The Natural Numbers Seen Philosophically
The Natural Numbers Seen Philosophically
The Natural Numbers Seen Philosophically
Index
Page
Introduction 7
Bibliography 156
Acknowledgements
The original idea of this book I set out for the first time in my doctoral dissertation that
called Mathematics and empirical science: What could be the numbers? UNAM, 1989,
México. However, there I used another strategy to prove the point. So, this book is
inspired by the dissertation, but rather, I used several subsequent works through which I
have advanced in the clarification of some ideas. So part of the material in this book has
previously been published in the form of articles or chapters in collective books, some
in Spanish and some in English. In some cases there have been no substantial changes,
but other changes have been greater. The following are references to paragraphs and
chapters containing previously published material:
- Chapter 1, "On the question, what are numbers?" is a updating of the chapter
“What is Philosophy of Mathematics looking for?” in 18 Unconventional Essays on the
Nature of Mathematics of Reuben Hersh (comp.), Springer 2006, USA.
The rest of the book is completely unpublished at the time of this writing.
Also thanks to the students of the course entitled "Philosophy of Mathematics",
taught in the School of Mathematics of the University Juárez of the State of Durango,
from 27 February to 27 March 2010. These students were Paola Ríos Alvarado, Andrés
Ceniceros Nájera, Miguel Ángel Ortiz Castañeda, Francisco Javier López Fragoso and
Gerardo Salvador Corral. The course focused on the content of this book, and the
stimulating discussions that occurred throughout the course led me to incorporate
several changes and clarifications.
Introduction
In looking at Frege’s definition of numbers,1 I discovered that Frege did not define
arithmetical numbers; rather, he built other numbers that resemble and explain
arithmetical numbers. Fregean numbers are similar to arithmetical numbers because
both meet Peano Axioms. In addition, Fregean numbers explain arithmetical numbers,
because Frege suggests that arithmetical numbers are not related directly to the
experience of counting but are only related indirectly with that experience.
While studying Euclid, I also discovered that he had also built certain numbers
that are similar to arithmetical numbers. Euclidean numbers were constructed in terms
of magnitudes. By using these numbers, one can attempt to explain, inter alia, how the
joining of arithmetical numbers gives rise to other numbers.
On the basis of these examples, I came to the idea that there are two kinds of
numbers, arithmetical and meta-arithmetical, with the latter being explanatory paintings
of the first.
This idea generated the following questions: a) What are arithmetical numbers,
ontologically speaking, and how is it that we know them? b) If Euclidean and Fregean
numbers can be viewed as paintings of arithmetical numbers, could we see the
arithmetical numbers as paintings of other numbers that are more directly related to the
experience of counting? c) What is the nature of those numbers that I call “pre-
arithmetical numbers”, if such numbers indeed exist?
1
Throughout this work, by “numbers”, I always mean natural numbers, of which I suggest that
there are three levels. Therefore, I shall not speak of real numbers, imaginary numbers, or other
numbers that are not natural.
I label “pre-arithmetical numbers” as first-level numbers, “arithmetical
numbers” as second-level numbers, and “meta-arithmetical numbers” as third-level
numbers. I must clarify that the expression “arithmetic” is equivalent, throughout this
work, to the expression “mathematical”; thus, to say “mathematical numbers” is
equivalent to saying “arithmetical numbers”.
As often happens, I will change the order of discovery and start by giving first-
level numbers, then second-level numbers, and conclude with third-level numbers. Prior
to that, we will see in chapter 1 the problem we are trying to resolve with the
proposition that there exist three levels of numbers. I want to stress that throughout this
text, I will use multiple diagrams because I believe that the notion of painting, which is
explained in section 2.1, is central to understanding why I say that third-level numbers
are paintings of second-level numbers and why these, in turn, can be viewed as
paintings of first-level numbers.
10
Chapter 1
11
1.1. A dual misunderstanding
There is a lack of clarity regarding the question “what are numbers?” First, we must
clarify from which approach we are asking the question; second, we must make clear
the class of numbers to which we refer. Failure to provide these clarifications has often
led to a dialogue marked by miscommunication.
We can pose the question from two approaches: the mathematical and the
philosophical. In mathematical terms, Peano (1889), Dedekind (1893) and Hilbert
(1900) defined numbers in terms of classes, systems (series) or the mutual relations
between numbers. For these authors, a number is defined within mathematics.
We want our numbers to be such that they can be used for counting common objects,
and this requires that our numbers should have a definite meaning, not merely that they
have certain formal properties.
12
place is in the world. It is symptomatic that for mathematicians in general, Peano is
more important than Frege, while for philosophers, the opposite is true.
From the philosophical point of view, there is also confusion about numbers and
the symbols we use to represent them. For example, does the symbol “3” mean the same
thing in the expressions “3 horses”, “3 + 2 = 5”, and “3 is a set”? I think not. In this
work, I will try to show that there are three levels of numbers: pre-mathematical
numbers, such as the number mentioned in “3 horses”; mathematical numbers, such as
those mentioned in “3 + 2 = 5”; and meta-mathematical numbers, such as the number
mentioned in “3 is a set”. I designate these numbers as first-, second-, and third-level
numbers, respectively.
In these and other similar cases, we must first ask what kind of numbers we are
talking about and what approach we will consider. That is why in the following
paragraphs, we first discuss different mathematical approaches.
13
question itself. The approaches could be many, but I will concentrate here only on the
mathematical and the philosophical.
To recognise this dialogue of the deaf, let us examine some examples. First, we
find that some authors, both mathematicians and philosophers of mathematics, are
apparently talking about the same thing. For example Körner (1967) says:
It is characteristic of mathematical theories that they can themselves become the subject
matter of mathematical theories. It is thus in principle possible for mathematical
theories and philosophical theories about mathematics to be incompatible. (p. 118)
Within the discussion that has taken place between the philosophy of
mathematics and mathematics itself, much has been said about the limitative theorems
of Gödel and others. Rodriguez-Consuegra (1992, p. 446), says:
Gödel proved the existence of propositions true but undemonstrated in a formal system
sufficiently rich for containing arithmetic... It seems to me that the more relevant
philosophical consequences are the following: Once they proved that truth and
demonstrability are different things, then the truth of certain propositions is directly
intuitive.
The meta-mathematical discoveries of the present century imply the falsehood of the
common doctrines shared by the classical philosophies of non-competitive
mathematical theories.
14
Though it is unanimously accepted that mathematics are recursive, the hidden
premise that philosophy, too, is formed by theories is not accepted. In fact, in writing
against this idea, Wittgenstein (1918, 4.112) says that “Philosophy aims at the logical
clarification of thoughts. Philosophy is not one doctrine but an activity”.
Confronted with the idea that mathematics and the philosophy of mathematics
can be rival theories, I believe that Wittgenstein (1967) would have responded in the
following way:
A philosophical problem has the form: “I don't know my way about” (123). “It leaves
everything as it is. It also leaves mathematics as it is, and no mathematical discovery
can advance it” (124). “It is not a matter of the philosophy to resolve a contradiction
through a mathematical discovery” (125).
We can find other examples of the dialogue of the deaf when we see that, in the
view of some mathematicians, philosophers have attempted to place mathematics within
their own philosophical perspective. However, those attempts are almost always
external to mathematics itself, and mathematicians reject the characterisations that are
made about them by philosophers. For example, Santiago Ramírez (1990, p. 419) tells
us that:
They [Philosophers] have conceived traditionally the relation between philosophy and
mathematics as that in which philosophy, whatever its metaphysical foundation, tries to
subject mathematics to philosophical discourse, or philosophical norm. From
15
Pythagoras to Analytical Philosophy the question is to exhibit mathematics as a
discipline, discourse, or special kind of knowledge where philosophical or
epistemological hypothesis about existence, about truth, and about method are
confirmed.
Perhaps the difficulty in resolving this issue is the nature of philosophy itself, as
Ramírez, Cavailles, and Courant Robbins seem to say. That is, philosophy cannot solve
this issue. Or perhaps, as Hersh (1979, p. 34) says, the reason is the fact that "there are
not many professional philosophers who know functional analysis, algebraic topology
or stochastic processes". This position is reaffirmed by Amor (1981, p. II), commenting
on the work of Hersh: "this is a reflection of a mathematician and not of a not-
mathematical philosopher, so it's a true reflection of actual Mathematics".
The first proposition forces us to define the limits and the reach of philosophical
reflection, which we will attempt in 1.2.3. The second proposition forces us to clarify
what we understand by “knowing mathematics”.
16
creator of a part of mathematics. Maybe even this would not be enough because of the
growing and unfinished complexity of mathematics.
It is also the case that some mathematicians, such as Cantor, Poincare and
Frechet, among others, have engaged in reflection on the different ways by which they
approach their own work, thereby providing us with access to their vast psychological
and historical experiences. Yet, are they doing philosophy? Hersh (1979, pp. 34-35)
said the following about this:
But the art of philosophical discourse is not well developed today among
mathematicians, even among the most brilliant. Philosophical issues just as much as
mathematical ones deserve careful arguments, fully developed analysis, and due
consideration of objections. A bald statement of one’s own opinion is not an argument,
even in philosophy.
17
1.2.2. Mathematical focus
Mathematicians in general are not interested in the question. Only a few among them
have stopped to explore the subject, and they have done so with various kinds of tools.
Nonetheless, it would seem that almost all of them believe that it is an internal affair of
mathematics itself. In Cavailles (1938, p. 172) words: “There is no definition, nor
justification of the mathematical objects, except mathematics itself”.
However, if that is true, how is it possible to reflect about mathematics from the
view point of mathematics itself? It seems there have been three ways: 1) doing meta-
mathematics; 2) examining the history of mathematics, and 3) practicing mathematics.
1.2.2.1. Meta-mathematics
It is generally accepted that mathematics is recursive; that is to say, mathematicians can
mathematically re-work their results. However, if we do not know what mathematics is,
it would be difficult to explain how we can do the mathematics of mathematics. In any
case, I believe that, at least, it is possible to do mathematics axiomatically and non-
axiomatically.
Let us remember that the use of axioms is a technique based on the ideas of
Plato and Aristotle. The use of axioms consists in ordering certain kinds of knowledge
(mathematical or non-mathematical) and finding affirmations (axioms) from which we
can deduce all the other affirmations of that body of knowledge. Knowledge organised
in this way can, in theory, substitute for the original knowledge while gaining in clarity
and precision.
18
Mathematics has two faces... Mathematics presented in the Euclidean way appears as a
systematic, deductive science; but mathematics in the making appears as an
experimental, inductive science.
Mathematics is not a completely logic theory... In spite of the fact that most of the
mathematical works consist in doing logical transformations from propositions admitted
as truthful..., it is not hard to admit that intuition guides the work in a specific direction.
This book offers another vision of mathematics, a vision in which the logical is merely
one dimension of a larger picture.
In this sense, there can be axiomatic and non- axiomatic forms of meta-
mathematics. It is characteristic of both of these forms that they depart from some
mathematical theories and construct other mathematical theories. It would seem that the
difference consists in the following. While the axiomatic approach proceeds with the
intention of substituting the primitive theory by another theory that makes theoretical
propositions clearer and more precise, the non-axiomatic approach does not provide a
substitute for primitive theory but rather makes such theory dependent upon another
theory. We can say that both axiomatic and non-axiomatic meta-mathematics explain
and clarify primitive mathematical theory. One does so by reducing primitive
mathematical theory to its constituent parts and the other by relating such theory to
other elements or to other mathematical theories.
With respect to the axiomatic theories (called foundations), I believe that they
are by their own nature meta-mathematical and certainly attempt to clarify the
relationships of mathematical entities. In Gödel’s own words:
19
The so-called logical or set-theoretical “foundation” for number-theory, or of any other
well established mathematical theory, is explanatory, rather than really foundational,
exactly as in physics where the actual function of axioms is to explain the phenomena
described by the theorems of this system rather than to provide a genuine “foundation”
for such theorems. (in Lakatos, 1978, p. 27)
However, the limitations of formal systems in axiomatic work are well known.
