(Athlone Contemporary European Thinkers) Nuno Nabais-Nietzsche and The Metaphysics of The Tragic-Continuum (2007) PDF
(Athlone Contemporary European Thinkers) Nuno Nabais-Nietzsche and The Metaphysics of The Tragic-Continuum (2007) PDF
(Athlone Contemporary European Thinkers) Nuno Nabais-Nietzsche and The Metaphysics of The Tragic-Continuum (2007) PDF
Nuno Nabais
Translated by Martin Earl
continuum
Contents
Translator's Preface
vii
Introduction
xi
1
37
65
85
99
133
Notes
159
Bibliography
185
Index
195
Translator's Preface
viii
Translator's Preface
Translator's Preface
ix
Translator's Preface
Introduction
xii
Introduction
opera. The result was disastrous. In the following semester not one student
enrolled in Nietzsche's course on Classical Philology at the University of
Basel. His book on tragedy and his philological territory expropriated by
the scholars and by Wagner, Nietzsche chose exile. In 1879, at the age of
thirty-five, he abandons the University to become an itinerant thinker,
wandering ceaselessly between Turin, Nice, Venice and the Engandine
region of Switzerland. The theme of tragedy disappears completely from
his texts, giving way to a new experience of silence, in which all trace of his
early work has completely vanished. In the books published between 1878
and 1882 it is as though Nietzsche had never written a single line on
Aeschylus and Sophocles.
This silence will only be tenuously interrupted in 1883. This occurs at
the end of The Gay Science. After the penultimate aphorism had for the first
time revealed the idea of the Eternal Recurrence in the form of a terrifying enigma that a devil has suddenly been placed before each of us,
obliging us to live each instant as though we wanted to return to relive it
an infinite number of times, the last aphorism issues forth with the title
"Incipit tragoedie."
What is proclaimed here is the arrival of the figure of Zarathustra, the
prophet of the idea of the Eternal Recurrence. Paradoxically, Thus Spoke
Zarathustra, published during the subsequent two years, once again keeps
silent about the subject of tragedy or the tragic. We know how Zarathustra's ascension, apogee and fall are constructed from beginning to end as
a repetition of the progress of Oedipus, the decipherer of enigmas and
destroyer of all gods. We know as well that his fundamental centre is in the
idea of the Eternal Recurrence, and that this idea is presented in the same
tragic tones, appealing to an absolute affirmation of each instant of existence, which we found in the descriptions of the Dionysian experience in
The Birth of Tragedy. Nevertheless, in order to embody the new evangelist in
this archaic prophet out of the East, Nietzsche must abandon the
Dionysiac/Socratic and the Hellenistic/Christian oppositions that had
framed his readings of tragedy. In spite of this, Thus Spoke Zarathustra will
forever remain Nietzsche's tragic testimony, the libretto for a new kind of
tragedy, which lets us hear in each word a new musical essence, that very
silence which Richard Strauss, Mahler, Schoenberg and so many others
would try to make real.
Thus Spoke Zarathustra reconciled Nietzsche with his reading of the tragedies. In 1886 he agreed to write an Attempt At Self-Criticism to be included
as a preface to a new edition of The Birth of Tragedy. In 1887, in the second
essay of The Genealogy of Morals he constructed a new phenomenology of
tragic guilt and, therefore, a new theory of tragedy as the representation of
cruelty between men offered up for the eyes of the gods. And in 1888, in
Ecce Homo - his nearly posthumous autobiography - he defines himself as
Introduction
xiii
the only tragic philosopher and The Birth of Tragedy as the first work of the
revaluation of all values, the first step beyond nihilism. Some weeks after
sending Ecce Homo to the editor, Nietzsche sank into delirium, or rather,
submitted himself definitively to silence. In the subsequent eleven years,
from the vantage of his total muteness, Nietzsche would see his youthful
reading of tragedy come to be discovered as the great aesthetic revolution
of modernity.
If there is a theory of the tragic in Nietzsche it is probably more present in
the texts that remain silent on the subject of tragedy than in those in
which Sophocles and Euripides are the subjects.
The chapters that follow dwell on that silence. Instead of reading what
Nietzsche wrote about the Dionysian, the music of the chorus, the metamorphoses of the hero, they try rather to trace the interior contours of his
interpretation of the tragic. The theory of tragedy is viewed in terms of the
Romantic tradition (of Kant, Schiller and Schopenhauer). It is also measured against the aesthetic debates of postmodernity that centre on the
significance of figures of the sublime and of the unrepresentable. This is
where the first chapter of this book, "Nietzsche's Place in the Aesthetics of
Postmodernity," situates itself. But it was also necessary to closely follow
the sixteen years of Nietzsche's theoretical work so as to root out the lines
of fracture and hesitation that would lead to a new understanding of that
immense absence of the tragic which follows the publication of The Birth of
Tragedy in 1872 and is only broken with Ecce Homo in 1888. The chapters
that traverse the stations of the Nietzschean theory of the tragic concentrate on the following:
The concepts of the individual and individuality.
The different figures of necessity and contingency.
The relation between Stoic ethics and the tragic maxim of Amorfati.
The place of the idea of the Eternal Recurrence in the evolution of
the Nietzschean oeuvre.
Each of these notions is developed haphazardly so as to better cleave to
the internal ruptures of Nietzsche's own thinking. But they take in five
moments, which can be schematized in the following fashion: (a) before
Schopenhauer; (b) following the reading of The World as Will and Representation; (c) the break with Schopenhauer and commitment to the
Renaissance programme of natural sciences; (d) works marked by the
inspiration of the Eternal Recurrence; and (e) theory of the will to power
and the diagnosis of the decadence of European culture and the resulting
nihilism.
xiv
Introduction
Postmodernity
' Here, when the danger to his will is greatest, art approaches as a saving
sorceress, expert at healing. She alone knows how to turn these nauseous thoughts about the horror or absurdity of existence into notions
with which one can live: these are the sublime as the artistic taming of the
horrible, and the comic as the artistic discharge of the nausea of
absurdity."
The Birth of Tragedy1
constraint, alike in the physical and in the moral sphere."12 This "third
kingdom" of the human condition, this Utopia in which humanity is liberated by art, is constructed through aesthetic education, and via the
reconstitution of a sensus communis, which, because it is not conceptual,
can be neither theoretical nor practical, but is rather realized in the
shared character of the judgment of taste as it operates before each work
of art.13 Kant and Schiller had perceived that the normative character of
any Utopia derives from an aesthetic faculty, and that it was therefore
important to cultivate the faculty of taste in each citizen in a programme
of scientific and ethical emancipation.
In The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, Habermas showed us to what
extent this programme of linking political Utopia to aesthetic education,
as a project for overcoming the antinomies of modern reason, persisted as
a point of orientation throughout the whole of romanticism, continuing
to exert influence even over Lukacs, Marcuse, and Hannah Arendt. What
is more: out of Schiller's Letters - which he defines as the "the first programmatic work toward an aesthetic critique of modernity"14 - Habermas
formulates a basis for the recuperation of the promises of rational
emancipation inherited from the Enlightenment, those promises that had
been stripped of their regulating power by the critique of metaphysical
presuppositions (or of metaphysical destiny) of modern rationalism,
especially in the work of Nietzsche and Heidegger and, most recently, in
those thinkers, such as Adorno, Derrida, Foucault and Lyotard, who
recognize themselves in the founding experience of modernity: precisely
in this critical corrosion of the metaphysical.
Habermas transforms Kant and Schiller into a bulwark against this
aesthetic shattering of the pretensions of the universal validity of value
judgments initiated by Nietzsche. The "metaphysics of artists" from The
Birth of Tragedy, and its recent prolongations in the works of Derrida and
Lyotard, signify, for Habermas, nothing less than the return to politically
conservative positions. In the famous 1980 lecture "Modernity : an
Unfinished Project?" Habermas considers that the spirit of Nietzsche, as it
was rediscovered in the 70s, is the inspiration behind political neoconservatism in Europe. As he says:
The Young Conservatives essentially appropriate the fundamental
experience of aesthetic modernity, namely the revelation of a decentered subjectivity liberated from all the constraints of cognition and
purposive action, from all the imperatives of labor and use value, and
with this they break out of the modern world altogether. They establish
an implacable opposition to modernism precisely through a modernist
attitude. They locate the spontaneous forces of imagination and selfexperience, of affective life in general, in what is most distant and
such they misrepresent the terms of the controversy over the sublime.
Because they read the "Analytic of the Sublime" from a Nietzschean
perspective - which is never made explicit - they are able to undermine
the Kantian fortress from the inside. Against Habermas, against his appeal
for the renovation of the promises of an ideal community of communication inscribed in the Kantian idea of objective aesthetic reason, Lyotard excludes the Critique of Judgment, separates it from Habermas's antiNietzschean reading. But this reading is, in turn, built upon an unspoken
assumption. It is never clarified to what extent this "Nietzschean" reading
of the Critique of Judgment is nothing more than a returning to Kant of that
which for a long time had been attributed to Nietzsche. What is dodged is
the very recognition that the Kantian sublime can only be subjected to a
postmodern interpretation because the actual postmodern models - with
their Nietzschean roots - are nothing more than a peculiar elaboration of
the theory of the sublime in the Critique of Judgment. It is by ignoring the
fact that the figures of the Dionysian are a metamorphosis of the Kantian
figures of the sublime that Lyotard can believe that he has discovered in
Kant a ratification that anticipates the aesthetic of the unrepresentable
that would come to define postmodernity.
An analysis of the category of the sublime in the aesthetic of The Birth of
Tragedy has never been written.22 What is more, there has been no attempt
to reconstruct the various metamorphoses of the Kantian sublime up to
the point of its application by Nietzsche in his interpretation of the Greek
tragedy as a musical drama. And this vacuum is more than just another of
those inevitable lacunas in philosophical historiography. The absence of a
description of the Nietzschean origins of the postmodern reading of the
Kantian sublime is so paradoxical that it might even be seen as symptomatic of something else: it shows us to what extent this real permutation of
the Nietzscheans into Kantians, or the permutation of the Dionysian aesthetic into the sublime, is predicated upon the fact that no one has yet
contemplated the tradition of the sublime itself in The Birth of Tragedy?* In
fact, this must be one of the more curious phenomena in the narrative of
postmodern discourse. It is as though a repressed Kantianism has
returned to disrupt the arrogance of the Nietzschean aesthetic - for too
long secure in its usurpation of the whole tradition of the philosophy of
art inaugurated by Kant and prolonged by Romanticism.
This leads us to another paradox. If it is the Nietzscheans who discovered the site of explication for a postmodern aesthetic in the Kantian
theory of the sublime, how should we treat the fact that this same theory of
the sublime is not used to read the programme of aesthetic dismissal of
the modern figures of rationality which orient the work of Nietzsche and
in this way clarify to what extent aesthetic Nietzscheanism is nothing more
than a detour or an escape hatch from the programme proposed by the
10
11
12
metaphysical and aesthetic axioms for the first time in Wagner's 1870 text,
Beethoven. This description of the sublime in the Nietzschean metaphysic
of the tragic will have to venture in that direction as well.
To understand some of the aesthetic plots in the debate between
Habermas and Lyotard we must return to that moment of transition
between Kant and Nietzsche, or better, to the transformation of the aesthetic theory of the Critique of Judgment into the metaphysical premises of
The Birth of Tragedy. Which is to say, we have to return to Schopenhauer, to
examine exactly how his aesthetic of pessimism developed out of his
metaphysical interpretation of the Kantian sublime. Unfortunately, there
is still much work to be done in this area. Because the Schopenhauerean
interpretation of the sublime, in spite of being central to his philosophy,
maintains a nearly secret status within the group of his works that treat the
aesthetic, it has been invariably forgotten. That is why we must take a
closer look at Schopenhauer.
13
14
15
mark of the universal disappears into each aesthetic feeling, while the
aesthetic itself recoils within feeling.
Schopenhauer's aesthetic is an ontology of the work of art and an
anthropology of feeling. Because of this, the determination of the sublime
and the beautiful addresses in the first instance the structure of the
respective objects and only later the forms of affection. It is certain, for
example in the sublime, that the feeling of transport is only produced
when the individual is raised to the condition of pure subject which is able
to abstract itself from the hostility directed at his own body by the object.
Yet the condition for the possibility of feeling this emotion occurs in the
object. There are immanent aesthetic characteristics in the sublime object;
it is these that demand a change in the observer: that is, he must abstract
himself from precisely this empirical relationship to hostility. Yet, even this
abstraction, which leads to the annulment of one's will, bursts forth from
the object. Its terrifying character annuls individual will, which in turn
transports the viewer, transforming him into one who contemplates nature, serenely yet ecstatically.
This reification of the aesthetic is riddled with paradoxes. The first one
has to do with the ontological condition of the aesthetic determinations of
objects. Because Schopenhauer retains the distinction between phenomenon and thing-in-itself, the effects themselves of the object upon the subject
of representation must be thought of as mere appearances, without any
footing whatsoever in the truth of the world. The harmonious or terrifying
aspects which forms display to the eye of the observer exist only in his own
angst; they are simply a means for affecting himself as condition of the
possibility for representation. In the contemplation of a storm or of some
terrifying situation of chaos, when I am crushed beneath that overwhelming sense of my form's corporal fragility, I am at once raised to a
level from whence the discovery of the illusion of this experience becomes
possible: the threatening object is nothing more than mere fiction constructed out of the pure forms of sensibility, and I am revealed to myself in
my condition of illusion, as a phenomenon of will, an ephemeral and
occasional manifestation of a will that exists beyond space and time and
that, for some unfathomable metaphysical reason expresses itself by
shattering itself within individuals in space and time, that is, in individuals
endowed with a body and a discrete will that manages to exist by maintaining this illusion of being real, of being a thing-in-itself.
