistent Measure,
consisting as it does of a specic internal ratio between, say, the length and thickness of
a guitar string. An individual note, however,
only achieves meaning in its relation to a system of other notes that are brought into Quantitative relation to each other through a specic
note that serves as the Unit, or key. A note
serving as the key in one system, is equally an
individual member in other systems in which
other notes play this role. Notes that harmonize when played together are demonstrating
their Elective Anity for one another, that is,
the higher Qualitative unity that results from a
combination in which each individual note nevertheless retains its self-subsistence.[79]
11
tential of the Nodal line to increase endlessly; the Qualitative Innite is manifested as the eternal beyond of
any particular Qualitative determination. Seeing as the
successive determinations are self-generated by an internal Quantitative Alteration of Measure, they can now be
seen, from the standpoint of the Measureless, to be different States of one and the same Substrate. The nature
of the Substrate is not tied, like the Something was, to
a merely external Qualitative appearance, but represents
the underlying unity of a variety of internally determined
appearances, which are its States.[82]
3.3.3 The Becoming of Essence
A. Absolute Indierence
This Substrate, as what persists through the succession
of States, is in a relation of Absolute Indierence to every particular determinationbe it of quality, quantity
or measurethat it contains. It is merely the abstract expression of the unity that underlies their totality.[83]
B. Indierence as Inverse Ratio of its Factors
Taken in its immediacy, this Indierence is simply the
result of all the dierent determinatenesses that emerge
within it. It itself does not determine its own inner uctuations, i.e., is not self-determining. However, in accordance with the measure relations developed so far,
each of its moments are in reciprocal, quantitatively determined ratios with one another. Formerly, from the
standpoint of Quality, a sucient Quantitative increase
or decrease would result in a sudden transition from one
Quality to another. Now, with Absolute Indierence as
our standpoint, every possible Qualitative determination
is already implicitly related to every other by means of
a Quantitative ratio. Every Quality is connected to, and
in equilibrium with, its corresponding other. It is therefore no longer meaningful to say that something can have
more or less of one Quality than another as if each
Quality were absolutely distinct from each other. Whatever Quality there is more of in one thing than another
can be equally said to be a less of whatever Quality exists in its stead in the other, i.e., there is an Inverse Ratio of their Factors. So, with a so-called Quantitative
change, one factor becomes preponderant as the other
diminishes with accelerated velocity and is overpowered
by the rst, which therefore constitutes itself the sole
self-subsistent Quality. The two Qualities are no longer
distinct, mutually exclusive determinations, but together
comprise a single whole.[84]
EXAMPLE: Here, Hegel makes a powerful argument in favour of the explanatory powers of
his speculative philosophy over those of empirical science, specically with regards to the
concepts of centripetal and centrifugal forces
as they are supposed to relate the elliptical motion of celestial bodies. If, as is supposed by
12
4
science, such an orbit is made up of an inverse
relation of centripetal and centrifugal forces
the former predominating over the other as the
body approaches perihelion, the reverse if approaching aphelionthen the sudden overtaking of the stronger force by the weaker that
takes place on either end of the orbit can only
be explained by some mysterious third force.
Indeed, what is to stop the dominant force from
completely overtaking the weaker, causing the
body either to crash into whatever it is orbiting or to y o at ever accelerating speeds
into space? Only the inherent unity of the two
Qualities, centripetal and centrifugal, arrived at
by the ascension of thought to Absolute Indifference, can adequately explain the Notion of
the elliptical orbit, says Hegel.[85]
4
4.1
4.1.1
Objective Logic:
Essence
Doctrine of
Reection-Within-Self
Illusory Being
A. The Essential and the Unessential The immediate characteristic displayed by Essence, once it nally
emerges from Being, is simply that it is not Being. This
apparently puts us back into the sphere of Determinate
Being (see above), where each side of a relation mutually determined the Other side as being not what it is.