For this reason, axiomatic theories, in general, have not replaced original theories, and
both subsist. Hersh (1979, p. 38) says:
The common presupposition was that mathematics must be provided with an absolutely
reliable foundation. The disagreement was on strategy, on what had to be sacrificed for
the sake of the goal. But the goal was never attained, and there are few who still hope
for its attainment.
It seems that the philosophy of mathematics went into crisis with the appearance
of Gödel’s work. However, his theorems concerning the incompleteness and
inconsistency of arithmetic address formal systems, in Hilbert’s sense. They are
important for axiomatic meta-mathematics (or foundational meta-mathematics). They
demonstrate that an axiomatic picture of arithmetic does not recollect the totality of
arithmetic. This demonstration is interesting for meta-mathematics and mathematics
because it allows us to examine the place and the utility of formal systems in the totality
of mathematics. It is an internal affair concerning the relations of mathematical entities.
That being the case, the crisis was internal to Hilbert’s and similar programs, such as
Logicism and Intuitionism. However, mathematics itself and its philosophy went their
own separate ways.
axiomatic theories as structures, this meta-mathematical work would be building other
structures formed by simple structures. In other words, it would be constructing
complex structures through which it is possible to study and clarify the properties and
relationships of certain primitive structures and their elements.
Formalism denies the status of mathematical to most of that which they commonly have
understood as mathematics and it does not say something new about its development.
For this reason, some believe that an answer that would take more completely into
consideration the fertility of mathematical work must utilise a historical analysis that
clarifies the facts and methods that make mathematical work possible.
21
As historians of mathematics and sciences we are interested in knowing the origins of
problems which men have tried to solve in the past time, the ideas they used as a
starting point, and what they expected as an answer…; that is, how an idea is born,
grows and changes in order to conform the science’s field.
For the first variety, such as that practiced by Courant and Robbins (1941),
What points, lines, numbers “actually” are cannot and need not be discussed in
mathematical science. What matters and what corresponds to “verifiable” facts is
structure and relationship... For scholars and laymen alike it is not philosophy [and
22
maybe history not either], but active experience in mathematics itself that alone can
answer the question: What is mathematics? (pp. iv, v)
From this perspective, we could perhaps agree with Newton Da-Costa that
“mathematics is all that which is in mathematical books and reviews”. This
characterisation, of course, is insufficient. However, in its defence, we could say that
mathematics is an interminable field and “with respect to the motor of progress, it seems
to escape to investigation” (Cavailles, 1938, p. 175).
2
Which De Lorenzo (1993) calls “figural work.”
23
Certainly, there are many mathematicians even in our times, such as Cavailles
himself (in some of his works) as well as others, who try to characterise mathematics by
reference to their own mathematical practice. This is the case for J. De Lorenzo (1992,
pp. 447, 448), when he says:
24
mathematical or historical projects, but it seems that philosophers3 ask other questions
as well.4 But for what are philosophers, or mathematician acting as philosophers,
looking? That is, what constitutes for them an acceptable, or even controvertible,
answer to the question “what is mathematics?”
3
This distinction, of course, is not exact. In fact, there have been mathematicians and
historians who worked on central philosophical subjects. We can mention, for instance, the
strong philosophical concerns of Gödel (1949), which, it seems, guided him to his technical
works. On the other hand, I believe that it would be unjust to classify Wilbur Knorr’s work as
only historical because, I believe, it is also philosophical.
4
As Shapiro (1994, p. 157) says, “Philosophers have their own interests, beyond those of their
colleagues in other departments”.
5
I understand philosophy here as a dialogue within Western culture. Other cultures, such as
that of China or India, have their own internal dialogues. That circumstance makes it difficult,
but not impossible, for a dialogue to exist between different cultures. Within Western culture
there are also various subcultures, each with its own internal dialogue.
25
Ontological and epistemological inquiries point in precisely the same direction
because the first kind of inquiry attempts to clarify concepts by which we think about
the world and the second seeks to clarify how our thinking is related to the objects
under study at a given time. In other words, how can we know objects?
This characterisation is tentative and only intends to pick out some of the more
general characteristics of philosophy to clarify the philosophy of mathematics. There
are, of course, other characterisations, though not an excessive number because only a
few philosophers have turned their attention to that question. We will comment on two
very common characterisations.
The first characterisation says that philosophy is the mother of science. For
instance, Cornman, Lehrer, and Pappas (1992, p. 5) say,
Philosophy was once construed so broadly as to cover any field of theoretical inquiry.
Any subject matter for which some general explanatory theory might be offered would
have been a branch of philosophy. However, once a field of study came to be dominated
by some main theory and developed standard methods of criticism and confirmation, then
the field was cut off from the mother country of philosophy and became independent.
In support of this thesis, we can mention the fact that, in the past, many
philosophers were also scientists, for example, Aristotle and Descartes. Some scientists,
such as Newton, for example, in turn called their scientific work “natural philosophy”.
Nevertheless, even and when from Tales philosophical work has closely resembled
scientific work, that does not give us license to say that philosophy and science address
the same subjects and attempt to discover the same things.
I believe that we can explain from my perspective why some people see
philosophy as the mother of science. In fact, I believe that it would not be hard to accept
26
that critical and dialogical works of philosophy addressing inherited knowledge can
provoke new research in some scientific fields. For example, the critical work of
Berkeley (1948-57) on Analysis provoked Weierstrass’ mathematical work (cf. Robles,
1993, pp. 219-227). However, such examples do not prove that mathematics was born
of philosophy, only that both disciplines influence one another.
Another common idea about philosophy has its roots in phenomenology and
existentialism. We can see this, for example, in the teachings of Ortega and Gasset
(1973, p. 177), where he says, "the radical problem of philosophy is defining that mode
of being, that primary reality which we call our life". This idea is close to what many
people think philosophy must be: a view of the world or a personal cosmological view.
27
However, there is a large problem with this conception, in that it requires that
philosophers must understand all the sciences, and attaining such breadth of
understanding is virtually impossible today. Philosophy, from my point of view, is not a
superior judge for the sciences and is not a super-science. I believe that any philosopher
can only know deeply one scientific discipline or, perhaps, only one theory in that
discipline. The only recourse any single philosopher has is to attempt to draw from that
theory its suppositions or the view of the world it implies.
6
From Burkert (1972), it is thought that the image we have of the Pythagoreans and about
Pythagoras himself was the work of the Neo-Platonists and Neo-Pythagoreans, who built a
28
attributes and permanent states" (in Aristotle, Metaphysics, A.5 986-a-16). In the words
of an important member of the Neo-Pythagorean group, Nicomachus (C 1 A.D., Book
1, Chap. IV),
Which of these four methods must we first learn?... this is arithmetic, not solely because
we said that it existed before all the others in the mind of the creating God like some
universal and exemplary plan, relying upon which as a design and archetypal example
the creator of the universe sets in order his material creations and makes them attain to
their proper ends; but also because it is naturally prior in birth.
For these reasons, it is said, Pythagoras started the systematic study of numbers,
and Nicomachus wrote the important textbook Introduction to Arithmetic, which was
used throughout the Middle Ages. These Pythagorean ideas about the place of
mathematical entities in the world are similar to those of Galileo (Saggiatore S-6): “The
universe is written in mathematical language, being its characters triangles, circles, and
figures” (in Galileo, 1638, p. 29). These ideas are also similar to those of Descartes
when he says that the entire world is composed of only two substances: extension and
thought. He adds that the first must be studied by means of Geometry.
We can say that almost all the empirical sciences that use mathematics rest on
the Pythagorean belief that the world is known only by means of mathematics or, at the
very least, that it is better known using mathematics. I believe that this conception about
mathematics implies that mathematical entities, and the relationships among them, are
the general structure of the world. In the words of Bigelow (1988, p. 13), “Mathematics
is the theory of universals”. This position would hold that mathematics is possible, or it
has meaning, as the study of that which persists under changes. We can agree with this
conception or not, but it certainly presents an ontology and epistemology that give
answers to the following questions: How is mathematics possible? What is the place of
mathematics in the world?
legend around this historical figure and his school. However, there are still some scholars, such
as Kahn (2001) and Riedweg (2005), who defend the idea that there must be some truth in this
image of Pythagoras to have generated such a legend.
29
Despite the affirmation of Wittgenstein (1967, 124) that “philosophy leaves
everything as it is", I believe that mathematics and the philosophy of mathematics have
influenced each other, just as we said above that there are mutual influences in the
relationship between mathematics and philosophy in general.
It is not certain that axiomatic mathematics came from Eleatic dialectic because,
according to Proclus (c-V A. D.), Thales and Pythagoras were the first to prove
theorems. However, pre-Greek mathematics was certainly different from Greek
mathematics, which was deductive and was born at the same time as Greek philosophy.
Maybe for these reasons, Plato affirmed in The Republic that mathematics was a
hypothetical-deductive science. Additionally, we ought not to forget the logic of
Aristotle and later that of Frege as a contribution from philosophy to mathematics. The
whole of mathematics is not axiomatic or deductive, but one part of it certainly is.
30
is not hard to accept that mathematics is the foundation of Kantian philosophy and,
perhaps, in the foundations of almost all contemporary Analytical Philosophy, which
started with Frege.
They have urged that the central issue in the philosophy of mathematics is to find a way
to identify ontology for mathematics that is compatible with epistemology that does not
invoke mysterious faculties. (Kitcher, 1988, p. 397)
Once the goal of the philosophy of mathematics was clarified, there has been a
revival of related philosophical discussion. On one side, there has been a renaissance of
empiricism with P. Kitcher (1984) and others, the realism of Maddy (1990) and
Bigelow (1988), and the structuralism of Shapiro and Resnik. On another front, we can
find the modal mathematics of Hellman and Putnam, and the nominalism of H. Field,
among other interesting conceptions.
31
mathematics?”, the first solution that I propose is to distinguish between the approach of
the mathematician and the approach of the philosopher. I believe that the distinction
established here lets us understand, at least partially, the limits and capacity of either a
philosophical or a mathematical view when they face the question “what is
mathematics?” The explanation of why, on certain occasions, the answers of some are
not important or satisfactory for others can be given by saying that these different views
ask different things with the same question. The mathematical view inquires into the
character and internal connections of mathematical entities. The philosophical view
inquires into the place of mathematical entities in the world; in other words, it asks how
mathematical entities are possible.
32
To address some confusion generated by Benacerraf (1965) and (1973), I
propose that there is a third class of numbers, the meta-mathematical, which we will
discuss in Chapter 4 and which are the fruit of mathematical work when it attempts to
explain numbers mathematically. This distinction between mathematical numbers and
meta-mathematical numbers allows us to suggest an answer to the problem of
Benacerraf, as we will see at the end of the Chapter 5.
33
34
Chapter 2
35
2.1 How do we understand the assertions of existence?
The title of the chapter 2 is both disturbing and provocative. The mere suggestion that
there are non-mathematical numbers that share the same nomenclature as arithmetic
numbers suggests an excess contrary to Occam’s razor. My proposal, however, is
realistic because I contend that not only mathematical numbers but also certain pre-
mathematical and other meta-mathematical numbers exist. All of these numbers, I
would argue, exist not only in the minds of people, but also, in a sense, in the empirical
world. To defend this idea, of course, it will be necessary to clarify how I understand
the assertion of existence, such as when I say that the number 3 exists.
Apparently, according to common sense, there are only individual objects. However,
how did we arrive at the idea of a stable and separate object?
But is that wave, for example, something built with my mind or is it something
outside of my mind and all people perceive it in the same way? It should be
remembered that, after Kant, it is difficult to ignore the participation of our mind in
what we perceive. Something, of course, comes from abroad: lights and shadows that
move in the case of the wave and that our eyes receive as changes in the environment.
But how or why do we isolate one wave from the rest of the sea?
36
In fact, today, we know that that a tree, for example, is not something separate
and independent but is part of an ecosystem in continuous motion. We also know that
the same tree has parts that make it up and that all are changing. However, we identify it
as "the same", i.e., as an object more or less stable, separated from the rest of the world
and therefore as something that is likely to be counted.
If we focus only on objects that can be sensed, to which we reportedly are first
attracted when we are born(and it is logical to think that that is the case), we find a very
confusing and changing totality of sensations. This could be something like the
following:
37
What captures our eyes is not the only record. Ernest Mach (1925), for example,
says feelings of emotional pleasure and pain should join such sensations as colour,
sound, heat, pressure, space, and time. These are called sensations. Carnap (1961) called
experiences as that which you are conscious of from outside or inside of ourselves.