For Schopenhauer, the characteristic ambivalence of the feeling of the
sublime - at once terrifying and transporting - results precisely in this
paradox of a representation that, the more real it appears, the more
strongly it reveals its condition as a mere appearance. It is precisely at that
very moment in which I feel crushed by the grandeur of that which I
contemplate, in the moment that I find myself reduced to a state of
16
absolute fragility and insignificance, that the only meaning I can give to
this annulment of self is that of a mere illusion. If I am nothing, then
everything I produce in my activity of representing is also nothing, and
that very same object that reveals to me my condition of being nothing can
also not be otherwise than nothing, just the dream of the dreamer, but of a
dreamer who, nevertheless, only exists in a dream. It is the peak of this
experience of fragility that the sense of expansion, or that relief of one
who has woken from an anguishing dream, is produced. "The feeling of
the sublime arises here through our being aware of the vanishing nothingness of our own body in the presence of a greatness which itself, on the
other hand, resides only in our representation, and of which we, as
knowing subject, are the supporter. Therefore, here as everywhere, it
arises through the contrast between the insignificance and dependence of
ourselves as individuals, as phenomena of will, and the consciousness of
ourselves as pure subject of knowing."31
3. The aesthetic and theory of knowledge
We must always bear in mind that the subjectivist realism of Schopenhauer's aesthetic - which will be decisive in The Birth of Tragedy - is the
result of a double transformation of critical philosophy. The first has to do
with the theory of knowledge, the second with the theory of will. We know
Kant plays a paradigmatic role in the Schopenhauerean exposition of the
nature of knowledge. The concepts of "representation" and of "will" (the
world's two modes of existence) are an exact tracing of the distinction
between "phenomenon" and "thing-in-itself'. Throughout the four
books of The World as Will and Representation, Schopenhauer's various
theses are built upon the foundation of this duality, whether they are
about the nature of sensibility, the structure of the color spectrum, the
reality or visual qualities of the objects of experience, or about the types of
figurative art, or even about the possible basis of a non-imperative morality. It is primarily this duality ("representation"/"will") that leads
Schopenhauer to his most important break with Kant the rejection of the
Kantian triad of the faculties. Instead of the distinction between intuition/
understanding and reason, Schopenhauer propounds the intuition/
understanding duality. Intuition is always intellectual, that is, it is always an
expression of understanding. To know is to apprehend matter beyond the
forms of space and time. Matter, while perennial activity and nothing
more than activity, manifests itself as causality whose subjective correlative
is the principle of sufficient reason, which is only apprehensible via
understanding. All intuition thus presupposes the participation of sensibility and understanding. Thus all intuition is intellectual intuition.82
This intellectuality of the intuition will lead Schopenhauer to transform
17
18
sees the mechanism itself for the annulment of individual will. When faced
with a beautiful form, I suspend my relation, based in motivation, to the
world of representation, suspending my will and elevating myself to the
condition of pure and disinterested subject. That which I contemplate is
no longer the unique and beautiful object, but the idea, of which the
object is the phenomenon.36 The experience of beauty is a cognitive
experience, not of the empirical object that offers itself to me in its harmonious forms, but of the Idea that this object exemplifies.
There are therefore two modes of fusion between the knowledge and
the experience of beauty. Beauty is a determination of the empirical
object; it is a property of its forms as they offer themselves up in time,
space, and causality. In the experience of the beautiful I know something
of the object, I know its beauty. It is that beauty which, a moment later, will
liberate me from my individuated will, that will annul the interested
condition of my knowledge and elevate me to the condition of pure
subject, subject of the disinterested contemplation of beautiful forms.
What is then revealed is no longer the beautiful empirical object, but the
intelligible idea that it expresses. In both experiences art is the real point
of entry into the sphere of knowledge: knowledge of empirical beauty,
knowledge of the Idea through empirical beauty.
This process is repeated in the experience of the sublime. In the sublime I am also elevated to the intuitive contemplation of Ideas, freed from
my relation to and motivation vis-a-vis the objects of representation. The
difference between the beautiful and the sublime resides in the process of
transition between the sphere of representation to that of Ideas. As
Schopenhauer wrote:
Thus what distinguishes the feeling of the sublime from that of the
beautiful is that, with the beautiful, pure knowledge has gained the
upper hand without a struggle, since the beauty of the object, in other
words that quality of it which facilitates knowledge of its Idea, has
removed from consciousness, without resistance and hence imperceptibly, the will and knowledge or relations that slavishly serve the will.
What is then left is pure subject of knowing, and not even a recollection
of the will remains. On the other hand, with the sublime, that state of
pure knowing is obtained first of all by a conscious and violent tearing
away from the relations of the same object to the will which are recognized as unfavourable, by a free exaltation, accompanied by consciousness, beyond the will and the knowledge related to it.37
19
20
certainly produces a change in the point of view, but only within the
sphere of knowledge:
If we lose ourselves in contemplation of the infinite greatness of the
universe in space and time, meditate on the past millennia and on those
to come; or if the heavens at night actually bring innumerable worlds
before our eyes, and so impress on our consciousness the immensity of
the universe, we feel ourselves reduced to nothing; we feel ourselves as
individuals, as living bodies, as transient phenomena of will, like drops
in the ocean, dwindling and dissolving into nothing. But against such a
ghost of our own nothingness, against such a lying impossibility, there
arises the immediate consciousness that all these worlds exist only in our
representation, only as modifications of the eternal subject of pure
knowing. This we find ourselves to be, as soon as we forget individuality;
it is the necessary, conditional supporter of all worlds and of all periods
of time.39
Schopenhauer repeats Kant's description of a tension brought on by a
greatness which, seeming to fill us entirely, attracts us and, at the same
time, because it is formally endless, unsuited and inappropriate to our own
faculty of representation, ends up by repelling us. But in Kant, the
immeasurability of the sublime calls for a certain measure to be taken, an
experience of respect for the immeasurable, that immeasurable which is
none other than the Idea of practical reason. Because of this, Kant
sometimes transforms the sentiment of the sublime into an exclusively
moral experience.40 In Schopenhauer the sublime does not heighten, it
only annuls - it annihilates aesthetic consciousness. The thesis that all
forms in space and time are illusory inevitably leads to the discovery of the
unreality of the colossal as well, namely that the sublime object itself is an
illusion. Kant's notion that the senses are of no importance in the
experience of the sublime (which he sees as a negative pleasure that
suspends the game of the imagination and imposes the seriousness
attributed to moral law, thereby confirming the essential relationship
between morality and the violence done to the senses) is precisely that
which in The World as Witt and Representation leads from knowledge of the
sphere of representation to knowledge of the sphere of the Idea. Nevertheless, the abyss of representation, the scuttling of the forms of the
sensibility, does not lead to the sphere of the supra-sensible. The sublime
leads to insensibility before the colossal, before the infinitely large and
terrifying. For Schopenhauer the sublime is more than an opposition to
the senses: it is the only experience that totally frees the subject from the
prison of sensibility. The experience of the aesthetic, as a process, is thus
21
an anaesthetic experience, it uses the senses against the senses and in this
way opens the consciousness to a metaphysical experience.
5. The truth of the sublime
Although Schopenhauer declares that the beautiful and the sublime are
both ways to reach the sphere of Ideas - in the beautiful via the intensification and later suspension of pleasure in the object, in the sublime via
the immediate suspension of interest before the hostility of the object examples of the experience of the sublime reveal a fundamental difference. The sentiment of the beautiful never exceeds the sphere of Ideas. It
raises itself out of individual beautiful forms to a form of intelligible
beauty of which they are the manifestation in space and time. In the
sentiment of the sublime, which, by definition, "is an exaltation beyond
our own individuality [Erhebung uber das eigene Individuum], a feeling of the
sublime"41 the violent annulment of my individuality is also an annulment
of my finitude and, therefore, the metaphysical conversion of my gaze. I
find myself essentially merged with the world. In the sublime I attain the
knowledge of the Vedas, the feeling that "we are one with the world, and
therefore not oppressed but exalted by its intensity."42 In other words, in
the sublime what is given are not Ideas - objectifications of the will - but
the will itself, one and eternal. In the contemplation of a colossal object I
am plucked from the empirical world in order to attain the world as thingin-itself. Yet, what kind of knowledge could correspond to an experience
which does not belong to the world of representation, does not take as its
goal the intelligible world of Ideas?
In chapter 39 of the 1819 edition - dedicated completely to the idea of
the sublime - Schopenhauer does not respond to this question. Here the
sublime seems only to have an effect through privation, that is, it simply
excludes the reality of something that occurs through representation. This
is the value that is emphasized precisely at that moment in which Schopenhauer expels mere pleasure for the form of an empirical object from
the aesthetic field. When he wants to distinguish the pure aesthetic
experience (which frees the subject of his motivational relations with the
world of representation) from the trivial aesthetic experience, or rather,
that experience of immediate pleasure that, on the contrary, binds the
subject of experience more intensely to empirical stimuli and so makes his
illusory condition even worse, Schopenhauer does not use the beautiful as
an example, but rather the sentiment of the sublime. It is the sublime that
becomes the counterpoint to the "pretty" (das Reizende). "The feeling of
the sublime arose from the fact that something positively unfavourable to
the will becomes object of pure contemplation. This contemplation is
then maintained only by a constant turning away from the will and
22
exaltation [Erhebung] above its interests. ... On the other hand, the
charming or attractive draws the beholder down from pure contemplation, demanded by every apprehension of the pretty, since it necessarily
stirs his will by objects that directly appeal to it."43 In the experience of the
infinitely great or threatening the aesthetic pleasure is pure, entirely disinterested, because in this experience the object is "unrealized," as it
were, as its representation is reduced to illusions. If the beautiful frees me
as well from representation because it absorbs my vision in Ideas, these still
maintain the marks of the empirical forms for which they are the Platonic
model. There is both a metaphysical and an aesthesic continuity between
the unique beautiful object and the universality of the Idea that it, the
object, expresses as its phenomenon in space and time. Because the
beauty of the object touches me, in my vision of it I separate it from its
function, that which in it might satisfy some project of my will, in order to
preserve it alone in its metaphysical condition of an appearance, the
apparition of something else, the manifestation of an Idea. In the sublime
this transition has no continuity. There is an abrupt severing in the sphere
of representation (I move from the representable to that which refuses
figuration) and a complete inversion in the motivational sphere (what is
terrifying, hostile, repugnant, transforms itself into a sentiment of pleasure as a species of abstracted contemplation of an illusion that seems to
exist for my own eyes alone). Unrepresentable and attractive, but without
being an attraction by the unrepresentable - that is the mystery of the
sublime within Schopenhauer's system of pessimism. And this is what
distances it from the Kantian theory of the sublime. Because it is atheological and because it refuses the imperative model of morality, the sublime in Schopenhauer leads only to an experience of undefined
unrepresentability, since it neither refers to the invisibility of a god, nor
does it want for foundational experiences of respect for invisibility, or for
the unrepresentability of the law. Pessimism lacks a metaphysic of the
sublime, parallel to the metaphysic of beauty; it lacks a doctrine that
establishes the nature of the objects which correspond to the experience
of pure contemplation, i.e. which are revealed through the collapse of the
individual will, that which is produced from the annihilation of the reality
of the grandiose, or colossal reality, given in representation.
In the 1819 edition the silence about the metaphysical correlative of the
sentiment of the sublime left open the way for two theses central to
Schopenhauer's aesthetics. They would only come to be articulated in the
1844 edition and would play a decisive role in the metaphysics of the tragic
in The Birth of Tragedy. They are: (a) the privileged place of tragedy in the
hierarchy of those works of art which occur in the sphere of representation; and (b) the value of the truth of music.
23
24
effects the work of art has on the spectator is an exact repetition of the
definition of the experience of the sublime:
Here and there it reaches thoughtfulness and is softened more or less by
the light of knowledge, until at last in the individual case this knowledge
is purified and enhanced by suffering itself. It then reaches the point
where the phenomenon, the veil of Maya, no longer deceives it. It sees
through the form of the phenomenon, the principium individuationis;
the egoism resting on this expires with it. The motives that were previously so powerful now lose their force, and instead of them, the
complete knowledge or the real nature of the world, acting as a quieter of
the will, produces resignation, the giving up not merely of life, but of
the whole will-to-live itself.47
Everything seems to lead Schopenhauer to the thesis of the tragic condition of the sublime or of the sublime condition of the emotion which is
produced in the contemplation of the tragedy. But this thesis will only
come to be formulated in 1844 when Schopenhauer adds a new volume of
supplements to The World as Will and Representation. In chapter 37 of these
Supplements, which is entitled "Aesthetics of Poetry," the tragic drama is
recognized as expressly belonging to, not the aesthetic of the beautiful,
but to the sublime.
Our pleasure in the tragedy belongs not to the feeling of the beautiful,
but to that of the sublime; it is, in fact, the highest degree of this feeling.
For, just as at the sight of the sublime in nature we turn away from the
interest of the will, in order to behave in a purely perceptive way, so in
the tragic catastrophe we turn away from the will-to-live itself. Thus in
the tragedy the terrible side of life is presented to us, the wailing and
lamentation of mankind, the dominion of chance and terror, the fall of
the righteous, the triumph of the wicked; and so that aspect of the world
is brought before our eyes which directly opposes our will. At this sight
we feel ourselves urged to turn our will away from life, to give up willing
and loving life.48
In the 1819 edition, the only examples of the sublime are natural phenomena of frightening grandiosity and violence, colossal examples of
architecture and the ethical sublime of character (which is illustrated by
the tragic personage). By this time the whole of tragedy as work of art has
been given a privileged status in the aesthetic of the sublime. Artistic
representation of the essence itself of the world, of the unjust condition of
existence conditioned, as it is, by the will to live, tragedy is the materialization itself of the infinite power of its unrepresentability.49 This tie
25
between tragedy and the experience of the sublime will lead Schopenhauer to make a positive determination of the validity of the truth of
this experience. In fact, returning to the doctrine in the Critique of Judgment, he will see the sublime as based on the idea of negative representation.