In this immediate, merely relative relation, Essence and
Being thus become the Essential and the Unessential, respectively. There is nothing arising within this relation,
however, to tell us what it is about something that is Essential and what Unessential. Those that apply this mode
of thinking to something are making an arbitrary distinction, the opposite of which could always be claimed with
equal justication. What saves Essence from falling back
in to the relativism of Determinate Being is the very radical and absolute distinction from Being that denes it as
Essence in the rst place. Being cannot therefore simply
preserve itself as an Other relative to Essence, but, having
been sublated by Essence, it has for that very reason itself
become nothingness, a non-essence, Illusory Being.[87]
C. Reection Reection in the sphere of Essence corresponds to Becoming in the sphere of Being. However,
in Being, this movement was between a positivepure
Beingand a negativepure Nothingness. Here however, the two terms are Illusory Being and Essence. Illusory Being, as has already been established, is a nullity,
nothingness. Essence, by denition, is non-being, absolute negativity. So Reection, the movement between
them, is the movement of nothing to nothing and so back
to itself. Both these terms, in being absolutely negative,
are identical to one another: Essence is Illusory Being and
Illusory Being is Essence. They are, however, also relatively negative, in that the one is, by denition, not what
the other is. This contradiction manifests in Essence in
that it presupposes or posits, on its own, that which it immediately dierentiates itself from: Illusory Being. This
absolute recoil upon itself is Essence as a) Positing Reection.[89]
The next determination of Reection, b) External Reection, shifts the emphasis from the absolute negativity,
or nothingness, in which the posited Illusory Being and
its positing Essence nd their identity, to the relative negativity upon which their opposition is based. Although it
4.1
Reection-Within-Self
knows that the Illusory Being it nds immediately before it has been posited by none other than itself, External
Refection nevertheless regards this Being as something
external to it from which it returns to itself. What concerns it, therefore, is no longer the act of positing itself,
but the specic determinateness of that which is posited,
since it is this and nothing else that establishes its externality in the rst place.[90]
EXAMPLE: Hegel oers for comparison with
his notion of External Reection the reective
judgement of Kant, which, in the Critique of
Judgement, is described as the faculty of the
mind that determines the universals that lie behind immediately given particulars. This action is similar to that of External Reection
with the crucial dierence that, for Hegel, the
universal does not simply lie behind the particular, but generates the particular from itself and so is the particulars own true Essence.
The immediate particular upon which Kants
judgement works is, in actuality, simply a nothingness posited by Reection itself solely in
order to generate its equally null universal,
Essence.[91]
With Positing Reection, the Illusory Being that was
posited was only a means for Essences mediation with
itself. Now, with c) Determining Reection, not only
is the moment of Illusory Being foregrounded again, but
the specic determinations of this Being come into play
as well. The absolute nothingness of Essence forms
the background to any and all of the determinations it
chooses to Reect itself o of. These Determinations
of Reectionformerly known as Determinate Beings
when they were in the realm of Quality (see above)
therefore share in the nullity that undergirds them. This
nullity actually serves to x them eternally in their specic determination and preserve them from Alteration,
because they no longer relate to each other externally
as Others to one another, but internally as equals in
Essences nothingness. All the possible determinations
of Being are thus preserved negatively in Essence as free
Essentialities oating in the void without attracting or repelling one another.[92]
4.1.2
The Essentialities
13
will share in this negativity and itself be essentially nothing. Therefore, an Essentiality, as opposed to a Quality, is
essentially the same as its otherthey are both essentially
nothing. As self-determining, whatever determination
Essence takes on is freely self-generated, it is what it is,
and so is simple Identity-with-self. This absolute Identity
rests on the absolute negativity that unites Essence with
its Essentialities. However, if we recall from Reection
above, Essence is also negative relative to its Essentialities. The Essentialities are determined Essence and, as
we know, determination by denition involves negation.
Therefore, while the Essentialities are absolutely Identical in their shared nothingness, their absolute negativity,
they are equally absolutely Dierent in their determinations, their relative negativity.[87]
EXAMPLE: Here Hegel embarks on a critique
on one of the most basic assumptions of classical logic, the Law of Identity, usually expressed
as A=A. Although supercially the immediate
truth of this proposition cannot be denied, further reection reveals that nothing absolute can
be derived from it. For it can only hold true
provisionally insofar as A is dierent from notA. The Law of Identity, the purpose of which
is to draw an absolute distinction between identity and dierence, therefore contains dierence as a necessary moment implicitly within
it. The paucity of the absolute truth it is meant
to represent becomes very clear when applied
empirically. If ... to the question 'what is a
plant?' the answer is given 'A plant isa plant',
the truth of such a statement is at once admitted by the entire company on whom it is tested,
and at the same time it is equally unanimously
declared that the statement says nothing.[93]
B. Dierence The Dierence of Reection must be
distinguished from the Otherness of Determinate Being.