Experiences may be visual, auditory, thermal, sentimental, and emotional. Finally,
Bertrand Russell (1914) also mentions as records the results of our own introspection.
From the drawing above, the Adding Theory (see, for example, Strawson, P.F.
1959) argues that in some way babies go isolating some of those impressions from the
rest; so the order is only as a result of the experience. Some argue that the first things
we can identify are individual things because we interact with them. However, I am
inclined to think that the first thing we can separate is still of a general nature as, for
example, the red, the green, vertical lines, crossed lines, and so on.
My position is that after we perceive a confused and changing set of images, the next
step is to separate “family resemblances”, i.e., to segregate similar sensations.
According to our drawing, we should obtain something like the following in one case:
38
Or something like:
These results can be called universals or features that are repeated again and
again, here and there; that is, they play freely in space and time.
The next step is to identify objects, i.e., to separate something out of the set of
sensations and see it as a stable individuality. If we follow this line of thought, we can
obtain individuals through the intersection of multiple universal features. Vision to
consider individual things as sets of properties begins, in my view, in Plato's Timaeus
(47-53), when he considers that,
Whenever we observe a thing perceptually changing –fire, for example- in every case
we should speak of fire, not as ‘this’, but as ‘what is of such and such a quality’, nor of
water as ‘this’, but always as ‘what is of such and such a quality’; nor must we speak of
anything else as having some permanence, among all the things we indicate by the
expressions ‘this’ or ‘that’, imagining we are pointing out some definite thing... In fact,
we must give the name ‘fire’ to that which is at all times of such and such a quality.
That way, when I say that X is an individual, this will be something that is black
and consists of crossing lines, while the individual ♥ is something that is black and
39
heart-shaped. For these simple examples, I need at least two universals to identify an
individual. Of course, in real life, we use many universals to define a particular.
Similarly for Quine, we perceive inside changing totalities certain fixed points
we call individual things. These are points because they are considered, in some respect,
to be indivisible and fixed because they differ from the rest of the perceived changes.
As Quine (1981, p. 9) says,
Our expressions on external things, our notion of things, constitute only a conceptual
apparatus serving us to predict and control activation of our sensory receptors in the
light of the previous activation of these receivers.
Taking this perspective, we can ask ourselves, for example, in what sense do we
conceive this portfolio I have front of me as a unique object? The notes that define it
are: a) the concept of portfolio, which is something like the "family air" in
Wittgenstein’s sense, and b) a set of Minkowski spaces, i.e., the fact that it was day x at
time y, and day z at time w, and so on when I recognised it as "the same" because of
various features, such as colour and size, which also form a "family air". The concept of
“portfolio” and this particular object can be viewed as having a "family resemblance"
and differ only in the degree of precision because when I designate as an individual an
instance of a concept, I am only adding to the "family resemblance" expressed in the
concept a new "family resemblance" that is represented by this instance and any other
that I would likewise designate.
40
The Gestalt theory of perception of Max Wertheimer (1945), Wolfgang Köhler
(1947) and Kurt Koffka (1927), and in our days Pylyshyn (2007) holds, in contrast, that
children perceive and respond holistically. Only later they are able to perceive the
individual sensations inside of totalities that they initially capture vaguely.
Perhaps we can represent this initial set of sensations by the following picture:
We start by sorting out all the confused and changing totalities that we register,
that is, those images that we do not know in detail and of which we could not enumerate
their constitutive universal features. However, we do identify them as something more
41
or less stable and separated from the rest, that being the tree. Carnap (1961) called these
“experiences”, while Mach (1886) described them as more or less stable complexes of
sensations.
Lakoff and Nuñez (2000, pp. 15-23) affirm that human beings have the ability to
make fast, precise judgments about the size of small collections of objects, which is
different than counting or estimating. That ability is called "subitizing". Apparently,
four-and-a-half-month-old babies, as well as some animals, can distinguish between two
and three element collections and can "say" that two objects less one object is the same
as, or results in, an object.
In my view, we can explain these findings in the study of the cognitive science
as the correlatives of "family airs" mentioned above or as the counterpart of totalities as
suggested by the Gestaltist school.
In advance, I must warn that I am not taking the term “exist” as many mathematicians
understand it when they say that one thing exists mathematically if it is consistent with
the interior of mathematics or when they prove the existence of certain entities or
mathematical relations by deducing them from certain axioms or mathematical
principles.
Now, in general terms, when we say that something exists, what do we mean?
Widely differing answers have been given to this question. In philosophy, the
discussion inevitably leads to the first philosophers. Among them, let us remember the
dispute between Plato and Aristotle. For Aristotle (Metaphysics, 981a), only particular
things exist: "experience, indeed, is the knowledge of singulars”. For Plato, existence is
certainly not limited to directly perceptible entities; instead, he posited what we today
call universals. From this tension, we can identify two major streams, each with their
42
respective nuances: a) there are those who claim (e.g., the Nominalists) that there are no
universals, even in individual things, as Aristotle would have accepted (This group
affirms that there are only physical objects, linguistic expressions, and mental events, all
of which are spatially and temporally determined in one Minkowski space); b) there are
those who, with Plato or today with Bigelow (1988, p. 4), defend the existence of
universals, which "play freely with the space and time".
43
question. Of course, a mental painting can be described by means of language, as with
Newton's theory.
However, after Kant, it is difficult to sustain a position that holds that we do not
know the participation of the structure of our perception and the activity of our minds in
the painting that we have of what exists independently of that we know. Therefore,
Quine (1981, p. 32) says:
All objects are theoretical..., [while, even] understanding of a term does not imply a
"designatum", precedes the knowledge of whether the term has or not a "designatum".
In these terms, the so-called physical things are not more real than other things
that are not seen as such. In the end, things, processes, and qualities do more than be as
44
such in the world or even in our perception; they are mental constructs that attempt to
separate and fix some aspect of the continuous and changing totality. Individual things
are such only in the way that we have conceptualised the world. In addition, we have to
remember that this conceptualisation is a cultural product expressed in our natural
language that guides us to "see" things where we can also see processes, qualities, or
totalities. As Orayen (1989, p. 289) said, "Ontology depends on a fairly high degree of
convention". For example, unlike what happens in Western languages,
...a great number of Chinese words do duty for both nouns and verbs-so that one who
thinks in Chinese has little difficulty in seeing that objects are also events. (Watts, 1957,
p. 5)
Therefore, as Quine (1951) says following Duhem and Carnap, "our statements
about the external world face the tribunal of sense experience not individually but only
as a corporate body". Therefore, when testing in general that a linguistic or mental
entity refers to something, that entity should be displayed within a total theoretical-
practical body, such that it directly or indirectly can be seen as an idealisation and
interpretation of something empirical. This is why it is not easy to determine the
references of singular terms because at the beginning and the end of the cognitive
process, we have totalities. It is only in the middle of that process that we have fixed
and isolated entities that could be the references of singular terms.
Therefore, in accordance with what we have said above, a mental painting can
refer to: A) another "mental painting"; B) an empirical universal; or C) an empirical
individual.
More precisely, in the first case (A), we can say that mental painting X refers to
another mental painting Z if: 1) We can establish a homomorphism in the way that
Krantz, Luce, Suppes, and Tversky (1971) propose for all numeric representations.
However, they suggest that there should be a homomorphism that is represented over
the representation. I am proposing that there should be, rather, a homomorphism in
45
reverse to express the idea that one painting is an idealisation of that which has been
painted. Not every element of the item painted is represented in the painting, as Plato
emphasised in the Cratilo; 2) We can show that X interprets Z; and 3) In addition, Z
refers to a universal or an individual empirical.
In the second case (B), we can say that a mental painting Z refers to a universal
empirical S, which is perceptible in certain conceptualisations if: 1) The universal has
empirical instances s1, s2, s3, and so on, i.e., individuals that are partially portrayed by
mental paintings of the universal; 2) We can demonstrate within a successful empirical
theory that Z interprets those instances and based on that interpretation we can predict
certain behaviours of s1, s2, s3, and so on.
We finally say, in the third case (C), that a mental painting Z refers to an
individual empirical M, which is perceptible in certain conceptualisations if: 1) The
painting can establish a homomorphism from Z to M; 2) We can demonstrate within a
successful empirical theory that Z interprets M and based on that interpretation we can
predict the behaviour of M.
Within the Nominalistic current, Field (1980) categorically denied the existence
of such entities as numbers. For him, as for many, there are only physical objects,
linguistic expressions, and mental events.
46
The best argument against Field that sustains the proposition that mathematics
can be seen as true (that is, viewed as if speaking of certain entities which execute
mathematical laws) has been the given by Quine and Putnam when they emphasised
that we need to apply such entities to carry out ordinary inferences about the physical
world and do science. However, against this argument, Field holds that mathematising
an empirical theory only creates a schema (which is not necessary) with the idea of
making deduction easier than in non-mathematised theory.
To Field, an empirical theory (F) for interpreting the domain (R) adds certain
theoretical terms to explain and predict the behaviour of that domain. This
understanding matches the position taken by the Structural Conception in the
Philosophy of Science (e.g., Balzer Moulines, Sneed, 1987). When mathematising the
empirical theory in question, we get a version (F') that does not expand on the theory (F)
and, therefore, is just another way of saying the same thing (F = F').
The example provided by Field (1980, p. 22) for arithmetic begins by replacing
references to numbers (21, for example) by Nominalistic expressions of the type
“∃21x(Cx)”, where
…there are not singular terms or quantifiers for numbers or other abstract entities:
number 21 occurs not as a name, but only as part of a symbol operator.
47
However, Field says that it is difficult to work with those Nominalistic
expressions. However, if you replace these expressions with mathematised phrases,
such as "the cardinal of the boxes set is 21", which makes explicit reference to the
number 21, you can use mathematics for deductions more easily. Field shows that we
can say the same thing by referring specifically to numbers, or by replacing references
to numbers with Nominalistic expressions, such as those mentioned above.
This strategy leads us to ask ourselves what it means that we can say "the same
thing" in two different conceptual systems: one containing arithmetic and the other not
containing arithmetic but utilising, at a minimum, some form of quantitative logic and n
X. Of course, to say that there are 21 X is not the same as saying that there is the
number 21: the second referent is not spatial and temporal, while with 21 X, we assume
that it is such.
However, to accept the conclusions that Field makes, we should still test to see
whether we accept that there is space-temporality associated with 21 X and not accept
implicitly the same ontology that we use when we accept that number 21 is the cardinal
of a set of space-time entities. To put the point in another way, we can wonder if Field’s
Nominalistic scientific theory is a numeric interpretation of reality or if F does not
contain F'. My intuition is that Field’s Nominalistic translation, indeed, does not remove
all numbers and only prevents us from speaking of them. Given that judgement, if we
can say the same thing in two different conceptual systems, we can ask, is this because
they share the same basic ontology? To change the language we use does not guarantee
the elimination of any entity that is explicitly spoken of in any of these languages. Thus,
to test for an entity, we need to do something more than just identify a way to talk about
it without explicitly mentioning it. As Maxwell has already pointed out in relation to
Ramsey’s statements and Craig’s productions,
48
We have seen that elimination of theoretical terms, even by explicit definition, would
not necessarily eliminate reference to theoretical (unobservable) entities. We have also
seen that, even if reference to theoretical entities could be eliminated,... the reality
(existence) of the theoretical entities is not thereby militated against... I should say the
likelihood-of the existence of unobserved causes for the observed events would still
remain. (Maxwell, 1962, p. 19)
Field’s (1980, p. 13) other argument holding that mathematics does not talk
about things that exist in some way is as follows:
I believe that Field is right in saying that his conclusions imply that mathematics
must be valid in all possible worlds; that is, mathematics does not contain some
interpretation of a particular reality. Indeed, as we affirmed above, Field could maintain
his conclusion that a Nominalistic theory F contains its mathematisation F' if he proves
that F' by itself has no interpretative elements of reality R. Thus, to reject Field’s
position, we must show not only that F contains F' but also that predictions F" of reality
R cannot be obtained from F alone if we remove from it all localisable or equivalent
items to F'.