Tragedy sets two experiences of the sublime in motion. The first is when
the spectator, at the pinnacle of that terror which crushes him in his
identification with the misfortune of the tragic hero, discovers that
everything is nothing more than a representation, that is, dramatic illusion, and because of this he suspends his interest in the destiny of the
characters, raising himself to the serenity of a pure contemplative subject
of the work of art. "At the moment of the tragic catastrophe, we become
convinced more clearly than ever that life is a bad dream from which we
have to awake. To this extent, the effect of the tragedy is analogous to that
of the dynamically sublime, since, like this, it raises us above the will and its
interest, and puts us in such a mood that we find pleasure in the sight of
what directly opposes the will."50 The second experience of the sublime is
like a transference of the first experience from the sphere of the stage to
existence in its entirety. The spectator suddenly sees himself as though he
were a mere figure in a tragic play, since tragedy is nothing more than the
figuration on stage of the cruel and illusory essence of existence.51 The
metaphor of theatre, which oriented Schopenhauer's work right from the
beginning with its duality between the world as will and the world as
representation, finds its most perfect expression in tragedy.52
26
27
And the world of the in-itself occurs as non-gift, as a negative gift, as a gift
of that which cannot possibly be given, therefore as the gift of a non-gift.54
8. Music
What is important now is to ask a retrospective question about the metaphysics of the sublime that organized the 1819 edition. As we have indicated, (a) there is a lack therein of an actual characterization of the
metaphysical condition of the sublime - frequently muddled together with
the experience of the beautiful by being seen as also having the world of
Ideas as its object - and (b) tragedy is never expressly incorporated within
the aesthetic of the sublime. Between these two phenomena there is a
rigorous parallel. The aesthetic of the sublime already points toward the
unrepresentable, without this unrepresentable ever having been determined: likewise, tragedy is placed at the highest end of the hierarchy of
the arts of figuration (those arts that produce or induce spatio-temporal
images), which already signals a transition to a world beyond sensibility.
These two points of suspension (the fact that the sublime presupposes the
unrepresentable and the fact that tragedy is held in suspension between
the figurative arts and the non-figurative) are present in chapter 51 of the
1819 edition. They encompass the figurative goal of art and its vocation for
the intuition of Ideas via material forms. Chapter 52 completely shifts this
particular analysis of art. It begins with the almost solemn declaration:
We have now considered all of the fine arts in the general way suitable to
our point of view. We began with architecture, whose aim as such is to
elucidate the objectification of the will at the lowest grade of its visibility,
where it shows itself as the dumb striving of the mass, devoid of
knowledge and conforming to law; yet it already reveals discord with
itself and conflict, namely that between gravity and rigidity. Our
observations ended with tragedy, which presents to us in terrible magnitude and distinctness at the highest grade of the will's objectification
that very conflict of the will with itself. After this, we find that there is yet
another fine art that remains excluded, and was bound to be excluded,
from our consideration, for in the systematic connexion of our discussion there was no fitting place for it; this art is music. It stands quite apart
from all the others. In it we do not recognize the copy, the repetition, of
any Idea of the inner nature of the world. Yet it is such a great and
exceedingly fine art, its effect on man's innermost nature is so powerful,
and it is so completely and profoundly understood by him in his
innermost being as an entirely universal language, whose distinctness
surpasses even that of the world of perception itself.. ,55
28
The passage from chapter 51 to 52, or rather that which remains in suspension in the earlier and which in the latter is brought to completion,
reveals a central ambiguity in the Schopenhauerean theory of art. In
chapter 51 the analysis of the sublime speaks of the representation, not of
ideas, but of something else from the dominion of the non-representable,
that non-representable which is evoked various times as the world itself,
beyond both the empirical and intelligible objectifications of it. In chapter
52 this non-representable is paradoxically seen as representable: and
music is that representation. What's more: Schopenhauer knows that by
modulating his notions in such a way he is formulating a thesis that he
cannot justify. "I recognize, however, that it is essentially impossible to
demonstrate this explanation, for it assumes and establishes a relation of
music as a representation to that which of its essence can never be a
representation, and claims to regard music as the copy of an original that
can itself never be directly represented/'56 Music then, as a copy of an
inexistence, furnishes a solution for the mystery of the sublime. What is
essentially of the order of the unrepresentable becomes representation.
But what could represent a representation of that which can never be the
object of a representation? Will it still be representation? Might not
Schopenhauer, in order to avoid the paradox of a copy without a model,
have removed music from the condition of mimesis to which he attributes
all forms of art? It is the double orientation - metaphysical and anthropological - of Schopenhauer's theory of art which makes it impossible to
think of music as the pure presentation of itself alone, absorbing into its
manifestation that model which it lacks. But, at the same time, it is exactly
this orientation which makes of music the material correlative of the
experience of the unrepresentable which occurs in the sublime. The sublime is that which opens sentiment to something beyond representation,
and beyond Ideas, that is, to the abyss of the world's will as thing-in-itself.
Negative representation, representation of that which in representation is
denied - our gaze swallowed by the abyss that annuls the whole of the
visible and toward which negative representation caused it to turn. The
world is, in essence, the unrepresentable. But this overwhelming of the
visible produces in turn a metaphysical revelation, a conversion of
knowledge into pure contemplation, a conversion of vision into listening,
in a word, the conversion of negative representation that defines the
experience of the sublime into representation without an object which defines
the work of musical art.57
Neither in the edition of 1819, nor in that of 1844, do we find any link
between the metaphysic of music and the aesthetic of the sublime. Music is
never expressly presented in its condition as perceivable resonance of the
unrepresentability established by the negative representation of the sublime experience. However, it is this music/sublime dyad which lies
29
concealed, as it were, at the centre of The World as Will and Representation and it is in the form of the music/tragedy/sublime triad that this work will be
transformed by Nietzsche into the programme for a renaissance of the
tragedy through the opera of Wagner. And it will be Nietzsche who will
attempt to create a unified vision of these three faces of the aesthetic of
pessimism, to test the invisibility of music through a unified theory of
artistic creation, the terrifying grandiosity of tragedy and the transfiguration of the subject of contemplation which is exclusive to the sublime. But
this unity which Nietzsche will call the "dionysian experience" depended
directly on Wagner. It was Wagner who gave substance to the thesis that
the metaphysical uniqueness of music, that which distinguishes it from all
of the other forms of art, was the result of its own aesthetic regime, or
rather, the fact that it alone belongs to the sphere of the sublime, while all
other arts should be understood through the category of the beautiful
9. Music and the sublime in Wagner
We know that Wagner offers the best path towards reconstructing precisely
how Nietzsche's aesthetic theory is derived from Schopenhauer's metaphysics. However, this path is far from being transparent. On the one
hand, we do not know to what extent the aesthetic of pessimism really
influenced Wagner's production.58 On the other, it is also difficult to
determine from which moment Nietzsche himself began to furnish
Wagner with certain of his own theoretical intuitions, intuitions which
were later incorporated into The Birth of Tragedy, as though they had been
inspired by the experience of Wagnerian opera.59
It is in the context of this mdetermination that we must read the only
text in which Wagner formulated the thesis which contained in latent
form the whole of Schopenhauer's aesthetic - that is, the thesis of the
sublime character of music. We refer to his essay Beethoven, written in 1870
to commemorate the centenary of the birth of the composer. This is the
only place in all of Wagner's writings where we find an elaboration of a
doctrine of the sublime, formulated here in the attempt to discover the
essence of Beethoven's instrumental music and through it the essence of
all music. After Beethoven, Wagner would never again defend the correlation between music and the sublime. And, what is more significant, the
doctrine of the sublime is not only constructed according to Schopenhauer's principles, but it also anticipates the articulation between
tragedy (as musical drama) and the Dionysian aesthetic (as an aesthetic of
rhythmic and melodic dissonance) which Nietzsche would elaborate a year
later. Wagner's Beethoven functions as a true bridge between Schopenhauer and Nietzsche. At the same time, it is surprising that in The Birth
of Tragedy this doctrine on the sublime condition of music, even though it
30
serves to organize the whole reading of the Dionysian/Apollonian opposition, only appears obliquely. It is as though Wagner, having appropriated
the interpretation of the theory of the sublime, which structured the
Nietzschean reading of the universe of classical tragedy, had forced
Nietzsche into silence about his own intuitions. In fact, we can imagine
that, recognizing Wagner's expropriation in Beethoven of his theses on the
link between music and the sublime, Nietzsche did not take them up again
explicitly in order to avoid raising the question of precedence. This would
explain why the central theses of The Birth of Tragedy on Greek culture did
not appear to repeat Wagner's aesthetic positions; Nietzsche may have
preferred to exclude the explicit formulation of his theory of the sublime
and, as such, condemned his reading of classic tragedy to theoretical
stillbirth. What is more, no other text by Wagner after Beethoven repeats
the thesis on the sublime in music. One might be led to speculate that
Wagner, conscious of his appropriation of the positions of this young
professor of classical philology from Basel, was anxious to erase forever the
marks of his "crime." Of course, these questions outstrip the bounds of
the present work. Nevertheless, they do tend to hover around any parallel
reading of Beethoven and The Birth of Tragedy.
In Beethoven the thesis on the sublime condition of music responds to a
very particular aesthetic problem: the determination of the metaphysical
nature of the "musical drama." Wagner wants to establish an objective
basis for joining music with other art forms (poetry, set design, the dance,
and the art of acting) in a single and "total" work of art. The plurality of
materials and languages which converge in the realization of each opera
cannot be the result simply of mechanisms of juxtaposition. They must
occur as a real organic unity, one which is indissoluble. Only in this way
can they provoke a single affect in the spectator. Wagner found his solution in Schopenhauer's interpretation of Kant's establishment of the difference between the beautiful and the sublime in the Critique of Judgment
Music ... can be judged, as far as it is properly concerned, only after the
category of the Sublime, for, as soon as it touches us, we are filled with
the highest ecstasy of the consciousness of illimitability. That which
results from our being absorbed by the perception of a work of plastic
art, i.e., the effect of Beauty, produced by the temporary emancipation of
the intellect from the service of the individual will (which takes place
whilst the connection of the will with the object perceived is severed),
that effect music produces at once; for, as soon as it strikes the ear, it
draws the intellect away from any apprehension of the relations of
external things, it shuts us off, as it were, from the outer world, and
causes us to look inwards, as into the essential nature of all things.60
31
32
38
34
unrepresentable, that the total work of art, the musical drama, is metaphysically possible. Music and drama pour forth out of this common
abyssal depth that is the intimate essence of things, the actual thing-in-itself,
from this underlying formless world, which sustains the surface of
appearance, the dramatic appearance of the characters, the audible
appearance of melody, of harmony and rhythm.70 Here is the perfect
resonance of Schopenhauerean polarities within a single work of art, the
"musical drama" - from the thing-in-itself to the phenomenon, from
music to the drama, the formless to form, Wagner brings all of the spheres
of art together, aligning them along that fundamental fault-line that distinguishes between the sublime and the beautiful.
10. Nietzsche
All the facts are in the open. It remains for Nietzsche to unite them in a
single vision of the Greek Tragedy as musical drama. Apollo, the divinity of
the forms of appearance, Dionysus, who spreads the vision of the formless
of chaos, the true vision of the essence of this cruel world - they will be the
symbols of this long metamorphosis of the difference between the beautiful and the sublime. After Kant, Schiller, Schopenhauer, and Wagner,
the Nietzschean moment in the history of the sublime is nearly insignificant. He will have to take this small step in the elaboration of this
ambivalent experience of pain that leads to a more elevated pleasure. Yet
this step marks the separation of two traditions. In The Birth of Tragedy the
sublime speaks the language of Schopenhauer and of Wagner, though its
consequences differ. The terror which the disciple of Dionysus feels in
that moment in which, led by music and dance, he immerses his vision in
the world's essence, fails to drive him to resignation, to the negation of
will. Crushed beneath the cruelty of existence, which is revealed in the
experience of the sublime, he does not aspire to another existence, he
doesn't attempt to raise himself to a negative representation of that which
lies beyond all representation, beyond the realm of forms, beyond life.
According to Nietzsche, the Greeks had discovered that at the pinnacle of
the sublime it is possible to aspire to the beautiful, to appearance, to the
return to the serenity of forms. And this would have been the discovery
that engendered tragedy. Apollo as the vestibule to Dionysus, the dream
that prepares for the revelation of the intimate essence of things. And a
revelation that, because it is intolerable, demands once again the pleasure
of appearance.
The beautiful that redeems the sublime is Nietzsche's invention. In a
Dionysus which aspires to the state of Apollo, there lies the ecstatic
experience which aspires to be itself, which is justified by itself alone. The
end of the sublime as an ethical experience, the beginning of the aesthetic
35
38
39
40
and intuitive way, the will of each individual. But the paradox lies therein.
This reification of the thing-in-itself implies that while embodied in a multiplicity of particular wills, it is still subject to space and time - forms whic
are the exclusive property of phenomena. Overcoming this contradiction is
left up to the thesis of the unity of will, as thing-in-itself, beyond the multiplicity of its spatio-temporal embodiments (the central thesis of Schopenhauerean metaphysics). Not only does a real distinction between
numerically distinct individuals not exist, from an empirical point of view,
but the existence of such a multiple is considered to be phenomenal and,
as such, unreal. The result of all this is that Schopenhauer generally comes
to see the individual as, on the one hand, the double incarnation of the
thing-in-itself- as much "intelligible character" as will - and on the other,
pure phenomenon. From the empirical point of view, therefore, the individual is not only not a real particular, he is not endowed with individuality.
What then is the real basis of each human being's individuality for
Schopenhauer? For, as Kant did before him, he considers individuality t
be the condition that makes any judgment of imputability possible and, as
such, that which clears the way for a personal ethics. This question is not
answered in his metaphysics. Schopenhauer is aware of this when he writes
in one of his final works: ''Individuality does not rest on the principio
individuationis alone and therefore is not through and through mere
appearance. Rather, it is rooted in the thing in itself, in the will of the
individual: for its character is itself the individual. How deep its roots go
here, however, belongs to the question which I do not attempt to
answer."8
An absolute criterion for individual differentiation exists only from the
standpoint of intelligibility. On the simple plane of representation, there
is no distinction save the numerical.