The latter is a relative relation between two Determinate
Beings whereby they distinguish themselves one from the
another and in turn determine themselves as specic Beings based on this distinction. In the sphere of Reection,
however, any determination posited by Essence is, as a determination, necessarily Dierent from the absolute negativity that is its Essence. The Dierence of Reection,
therefore, is dierent in relation to its own self, and so it
is not relative but a) Absolute Dierence.[94]
Absolute Dierence contains both Dierence and Identity within it as moments just as, conversely, Identity contains itself and Dierence as its moments. The relation
between Identity and Dierence takes the form of one
term reecting o the other back into itself: Dierence
o of Identity back into itself or Identity o of Dierence back into itself. This is to be considered as the
essential nature of reection and as the specic, original
ground of all activity and self-movement. Because each
14
of these two moments are self-related in this way, they
do not mutually determine one another. Instead, they are
indierent to one another. Therefore, Dierence is b)
Diversity.[95]
of this, the Negative can equally well be regarded as positive and vice versa. They are not Positive and Negative
merely in comparison with one another, but each contains
within itself the other as an essential element of its own
[96]
Yet another duality emerges at this point. As moments, determination.
Identity and Dierence require each other and are bound
up with one another: one term could not exist without
EXAMPLE: An hours journey to the east and
the other. But at the same time, they absolutely negate
the same distance traveled back to the west,
one another and only are at all by virtue of their mucancels the rst journey. ... At the same time,
tual negation of each other. So if we are an external
the hours journey to the east is not in itself the
party concerned with a specic determination of Idenpositive direction, nor is the journey west the
tity, the moment of Dierence, though intrinsic to the
negative direction; ... it is a third point of view
fact of this Identity, is very far from our minds. That it
outside them that makes one positive and the
is Dierent from other things does not concern us or it
other negative. ... [T]he distance covered is
at the moment: it is implicit. The category of Identity itonly one distance, not two, one going east and
self, however, is not determined by whatever it is that it
the other going west. But at the same time,
is applied to, but by its reection o of Dierence back
the distance traveled east and west is the sum
into itself. So if, from our external standpoint, that which
of a twofold eort or the sum of two periods
comprises the Identity of something cannot be established
of time.[97]
without a Comparison of Likeness with something else.
What specically is Dierent about something can similarly only be determined by a Comparison of Unlikeness
between it and something else. Like and Unlike, being C. Contradiction Both the Positive and the Negative
external to the things they refer to, can each be equally are self-subsistent determinations: each side can stand on
applied to one and the same Determination. Things are its own without explicit reference to the other. At the
Like each other insofar as the are not Unlike each other same time, however, they completely exclude one another
and vice versa: the two terms are mutually exclusive in- and in fact rely on this exclusion for their self-subsistence.
sofar as they refer to the same thing, but in themselves, In that sense, the Positive itself is constituted by the very
apart from the things they refer to, there is no dierence Negative that it excludes; it is based on this exclusion and
between them. Since any aspect may be externally se- thus contains what it excludes it within itself. Ditto the
lected to demonstrate the Likeness and Unlikeness of any Negative. This inclusion of what is excluded is what contwo things, these terms really only refer, not intrinsically stitutes the Positive and the Negative as what they are.
to their objects, but to themselves only and, as likewise This is Contradiction. (In the Negative, this self- conself-referred, are indistinguishable from each other inde- tradiction is explicit, but it is no less the nature of the
pendent of their objects. Likeness and Unlikeness are Positive.)
both in fact only Likeness. The internal union that existed So, similar to Becoming above, the Positive and the Negbetween Identity and Dierence which is merely implicit ative immediately transition the one into the other: the
to the outside observer, therefore emerges again in exter- Positive includes the Negative which immediately exnal reection between Likeness and Unlikeness, and thus cludes the Positive; the resulting Negative however also
overcomes the external Diversity that held Identity and includes the Positive which in turn excludes the Negative
Dierence indierently apart from each other. This re- and so on ad innitum. This mutual inclusion and excluconstituted unity that thus comes out of Diversity is c) sion cancels out the both of them. This results in nullity.
Opposition.