I believe that both the Field position and the opposite are yet to be tested.
However, against Field, Frechet (1958), and Lakatos (1978) have already suggested that
mathematics is falsifiable, and Hossack (1991, p. 157) recently stated that
49
The proofs need worlds like our spatio-temporal-causal one, and would fail at less
obliging possible worlds; this implies that the mathematical truths are not necessary
since they do not hold throughout logical space.
We are left with the ontology of pure set theory, since the numbers and their quadruples
can be modelled within it.
For Quine, as for other reductionists, there are no numbers because every number used
in every context can be replaced by other, presumably more basic, entities, namely sets.
Thus, in attempting not to multiply ontology unnecessarily, Quine (1981, p. 31) only
supports an "unwavering belief in external things,... and also, albeit with less firmness,
in atoms and electrons, and classes". He only reluctantly supports these latter entities
because they permit one to model all mathematics.
This position refers to the situation when, given two conceptual systems, one (in
this case, set theory) contains another (in this case, arithmetic). Set theory does not
explicitly speak of numbers, but if numbers are certain sets, I see no difficulty in saying
that there are numbers, just as there are sets. In fact, for Frege, one of the most
important reductionists, to say that mathematics is logical and that numbers may be
expressed in terms of extensions of concepts (or sets) does not deny the existence of
numbers. It only involves dealing with certain particular sets.
50
Bigelow (1988, p. 3) argues that "numbers and mathematical objects in general
are universals".
The theory of universals will be a systematic collection of statements about the relations
among universals. And that, I claim, is precisely what mathematics is… In mathematics
we study the relations among relations. (Bigelow, 1988, p. 16)
Contrary to this statement, Berkeley (prior to Frege, 1884) argued that "the
number is entirely a mind creature,... because the same thing has a different numeric
designation according to the perspective from which is designed" (in Baum, 1973, p.
184 and Robles, 1993, p. 99). Thus, a house, for example, does not have a single
number assigned. Instead, it would have several because it has, for example, 2 doors, 4
windows, and 200 square yards.
51
However, to Bigelow, numbers are not properties of physical objects, as claimed
by Mill (1874), nor are numbers part of the preaching about concepts, as Frege (1884)
states; they are relationships between specific objects. According to Bigelow, doors
have a relationship called 2, windows have a relationship called 4, square yards have a
relationship called 200, and the house has a relationship with itself called 1.
Therefore, even if I share with Armstrong and Bigelow the idea that there are
more objects than those defined spatiotemporally, I do not see the need to maintain the
belief that the world can only be conceptualised from physical objects and their
relationships. Therefore numbers, because they are not in space-time, are not necessarily
relations between objects, as Bigelow concludes.
Resnik (1988, pp. 400, 401), supporting the considerations of Quine, states:
52
That idea contests the pretence put forward by Field that it is possible to have a fully
Nominalistic theory that does not contain, even implicitly, mathematical items.
To know the natural number sequence involves knowing that it contains an initial
position (zero), that every position has a unique successor, that the sequence goes on
without end, and that the principle of mathematical induction holds for its positions.
However, Resnik does not conclude there that "there are no such things as
numbers" as Benacerraf did (Benacerraf, 1965, p. 73). Resnik (1997) suggests that
mathematics studies the structures (patterns) that exist in the empirical world, as the
universals of Amstrong and Bigelow.
Penelope Maddy (1980, 1990) supports the ideas of Gödel (1944 and 1947):
there is an analogy between mathematics and physical sciences. This analogy is in
agreement with the reductionists, such as Quine, in defending the idea that mathematics
(and particularly natural numbers) can be reduced to the theory of sets. On this basis,
Maddy was given the task of displaying that the direct perception of sets provides the
foundation to sustain a causal theory of our knowledge of mathematical objects.
Set-theoretic realism is a view whose main tenets are that sets exist independently of
human thought, and that set theory is the science of these entities. (Maddy, 1980, p.
163)
To substantiate this realistic position in mathematics, Maddy (1990, p. 180) states, “all
sets have physical grounding and spatiotemporal location, and all physical objects are
sets”.
53
To the objections of Benacerraf (1965), that numbers can be identified with
different sequences of sets and that, therefore, numbers may not be sets, Maddy (1990,
p. 179) responds “that neither sequence is the numbers, that numbers are properties of
sets”.
2.2.3. Synthesis
According to the ideas put forward in paragraph 2.1, claims about the existence or non-
existence of numbers result in terms of mental paintings, while for some realistic
authors, such as Bigelow, Resnik and Maddy, numbers are real paintings of something.
For other non-realistic authors, such as Field and Quine, numbers are only pseudo-
paintings. For the former, numbers have a counterpart outside of mind, whereas for the
latter, numbers are mental entities but that do not relate to the real world.
distinction obliged Field to deny the existence of the numbers because they are
universal. To the contrary, defending the existence of numbers obliged Bigelow and
Resnik to defend the existence of universals in general and Frege and Maddy to defend
the idea that numbers are individuals. However, if in the end, if it is possible to perceive
a “family resemblance” of individuals and universals, stating that numbers are
individuals or universals does not allow us to decide on their existence.
Thus, in the case of the natural numbers, we can say, for example, that
arithmetic number 3 exists if we can see it as a mental painting that directly or indirectly
portrays something in the empirical world. In fact, I will attempt to display in the
following chapters that meta-mathematical numbers are mental paintings of arithmetic
numbers, which are mental paintings of pre-mathematical numbers, and these last
numbers refer to empirical events.
55
First, I will explain that pre-mathematical numbers are the result of a
reclassification of the empirical in pairs, trios, and so on which is possible only after a
primitive conceptualisation of experience. These pre-mathematical numbers, which
multiply and complicate the already questionable ontology of arithmetic numbers, allow
us to build a plausible bridge between the empirical world and pure arithmetic.
With the goal of clarifying how we reach these reclassifications, we start from
the idea that we perceive the world as a changing totality, as demonstrated in 2.1.1.
From that idea, we can imagine that the classification process starts grouping, i.e.,
isolating and settling certain parts or aspects of that changing totality. We call
universals to these parts or aspects. Then we can “see” certain individuals as the cross of
several of those universals. To clarify this idea, I suppose that we have globally
conceptualised the world so that only we "see" the following objects:
Now, once we have these individual objects, we can regroup them by means of the
following concepts:
56
(B) “Gray squares”
We can see that there is a "family resemblance" between objects that fall under
"gray triangles", "gray squares", “black triangles”, and "black circles". We call this
reclassification “pair”: a pair of gray triangles, a pair of gray squares, a pair of black
triangles, and a pair of black circles. That is, the family resemblance is expressed as “be
a pair”. There is another family resemblance between the objects that falls under "black
square” and “gray circle”. We call this reclassification “trio”: a trio of red squares and a
trio of red circles fall under “trio”. This is the family resemblance “be a trio”.
These reclassifications, which I call pre-mathematical numbers, are those that
Russell (1919, p. 14) describes by saying, "it is clear that to conceive numbers is a way
to group... we can assume all pairs in a group, to all trios in another and so on".
Concept A
Concept C “Pair” 2
Concept F
“Trio” 3
Concept E
58
Now, to support the idea of arithmetic numbers linked to the empirical world by
mean of numbers that I call pre-mathematical, next we will discuss the following
questions: A) Can arithmetic numbers be viewed as mental paintings of the pre-
mathematical numbers? B) Can pre-mathematic numbers be seen as mental paintings
with perceptible instances in the empirical world, and in that sense, can we see
arithmetic as a double idealisation and interpretation of something empirical?
Now, if n1, n2, n3,... are arithmetical numbers and r1, r2, r3,... are the
corresponding pre-mathematical reclassifications, (A-1a) is already true because given
any n natural number, I can find the corresponding reclassification, which would be the
"family resemblance" between that which falls under the concept "things that added get
n” and other concepts with instances that can be one-to-one with the instances of "things
that added get n”. Even with the "family resemblance" corresponding to infinitely large
natural numbers, it is possible to find a corresponding reclassification because the world
does not have a fixed number of empirical objects. It has as many "items" as we are able
to imagine. I understand here “imagine”, not as the creation of fictitious items, such as
59
unicorns, but rather as our ability to split our experiences in multiple ways. For
example, in the above conceptualised world, we have 14 objects: squares, triangles and
circles, black and gray. However, it is possible to have 37 objects, grasped as long, short
and curved lines, or more, if we conceptualise in other ways.
To test (A-1b), let us determine whether the successor and the operation of the
sum that governs between mathematical numbers also operate similarly between pre-
mathematical numbers.
XXxxχ IIIII
X x II X x χ III
+ =
TT // TTT OO T T T T T
If we look only for the “X”, we can see that this "sum" has multiple constraints: the
“Xs” that are grouped by the concept "pair" must be different from the “Xs” grouped by
the concept "trio" (in the picture, this is true because the pairs are black and the trios are
60
gray); each element of the couple and of the trio is a different object, with the exception
of be “X”; to join the two groups, we obtain another group consisting of five different
“Xs”; there must be “Xs” in both groups to carry out the "sum"; in this regard, there
may be pairs without a corresponding trio, as in the case of (//). From this simple
example, we can see that, indeed, an operation analogous to (though with certain
restrictions) arithmetic addition can occur between the so-called pre-mathematical
numbers. With pre-mathematical numbers, we form a new "family resemblance" from
the two "family resemblances" given. It is not difficult to show that this “sum” is both
commutative and associative.
However, to explain the relationship "z is w successor", we must show that some
Peano Axioms are met for all rx entities: namely, that there is a reclassification, say r1
(axiom 1), that is not successor of any other (axiom 8) and rx + r1 = Srx, where Srx is
also a reclassification (axiom 6), and Srx is rx successor.
There is, indeed, r1, which is the "family resemblance" between all the concepts
that may be deemed as "defined descriptions", i.e., that each of these concepts are
satisfied by one object only. However, r1 is not rx successor for any n if we do not
accept r0 as a true reclassification. However, as in the arithmetics, we could accept r0,
extending the notion of pre-mathematical numbers. Finally, for all rx exists Srx because
if rx is a "family resemblance" between certain concepts, there will be a new "family
resemblance" when objects described by those concepts add another object, which is
true if we accept the conditions of possibility of the “sum” of reclassifications, i.e., that
they are different groups of similar objects.
61
xxxx…n+1
xxx…n
+ = + x o =
ooo…n
/
oooo…n+1
We can finally briefly show that (A-1c) is true: in other words, arithmetic
numbers are individual objects (as was emphasised by Frege and Russell) that portray
other individual objects (i.e., pre-mathematical numbers). We can see that arithmetic
numbers and pre-arithmetical numbers are individual objects because these numbers can
be defined individually. Frege did so with the meta-mathematical numbers that we will
present in Chapter 4, and here, I have attempted to show that pre-mathematical numbers
are closely linked to certain specific concepts; thus, to define each pre-mathematical
number we do not need other pre-mathematical numbers, i.e., we can define, for
example, “unit” with the concepts that encapsulate an element, “pair” with the concepts
that encapsulate two elements, and so on.
odd numbers or two even numbers produces an even number and that the sum of an odd
number and an even number always produces an odd number. Within the pre-
mathematical numbers, we define as "odd number" (rO) all reclassifications of r1 or the
successor of an "even number" (rE), where rE is defined as the successor of an "odd
number". In effect, that is true for all rO and rE, that rO + rE = rO. This equation is true
because, in general, pairs and trios, which are the entities that fall under the
reclassifications r1, r2, r3, behave as mathematical numbers; that is, a couple of horses,
together with a trio of different horses, produce a quintet of horses. The same is true for
any other pairs and trios.
However, with the “sum” of empirical objects this does not have to always be
the case. It is perfectly conceivable that, for example, the empirical “sum” of the weight
of two bodies be unequal to the arithmetic addition of the respective numbers, perhaps
due to where energy is produced in the union of bodies. In fact, similar events occur in
the subatomic world, for example volumes of water and alcohol, or other quantities,
such as the temperature of two bodies, join together.