This paradox of individuation is freighted with ethical consequences.
Since for Schopenhauer no real difference exists from the point of view of
the multiplicity of individual wills, the unremitting struggle for survival
between them is considered essentially groundless.
From the perspective of the thing-in-itself, it is the same will, one and
indivisible, "which digs its own teeth into itself."9 Therefore, surmounting
injustice and sundering appearances can only be achieved, according to
Schopenhauer, through the nullification, by each individual, of his own
individuality and of his own individual will, raising it to the generic status
of pure subject of knowledge.
2. Individuation between the aesthetic and the ethical
The works of Nietzsche's first period (1872-8) are profoundly marked by
this paradox which lies at the root of individuality in Schopenhauer's
41
metaphysics. They adopt the fundamental distinction between the thing-initselfand phenomenon, just as Schopenhauer in his fashion (using it as the
paradigm for a series of oppositions such as one/multiple, essence/
existence, reality/appearance) adopted it from Kant. Already in the first
chapter of The Birth of Tragedy, published in 1872, Nietzsche makes no
bones about specifying the metaphysical principles from which he is about
to launch himself. "Philosophical natures even have a presentiment that
hidden beneath the reality in which we live and have our being there also
lies a second, quite different reality; in other words, this reality too is a
semblance."10 In another passage he goes so far as to characterize this
appearance as "absolute inexistence."11 Yet, admitting to the unreal nature of the forms of space and time, wherein the existence of each individual being unfolds, will be equally consequential for Nietzsche's
meditation on the individual and his individuality. In Nietzsche's eyes the
empirical individual will always be doubly groundless, whether he is particular, before the One of universal will of which he is only an ephemeral
manifestation, or singular, before his own individuality, which renders his
empirical action a simple, imperfect and chaotic copy of the intelligible
law it embodies.
The Birth of Tragedy builds itself precisely upon the figures of Dionysus
and Apollo, around the opposition between the One and the Multiple,
while the Untimely Meditations, especially the third one, entitled "Schopenhauer as Educator", published in 1874, try to overcome the radical
incommunicability between individuality and empirical individuation.
However, like all great disciples, Nietzsche is no mere parrot of his
master. Already in these works the fault-lines that signal a rupture with
Schopenhauer's thinking have begun to appear precisely in Nietzsche's
search for a justification of individual empirical existence. Nietzsche
breaks not only with Schopenhauer's definition of the principle of individuation, but also with the ethical consequences of the absence of any
real empirical correlative for individuality. In this way, even though he
acknowledges that individual existence is an injustice against the One,
Nietzsche tries to justify the plane of appearance and, with it, the empirical
existence of each individual, instead of proposing, like Schopenhauer, a
process of ascetic negation of the individual will. How does he do this? He
establishes a dialectic tension between Truth and Appearance, a vision of
the One and an affirmation of the Multiple, a knowledge of the Intelligible and an apology for the Empirical. In The Birth of Tragedy, for example, if Dionysian ecstasy represents the state of aesthetic fusion with the
"Primal One" (das Ur-Ein) which, as Schopenhauer had affirmed, is
reached in the disinterested contemplation of the Whole beyond all personal motivations,12 that ecstasy is nevertheless offset by the figure of
Apollo, "the magnificent divine image [Gotterbild] of the principium
42
43
which defines the individuality of each person and which grounds his
identity in time, is still not thought of as a serial law containing all of the
states of the individual's biography and for which temporality would,
therefore, be immanent As Schopenhauer did, the 1874 text conceives of
individuality as the atemporal rule that manifests itself as a reiterated point
within the series of events that constitutes the existence of each individual;
because individuality, in its immutability, is unconditioned, it remains
essentially distinct from this same existence. The evolution and the mutability of each biography are not contained within the law, but are merely
the aftermath of the diversity of external conditions which make up the
empirical framework of its manifestation. As such, the only way that an
individual can recover his true individuality is by abstracting his existence
from empirical determinations, transforming each moment of his biography into the exact expression of his meta-empirical individuality. "That
heroism of truth" - writes Nietzsche - "consists in its one day ceasing to
be its plaything. In the process of becoming all is hollow, deceitful, vain,
worthy of our contempt; the puzzle which man ought to solve, he can only
release from being, in being such and not other, in the everlasting. Now
he begins to check how deeply he is united with becoming, how deeply he
is united with being - an enormous task wells up before his soul; to destroy
all being, to illuminate all falsity in things."19 By identifying with this
everlasting individuality which constitutes the pith of all that he is, and
which secures his identity in its becoming, that is, his status as a being, the
individual is reduced to a pure and petrified essence, to a disembodied
spirit, while at the same time the spatio-temporal plane against which his
biography unfolds, condemned as it is to being "vain and deceitful," still
lacks inherent consistency, no longer, as it were, before the One, but
before the individual and atemporal law of which it is considered a mere
sensory manifestation.
In the works of this first period Nietzsche is never quite able to work out
a positive concept for either the individual or individuality. The most he
can do is to invert the ethical consequences of Schopenhauer's paradox of
intelligible individuality to which no empirical individuation corresponds,
without questioning the metaphysical postulates which establish it. The
individual that Nietzsche would justify remains divided between an
extrinsic definition (as a particular in the heart of the spatio-temporal
Multiple, where all differentiation as such is considered unreal) and an
intrinsic definition, an atemporal individuality which reduces the individual to an abstract entity, in other words, between a merely numerical
differentiation and one which is real yet abstract.
44
45
46
47
this series would have to be eternal in the sense that it would always have
existed and would always continue to exist.30 However, since Nietzsche
starts from the principle that the number of possible events within this
chain of causation is finite - as the totality of the force of the universe is
constant - he concludes that becoming is circular in character. Each
episode in the biography of each individual is absolutely equal to an
infinite number of other events in these biographies already lived in
earlier phases of the great recurrence of all things. "Thus the development of this moment must be a repetition, and also that which generated
it, and that which arises from it, as so forward and backward again!"31
The idea of an eternal recurrence of all events allows Nietzsche to
innovatively reformulate the basis of each individual's individuality,
though the result will be terribly paradoxical.
We have seen how, by reducing reality to the plane of representation,
Nietzsche does not contest Schopenhauer's principle of individuation; he
simply considers it objective, that is, as the real determination of the
objects of experience. Yet, we have also seen how this principle limits us to
thinking about numerical difference and not real difference. After 1878,
the individual is conceived objectively as a particular being, numerically
distinct from other beings, though not distinct in terms of individuality.
What constitutes the individual, as such, is simply the fact that he cannot
have two separate beginnings in time and cannot occupy two different
points in space simultaneously. Because an individual continues to be
conceived of exclusively as a function of his place in an order of succession
and simultaneities, Nietzsche concludes that temporal differences are
necessarily translated into individual differences. Just as the same individual cannot be in two places at once, he can likewise not be present in two
different moments. From one moment to the next he is other. Thus,
"there is no Individual, in the shortest instant it is something other than
in the next, and its conditions of existence are those of innumerable
individuals."32 The impact that the idea of Eternal Recurrence will have on
the basis of individuality is to confer individuality upon each individual.
This happens by simply prolonging ad infinitum the spatio-temporal definition of individuation. Because time is considered to be not only real, but
infinite, the individual in time is now endowed with new determinations he will be defined as the infinite repetition of himself.33 If via this continual succession of instants, the identity of the individual - who is obliged
in each new moment to become another - is dissolved in time, it is also
through time that this same individual, with the passing of each new
instant, really becomes himself. "Man! Your entire life will become like an
hourglass, always again turned over, and always running out."34
This individual can now be viewed, not as an identity which is part of a
continuous order in the linear succession of time, but one which is part of
48
49
dissolved in the depths of time; it can only be prolonged up to the individual himself. The long chain of causation which originates in each
individual terminates there as well. And it is there that the new genesis of
his own repetition is likewise initiated, or rather the genesis of the infinite
number of other individuals whom he repeats and announces, and who
are only distinguished from him on the temporal plane, as different
occurrences in time of the same individuality. This radical individuality is
based on the fact that, within the same locus of concurrence, that is, in the
same completed cycle of all possible individuals brought into being, no
two indiscernible individuals can appear. Given the close interlinking of
all causes, the implication would be that these two individuals had
experienced the same genesis and that, in this case, they would not be two,
but rather one in the same individual (either spatially or temporally
identical as the single occurrence of the same individual, or merely temporally distinct, as different occurrences, in different cycles of recurrence,
of yet the same individuality). "Whether indeed ... something identical
has existed is entirely indemonstrable. ... Whether there can be something identical in one total state - two leaves, e.g.? I doubt it: it would
presuppose that there were an absolutely identical generation, and for
that we would have to assume that throughout all eternity something
identical had endured despite all alterations to the total state and the
creation of new properties - an impossible assumption!"38 The idea of the
Eternal Recurrence provides a "radical" basis for the principle of the
identity of the indiscernible: because the roots of his genesis are plunged
in eternity and even in himself, the individual becomes absolutely unique,
a uniqueness which is confirmed by the eternal repetition of himself and
of the entire chain of causes which lead to him.
Despite the fact that individuality is still thoroughly determined by its
place in the order of temporal succession, it is certainly not annihilated
there. On the contrary, new temporal determinations are found within it.
This happens in two ways: within each cycle as a radically individualized
and unique genesis, and within eternity as an infinite repetition of itself in
each moment of its existence.
In developing his idea of the infinite repetition of all events, Nietzsche
pushed his "anti-metaphysical" decision to remain on the plane of
representation to its ultimate consequences, rejecting the categories of
"reason," "beginning," and "finality." By eternally returning upon
themselves, spatio-temporal relations become self-subsistent, conferring
upon themselves, in a circular fashion, sufficient reason for being as they
are, and not as they are not. In this universe, each individual consequently
shares - by the mere fact of existing in a determined space and time - the
privilege of being able to sport his raison d' etre as the eternal basis of his
instantaneous individuality.
50
And yet Nietzsche's notebooks of the period tell of the search for some
other kind of cosmological justification for this new figure of individuality
contained in the idea of the Eternal Recurrence. It is as though he had
understood that the hypothesis, of all things being subject to repetition,
still needed something to complement it. The Eternal Recurrence needed
to be developed from the internal perspective of the individuality of each
person and it had to go beyond the idea that one's temporal condition
could be extended into infinity. It is precisely this perspective which
Nietzsche would develop from 1885 on in his theory of the will to power.39
51
52
with the individual as the subject of knowledge and proceeds to the world
as it is named from within. The second attempts to elucidate the whole of
the visible world, deriving it - as a symptom - from those internal processes revealed in the relationships between individuals.
Adopting man as an analogical principle does not reflect a simple
methodological decision, but one based on a de facto observation.
According to Nietzsche, man is condemned to being the primordial
analogical referent of all interpretations of the world. The theory of the
will to power is not distinguished from other interpretations of the world
by the fact that it takes man as an analogy. The mechanistic perspective
itself is nothing more than a consequence of this analogy - the concept of
the atom, Nietzsche believes, is a projection of the concept of subject/
substance upon the smallest structure of the immaterial extension. For
this very reason, the analogy is no longer a neutral procedure. Actually
taking oneself as the first term of the analogy does not guarantee
immediate access to the internal processes that preside over all phenomena. To start with man is to necessarily start from a particular
interpretation.
So there is a need for a prior critique of systems for interpreting man
and his fundamental stigmata before one can attempt to attain, through
him, the internal perspective on the world.
Nietzsche believes that the fundamental error common to all interpretations of man - and that he, therefore, unjustifiably projects upon the
world and upon the integers of his experience - is the error of the
"individual." "The Individual [is] the more subtle error."43 Does
Nietzsche then deny the existence of particular beings, numerically distinct and temporally self-subsistent? Hardly. What he denies is a specific
concept of the individual by which man can conceive of himself and, in
consequence, the world. "In truth there are no individual truths, but
rather mere individual errors - the Individual itself is an error. Everything
that happens in us is in itself something other, that we do not know: we
put intention and background and morality into nature in the first place. I distinguish, however, the imagined individuals and the true 'systems of
life' [die eingebildeten Individuen und die wahren 'Lebens-systeme'} of which
each of us is one."44 It is in the name of a new concept of the individual, as
"system-of-life," that Nietzsche considers the concept of the "individual"
as the most subtle of errors. This is why seeing the non-imaginary nature of
every individual (as a "system-of-life"), which constitutes the analogical
portal to the world's inner processes, presumes a critique of the "individual" (as an imaginary concept). Therein lies the error - man's false
interpretation of himself leads him to a false interpretation of the world.
The theory of the will to power is above all geared toward the deconstruction of these false images of individuation. Nearly all of the notes
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
force, perception, in turn, exists only in function of its relational character: a disconnected and isolated force (in every sense impossible, due to
its essentially functional nature) would be "blind."