Out of this nullity, the unity of the two sides is restored
The hidden, internal unity that bound the two moments in the following way. As stated above, both the Positive
of Identity and Dierence together despite their appar- and the Negative are each self-subsistent on their own, but
ent mutual indierence becomes explicit once they are it is a self-subsistence that is immediately obliterated by
mediated from the outside by Likeness and Unlikeness. the others. Now, however, arising out of their mutual deThey are no longer indierent to one another but relate to struction comes a self-subsistence that is common to the
each other intrinsically as Opposites. A given determina- both of them. Instead of merely excluding each other,
tion, as seen from its Positive aspect, is Likeness reected each side sublates the other, meaning that whatever is
back onto itself o of Unlikeness. Seen from its Nega- posited as Positive is at the same time equally the Negative
tive aspect, it is Unlikeness reected back onto itself o of its Negative, and whatever is Negative is at the same
of Likeness. These two aspects, however, are the con- time equally a Positive. The two sides posit and negate
stitutive moments of one and the same overall determi- each other simultaneously, and in doing so they no longer
nation. Although as a whole, the Positive and Negative destroy each other, but preserve one another. Therecomprise a unity, the Positive on its own is also a self- fore the Positive and Negative are in fact the same and
their
subsistent being, as is the Negative on its own. Because this, their samenesswhich nevertheless includes
Contradictionis their Essence as Ground.[98]
15
EXAMPLE: Light is usually reckoned as
purely Positive and dark, purely Negative: the
absence of light. However, it is not inherent
to these terms that they should be so. Darkness can be taken to be a Positive in its own
right as the non-self-dierentiating womb of
generation and vice versa. Furthermore, although they are usually dened as being mutually exclusive, the one being the absence of the
other, there is a quantitative spectrum of grey
and a qualitative spectrum of colour which exist between the one extreme and the other. The
Ground would be a concept of light which includes all of the above.[99]
4.2
Ground
6 References
[1] Hegel (1969), 3541
[2] Hegel (1969), 51
[3] Hegel (1969), 5053
[4] Hegel (1969), 7880
[5] Hegel (1969), 1814
[6] Hegel (1969), 93
16
REFERENCES
17
Di Giovanni, George (ed) 1990. Essays on Hegels
Logic Albany: New York State University Press.
Rinaldi, Giacomo, 1992. A History and Interpretation of the Logic of Hegel Lewiston: Edwin Mellen
Press.
6.1
Bibliography
9 External links
Source text (German) Wissenschaft der Logik Vol. 1
Vol. 2
Outline of Hegels Logic at marxists.org
The Meaning of Hegels Logic (commentary at
Wikisource)
Dunayevskaya : Rough Notes on Hegels SCIENCE
OF LOGIC
Secondary literature
Bencivenga, Ermanno 2000.
Logic Oxford.
Burbidge, John W., 1995. On Hegels Logic. Fragments of a Commentary Atlantic Highlands, N.J.
Burbidge, John W. 2006. The Logic of Hegels
Logic. An IntroductionPeterborough, ON.
Butler, Clark. 1996. Hegels Logic. Between Dialectic and History Evanston.
Carlson, David 2007. A Commentary on Hegels Science of Logic New York: Palgrave MacMillan. 9781403986283
18
10
10
10.1
Science of Logic Source: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Science%20of%20Logic?oldid=656910282 Contributors: Charles Matthews, Steinsky, Jjshapiro, Goethean, Herzen, Pearle, Snowolf, Gene Nygaard, Stemonitis, Woohookitty, BD2412, YurikBot, TheGrappler, Zwobot,
Mike Serfas, Sardanaphalus, SashatoBot, John, Amakuru, Gregbard, Cydebot, Jazzbox, PhiLiP, Mentisto, Spartaz, Matthew Fennell,
Gavia immer, KConWiki, Belovedfreak, VolkovBot, Ontoraul, StAnselm, Jorgen W, JL-Bot, SchreiberBike, Good Olfactory, Addbot,
LightSpectra, Yobot, LilHelpa, Srich32977, Omnipaedista, Wdrwdr, FreeKnowledgeCreator, FrescoBot, Shiki2, DrilBot, LilyKitty, Uanfala, Peter Remmers, John of Reading, GoingBatty, ZroBot, ChuispastonBot, CocuBot, Snotbot, BG19bot, Mark Arsten, Xianmw,
Khazar2, BoltonSM3, ALCIBEADES, Sol1, OccultZone, Kerstenstudent, Vieque and Anonymous: 40
10.2
Images
File:Georg_Wilhelm_Friedrich_Hegel00.jpg Source:
http://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/b/bc/Georg_Wilhelm_
Friedrich_Hegel00.jpg License: Public domain Contributors: http://portrait.kaar.at/ Original artist: Unknown
File:Wissenshaft_der_logik.jpg Source: http://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/en/5/5c/Wissenshaft_der_logik.jpg License: Public domain Contributors:
Scan of the original book
Original artist:
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel
10.3
Content license