On this basis, we can say that arithmetic numbers laws idealise and interpret the
general behaviour of, for example, pairs and trios. Arithmetic is not valid in all possible
worlds, as Field supposed, and we cannot use arithmetic with all pairs and trios in our
world, even though it seems irrefutable by its indirect reference to the empirical world.
Thus, we conclude that arithmetic numbers can be seen as mental images of pre-
mathematical numbers.
3- Finally, to prove that the arithmetic numbers can be seen as real paintings we
subtract show that pre-matemáticos numbers can be seen at the same time as conceptual
paintings with instances in the empirical world. This brings us to the second case (B).
63
B) To test that a mental painting (pre-mathematical number) refers to a universal
empirical, we need to determine the following: 1) if there are empirical instances of this
universal; 2) if we can show in the interior of a successful empirical theory that mental
painting interprets and explains the behaviour of these empirical instances.
From those definitions, Galileo mathematically figured the corollary that a body in
freefall during times 1, 2, 3, 4, and so on runs spaces that are as the odd numbers 1, 3, 5,
7, and so on. This result, verifiable in experience, astonished Galileo and convinced him
that the laws of nature work mathematically.
Now, how are the numbers 1, 2, 3, and so on used here? In other words, do they
refer to the mental paintings r1, r2, r3, and so on? Also, in turn, does each of these
reclassifications respectively cluster empirical units, pairs, and trios? And, finally, can
64
we bypass them without mutilating the image of the world that we form with this
theory?
Galileo mentions durations and distances and assign numbers to them. However,
what is the meaning of the expression “2 seconds” or “3 centimetres”? The duration is
the perception of relative changes. There are, however, some changes longer than
others, such as the rotation of the Earth around the Sun or the rotation of the Moon
around the Earth. In the case of this experiment, we have a comparative concept that
distinguishes between what is time and what is not while also distinguishing between
times. The next step in the accuracy of the concept, as Carnap (1961) states, is assigning
numbers to different times so that we can say that, for example, the time tn is 2 times the
time tm, etc. When we reach this point, we are able to apply arithmetic laws to the
domain in question. Galileo’s references could be as follows:
↵ in seconds
Time “Pair” 2
Y 1 Y2
Spaces travelled
Z1 Z 2
↑
Z3
“Trio” 3
⇐ Time in seconds
S 1 S 2
S 3
65
We can see in this schema that the conceptual painting of "pair" is instantiated
by a couple of seconds or a couple of centimetres, being that these instances are
perceived by the senses. The same is true for "trio", which is instantiated by different
trios perceptible to the senses. The same would occur with other many reclassifications
of this type.
Aristotle’s study
Distances between of motion Quantification of the
objects and times movement s with the
definitions of Galileo
66
In the words of Galileo (1638, p. 190):
There is nothing in the nature oldest than movement and there is no shortage of
voluminous books on this subject... In spite of this, many of their properties, very
worthy of unknown, have not been observed or demonstrated so far... Indeed, as far as I
know, no one has shown that a mobile that falls on the basis of rest, iterates in equal
times spaces that keep together the same proportion between successive odd numbers
starting with the unit.
67
68
Chapter 3
69
3.1. Mental operation for counting
Regardless of the possible source of numbers or the beginning of the process for
counting objects, one might wonder, how do we count today? In other words, what
mental operations are necessary to count? Perhaps analysing these operations will shed
some light on how it was possible that the process for counting arose and how the same
numbers arose.
We now move from the original chaotic state to the formation of more or less
stable individual objects, and we obtain certain objects, such as the following: © ∏ ♦
♠ ♥ ϕ Ξ ♥. When we have obtained these objects, we need to do the following:
a) We group some of these objects in a set; in other words, we take one or more of
the characteristics of what has been identified to differentiate objects that
have these characteristics from objects that do not. Thus, we have a group
of objects that share one or more features. Objects that are black, for
example, will be in a group, or there will be a group of gray, or a group of
objects with the same figure. Thus, we should obtain the following groups,
among others that are possible:
{© ∏ ♥ ϕ Ξ }
{♥♦ ♠ }
{♥ ♥}
c) We then deprive © of all its attributes except for the fact that it is (or we see it
as) a stable singular object. Thus, we are left with a sort of ghost without
any attributes, which we denote as . This ghost, in the words of
Euclid (Elements, Book VII, def. 1), “is that with respect to which each
existing thing [and which is to be counted] is called one".
70
d) We do the same with ∏, then with ♥, ϕ and Ξ. At the end of this process, we
should obtain the following:
{ },
g) As a next step, we would do the same with the second group, thus obtaining
the following: ⏐ ⏐ ⏐.
h) Finally, we would obtain ⏐ ⏐ from the third group in the same way.
i) We can represent the grouped objects in the first, second, and third group in
the following manner:
⏐⏐⏐⏐⏐
⏐⏐⏐
⏐⏐
71
3.2. Primitive languages for counting
In this book, we try not to investigate the history of the numbers of arithmetic. Our inquiry
is logical. However, at this point, we pursue certain historical data about the primitive
languages with the idea of seeing a form that could conform to the process of the symbolic
representation of the results of accounts.
⎮⎮⎮
From that time, symbols were established with writing and handling that did not
depended on objects that they represented. Apparently, they went from managing diverse
objects to managing something perfectly homogeneous as points (...), lines (⎮⎮⎮), or
marks (Ú Ú Ú) on stone.
72
It is interesting to note that in older known numbering systems (see Cajori, 1928-
29), small sums represented numbers, or at least a meeting, of the symbol used to represent
the number one. This can be seen in the following box:
Indo-Arabic 1 2 3 4 5 10
Babylon Ú ÚÚ ÚÚÚ ×
Egyptians
(Hieroglyphic) ⎮ ⎮⎮ ⎮⎮⎮ ∩
(Hieratic) ⎮ γ ψ >
Chinese, Japanese ~ ~ ~ †
Romans I II III V X
Maya . .. ... - =
Hindu - = ≡
In the Hieratic Egyptian and Chinese languages, there were slight differences
between the symbol for one and the symbols for two and three; regardless, two is
represented by two features similar to the features used to represent one, and the same goes
for the three. The Indo-Arabic symbols, which we use today, stylise Hindu characters: the
"=" shifted to 2, and "≡", written quickly, became 3. On the contrary, the box above shows
that they adopted different symbols for larger numbers, sometimes from the four, five or
ten. This adoption surely was due to the impracticality of representing, for example, the
number 100 by repeating the symbol used for the number one.
73
Therefore, because the same sign was used to refer to three horses, three stones,
and so on, the sign already did not refer to horses or stones; rather, they referred to
something different than the numbered objects. Now, what do symbols such as Ú Ú Ú or
⎮⎮⎮ refer to? Do those symbols concern, perhaps, specific threesomes? To trios in
general? To the concept of "trio"? Or, perhaps, these marks simply scored the objects as
they were counted? The hypothesis that I will defend is that this last answer addresses the
handling of these symbols better than the other possibilities.
With respect to whether such symbols represented, perhaps, a trio in general, the
concept "trio", or simple marks, we should consider the handling of such symbols.
74
This behaviour of the numbers can be explained if we conceive, or simply handle
the number 2 and number 3 as formed by repetitions of the number 1. If so, it can be seen
easily that ⎮⎮ + ⎮ =⎮⎮⎮. This idea would explain how we obtain three from two and one.
In short, primitive languages reflect the widespread sum operation and the relationship of
equality between different groups of numbers, implying a common basis.
Now, based on the above, the Ú Ú Ú or ⎮⎮⎮ symbols cannot represent specific
trios. In a trio, the three elements are different, although possibly similar, while the three
elements of each group that represents the number 3 are exactly the same: it is the same
symbol repeated three times. The oldest languages were pictographic, so if you wanted to
represent a trio, it would be more correct to do so with three different symbols (for
example: λÚ♣). There would be a different symbol for each different trio, and, as stated
above, once numeric languages unified, only one symbol was used for each number.
However, if we identify the symbol ⎮⎮⎮ with a trio in general, i.e., if that symbol
represents all trios or each possible trio, the sum operation, for example, would not be
general. To add any pair with any trio we would need, at least, for the grouped objects in
the pair to be different from those grouped in the trio; i.e., that there were no repeats of any
of the grouped objects because if this is the case, we should obtain three or four objects
instead of five. However, ⎮⎮ + ⎮⎮⎮ = ⎮⎮⎮⎮⎮ does not give any restrictions, provided
that with two and then three vertical lines, will we obtain five vertical lines.
However, the number ⎮⎮⎮, for example, cannot represent the concept that all trios
fall under. I called these concepts that are divided worldwide into pairs, trios, and so on
"first level numbers". Certainly, these reclassifications resemble arithmetic numbers, but in
spite of that resemblance, I do not think that we can identify arithmetical numbers 1, 2, 3,
and so on with the concepts “unit”, “pair”, “trio”, and so on as shown in 2.3.
75
Finally, assuming that primitive symbols are only marks repeated many times, in
this case it should be noted that I am not talking about those in space-time: these are
always different from each other. I mean, rather, the result always equals of the action of
marking, which can be repeated as many times as desired. There is no difference between
⎮ and ⎮: in fact, they are exactly the same mark drawn twice. Therefore, both symbols
refer to the same item. This item is not the singular act of marking that is also given in
space-time but the result of an action that, as considered in the abstract, can be repeated as
many times as desired. The result of the action of marking is an individual abstract. In
other words, it is the result of an action that is not defined in space-time, but only by
characteristics that make it such object and nothing else.
Hilbert (1922) adopted a similar idea, saying that numbers are a series of trade
marks ⏐, ⏐⏐, ⏐⏐⏐,... "whose form is space and time-independent, and independent of
the circumstances in which were produced". This proposal differs from mine because to
Hilbert, numbers are marks, while I propose that such marks are only symbols. Thus,
primitive languages for counting repeat the same symbol and reference to something that
can be repeated many times. Thus, ⎮⎮⎮ refers to the outcome of the action of counting,
repeated three times. There is no difference between one brand and another, as there is no
difference across a sum of ones.
76
The results of the accounts represented, for example, ⏐⏐⏐⏐⏐, ⏐⏐⏐, ⏐⏐,
become autonomous entities as well as any other result that can be represented with
repetitions of ⏐ or another equivalent symbol.
Once we have obtained these symbols, we can forget about their meaning and
manipulate them in multiple ways. Let us look at this situation in some detail:
{© ∏ ♥ ϕ Ξ }
{♥ ♦ ♠ }
{♥ ♥}
⏐⏐⏐⏐⏐
⏐⏐⏐
⏐⏐
⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐, ⏐ ⏐ ⏐, ⏐ ⏐
⏐ ⏐ + ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ = ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐;
⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ > ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ > ⏐ ⏐;
⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ + ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ + ⏐ ⏐ = ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐;
⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ and ⏐ ⏐ are pairs because they can be divided into two equal
parts ⏐ ⏐ /⏐ ⏐ and ⏐/⏐;
77
⏐ ⏐ ⏐ and ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ are odds because they do not have two equal
parts ⏐ ⏐/ ⏐ and ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ / ⏐ ⏐.
e) Then, we discovered the laws governing such unions and the general
behaviour of these symbols that represent numbers:
⏐ ⏐ ⏐ +⏐ ⏐ =⏐ ⏐ +⏐ ⏐ ⏐ Commutative Law
(⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ + ⏐ ⏐ ⏐) + (⏐ ⏐) = (⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐ ⏐) +
(⏐ ⏐ ⏐ + ⏐ ⏐) Associative Law
In conclusion, we can say that the process of counting objects creates certain
autonomous entities that can be handled. My proposal here is that these entities are fairly
natural numbers of arithmetic.
78
3.4. The ontology and epistemology of numbers
3.4.1. Ontology
Regardless of the historical origins of numbers, which go beyond the aims of the present
study, the question that we want to pose here is what are the numbers of arithmetic? We
know what arithmetic numbers are and what their properties are because the discipline
of arithmetic has reported that knowledge, but we do not know what these numbers are
in terms of their ontology. That is, what type of entities are they? Are they universal or
individual? Are they abstract or concrete?
Numbers are objects because we can distinguish them from one another. The
number 4, for example, has the feature that it is greater than 3, less than 5, and so on.
We say that they are abstract objects because we cannot identify them spatiotemporally,
but they have relationships that are well defined.