7. Perspectivism
Even if, according to his thesis on the perceptual character of the relation
between forces, Nietzsche consolidates the anteriority of the right of
dynamic singularities and of their perceptions vis-a-vis the relations they
establish through them, the perception that each force has of the system
of power differences in which it is contained still does not allow for the
internal determination of its individuality. Since perception is only possible at the heart of a dynamic structure, each force expresses, within itself,
only differences of external power. Its uniqueness derives utterly from its
status as a single pole of convergence for the multiplicity of perceptions
that make up the field of forces within which it develops. Its definition is
still exterior: that would require a knowledge of all of the perspectives that
are directed its way. That is why Nietzsche says: "A thing would be defined
once all creatures had asked 'what is that?' and had answered their
question. Supposing one single creature, with its own relationships and
perspectives for all things, were missing then the thing would not yet be
'defined'."63
It is not so much in the concept of perception (Wahrnehmung) as it is in
perspective (Perspektiv) that it is necessary to look for the way in which
Nietzsche conceived of the internal principle of individuality. This distinction between perspective and perception is not elaborated systematically in
Nietzsche's oeuvre. And yet, it is only through it that we will understand
other criteria for differentiating between the kinds of perceptions used by
Nietzsche, that is, beyond those already established, between the inorganic
and organic world. Indeed, a hierarchy of prolongation and accuracy of
perspectives that each force exercises over the totality with which it relates
corresponds, according to Nietzsche, to a hierarchy of the degrees of
power various forces can claim. 'You shall above all see with your own eyes
the problem of order of rank, and how power and right and spaciousness of
perspective grow into the heights together."64
While, from the point of view of the perception of external differences,
the increase in internal structuring of each force - which corresponds to
the passage from the inorganic to the organic world - amounts to a
diminution of perspectival clarity and exactitude, by contrast, from the
point of view of perspective, Nietzsche considers that an increase in power
creates an enhanced sense of extensiveness and accuracy in the "vision"
of each force. The clarity and exactitude of perception vary with the
degree of external stability of power differences, while the extensiveness
60
61
62
affect the whole system."70 If the universe is a dynamic whole, does that
mean that the rise and fall of each individual's relative power would be the
result of general alterations in the system as a whole? If that were the case,
individuality would have to transcend the individual, and the individual's
internal viewpoint would be exclusively the reflection of his external
relations. Nietzsche would then end up by conferring ontological primacy
on the fact of the relation, to the detriment of the true multiplicity of
individuals that make up the universe. This is the point at which the
definition of the dynamic principle of force takes on a truly metaphysical
significance, not as the struggle for self-preservation, but as the struggle
for the continual increase of power. The fundamental principle of the
theory of the will to power lies less in the thesis which sees the individual as
a functioning whole, and more in his absolutely spontaneous nature. All
transformations of power that happen within an individual are the result
of his internal activity; general alterations of power in the force field or
system in which he finds himself are an expression - a "symptom" - of
that activity, and not the reverse. "The force within is infinitely superior;
much that looks like external influence is merely its adaptation from
within. Exactly identical means can be interpreted and used in ways diametrically opposed."71 Only the principle of the essential spontaneity of
each individual, as will to power, lets Nietzsche arrive at a basis for his
thesis on the anteriority of the right to individuation vis-a-vis differential
relations of power. Likewise, it is only this principle that allows for the
foundation of a thesis on the intrinsic nature of the individuality of each
individual.
The external definition of individuality, as the unique expression of the
multiplicity of differential relations of power, is, strictly speaking, a
"symptom" of the internal definition, the degree of power and the quality
of the perspective, just as all movements or events which occur on the
plane of representation are "symptoms" of the internal processes in the
conflict between absolutely individualized individuals. The opposition
itself, between the interior and the exterior of each individual, is abolished
- each individual is nothing more than interiority. If his interior force is
infinitely superior to exterior influences, the latter being simply expressions of the interior forces of other individuals, what is left in each instant
is the co-possibility between a multiplicity of absolutely spontaneous and
individualized forces, within a finite and constant quantity of global
energy.72
9. Individuality and eternity
The model of an instantaneous co-possibility among the totality of individual actions in conflict confers upon individuality the nature of a given,
63
and, at the same time, a task. From the internal viewpoint, individuality is
the law of the series that already contains the totality of an individual's
future actions within it by virtue of this individual's essential spontaneity.
This is the sense in which "each one turns into that which he is ..., the
beginning is simply a complex symptom of the what comes after."73 From
an external viewpoint, on the contrary, each action, since it is the result of
the relation of co-possibility between individuals in conflict in the context
of each event, has to be conquered through the instantaneous mediation
of all other individualities. Co-possibility operates as though it were a
natural selection among virtual beings, creating, in the end, the individuality of each individual. This is why the sphere of individuality is not
cancelled, but rather truly realized in co-possibility. To this effect,
Nietzsche states: "Every basic character trait that is encountered at the
bottom of every event, that finds expression in every event, would have to
lead every individual who experienced it as his own basic character trait to
welcome every moment of universal existence with a sense of triumph."74
Each instant of universal existence, each event, as co-possibility, is thus an
expression of each one of these individuals in conflict, a disparate convergence of a multiplicity of virtual beings. There is a metaphysical correspondence between "every basic character trait that is encountered at
the bottom of every event, that finds expression in every event" (jeder
Grundcharakterzugy der jedem Geschehen zu Grande liegt) and the basic character trait of each individual who takes part in this event. The individuality
of the individual, his Grundcharakterzug, is the individuality of the event
that, at each moment, is in the process of realizing his individual biography. Simultaneously, the basic character of each individual is the
expression of the character of each event as the event, in turn, actualizes
his virtual individuality.75 In this metaphysical correspondence, Nietzsche
discovers the basis for a new figure for the tragic yes to universal existence.
The individual who discovers his individuality in the very fact of each of
the events of his existence is led to experience "every moment of universal
existence with a sense of triumph." As Nietzsche says in the following
fragment from 1887: "It would need this fundamental characteristic in
oneself to be felt precisely as good, valuable, with pleasure."76 Only the
one who validates himself as a unique being, in his absolute singularity,
and who feels this singularity as good and valuable, only he can conceive of
the totality of existence in that which is also unique and individual in
existence. Only he has the right to judge existence in its entirety. And it is
out of his judgment that the Dionysian "yes" to all things and the triumphal validation of all things will burst forth.
The theory of the will to power, in this way, disengages itself completely
from the theory of the Eternal Return, upon which it was meant to confer
it a metaphysical basis. The Will to Power not only contains a completely
64
new concept of the individual and of his individuality, it lays the way for
the conception of a new figure for the tragic "yes", a new metaphysical
legitimization for the experience of affirming the universe in all its
instantaneity and eternity. Since each event, each moment of universal
existence is the result of a finite totality of individuals that in the twining of
their perspectives and in the constant co-possibility of their actions, affirm
and realize their individuality, to say "yes" to their own individual existence, and affirm it in its absolute difference, in its unicity, is, according to
Nietzsche, to also say "yes" to the entire universe and to eternity. "If we
affirm one single moment, we thus affirm not only ourselves but all existence. For nothing is self-sufficient, neither in us ourselves nor in things;
and if our soul has trembled with happiness and sounded like a harp
string just once, all eternity was needed to produce this one event - and in
this single moment of affirmation all eternity was called good, redeemed,
justified, and affirmed."77
It is because individuation and individuality are formally anterior to the
universe of difierence and relation, that Nietzsche can now conceive of the
immanent basis for the Dionysiac "yes" to all existence. Yet now, within
the theory of the will to power that "yes" no longer compromises individuation. This intuition - first formulated in The Birth of Tragedy - of a
purely affirmative existence, of a "yes" to the world and everything in it,
can now be conceived within a metaphysics of the individual. The Dionysiac experience no longer entails the dissolution of each initiate in the
delirious experience of the mystical One. On the contrary, since each
individual bases his individuality on the deepest essence of the world, or
rather, on eternity itself, that eternity that was needed to give birth to every
event of his existence, to say "yes" to the whole of the universe, is to say
"yes" to oneself and to one's character as a unique event. It is to affirm
our own individuality in the moment in which our soul vibrates with joy
"like a harp string." In that moment, as Nietzsche writes, "all eternity was
called good, redeemed, justified, and affirmed."
66
67
I. Before Schopenhauer
It is particularly significant that the theme of necessity was given centre
stage in Nietzsche's earliest substantial essays - Fate and History (Fatum und
Geschicht) and Freedom of Will and Fate (Willensfreiheit und Fatum).3 Nietzsche
wrote them in April 1862 when he was just eighteen years old for his
contribution to the Germania Society at the Pforta School. In both texts
the concept of necessity is embodied in the Latin expression "fatum."
Nietzsche's insistence on the Latin is more than a simple affectation of
style. In the inde termination of this term Nietzsche is able to condense a
great variety of meanings without having to confront the theoretic problems which the concept perforce implies. Because fatum designates,
simultaneously, both a physical determinism and the teleological category
of "fate," as well as the facticity of existing, Nietzsche can employ these
three meanings as though univocal relationships between them were a
given. Certainly his exploitation of the ambivalence of the concept of
fatum is what makes these essays so fecund. They condense the great
metaphysical and ethical questions that will run through the whole of
Nietzsche's work into this one concept.
The two essays are conceived as a whole. They explore the collective and
individual spheres of the conflict between necessity and freedom, through
68
the figures of history and free will What is so impressive about the questions that Nietzsche raises in these essays is how they anticipate his later
work. "We hardly know whether mankind itself is only a stage, a phase in
the universal, in becoming; whether it is not merely an arbitrary appearance of God. Is man not perhaps the development of stone through the
medium of plant or animal? Could it be that perfection is already attained
here, that herein lies history? Has this eternal becoming no end? What are
the mainsprings that drive this great clockwork? They are hidden. But they
are the same in the great clock we call history."4 Some of the themes that
will come to characterize Nietzsche's philosophical style are already present here. Among them are the questioning of man's place in nature, the
search for the immanent meaning of history, the inconceivability of an
interminable becoming and, finally, the link between history and eternity.
The fundamental question is whether it is possible to create a moral order
for the world that would go beyond intelligibility, beyond the metaphysical
justification that the world is an "arbitrary appearance of God." The world
is justified as order, regularity. Chance, which in Thus Spoke ZarathustravAll
be the principle of the innocence of becoming, is just the opposite here,
clearly synonymous with the arbitrary. And God manifests himself arbitrarily. In the search for a moral order for the world, Nietzsche must
respond to the theological imperative: that of immanence. God is pure
will, the arbitrary. The world is the reciprocal conditioning of its parts, that
which is determined. This incommunicability between God and the world,
which serves to organize the way in which Nietzsche takes up the classic
question of theodicy, is also manifested in each one of his responses.
Transcendence is not rejected via the figure of the arbitrary alone. In the
hypotheses that he advances for the ordering of the universe, Nietzsche
above all rejects the theological perspective. The interminable prolongation of becoming cannot be an expression of any totalizing finality which is
yet unrealized. As a finalized process, the world renounces effectivity
unjustifiably, becoming the eternal deferral of itself. Nietzsche confronts
theology with a general archaeology, which he calls "the common center
of all oscillations" (das gemeinsame Centrum atter Schwingungen).5 The
obvious contingency and multiformity of history is the manifestation of an
immutable form, the ahistorical groundwork that maintains itself as the
unifying principle of diversity. Only as "essence," as the expression of an
archetype, can humanity be seen as an immanent end. In order to deny
the transcendence of a "telos," Nietzsche adopts a Platonism of general
forms.
But this Platonism does not adequately meet the requirements of his
anti-transcendentalism. It is precisely the idea of "a common center of all
oscillations" that Nietzsche designates as the concept offatum. In this way
he can get around the realist interpretation of universal form and of the
69
70
71
of opposition against free will. Free will without fate is just as unthinkable
as spirit without reality."12
On the other hand (and from the perspective of modalities created by
the structure of time), fatum alone is conceived as a figure of the past. The
past, because it is irrevocable, is necessary and limits the freedom of will:
the will can do everything except re-do what is already done. If this were
not the case, the will would cancel its own link with the real. Altering the
past would annul the will's condition of possibility, which would cause it to
destroy itself. The possible, in and of itself, cannot become action if there
is not already something real and present. And something real and present, when it is an act, necessarily participates in the past and in its irrevocability. It is the necessary condition of the effectivization of the possible,
in short, its fatum. The total freedom of the will would lead to a merely
virtual universe, where all possibilities would be waiting to be realized
because of a failure to commit to the effective. Man would be a pure god,
but a god without a nature. In this sense, "If it became possible completely
to demolish the entire past through a strong will, we would immediately be
transported into the realm of autonomous gods, and world history would
suddenly be for us nothing but a dreamy self- deception/'13 Nietzsche still
lacks a modal understanding of the difference between the past and the
future. He likens the irrevocability of the past to the finitude of the will. It
is not the metaphysical impossibility of realizing the possible in the past
that explains why the past is immutable. For Nietzsche the past is an object
of wanting, just as the future is. If the past cannot be revoked, that is only
due to a determination of the will. The will is not sufficiently "strong" to
alter it. This confusion between two meanings of "impossibility" - the
modal and the anthropological - will be repeated in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, when Nietzsche equates the irreversibility of time with the irrevocability of the past. The revolt against the "already was" which in Thus Spoke
Zarathustra defines the "spirit or revenge," the rage of the will when
confronted with its powerlessness to change what has already happened, is
redeemed in the idea of the Eternal Recurrence.14 The presumption is
that the recurrence of a series of events can change the irrevocability of
the past, as though repetition would influence time whilst leaving the
contents of time untouched.
Nietzsche could not come to terms with the problem of articulating
both the metaphysical and the temporal perspective of the concept of
fatum. To base the immutability of human essence on the irrevocability of
his biological and spiritual history is to transform man into a contingent
reality, to make him the consequence of the sedimentation of free action.
Inversely, to infer the immutability of the past based on man's atemporal
essence, as though he were a manifestation of time, would be to deny his
free will.
72
73
each subject. Like Kant, Nietzsche will theorize human existence according to the series of phenomenal, spatio-temporally determined manifestations of this individual fatum.
74
75
configured positively, as intelligible character, that is, as immutable individuality, unconditioned when faced with empirical motives, he is unable
to freely project himself into the dimension of action. Freedom is the
moral subject's property of being, it is the fundamental attribute of its
individuality as it presents itself as a pure given, primordial and immutable. In other words, freedom is a metaphysical given and not a virtual
form that only comes into being by playing a role in the time of individual
essence. Man is irremediably free because he is an "intelligible character,"
an atemporal, individual law that stipulates that he will act in a particular
way. The foundation for the legality of this action is constituted solely by
freedom. As Schopenhauer says in On the Basis of Morality: "Freedom
appertains not to the empirical character but only to the intelligible. The
operari of a given person (what he does) is necessarily determined from
without by motives, and from within by his character; hence everything he
does necessarily takes place. In his esse (what he is), however, freedom lies.
He could have been a different man, and guilt or merit lies in what he is."19
The tension between necessity and freedom disappears in Schopenhauer.
Each individual is free because his individuality is necessary. And it is that
metaphysical necessity which at once establishes and absorbs the individual's freedom. Contrary to Kant, the unconditioned in Schopenhauer,
the undetermined, is not that which in the moral decision is conditioned
by something else - the respect for moral law - but solely that which i
immutable, the necessary. Human acts are doubly necessary: in the phenomenal order, everything is determined as a regulated linking of the
series of motivations in time. In the order of the thing-in-itself, of the
intelligible character which these acts empirically express, everything is
immutable since it is atemporal. Man is free according to Schopenhauer,
yet, paradoxically, "condemned" to his freedom, that is, to his immutable
individuality.
76
77
78
provided the content for this idea in 1862, so unconditioned life does now
in 1874. But this occurs in a diversity of ways, because the models of
necessity adopted are now different While in the concept of fatum the
necessary is the past, the irreversible that, in its immutability, constitutes
the condition of the possibility of the present and the contingent, now, in
the concept of life, the necessary is the atemporal, that which is outside of
time, because it is absolute spontaneity and free causality. Thus, the
essential tension between the mode of being, the "character" of a people
and its role in time as history, disappears. Not only does the being of each
people lose its status as materialization, as the sedimentation of the whole
of the past, but history itself can no longer empower a collective fatum.
History has now become that which manifests itself temporally in a reality
that is truly atemporal and nonhistorical.
The metaphysical abyss between life, as an essentially ahistorical reality,
and history, as a mere ephemeral manifestation in the temporal sphere of
this atemporal life, has enormous consequences for the status of History,
that is, for the condition of the possibility of a knowledge whose end is the
visible configurations of the life of peoples and individuals. Nietzsche
wants History to respect its metaphysical dependence vis-a-vis life, vis-a-vis
this unfathomable sphere of pure creation outside of time. Nietzsche
bases his denunciation of the pretension of historical discourse in constituting itself as a science on this metaphysical subordination. "Insofar as
it stands in the service of life, history stands in the service of an unhistorical power, and, thus subordinate, it can and should never become a pure
science such as, for instance, mathematics is."23 He is essentially proposing
a different ethical posture for dealing with historical phenomena in general. This Untimely Meditation interrogates, precisely as the tide indicates,
"the advantage and disadvantage of history for life." The questions asked
therein are directed at the possibility that historical knowledge could
strengthen life as a nonhistorical reality.
Early on in the preface to this "meditation," Nietzsche, citing Goethe,
underlines the following absolute primacy of life. "In any case, I hate
everything that merely instructs me without augmenting or directly invigorating my activity."24 Knowledge is only justifiable when it enlivens,
when it fortifies the individual's vitality, his ability to play a role in time.
Historical knowledge, the subject of the essay, which takes the action of
man in time as its object, is thus seen to have an ambivalent relationship
with life. To act is to act in time, it is to anticipate the future from a
consciousness that is founded on the unveiling of itself as law of the past; it
is through the past that man understands the meaning of his existence in
the present and is able to project it into the future - where it can be
realized. This whole - past-present-future - is condensed in each act. This
means that every act has a historical texture. So, to the extent that this
79
historicity of action constitutes the object of knowledge, life itself, with its
role to play in time, becomes an object of knowledge. In other words, if
history, as knowledge, is opposed to life, to the extent that it takes life and
its role as an object, history can create a life-instilling force. Through
knowledge of the past, history roots man in the present, establishing
reference points, paradigmatic moments in which the present can be
recognized. But, simultaneously, given that it exposes the ephemeral
nature of events and the ruin of everything, history also leads to the
weakening of our confidence in the process of eternalization, which animates the activity of peoples. "We want to serve history only to the extent
that history serves life: for it is possible to value the study of history to such
a degree that life becomes stunted and degenerate/'25 Through the
intermediary of history, Nietzsche makes his first attempt to overcome the
opposition between spontaneous life and life which knows the laws that
condition action. Knowledge is no longer absolutely separated from life
and its activity; the attempt to know something can be converted into an
affirmation of the will to live. Nevertheless, the structure of the original
opposition is maintained. In the subordination of history to the imperatives of life there is no metaphysical continuity between the unconditioned
and the series of events in time. The subject of knowledge that learns how
to act in time and the ethical subject, the subject of life, run on parallel
tracks, even if their interests converge. The persistence of this schism
causes Nietzsche's meditation to swing between two extremes: it moves
between using history as a way of looking at life, questioning which types of
history most serve it, and life, as a way of looking at history, to question its
existential limits. The intersection of these perspectives comes to bear
around a new determination of life's essential temporality, based as it is on
the temporality of being an immutable single being.
In terms of the historical point of view, Nietzsche breaks with diverse
extant historiographies, seeing them as symptoms of various types of life,
or as a way of understanding the extent of a people's historical knowledge
of life, or of an individual. "History pertains to the living man in three
respects: it pertains to him as a being who acts and strives, as a being who
preserves and reveres, as a being who suffers and seeks deliverance. This
threefold relationship corresponds to three species of history- insofar as it
is permissible to distinguish between a monumental, an antiquarian and a
critical species of history."26 Monumental History interests the active man
because of the necessity that he has for models and for heroes. To believe
in the possibility of repeating in the present great moments that have
already occurred in the past gives him courage, frees him from the doubt
which assaults him in moments of weakness.27 From this perspective, the
totality of the process of humanity is seen as an atemporal chain of
paradigmatic events which, once they have become real, are proof of the
80
81
History remain. In its immutability and as the place where the essence of a
people is constituted, the past forms a people's basis, confers upon them
the status of the necessary and thus justifies them in what they are.
The third form of historiography, critical History, is the antidote to the
first two forms. Its job is to animate the past by questioning the advantages
it has for life.
Here it becomes clear how necessary it is to mankind to have, besides
the monumental and antiquarian modes of regarding the past, a third
mode, the critical and this, too, in the service of life ... he does this by
bringing it before the tribunal, scrupulously examining it and finally
condemning it; every past, however, is worthy to be condemned - for
that is the nature of human things: human violence and weakness have
always played a mighty role in them. It is not justice which here sits in
judgment; it is even less mercy which pronounces the verdict: it is life
alone, that dark, driving power that insatiably thirsts for itself.x
It is not in the past that critical History seeks its condition as past, which is,
in fact, irrevocable. Instead, it would look for a living force within the past,
that of the anticipated and eternal present. That is why this form of
historiography would forget the ephemerality of all events and reconstrue
the past a posteriori in a way that it would like the past to have been. Judging
the past and condemning it in the name of life is a true reformulation
of the resulting essence, that essence whose only mode is irrevocability, the
immutability that has passed. "For since we are the outcome of earlier
generations, we are also the outcome of their aberrations, passions and
errors, and indeed of their crimes; ... The best we can do is to confront
our inherited and hereditary nature with our knowledge, and through a
new, stern discipline, combat our inborn heritage and implant in ourselves a new habit, a new instinct, a second nature, so that our first nature
withers away. It is an attempt to give oneself, as it were a posteriori, a past in
which one would like to originate in opposition to that in which one did
originate/'31 Through critical History man raises himself to nearly the
condition that, in 1862, Nietzsche attributed to the gods. Critical History
modifies man's nature because it modifies that past form whence this
nature emerged, substituting its first fatum with a second one founded on
a past reconstructed a posteriori. If this reformulation is not in itself reasonable, since the past is immutable, it is still within the reach of History,
or rather, of a certain use of History, that is within the reach of critical
historiography. Through the fiction of a desirable past, life moulds its
second fatum, a second nature, a second necessity.
Through these three approaches of creating History, Nietzsche discovers a common line - vis-a-vis the past all of them are unjust; all of them
82
seek to wrest it from its state of inertia and petrification; all of them would
like to reinscribe it in the dynamism of the present so that it might serve
life in its incessant search to justify its spontaneity, its atemporality.
Because in and of itself life has no reason for being, it has no immanent
nature that would justify its spontaneous reality, but rather invariably
depends on its sedimentations in the past which channels back to it the
nature it lacks, the essence which it is incapable of constituting, life needs
to be unjust with the past. Life is forced to decry knowledge.
Yet, in this seeming subordination of the epistemological to the ethical,
what is effectively in play is the cancellation of ethics from the metaphysics
of life. If life is autonomous in its ahistoricity, and necessary as pure
actuality, then History would be unable to alter its eternal nature. No
longer is History a dimension of free will, since freedom is not a mode of
acting but of being. History is reduced to a mere manifestation of the will
and plays no role in its workings. To finally understand the nonhistorical
content of existence is to discover one's nonteleology, that is, to discover
one's completeness in each instant. Nietzsche defines this new awareness
as "supra-historical." The "supra-historical man, who sees no salvation in
the process and for whom, rather, the world is complete and reaches its
finality at each and every moment."32 The Schopenhauerean philosopher's true way of seeing time is "supra-historical." Here Nietzsche
repeats, almost word for word one of Schopenhauer's fundamental theses:
time is a pure irreality. "He will not believe with the general public that
time may produce something actually new and significant; that through it
or in it something positively real may attain to existence, or indeed that
time itself as a whole has beginning and end, plan and development, and
in some way has for its final goal the highest perfection (according to their
conceptions) of the latest generation that lives for thirty years."33 Just as in
Schopenhauer, Nietzsche's "supra-historical man" understands that the
world, in its unconditioned totality, is a pure act; in each moment it
achieves perfection.
Present also in the figure of the "supra-historical man" is that other
experience of the atemporal, which has occupied the centre of The Birth of
Tragedy. Dionysian ecstasy. Just as the members of the tragic chorus
become aware of the dissolution of their condition as subjects of knowledge, which affects them at the moment they are raised beyond the
temporal, after having torn their veils of representation away, so what is
important to the "supra-historical man" is the revelation that there is
something unconditional and immutable underlying his own "becoming"
and that is what gives him his eternal character. Both express the mode in
which, just as in the Kantian/Schopenhauerean conception of the
unconditioned, Nietzsche bases the necessary on the eternal. The metaphysical concepts of "Life" and "the primordial One" - where this
83
86
or in other words, the human will is absorbed in natural necessity. The only
explanation for Nietzsche's response is that what he is really doing is taking
issue with himself, since, in the moment that he jeers at the Stoic ideal of
the complete absorption of human will in the cosmic dynamism of each
happening, he betrays the basis of his own ethic of immanence.
Unfortunately, whether in studies of the Stoics, or in those dedicated to
Nietzsche himself, we only occasionally find references to Nietzsche's
problematic relationship with the Portico. Yet, to really understand the
Stoic resonance in the history of Western philosophy, we are obliged to
take Nietzsche into consideration. His idea of the Eternal Recurrence
gives new life to the Stoic cosmology and once again places the heroic
figures of destiny at the centre of ethical theory.5 One scholar who does
discuss Nietzsche's relationship with the Stoics is Charles Andler. He is
most concerned with the Roman Stoics and their influence on Nietzsche's
ethics, frequently underlining the Stoic roots of the idea of the Eternal
Recurrence and the importance of Epictetus's maxims on the autonomy
of the will in the critique of the ethics of duty. But his estimation is that the
influence of Stoic morality is restricted to Nietzsche's so-called "intellectualist period," that is, to that period which corresponds to the composition of Human, All-too-Human, in which the Stoics crop up mostly as
symbols of a rational serenity against the fictions of the metaphysical and
the moral.6 Georges Morel, in Nietzsche: Introduction a Une Premiere Lecture,
in the chapter on the decisive moments in the history of nihilism
according to Nietzsche, dedicates two pages to Stoicism. Based on certain
stray comments Nietzsche made on the Stoics, Morel concludes that
Stoicism in Nietzsche's eyes was nothing more than a simple prolongation
of Socratic decadence.7 Jean Granier tries to distinguish between inner and
outer finality in the concept of the will to power (Wille zur Macht) based on
the Stoic distinction between skopos and telos, though he never discusses
any of the influences of the Portico's physics on the Nietzschean theory of
the will.8 It was Deleuze who got closer to the nucleus of the relationship
between Nietzsche and the Stoics. And, in spite of the fact that he contributed greatly to the rebirth of Stoicism in contemporary thought,9 in
Nietzsche et la Philosophic, Deleuze highlights Nietzsche's reductive interpretation of the Stoics in the ninth aphorism of Beyond Good and Evil. For
this reason, even if he correctly establishes the parallel between the Stoic
maxim "Live according to Nature" and the Dionysian "yes" to life, as
proof of Nietzsche's original approach to the tradition of the necessary,
Deleuze nevertheless cites the basic difference being between the physics
of the Stoics and Zarathustra's nature metaphors, declaring that there is
an utter opposition between the acquiescence to Epictetus's notion of
destiny and the Nietzschean amor fati. Yet nowhere does he attempt to
determine the real lines of confrontation between Nietzsche and Stoic
87
ethics.10 In the end, all that we get from Nietzschean studies are casual
intersections, parallels drawn, resonances and radical oppositions. There
is no systematic study of Nietzsche's relationship with Stoicism.
The urgent need for such a study goes beyond just Nietzsche's oeuvre.
What is at stake is not only an elucidation of Nietzsche's contradictions
(that is to say the mechanism which allowed him to move, without any
principles of continuity in place, from a highly elaborate and pedantic
identification with the thinkers of the Portico, to insulting their ideal of
the sage and crudely caricaturing their maxims) but our ability to conceptualize our own ties to the Stoics. For it is in these contradictions, in
these often vague and disconnected evaluations of Stoicism that punctuate
Nietzsche's texts throughout, that our perspectives about the ethical
experiments of Antiquity come into play. If much of our knowledge of
Greek culture is marked by Nietzsche, this is not only due to his interpretation of the place of Dionysian cults in the birth of tragedy, or to his
turning away from Platonism and his return to the tragic experience of the
Presocratics, against the formalism of Kantian morality and against its
epigones in Hegel's theory of law, in Schopenhauer's morality of compassion, and in the utilitarianism of Mill and Spencer, Nietzsche revives
the major components of the ethics of Antiquity. His programme for a
tragic anti-morality and his thousand metamorphoses of the Promethean
hero, who dares to face down the gods and who dwells beyond good and
evil, open to contemporary thought a unique road back to the ethical
world of the pre-Christians, oriented as they are toward the question of
how to achieve a happy life, toward the ontologies of pleasure, the practices of caring for oneself, in a word, toward the "aesthetics of existence,"
to use Michel Foucault's expression.