Actions that generate musical notes are physical actions that produce sounds.
For example, we can vibrate a rope that produces a "C", and as long as I vibrate the
same rope or other similar rope I get "C". Actions that produce geometric figures are
mental actions because I came, for example, to the triangle by measuring, which is a
mental activity.
7
As Hersh (1997) says, “Frege showed that mathematical objects are neither physical nor
mental. He labeled them abstract objects” (p. 13).
79
I can reach the number 3, for example, in a process of counting and consider the
balance on the account as an object in itself. In that sense, the 3 is the result of isolating,
removing attributes, and symbolising each entity isolated. Then, I obtain something
such as this: ⏐⏐⏐.
Thus, the ⏐⏐⏐ arithmetic is an abstract individual, as the musical note "C",
which is also, incidentally, the result of a repeatable action. Therefore, ontologically, we
equate numbers to musical notes and to geometric figures and other "entities",
classifying them as abstract objects; i.e., that are not spatial-temporal but have well-
defined mutual relations. For example, the result of issuing musical note "E" shall be
treated as equal, regardless of whether emits a singer or another emits the note, in a one
moment or another. This note will have the same musical value and relations with other
musical notes, such as "C" and "A". The same idea holds true the numbers ⏐⏐⏐ and
⏐⏐: they will have the same value and same relations to each other regardless of their
origin.
80
Now, second level numbers may be seen as paintings of first-level numbers, as
we established in 2.3. I do not mean that arithmetic numbers arose with the intention to
portray the pre-mathematical numbers, but only that we can see the arithmetic in that
way. We clarify the relationship between the first and second level numbers using the
following scheme:
Numbers
of 1st Pair Trio Quintet
level
Empirical
objects
Numbers
of 2nd ⎮⎮ ⎮⎮⎮
level
This schema shows that, based on certain empirical objects (or even abstract
objects), two mental processes can operate: one that reclassifies the objects, giving rise
to the first-level numbers, and another that counts them, which represents the origin of
81
the arithmetic numbers, or second-level numbers, as represented by the repetition of a
single numeric symbol. The schema shows that the manipulation of these symbols is the
source of another symbol of the same class that falls under a number of the first level.
b) The elements of the pair and the trio are different from each other.
Therefore, these assumptions are implicit in the expression: "A pair of horses added to a
trio of horses produces a quintet of horses". The expression 2 + 3 = 5 is an idealised
picture of the first expression.
Therefore, according to the above, we can say that, in fact, arithmetic can be
seen as the systematisation of the mental acts of counting and the combination of the
results of the accounts. If so, arithmetic does not explain a domain as do the empirical
sciences, but arithmetic does systematise certain mental operations. Perhaps, but only
perhaps, the same passes for other formal sciences.
82
Clasification Severe Acute
Symphony X
The movement
of bodies
produce
sounds
Symbolise
The sounds C A
Study of sounds
This scheme shows that the movement of bodies, which can be natural or
produced by human beings, generate certain sounds that, on the one hand, may be
classified as severe, acute, and so on; and on the other hand, can be symbolised and
studied by means of the symbolisation, generating a combination of sounds that, in turn,
will fall under any appropriate classification.
Thus, both the numbers and musical notes can be seen as ideal paintings of
empirical entities or entities close to empirical. Number 3 can be viewed as a painting of
83
the concept "trio", which, in turn, is instantiated by specific trios. The note "C" can be
seen also as a painting of a certain class of specific sounds.
3.4.2. Epistemology
From an epistemological perspective, we can now ask ourselves how it is that we obtain
knowledge of arithmetic numbers without invoking mysterious powers. According to
the ontology we proposed, we can know the properties of these numbers from the
moment we have contact with them through the mental acts that produce them, and we
can repeat those acts.
For example, we know that 2 + 3 = 3 + 2 = 5 because if certain mental act A and all
similar acts give the result ⏐⏐, mental act B and similar acts give ⏐⏐⏐, and mental act C
and similar acts give ⏐⏐⏐⏐⏐, then by making mental act B after the mental act A, we still
have the same result as if we make first the mental act B and then the mental act A.
Additionally, if we make only mental act C, then we obtain what we symbolically
represent with several identical symbols: ⏐⏐⏐⏐⏐.
This method of viewing the arithmetic natural numbers as the result of mental
repeatable acts tends to create a causal bridge between us as connoisseurs and the
abstract numbers that result from certain repeatable mental acts.
Mathematical proofs are internal to the same mathematics and do not need any
empirical confirmation. We can deduce from the Peano Axioms that, for example, "The
sum is commutative". My point here is that we accept that the arithmetic sum is
commutative because in most cases, the sum of things is commutative. This idea is not true
in a few cases, such as the temperature of two bodies together. However, because the law
applies to most of the items that we add, we adopt this law as an idealisation of the
empirical.
84
Chapter 4
85
In this book, I propose that the numbers described in Chapter 3 are second-level
numbers that can be viewed as paintings of the reclassifications in pairs and trios
described in Chapter 2, which I called first-level numbers. In this chapter, we will
examine the third-level numbers by means of two concrete examples: the numbers built
by Euclid and the numbers built by Frege.
First, the reader will be presented with the context in which Euclid’s Elements
was done with respect to deductive way of working and with respect specifically to
numbers. Second, an attempt will be made to show that Euclid handles two classes of
numbers: one of these, I call Euclidean mathematical number; the other, I call Euclidean
meta-mathematical numbers. My proposal here is that Euclidean mathematical numbers
are the arithmetic numbers described in the previous chapter.
86
To say that Greek mathematics of the Euclidean style is a strictly Greek
development does not mean to deny a general Oriental background for Greek
mathematics as a whole.
Concerning this last point, Gillings (1972, pp. 232-4) defends the notion that the
Egyptians, contrary to what was believed, often gave mathematical proofs as rigorous as
the given Greeks, even though they were presented in non-symbolic form.
However, Szabó, (1967 and 1978), and Burkert (1972, pp. 424-425) propose that
Parminides and Zenon (while investigating the ontology of being) marked the beginning
of purely rational thought, i.e., that which transcends sense perception and should be
disregarded on the grounds that one ought to follow the argument. According to these
authors, the attempt at purely logical argumentation, a systematic progression from one
thought to another, and the advancement of proofs and conclusions in the Euclidean
way are an invention of the Eliatics. From this perspective, we could say that geometry,
as styled by Thales, was reinforced by the contributions of Parmenides and Zenon.
Netz (1999, p. 273), however, affirmed that the most significant contributions go
no further than the fifth century B.C. In fact, for Netz, Greek mathematics could have
been a sudden explosion of knowledge in Plato’s lifetime, starting with Hipócrates of
Chio, who was the first mathematician to write on Euclidean subject matter.
However, according to Simplicius, he reproduces Eudemus “word for word, adding
only for the sake of clearness a few things taken from Euclid’s Elements”. Fowler
(1999, p. 390) and Netz (2004) have agreed with that idea.
According to Netz (1999, p. 277), the precision of the definitions and the
characteristics that the deductions must have were adopted from Aristotle, as can be
seen in Posterior Analytics. Under that influence, the theorems that appear in the
Elements of Euclid are proven one after the other, in a deductive chain. Although it is
known from Muller (1981) that the deductive chain in the Elements is far from perfect,
there are, for example, implicit elements, and some theorems are not used in subsequent
proofs.
For this reason, the previous context is important here because we must explain
the role of the first two definitions of the Euclidean arithmetic, which seem not to have
any role in the deductive chain. We must also explain, or at least suggest, why Euclid
placed arithmetic within his geometry.
88
centred on geometry”.8 According to Aristotle (Metaphysic 1092b), the Pythagoreans
“decided what was the number of a thing by imitating its form with pebbles”. According
to this statement, some people (see Knorr, 1975, p. 170) have sustained the claim that
Pythagoreans proofs were made with pebble figures. But, the fact that most of the
Euclidean propositions on numbers, as Becker (1957) showed, can be proved with
simple pebble figures does not prove that the Pythagoreans made such proofs. In fact,
the Neo-Pythagorean Nicomachus, for example, did not use that type of proof, or any
other type, in his Introduction to Arithmetic.
Notwithstanding, the correlation between numbers and figures made with pebbles
could have inspired to Euclid to make the correlation between numbers and magnitudes,
as we show here.
In this context, Plato makes the following distinction in the study on numbers. He
affirms in Republic, Georgias and Philebus that there is a theoretical science and a
practical science about even and odd numbers. Following his other distinction between
a pure idea and a sensible object, he says that theoretical science deals with evens and
odds formed of equal (i.e., pure) units, while practical science deals with evens and
odds formed of unequal (i.e., physical) things. In the Republic VII, Plato asks “What
numbers are those that you speak about, in which the units are equal amongst them, do
not differ in the least one from the other, and do not contain in them any part?” The
answer is the mathematical numbers because different units that might not even be
indivisible form empirical numbers. Euclid, we show below, worked with the numbers
that Plato called mathematical or pure.
8
That would also explain that in Euclid's elements, arithmetic (Book VII-IX) is inside of a
treatise of geometry.
89
I called the concepts "pair", "trio", and so on, pre-mathematical numbers. Indeed,
neither these concepts nor empirical pairs and trios are mathematical numbers in the
Platonic sense. In paragraph 2.3, we discussed the idea of seeing the arithmetic
numbers⎮⎮, ⎮⎮⎮,… as paintings of “pair”, “trio”, and so on. In a similar way, ⎮⎮ is a
painting of each of the objects that fall under "pair". In this case, there is a single
painting for different pairs because this is an idealised painting that only collected the
“family resemblance” between a pair of horses, a pair of trees, a couple of houses, and
so on. Therefore I maintain that pure numbers of Plato can be seen as idealized
paintings of arithmoi formed of physical units.
Euclid’s Elements expresses his notion of numbers, with 23 definitions and 102
propositions in Volumes VII to IX. The first two definitions are significantly different
than the rest of the definitions and propositions; thus, what is the place of these two
definitions in the deductive chain of the arithmetic?
This remarkable question has been explained in different ways. Some scholars, as
Iamblichus, have suggested that the two first definitions are not Euclid’s. In that regard,
I accept the two first definitions as part of the Euclidean work, like Szabó (1978),
Mueller (1981), Fowler (1999) and others scholars, who have studied the logical
structure of The Elements. And I focus on how that singular fact is possible or under
what suppositions it has meaning.
90
In the two first definitions, Euclid defines unit and number as follows:
Def. 1. A unit is that with respect to which each existing thing is called one.
Def. 2. A number (arithmos) is a multitude composed of units.
Euclid never uses his definition of a unit in any of his proofs, and he uses his
definition of number only in the following cases:
a) Explicitly as a help in some definitions. For example, we mention definition
15: “A number is said to multiply a number when that which is multiplied is
added to itself as many times as there are units in the other, and thus some
number is produced”.
b) As a guiding idea in some proofs. For example, the proposition 31 of book
VII states: “Any composite number A is measured by some prime number”.
To prove this, he used the idea that a number is composed of units. Euclid
must have used this idea because he says the following: “For, if it is not
found, an infinite series of numbers will measure the number A, each of
which is less than the other: which is impossible in numbers”. He must have
thought that it is impossible to have an infinite series of numbers more and
smaller because numbers were constructed from certain elemental blocks, the
units.
c) As a bridge between numbers and magnitudes, as we will see in the current
chapter.
Euclid did not use those definitions in the rest of his arithmetic; rather, he changes his
strategy and analyses numbers by measuring one with the other.
My solution to this disparity is that the definitions of number and unit (Defs. 1
and 2, book VII) defined the entities that the rest of the arithmetical books discuss; that
is, the definitions of number and unit provide the ontology. In the rest of his arithmetic,
Euclid studied the structural relations of these entities between themselves by means of
representing these entities with the supposedly clearest analogous entities: the
91
magnitudes. This analysis explains why the first two definitions had a different status in
the advancement of proofs and conclusions.
With respect to the ontology expressed in the two first definitions, Reed (1995, p.
65) comments on the definition of unit: “A key point is the use of the phrase “is called”.
The definition of unit is verbal”. He continued, “a unit is that which results from a
particular way of regarding already defined things, namely regarding each of them as an
existing thing”. I believe, similarly to Reed, that the first definition indicated separation
or segregation of one thing from the rest, therefore making it individual.9 In this way,
the unit is a representation of one individualised object. As we described it in 3.1 and as
Plato has said, “each unit is equal to every other unit without the smallest difference and
contains within itself no parts”. (Plato, Republic, Book VII, Sect. 525d-526a).
Some modern interpreters have argued that the Platonic numbers are finite sets of
pure monads, and all equal each other. However, if “arithmos” is a count of pure
monads or of something that is the same, how can I count one and the same thing
several times? Frege (1884 to 1894) clearly saw this difficulty because he states that
monads are identical to each other, but when he counts them, they are different”.
Because of this and other problems, I think that Euclid’s first two definitions describe
arithmetic numbers not as sets of pure monads but as the result of counting various
things. The “arithmos” word means the account of a number of things, which conforms
to the definition of mathematical numbers in chapter 3 as the result of counting. What
counts are not pure monads because Euclidean unit definition refers to the empirical
things. He does this by saying that "everything that exists is called one". Euclidean
numbers are not, therefore, crowds of pure monads, whatever they are, but crowds
formed of things viewed only as existing things at the time that we count them.
9
Kitcher (1984, p. 108) adopts a similar view, taken from J.S. Mill: “arithmetic describes those
structural features of the world in virtue of which we are able to segregate and recombine
objects”.
92
Other than two first definitions, Euclid’s definitions, problems, and theorems are
given in terms of parts and measures. Euclid’s general strategy was to measure numbers
with each other to prove there are different number types, and then to describe the
syntactic relations among the types. In fact, many definitions and propositions, or their
proofs, include the word ‘measure’ (katametre); i.e., as Mueller (1981, p. 61) suggested,
“The fundamental undefined notion in Euclid’s arithmetic is the notion of
measurement”.
But how can we measure numbers? We can measure one thing with another
when one is an aliquot part, which is the case when the larger thing is equal to n-times
the smaller thing. However, we cannot measure them if the smaller thing does not fit
exactly n-times into the larger thing. In that case, the smaller thing is a non-aliquot part
of the larger thing, and Euclid says that the smaller is ‘parts’ of the larger.
Def. 3. A number is a part of a number, the less of the greater, when it measures
the greater;
Def. 4. But parts when it does not measure it.
Euclid’s point of view, as Reed (1995) says, implies that numbers are viewed as
magnitudes, since the things that are measured are seen as magnitudes. I argue, more
specifically, that the Euclidean numbers from the third definition are magnitudes, since
only the magnitudes can be measured, and following Euclid, only the magnitudes can be
exemplified with line segments. As we know, in this part of his arithmetic Euclid
represents the entities that he calls numbers, and even what he calls “unit” (proposition
1 of book VII) by means of line segments.
At this point, these entities are really magnitudes. In fact, Euclid similarly
represents magnitudes by means of line segments in book V, which is dedicated to
magnitudes in general. Nevertheless, the magnitudes of the arithmetical books are a
93
special class of magnitudes. Arithmetic numbers, described in the two first definitions,
"are not a special class of magnitudes", says Grattan-Guinness (1996, p. 370). But the
Euclidean meta-mathematical numbers, described in the books VII to IX with the
exception of the first two definitions, are a special class of magnitudes because Euclid
arbitrarily fixed one as the smallest of the magnitudes he considered, with the condition
that it could measure the other magnitudes. For this reason, Euclid has to prove similar
theorems in books V and VII-IX.
Even though numbers that are defined by means of the first two definitions are
very similar to these magnitudes, arithmetical numbers are not magnitudes; “Numbers
and magnitudes are distinct types of quantity” (Grattan-Guinness, 1996, p. 366). The
peculiarity of Euclidean arithmetical numbers is that every number is formed by
repetitions of the unit. Therefore, we can think of the unit as a basic block for making
any arithmetical number. In this way, the unit is not a number. On the contrary, there is
no basic block for making magnitudes. As Vega (1991, p. 86) says:
They do not say in any part of the Elements that numbers of VII-IX be a kind of
commensurable magnitudes… It seems that numbers are mathematical objects
relatively autonomous and independent from magnitudes of V-VI.
I suggest that the Euclidean arithmetical numbers defined in the two first
definitions are not magnitudes. However, Euclid studied these numbers, and the unit, by
means of certain magnitudes, which I call Euclidean meta-mathematical numbers.
The question, then, is how was it possible that Euclid selected these magnitudes
(which I call third-level numbers) to explain the structural relations of the arithmetical,
or second-level numbers? The answer, I suggest, is because the arithmetical numbers
have structural similarity with these magnitudes. As stated in Grattan-Guinness (1996,
pp. 362 and 370), “structural similarity between them is evident”.
In general, the magnitudes have two main structural qualities: a) each one is
different from any other only because the first is larger or smaller than the others, and b)
94
we can add a magnitude to another magnitude of the same kind (or to itself) and get a
bigger magnitude of the same kind.
The same can be said of arithmetical numbers and units, where one is bigger or
smaller than the other. Indeed, according to the second definition, numbers are made of
units, and each number is different only because it has more or fewer units: II ≠ III ≠
IIII.
On the other hand, we can add a number or a unit to another and get a bigger
number, even by adding several small numbers: II + II + I = IIIII. All numbers are
comprised of units. Here the second definition is used as a bridge between the numbers
defined in the first and second definitions and the magnitudes handled in the rest of the
Euclidean arithmetic.
The described magnitudes in the arithmetical books of Euclid, which I call meta-
mathematical, or third-level, numbers, can be seen as pictures of the arithmetical, or
second-level numbers. As we saw above, the Pythagoreans represented numbers by
means of pebble figures, which could have allowed them to study many properties of
numbers. The pebble figures ∴ and :: are not difficult to consider as explicative
paintings of some similarities and differences between the numbers 3 and 4. In the same
95
way, Euclid uses the line segments that represent determined magnitudes as explicative
figures of the numbers.
Netz (1999) emphasises the important role that diagrams play in Greek
mathematics. For the geometry of Euclid, Netz (1999, p. 19) shows that the diagrams
frame the reference such that, “there are assertions which are directly deduced from the
diagram”. However, as Netz (1999, p. 267) puts it, “it is clear that the relation between
diagram and object represented by the diagram is much less iconic in arithmetic than it
is in geometry”. In Euclidian arithmetic, segments of lines are treated as variables
because we do not know the concrete numbers they represent. All we can know is that
one is smaller than the other. In fact, “the only numerals found in the earliest and best
manuscripts of Euclid’s works… [are] the three numerals in Elements, Book XIII, 11”
(Fowler, 1999, 222). Consequently, we can deduce very little from the diagram.
Along this line of reasoning, Muller (1981, p.67) asserts that in proposition VII-
14, “One notes that the diagram plays no real role in this proof except possibly as a
mnemonic device for fixing the meaning of the letters”. The same could be said about
many other propositions in the arithmetic of Euclid’s, since the diagrams are
deductively superfluous. The result is that the relationship between the magnitudes and
line segments is less iconic in Euclid. I contend that managed magnitudes of books VII
to IX can be seen as paintings or diagrams of arithmetic numbers.
Finally, I would like to emphasise that Plato, in the Republic, was not in
agreement with the use of diagrams because they added ambiguity to the ontology of
mathematical entities, since it would seem that the mathematicians were speaking of the
specific diagrams they worked with. In contrast to Plato, as Netz (1999, p. 57) says
about their diagrams, “Greek mathematicians need not speak about their ontological
principles”. Greek mathematicians, according to Netz, decided to engage in
mathematical pursuits without considering ontological matters. This decision was, and
continues to be, advantageous to mathematical work.
96
However, in this essay, I am interested in ontology. Accordingly, I assert that
ontologically, the first two definitions describe the Euclid’s object of study and the
technical work is found in Euclid’s arithmetic beginning with the third definition.
Euclid studies arithmetical numbers, and he elaborates theorems about them in a dual
process by: a) representing them with other entities that are structurally similar, and b)
studying particular cases with diagrams that work like metaphors, applicable to general
and abstract cases (See Netz, 1999, p. 54).
According to Frege (1884), numbers are extensions of concepts such that each
number is the extension of one concept.10 Frege writes: “The number which applies to
the concept F is the extension of the concept ‘equinumerous with the concept F’”. For
example, the number 2 is tied to the concept that groups all pairs, and the number 3 is
tied to the concept that groups all trios, and so on.11
10
We can see this most widely in Ávila (1992b).
11
Before Frege, Mill (1974, cap. XI) argued that “Two, for instance, denotes all pairs of things”.
In our time, Bigelow (1988, p. 5) says that “The number three is instantiated by any three
97
According to Russell, numbers are classes of classes. As Russell affirmed in
Principia, which I analysed in detail (Avila, 1992b), his definition is equivalent to the
definition provided by Frege.
In order to prove that their definitions are correct, Frege and Russell define the
number 0, the number 1 as the successor of 0, and so on. Then, they show that 0 + 1 = 1,
and they describe other mathematical characters, including that extensions or classes
defined as numbers execute Peano’s axioms. By introducing the concept of cardinality,
Frege and Russell’s discoveries enable us to analyse the extra-mathematical use of
numbers. But what is the meaning of executing Peano’s axioms and the cardinality
condition?
Peano’s axioms say the number sequence is a system of elements that stand in a
certain relation to one another. In other words, the elements have certain syntactic
relations. The cardinality condition enables us to analyse that sequence in terms of
counting. But Benacerraf (1965) shows that there could be different groups of sets that
execute Peano’s axioms and the cardinality condition, and he concludes that numbers
are nothing but places in any recursive sequence.
From a philosophical point of view, to say that numbers are the extensions or
classes that group all pairs in one group, all trios in another group, and so on, links
numbers with the process of counting different things and of grouping things that have
similar results when they have been counted. This process of differentiation makes a re-
classification of the things in pairs, trios, and so on. The process is a reclassification
because concepts classify the world in horses, dogs, and so on, and once they are
distinct things”. I call the concept that groups all pairs, trios, and so on, numbers of first level
(Avila, 1989, and here 2.3).
98
grouped in a certain way, we can regroup the trios of horses or dogs in a new group, and
the pairs of horses or dogs in another group, and so on. Then, if we see numbers
associated with these re-classifications, we discover an ontology for numbers that is
perfectly clear, and it places numbers in the world of concepts. This process has an
abstract character, but it allows us to relate numbers to the empirical world. For these
reasons, the Fregean and Russellian proposal is very suggestive for philosophers, but it
has some problems that we will summarise below.
On the other hand, from a mathematical point of view, Steinhart (2002) affirms
that mathematicians ordinarily identify the natural numbers with the finite von
Neumann ordinals. This is so because the von Neumann w-series satisfies not only
Peano’s axioms and the cardinality condition as other w-series, but it is the only one
which is recursively defined, it is uniformly extendible to the transfinite, and satisfies
other mathematical conditions, which Steinhart enumerates. Notwithstanding, I think
that the von Neuman w-series have some problems too as we will see below.
In the first place, both the Fregean and von Neumann series seem very artificial
and forced. While we can sum two Euclidean arithmetical numbers so easily, when we
want to sum two Fregean numbers we must complete several complicated operations;
the same is true with the numbers of von Neumann.
With mathematical, or second-level numbers you only need to collect the result
of two accounts (both represented by the repetition of a symbol) and bring together both
results, or representations: ⎮⎮ + ⎮⎮⎮ = ⎮⎮⎮⎮⎮.
But in order to sum the class of all pairs with the class of all trios, we must
choose one element of the first class and another element of the second class, both of
which must execute certain conditions. Basically, both elements, which are really sets,
are disjoined and group elements of the same kind. Once we have selected one pair of
the first class and one trio of the second class, we do the same thing we did with the
Euclidean arithmetical numbers to obtain a new set that groups five element of the same
99
kind. Finally, we form a new class that combines all of the equinumerous sets with the
set of five elements. That class is the result of the sum.
As Benacerraf says, there is another reason to deny that numbers are really sets
after all: the work of Takeuti (1954), in which he shows that the Gödel-von Neumann-
Bernays set theory is reducible to the theory of ordinal numbers. In his paper, for
example, Takeuti defines ∈ in terms of <. The question is, which is really which?