Nietzsche was one of the great interpreters of those aesthetics of existence. To ignore his confrontation with the Stoics would hamper our ability
to understand not only Nietzsche himself, but also our ability to properly
discuss the full evolution of ethical systems. The maxim "Live according to
Nature," was formulated for the first time in the fourth century BC by Zeno
of Citium and then six centuries later, by Epictetus, from whom Nietzsche
would wrest it for the purposes of debate. Its proximity to the amorfati of
the revaluation of all values is what concerns us here.
88
his essay for that year's university Latin prize (on the sources of Diogenes
Laertius), he hardly suspected that this would be the beginning of an
immense dialogue with the philosophy of the Portico, which would only
deepen as time went by.
In this, his first philological essay, Nietzsche shows how all of the
information contained in Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers about
the school of Zeno of Citium, calls for serious philological reservations.
According to Nietzsche, the lost work of Diocles of Magnesia, Cursory Notice
of Philosophers, did not simply constitute, as Diogenes would have it, the
source of paragraphs 49 to 82 (on logic), but all of book VII dedicated to
Stoicism.11 Nietzsche also shows that Diocles of Magnesia was a partisan of
Epicurus and, as such, wrould have been an unreliable witness of a rival
school.12 Nietzsche is calling into question one of the most important
doxographical sources for ancient Stoicism, and nearly the only one on its
logic.
It is interesting to highlight the research methods employed in this
essay. Nietzsche's work did not consist in discovering or presenting new
doxographical data. It was not in the name of some more credible source,
but simply through a well-founded internal critique of the sources of
Diogenes Laertius that Nietzsche dared to call the credibility of his image
of Stoicism into question. Thus, Nietzsche's essay - the first in the history
of classical philology dedicated to this important source of ancient
thought - ends up by paradoxically casting the original members of the
school that occupied the centre of the philosophical debate in the third
century BC into even greater obscurity. Nietzsche, we can say, in addressing
the doxographical tradition of Stoicism, had already fallen upon that
which would be the fundamental experience of his philosophical style: the
truth is essentially the denunciation of a palimpsest.
On the frontispiece of this essay, Nietzsche inscribes, through the voice
of Pindar, the maxim which would punctuate the whole of his oeuvre:
"Become who you are!"13 Just as the singularity which we are does not
necessarily directly manifest itself as identity via some thetic judgment, but
is rather the difficult goal of an ethical experience, so, with Nietzsche's
essay, our understanding of Stoicism emerges looking less like a philologically acquired given and increasingly like a philological and philosophical task. As we will try to show, the combat that Nietzsche wages in
support of the truth of Stoicism against the Epicurean deformations of
Diogenes Laertius's sources will reveal what is more truly a combat with
himself, and a precedent for his own philosophical project. As an ethical
model, as inspirer of the most beautiful metaphors for nature and necessity,
the philosophy of Zeno and Chrysippus will provide a constant and decisive reference for an oeuvre that will culminate in Nietzsche's Ecce Homo his philosophical autobiography, written a few months before he
89
90
91
world if the world wants to rob him of it. Christianity was made for a
different species of antique slave, for those weak in will and mind, that is
to say for the great mass of slaves.24
Ten years after his essay on the sources of Diogenes Laertius, Nietzsche
is once again fighting for the truth of Stoicism. It is no longer a philological combat, but philosophical. What is at stake in terms of the Stoicism
of the imperial period is not the credibility of the sources, but the interpretations, since the texts, in this case, constitute an irrefutable philological given.25
One question, however, is whether or not the struggle for the Hellenic
purity of Stoicism is spent in the polemic Nietzsche conducts - via this very
struggle - with Christianity? Is he not playing the part of some latter-day
Hellenist looking for the whys and wherefores of the decline of Greek civilization? Something more decisive seems to be at stake. Nietzsche's affinity
with the ethical ideal of the Portico is an expression of a real programmatic
similarity, which is to separate human action from the moral universe and
thus demonstrate the essential necessity of all of that which does not depend
on us and upon which the infinite power of our will is exercised.
Among the posthumous fragments of this period, there is one which,
because of the rare clarity with which it defines Nietzsche's philosophical
programme and for the similarity between it and the philosophy of the
Portico, allows us to highlight this subterranean affinity. Here is what
Nietzsche has to say in the fragment, which is contemporaneous with the
publication of Daybreak. "To not acknowledge false necessity - which
would mean useless submission and would be servile. Therefore, knowledge of nature! But also want nothing that goes against necessity! That
would mean a waste of strength and weakening our ideal and, as well, to
want deception more than success."26 Here we find, in condensed form,
arguably the two most cardinal imperatives in Nietzsche's philosophy: the
first, theoretical in character, calls for a knowledge of Nature and of its
true Necessity, and orients Nietzsche's research into physics, which will
lead him to the idea of the Eternal Recurrence in 1881, as well as to the
theory of the Will to Power in 1885;27 the second imperative, this time
ethical, is stated, unusually so, in negative terms: "want nothing that goes
against necessity!" (nichts gegen die Notwendigkeit wotteri), but which, in the
maxim amorfati, love of the necessary - its positive formulation - will be
considered by Nietzsche to be the supreme expression of his morality.28
The philosophy of Stoicism resonates clearly through these two imperatives and in the way in which they are articulated, that is, to use the
language of the Portico, in the way they link Physics to Ethics. It is the
need to contain the will within its limits, while preventing it from being
stripped of force, which obliges us to know Nature and its dynamic. But, if
92
So long as one always lays blame on others one still belongs to the
mob, when one always assumes responsibility oneself one is on the path
of wisdom; but the wise man blames no one, neither himself nor
others.' - Who says this? - Epictetus, eighteen hundred years ago. - It
was heard but forgotten. - No, it was not heard and forgotten: not
everything gets forgotten. But there was lacking an ear for it, the ear of
Epictetus. - So did he say it into his own ear? - Yes, that is how it is:
wisdom is the whispering of the solitary to himself in the crowded
marketplace.30
Nietzsche's use of the morality of the Stoa to critique Christian morality
is not then a simple rhetorical and circumstantial expedient, but expresses
a real (however undeveloped) affinity between Nietzsche's programme
and that of the Stoics. As we will see, it is upon this radical innocence of
the universe and all the acts contained therein that Nietzsche will base his
critique of what he will come to consider the nihilistic theses of Christianity.31 What's more, it will be this same programme (which calls for both
a knowledge and a love of Nature) from which the idea of the Eternal
Recurrence will emerge - the idea in which the philosophy of the Portico
93
will resonate most clearly and which Nietzsche will consider in 1887 to be
the experience that spells the definitive end of Christian morality.
94
But this nearly perfect symbiosis between Nietzsche and the Stoics will
lead Nietzsche, paradoxically, into a desperate search for differences. In
that very moment in which his greatest affinity with the physics of the
Stoics and with their ethic based on love of one's own destiny is reached,
Nietzsche suddenly becomes their fiercest critic. The sudden change
becomes apparent in the autumn of 1881. Look, for example, at the following passage from his notebooks: "Stoicism in its resolute patience is a
sign of paralyzed strength, counterbalancing suffering by its own inertia lack of heroism, which is to always fight (and not suffer), the stoic
Voluntarily seeks' suffering."37 How to explain such a change of mind?
Nietzsche seems to be almost desperately trying to mark out his differences with the Stoa, and at the precise moment in which those differences
had all but dissolved. We need look no further than The Gay Science,
published in 1883, for examples. It is here that those central ideas that owe
so much to the Ethics and the Physics of Stoics first appear - amarfatf8 and
the idea of the Eternal Recurrence.39 But this is also the book in which
Nietzsche endeavours - also for thefirsttime- to denounce Stoic morality.
And yet, significantly, at issue is neither the egoism nor the probity of the
Stoic wise man, whom Nietzsche had previously praised as a counterpoint
to the morality of piety. Nor are the innocence and the amorality of
human existence as they were proclaimed by the solitary voice of Epictetus
at issue. On the line now is the very foundation of his whole affinity with
Stoics - with the sage's notion as to the necessity of nature. "The Stoic, on
the other hand, trains himself to swallow stones and worms, slivers of glass
and scorpions without nausea; he wants his stomach to become ultimately
indifferent to whatever the accidents of existence might pour into it ' >4
When it comes to love of necessity (accepting what happens in a manner
that befits its happening), Zarathustra's creator will beg to differ from the
Stoic wise man. Yet Nietzsche's criticism is directed beyond the trivial and
superficial image of this ideal of the Portico, the sage. This is obvious when
he comments: "At least the Stoics believed that this was how things were,
and they were consistent when they also desired as little pleasure as possible, in order to get as little displeasure as possible out of life."41 That
which is an essentially active morality - permanently geared toward action,
toward the actualization of reason and of passion, in the presence of
happenings whose necessity must be understood in order to be accepted42
- is interpreted by Nietzsche as a flight from the real, as an incapacity to
accept the unforeseen amidst the hypothetical imperturbability of permanence and its anaesthetizing quietism.
Because Nietzsche at this point only views the sage at his tritest, the basis of
that secret resonance between the two will remain unquestioned. We will have
to wait until 1886, the year which coincides with the first formulations of the
doctrine of the will to power, to witness the crucial experience in this affinity.
95
96
97
98
100
longer tell of new projects. His only preoccupation during this period is in
extracting all of the theoretical and political consequences of the theses
contained in The Antichrist -a book which he repeatedly refers to as "The
Revaluation."6 And on one of the last pages before delirium set in, we
read: "A last word. From now on I will have to have steady hands, a great
number of them - immortal hands! - the Revaluation should appear in two
languages. It would be well to found associations everywhere in order to
make available to me, for when the time is right, thousands of partisans."7
We can thus conclude that, as much in its original intention as in its
formulation, the programme for the revaluation of all values - in which
Nietzsche's final philosophy came to be polarized and which constitutes
the context in which his fundamental works are elaborated, books such as
The Genealogy of Morals, Twilight of the Idols, The Antichrist, and Ecce Homo should only be identified with the last three years of Nietzsche's production. What's more: emerging out of the soon-to-be-abandoned Witt to
Power, the programme for the revaluation of all values would seem to be a
substitute for this work in progress. As such, it is clear that the Will to Power,
as a book in and of itself, was abandoned, not merely interrupted, as
Nietzsche's sister would have us believe. The "Revaluation" will therefore
find its footing, its whole speculative measure, in that which we will call an
anthropology of the will and its typologies. As can be seen by reading the
notes for the book which Nietzsche abandoned, in this phase the "Revaluation" provided Nietzsche with the structural underpinning he needed
and guided him in his attempt to create an all-inclusive system: the will to
power. We should also underline the fact that, though it defined Nietzsche's work throughout 1888 and 1889, the programme for the revaluation of values is most clearly explained in The Antichrist. This brings us to
two further conclusions: first, the revaluation is an essential critique of
Christian Morality and how it had come to determine the axiological views
of the Western world;8 and second, if it is true that this programme was
abruptly interrupted by delirium, this interruption has to do, not with its
theoretic formulation, but rather with the "political" exploitation of its
theses. From Nietzsche's point of view, the critique of all values was concluded at that moment in which his consciousness foundered in silence.
During the beginning of January 1889, when Nietzsche stopped writing
definitively, it almost seems as though it were the writing itself that had
finally spent what there was to write.
This brief biographical and thematic outline of the programme for the
revaluation has only been made possible in light of the new critical edition
of Nietzsche's texts, in which all of the posthumous writings are rigorously
gathered and arranged in chronological order. This has given us a new
foothold in our understanding of the genesis and the underlying pattern
of Nietzsche's last philosophical concerns. But it also raises new
101
102
103
104
Recurrence from the body of Nietzsche's work starting in 1885, and the
beginning of the elaboration of the doctrines of the mil to power and of
nihilism which will serve to structure the programme of revaluation. One
can argue that these last doctrines are the result of an attempt by
Nietzsche to respond to the most important ethical and metaphysical
problems before him, both of which emerged out of the idea of repetition.
If our hypothesis can be confirmed, the role attributed to the idea of the
Eternal Recurrence in the programme of revaluation will have to be
reformulated. Contrary to what is normally supposed by the critics, the
Sils-Maria inspiration does not turn out to be the fundamental proposal in
the programme of the exhaustion of all values. This does not, of course,
imply that it has played no role whatsoever. If the doctrine of the Eternal
Recurrence is, in fact, a condition for the possibility of the project of the
revaluation of values, it is so on the *'biographical" plane. It was the
transformation of the idea of the eternal recurrence into the doctrine of the
will to power that, as we will try to show, gave rise to the doctrine of nihilism,
which would, in turn, constitute the fundamental contents of the programme for the revaluation of all values.
Our inquiry will take two different directions. Firstly, we will trace the
genesis of the idea of the Eternal Recurrence and the problems which this
idea creates in Nietzsche's work after 1881. Secondly, we will not only
underline the novelty of the doctrine of the will to power and nihilism (both
arising in 1885) but, more importantly, show to what extent these doctrines should be read as solutions to those problems inscribed in the
cosmological and ethical idea of the recurrence of all events.
To ponder the appearance of the idea of the Eternal Recurrence in the
writings of Nietzsche is an immense project. As we have already said,
Nietzsche always described this idea as having taken the form of pure
"inspiration," something which came suddenly to dominate his thinking
and force him to search for cosmological and existential truth. In Ecce
Homo, when he meditates upon the precursors of this inspiration, he refers
only to an alteration in his musical tastes.22 This is certainly not the place
to describe the complete evolution of the idea of Recurrence. That would
imply a profound examination of Nietzsche's rupture with Schopenhauer's metaphysics, out of which his mature view of nature, his
positions on the human condition and, finally, his theory of the will would
develop. These were the tendencies which led to his thinking on the
revaluation of morals. In this chapter we will concentrate on a vein in
Nietzsche's thinking which seems to underlie these tendencies, that is, his
notion of the role of guilt - for this is where the real genesis of the project
for the revaluation of all values lies.