The Takeuti’s work, among other examples, and the complexity of operations
with the Fregean or Russellian numbers and those of von Neumann, in spite of having
certain advantages, suggests that the arithmetical numbers are not these constructions
that have been made to explain the arithmetical numbers. We must admit the separate
existence of the arithmetic numbers on the one hand, and certain explanatory structures
on the other.
100
My proposal is that the arithmetic numbers are those to which Euclid refers with
his two first definitions in book VII and we described in 3.4. The arithmetic numbers
have been used in different cultures, and they have been explained with different
resources, resulting in the meta-mathematics numbers. For this cause, the meta-
mathematics numbers can be viewed as paintings of the arithmetic numbers.
101
102
Chapter 5
103
We resolved the confusion of approaches to the question, “what are the numbers?” at
the end of chapter 1. We intended to solve the second confusion regarding references of
the numerical terms in chapters 2, 3 and 4, which we summarise below.
We can see the relations between the first, second, and third level of the
Euclidean numbers as follows:
Magnitudes:
Reclassifications:
X ZZ UUU XXXX
0 JJ 000 TTTT
The idea in this picture is that the magnitudes of Euclid, represented with line
segments, can be seen as paintings of the mathematical numbers represented by the
repetition of identical marks, which are also visible as paintings of the reclassifications
in pairs, trios, quartets, and so on.
104
As we saw in chapter 3, arithmetic numbers are the abstract result of counting
objects. In other words, arithmetic numbers result from isolating certain objects,
removing all of their attributes, and keeping only groups of identical ghosts, each of
which represents a different object. These results are the natural numbers of the
arithmetic.
For better handling, these ghosts can be represented by identical marks, and
thus, we can more easily perform comparisons and operations between different
mathematical numbers, as well as find new mathematical numbers. We can easily see,
for example, that || + || = |||| or that ||| < |||||. Thus we can study structural relationships
of the numbers and forget what the marks represent. But when these marks are replaced
by other less explicit marks such as 7 or 9, we have to take into account that 7 = |||||||
and 9 = |||||||||.
Now, mathematicians can know that their operations are correct when they
prove the operations with the identical marks. But if we want to obtain empirical
certainty, we can return to repeatable acts that caused the mathematical numbers. For
example, if we do certain mental acts over some objects and we get |||, we repeat these
acts over others objects and we get |||||, and then we repeat a third time these acts on
other objects and we get |||, then we can compare the resulting marks and observe that
there were the same number of objects in the first and the third results.
On the other hand, reclassifications in units, pairs, trios, and so on, surely
emerged as a process arising from the original classification because they found a
family resemblance between three horses, three dogs, or three other things. These
reclassifications are linked directly with physical objects, and even with non-physical,
since they arise from a mental process that allows us to organise experiences in different
ways. Yet no matter what historical order in which numbers and reclassifications
emerged, my proposal is that we can see mathematical numbers as paintings of the
reclassifications. This is so because they have a large structural resemblance. Of course,
105
there are differences that we annotated in 2.3, but the similar structure enables us to
think that || is an idealised picture of the concept “pair”, under which fall things like ||,
xx, II, and OO.
Finally, the third level numbers, such as the magnitudes of Euclid symbolised
with line segments, can explain arithmetic numbers using other supposedly more basic
entities. However, this explanation is not the only possible explanation of the
arithmetical numbers. Indeed, we mentioned in subsection 4.2, other explanation
proposed by Frege and Russell, which we can see by mean of the following
representation:
ZZZZ
JJ JJJ
UUUU
Set of sets X X
X
II
0 TTT XXXX
VV
106
A full diagram would appear as follows:
xx Level
{{} {{}}} 3rd.
II
VV
|| 2nd.
pair
ZZ 1st.
JJ
We have said in this book that the meta-mathematical numbers have been built
from Euclid to explain some of the features of the mathematical numbers because this
last numbers became mysterious since they are abstract objects handled by means of
symbols. My proposal is that Euclid attempted to explain how mathematical numbers
can be combined to create other numbers, and that his explanation was to show that they
behave similarly to magnitudes in general. Frege, for his part, tried to explain how these
107
abstract objects are related to the things of the world. His explanation was to suggest
that numbers apply to the world by means of concepts.
In the previous diagram, you can see that mathematical numbers are unique. As
Frege said, there is only a 2. Therefore, 2 + 3 always have been ‘= 5’, even in different
cultures (see Urton, 1997, p. 7; and Verran, 2000, p. 356). Greiffenhagen and Sharrock
(2006, p. 113) say
However, different cultures assign very different ontology to the same numbers.
On the other hand, the "pair" concept is also unique because it has a precise
meaning. Although we could imagine concepts that group all pairs, where different
meanings grouped the same objects, what interests us is the extension of the concept
rather than its intention. Therefore, these different concepts would be only different
names to group the same objects. In the same way, we can have different symbols for
arithmetical numbers that would not alter their meaning or the operations we can do
108
with them. In short, in the second level, we have only one arithmetical number and only
one set of pairs.
109
The distinction also enables us to understand the emergence of efforts to explain the
mathematical numbers by means of other mathematical entities such as magnitudes and
sets.
I defined the actual mathematical numbers as abstract objects resulting from the
mental process of counting. I defined the arithmetic work as the systematisation of the
results of the counting process. Systematisation consists of symbolising results of the
counting process and the manipulation of these symbols once they are freed of their
origin. In these terms, the arithmetic of the natural numbers does not attempt to explain
a physical domain, as does the experimental sciences, but is the systematisation of one
mental operation.
12
This idea was taken from Ávila (1989 and 1992b).
110
Bibliography
Amor, J.A. (1981). “Prólogo” in Spanish edition of Hersh (1979) published by Facultad
de Ciencias, Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México.
Ávila, A. (1989). Las matemáticas y las Ciencias empíricas: ¿qué podrían ser los
números? Doctoral Dissertation, UNAM, México.
Ball, W.W. (1993). A short account of the history of mathematics (Fourth edition). Dover
Publication, Inc., New York.
Balzer, W., Moulines, C.U., and Sneed, J.D. (1987). An architectonic for science. D.
Reidel Publishing Company, Holland.
Baum, R. (ed) (1973). Philosophy and Mathematics: from Plato to the present,
Freeman, Cooper and Co., San Fancisco.
Benacerraf, P. (1965). “What numbers could not be” in Paul Benacerraf and Hilary
Putnam (eds.) Philosophy of Mathematics (1983). New York: Cambridge
University Press, pp. 272-294.
Berkeley, G. (1948-57). The works of George Berkeley Bishop of Cloyne. A. Luce and T.E.
Jessop (comp.). Thomas Nelson, Londres, vols. I-IX.
Buldt, B., Löwe, B. and Müller, Th. (2008). “Toward a new epistemology of
mathematics” Erkenntnis 68: 309-329.
Burkert, W. (1972). Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press.
Byers, W. (2007). How mathematicians think. Princeton: University Press.
Cajori, F. (1928-29). A history of mathematical notations. Dover Publication, Inc., New
York, 1993.
Carnap, R. (1961). Der Logische Aufbau der Welt. 2nd. Edition, Hamburg: Felix Meiner.
Cornman, J.W., Lehrer, K. and Pappas, G.S. (1992). Philosophical Problems and
Arguments: An introduction. Fourth edition, Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Co.
Courant, R. and Robbins, H. (1941). What is mathematics? Second edition, New York:
Oxford University Press, 1996.
Dedekind, R. (1893). “The nature and meaning of numbers” in Essays on the Theory of
Numbers (1963). Translated by W. W. Beman. New York: Dover Publications,
Inc.
Euclides (c-III, BC). The Thirteen Books of the Elements. Translated by Sir Thomas L.
Heath (1956). New York: Dover Publications.
112
Frege, G. (1884). Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Translated by Austin in The
Foundations of Arithmetic (1950). Oxford: Blackwell and Mott.
Gödel, K. (1949). “A remark about the relationship between relativity theory and
idealistic philosophy” in Albert Einstein, Philosopher-Scientist edited by Paul
Schipp, Evanston, Illinois: Library of Living Philosophers, pp. 555-562.
Hersh, R. (1997). What is mathematics, really? New York: Oxford University Press.
Kline, J. (1968). Greek mathematical thought and the origin of algebra. New York:
Dover.
Knorr, W.R. (1986). The Ancient Tradition of Geometric Problems. Boston: Birkhauser.
Knorr, W.R. (1975). The evolution of the Euclidean Elements. Boston: D. Reidel
Publishing Company.
Koffa, K. (1927). The growth of the mind: an introduction to child psychology. New
York: Harcourt, Brace & Company, Inc.
Köhler, W. (1947). Gestalt Psychology. New York: Leberirght.
Körner, S. (1967). “On the relevance of Post-Gödelian Mathematics to Philosophy”, in
Lakatos (1967), pp. 118-137.
Krantz D., Luce, D., Suppes, P. and Tversky, A. (1971). Foundations of Measurement.
New York: Academic Press.
Lakatos, I. (ed.) (1967). Problems in the philosophy of mathematics. Proceeding of the
International Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science. London 1965.
Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.
114
Lakatos, I. (1978). Mathematics, science and epistemology: Philosophical Papers, vol.
2, edited by J. Worrall and G. Currie. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lakoff, G. and Núñez, R.E. (2000). Where mathematics come from. USA: Basic Books.
Lorenzo, J. (1993). “La razón constructiva matemática y sus haceres”, Mathesis IX (2):
129-153.
Mach, E. (1885). Analysis of Sensations, and the relation of the Physical to the
Psychical. Translated by C.M. Williams. Edited by Sydney Waterlow.
115
Netz, R. (2002). “Counter culture: Towards a history of Greek numeracy.” Hist. Sci.,
xl.
Netz, R. (2004). Eudemus of Rhodes, Hippocrates of Chios and the Earliest form of a
Greek Mathematical Text. Centaurus 46: 243-286.
Neugebauer, O. (1957). The exact sciences in antiquity. USA, Providence: Brown
University Press.
Nicomachus of Gerasa (c-I, AC). Introduction to Arithmetic. Translated by M. L.
D’Ooge. London: Encyclopaedia Britannica (1952).
Platon (c-IV, BC). The Dialogues of Plato. 5 vols. Edited by B. Jowett. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Poincaré, H. (1908). Science et Méthode. Paris: Flammarion
Pólya, G. (1957). How to solve it? Second Edition, Princeton: Princeton University
press.
Proculs de Lycie (c-V, AC). Les commentaires sur le premier livre des Eléments
d’Euclide, Brujas (1948).
Pylyshyn, Z. (2007). Things and Places: how the mind connects with the world.
Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Quine, W.V. (1951). “Two dogmas of empiricism”, Philosophical Review 60 (1): 20-43.
Quine, W.V. (1981). Theories and Things. Harvard University Press.
116
Ramírez, S. (1989). El desconocido número 5. Doctoral Dissertation, FFyL-Universidad
Nacional Autónoma de México.
Ramírez, S. (1990). “El reencuentro del cosmos: filosofía del caos”, Mathesis, VI (4):
419-431.
Riedweg, Ch. (2002). Pythagoras: his life, teaching and influence. Translated by S.
Rendall. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2005.
Robles, J.A. (1993). Las ideas matemáticas de George Berkeley. México: UNAM.
Russell, B. (1914). Our Knowledge of the external world. Cornell University Library
Takeuti, G. (1954). Construction of the set theory from the theory of ordinal numbers.
Journal of the Mathematical Society of Japan 6: 196-220.
117
Thom, R. (1980). Parabole e Catastrofi: intrevista su matemática, science e filosofia.
Milano: Il Sagiatore.
Triplett, T. (1986). Relativism and the sociology of mathematics: Remarks on Bloor,
Flew, and Frege. Inquire 29 (4): 439-450.
Urton, G. (1997). The Social Life on Numbers. Austin: University of Texas Press.
Watts, A. (1957). The way of Zen. Panthom Books Inc. of Random House Inc. NY.
Willerding, M. (1967). Mathematical Concepts: A Historical Approach, Volumen Five.
Prindle, Weber & Schmidt Publishing.
118