105
106
manifestation of his immutable individuality) - we are able to see intuitively the essence of the will and, therefore, its moral destiny. For Schopenhauer all of us, when confronted with the sense of the imperfection of
action, will return to the done in an attempt to redo it. Such a sentiment has
a metaphysical dimension. "Now as responsibility presupposes a possibility
of having acted otherwise and thus freedom in some way, there is to be
found indirectly in the consciousness of responsibility the consciousness
also of freedom/'24
This surprising thesis, which affirms the intuitive condition of freedom,
as though it could be obtained immediately in the experience of guilt,
does not have a descriptive status. In spite of the phenomenological tone
that Schopenhauer adopts whenever he speaks of the consciousness of
guilt, a reading of his demonstration reveals to what extent the immediate
equivalence which he posits between the experience of guilt and the
intuition of freedom originates in his attempt to avoid the paradoxes of
the Kantian concept of freedom, or, rather, in his attempt to break out of
the freedom/morality circle which had organized the Critique of Practical
Reason. It will be recalled that freedom - an idea of the reason - only
acquired objective reality for Kant when it was rigorously deduced from
moral law. For its turn, moral law, even though it is a fact of reason, only
has an objective basis, its "ratio essendi," in the fact of freedom. As Kant
himself affirmed: "One must freely admit it that a kind of circle shows
itself here, from which it seems, there is no way out. In the order of
efficient causes we assume ourselves to be free in order to think ourselves
as under moral laws in the order of ends, and then afterward we think of
ourselves subject to these laws because we have attributed freedom of the
will to ourselves."25
Schopenhauer wanted to break out of this vicious circle, this reciprocal
dependency between freedom and morality. At the same time, he intended to strip the sphere of the will of its monopoly on moral experience.
How would this be done? On the one hand, he denies moral law the status
of a "fact of reason" as was proposed by Kantian formalism. On the other,
because he wants to break out of the Kantian circle, he construes freedom
not as postulate of reason, but as an intelligible metaphysical property of
the ethical subject's own will. Schopenhauer thus displaces one of the
terms of the freedom/morality relation. It is no longer the moral fact, as
an idea of the reason, but the fact of remorse, that reveals the essence of
human morality. And for man, this fact of remorse has a simple and
absolute condition. It does not depend on any moral postulate. Guilt is the
discovery of the fundamental freedom inscribed in the intelligible character
of the subject that acts and that leads to the revolt of will against itself.
This metaphysical justification of remorse - and the consequent
amplification of its significance as the basis of morality - would inevitably
107
108
109
110
he cannot move" - the false exteriority of time before the one who would
convert it into a moral phenomenon. It is as though, putting pressure on
each moment of existence, time were a form of "justice," and life, which it
moulds, a kind of "punishment." "Everything passes away; therefore
everything deserves to pass away. And this too is justice, this law of time
that it must devour its children. Thus preached madness."82 The illusion
of a link between time and will transforms itself into "madness." It is this
that gives moral meaning to a conception of time that has been made
artificially autonomous, reified. From the illusion of seeing time as
something which happens comes the madness of affirming that "therefore
everything deserved to happen!" (darum ist attes wert zu vergehen!) - in
which the happening suddenly takes on a moral meaning, a "deserving to"
(werteri), a value (Wert). Representing time in the figure of "justice" are all
the things that exist in time and arise infected by this moral valorization,
this guilt. " 'Things are ordered morally according to justice and punishment. Alas, where is redemption from the flux of things and from the
punishment called existence?' Thus preached madness."33 Existence is
transformed into a moral phenomenon in that moment in which the
uniqueness of doing is pondered from the point of view of time and not
from the perspective of the fact of itself alone. For this reason, when a man
reflects on himself as existence in time, his only possibility is to discover
that he has been infected by the experience of punishment and by
the desire for vengeance, by the will to revenge against time. Nietzsche
himself would say "The Spirit of Revenge, my friends, has so far been the
subject of man's best reflection; ... For 'punishment' is what revenge calls
itself... ,"34
111
basis of morality no longer has its roots in illusion, it is no longer a consequence of the presupposition of freedom (as Nietzsche had argued in
Human, All-too-Human). Now, morality takes on a universal value; it is seen
as an anthropological given, as if the pathos of the revolt against life had
been inscribed in the experience itself of time.
But Nietzsche is deluding himself here. We can verify that what is tacitly
at stake is thetypologicalunderstanding of this same experience of time. It
is as though Nietzsche had already formulated the thesis that would
organize the theory of the will to power: experiences of time are not
universal, rather they are derived from different types of will. Indeed,
irrevocability of the past in itself cannot be experienced univocally. As
Nietzsche will recognize once he begins to explore the inbuilt selectivity of
the idea of Eternal Recurrence, it already inevitably contains an unavoidable ambivalence. The irrevocability of the already done can be distinguished in two distinct ways: as nostalgia, or as remorse. In nostalgia the
will discovers the obstacle of temporal distance because it wants to
recuperate the past in order to relive it in its uniqueness, because it
recognizes in it the plenitude of a unique conjugation, of a perfect
intensity which wants to be repeated. In remorse, it is the impossibility of
destroying the past, or erasing an act that is seen to be imperfect and
which, in its irrevocability, lingers on as a wounded memory which refuses
to heal. While in nostalgia temporal deferral is manifest in the property of
irreversibility, it is irrevocability which obsesses the guilty conscience. In
remorse, as Jankelevitch says, "this is not about reliving an event already
lived through, but definitively putting aside the memory of an event, or of
a decision; this is not about bringing charming ghosts back to life, but
driving away the sinister specters who frighten a guilty conscience."35
Remorse is the despair which comes of never being able to revoke the
irrevocable. For this reason, remorse leads the will into rage against time.
The originating "no" which Nietzsche discovers in all of the commandments of value can only be the result of the experience of time as remorse.
Nostalgia would never be able to induce "revolt," or the will to revenge. It
is precisely the experience of a nothingness beyond repair which follows
an absolute - the knowledge of the disappearance of the already lived that makes the nostalgic consciousness suffer. Remorse, to the contrary,
desires the nothingness, or at least the nothingness of a certain past. It is a
principle of nihilization. It wants to erase the traces of imperfection from
memory. The revolt of remorse against time is, in its essence, the will's
revolt against itself, against its finite condition and against the infinitude
of its memory.
Thus it is understood that in the description of the human experience
of time, the experience which gives birth to the concept of the "spirit of
revenge," the experience of the past, "of that which was" (das, was war), is
112
113
remove from remorse this primitive character attributed to it by Schopenhauer. Derived from a precise experience of time, remorse could be
seen as arising as an illusion, as the effect of a false interpretation of the
structure of irrevocability. Yet, with this gesture, Nietzsche contaminated
his own phenomenology of temporality. To strip remorse of its metaphysical status, to reduce it to a simple, impoverished sentiment of time, to an
*'all-too-human'5 sentiment, resulted in turning remorse into a "human"
experience, an experience which concerned Man in all his universality
and that would be inscribed in his condition of existing in time.
The diagnosis of morality in Thus Spoke Zarathustra is, as such, built upon
an ambiguity. Nietzsche wants to start from a pure description of the
experience of temporality in order to trace the pathos of revenge against
life back to it and, therefore, deduce the condition of the possibility for
the whole moral valorization of existence. Yet, if the experience of time
produces in the will the consciousness of its own finitude, resulting in a
pathos for revenge against the past, it is because the experience itself of
time already finds its genesis in another experience closer to the origin of
revolt: that of remorse. And this latter experience no longer has a universal character; it has merely to do with certain kinds of wills - those that,
because they do not carry each act to its possible limit, live obsessed with
redoing the done.
We can say that there is not one, but two perspectives from which we can
understand the condition for the possibility of morality: one anthropological
and the other typological In the first it is the uniqueness of the act that, in
itself, sets off a revolt against time in the will; in the second, the revolt
against existence is a predetermined interpretation of this uniqueness. In
the anthropological perspective, the spirit of revenge acquires universal
status - it is a constituent of man's consciousness as a being that exists in
time. Time thus acquires a metaphysical condition. It is its reality, its very
passing, in itself irrevocable and unrepeatable, that produces the human
condition in man. It is because time is this impassible mass, this monstrous
material that in its immateriality reduces everything that exists to nothingness, that man is a being whose most fundamental nature is the revolt
against time, against existence, against life, in a word, that man is a
"moral" being. Because time exists, man is man. In the typological perspective, the reality of time is dissolved. Not because the human condition
is previous to the constitution of temporality as experience. The idea of
man as a stable entity also dissolves. What exists are types.38 And they
constitute different modes of temporality. The revolt against time and,
therefore, the invention of the figure of time as an irrevocable elapsing,
only pertains to the reactive type of will, that will which does not employ
the full potential of its power in each moment because it reduces its act to
remnants, to the excess of circumstances.39
114
115
116
and curse the demon who spoke thus? Or did you once experience a
tremendous moment [oder hast du eimal einen ungeheuren Augenblick erlebt]
when you would have answered him, 'You are a god, and never have I
heard anything more godly/ "4S Since the will to the return of the past can
render radically heterogeneous experiences - nostalgia or remorse - the
idea of Eternal Recurrence must be comprised of unavoidable existential
ambivalence. It induces existential postures that are as distinct from each
other as are the ways of seeing the past For the one in whom memory of the
past is always refracted through the knowledge of impotence and a guilty
conscience and who, as a consequence, only wants to turn it off, annul it,
for this person the idea of infinite recurrence of this past exactly as it was,
the idea of the repetition of each and every one of these acts that they want
to forget, is a curse, a terrible punishment this idea annihilates him.
On the other hand, the idea of Eternal Recurrence will confer plenitude
to each and every one of the instants of our existence only if this plenitude
has already been realized. It is only in one for whom the experience of the
past is already contained in this feeling of nostalgia that the idea of the
return of this same past can possibly represent "divine thinking." Eternal
Recurrence affirms the promise of the repetition of "a tremendous
moment" already experienced and which one wants to be lived anew. As
Nietzsche asks us, "or did you once experience a tremendous moment";
then, at the conclusion of this same aphorism (341) of The Gay Science
when we read: "Or how well disposed would you have to become to
yourself and to life to crave nothing more fervently than this ultimate eternal
confirmation and seal?" The "selectivity" that Nietzsche attributes to the
idea of recurrence therefore presupposes a typological understanding of
temporality. What is expressed in the duality of responses to the revelation
of Eternal Recurrence is the duality of postures when confronting the past
- remorse or nostalgia.
But this undermines the idea of Eternal Return. As soon as Nietzsche
adopts the typological perspective to ponder the inescapable ambivalence
of the doctrine of Eternal Return, he annuls, at one stroke, its existential
value. The revelation of the Eternal Recurrence of all things ends up by
being existentially derivative. It is not the idea of repetition that refigures
the experience of temporality. Instead, this idea simply confirms, in cosmological terms, an experience of temporality previously prefigured. It
empowers the experience of each past event as a site of the instantaneous
plenitude of each act. Nietzsche seems to have been aware of this derivative efficacy when, in 1882, he writes in one of his notebooks: "We want
to experience a work of art over and over again! We should fashion our life
in this way, so that we have the same wish with each of its parts! This is the
main idea! [Dis der Hauptgedanke}. Only at the end will the doctrine be
presented of the repetition of everything that has been, once the tendency
117
118
119
120
of the idea of Eternal Recurrence when he writes "Who could teach him
also to will backwards?"
There is another surprising element in the way Nietzsche reveals the
idea of Eternal Return. It is presented as the symbol, the emblem, of an
experience of fundamental nostalgia. The will to relive the act of having
wanted absolutely in the past induces the will to want the recurrence of all
that was wanted. The "redeeming" idea therefore is a response to nostalgia, and not to remorse in confrontation with the past. This link
between the experience of nostalgia and the idea of Eternal Recurrence is
laid out in the chapter entitled "On the Great Longing" (Von dergrossen
Sehnsucht). Zarathustra, convalescing from the interior metamorphosis
suffered after his reveladon of the idea of Eternal Recurrence, intones a
canticle of nostalgia, a canticle to the dissolution of the temporal differences between "today" and "formerly." "O my soul, I taught you to say
'today' and 'one day' and 'formerly' and to dance away over all Here and
There and Yonder."49
121
122
Instant as a way of viewing time in its different aspects, but rather wanting
to conceive of time in general, in terms of its circular totality, thus weakening the atomicity of each of the moments of this totality.
The existential consequences of this difference of perspectives for the
totality-temporal/each-instant-singular relationship are dramatized in this
same chapter in the third book of Thus Spoke Zarathustra, in the vision of a
shepherd into whose mouth a serpent crawls as he sleeps. Zarathustra
moves abruptly from the conversation with the Dwarf to the memory of
this horrible vision. In this narrative it seems to us that the serpent which
slides inside the shepherd symbolizes the linear time of past-present-future
that, in its passing, sets up residence inside of man without him being
aware of it. In a slow and continual movement, like that of the serpent,
time gradually enters us until finally it has completely consumed us. Once
awake, the man is already in time, just as the serpent is in his entrails.
Zarathustra says that he had tried to save the shepherd by pulling at the
serpent's tale. But this, as he said, was in vain. The movement of the
serpent, like that of time, goes in a determined direction, it is irreversible.
How to evade this being-in-time, how to interrupt this anguish of time's
incessant passing on the way to death, this horror of feeling as though one
were being continually devoured by time? That is when, suddenly, as
Zarathustra relates, a voice rose from within him yelling at the shepherd:
4
'Bite it! Bite it!" And that's what the shepherd did, he bit the serpent,
cutting his unending body in half, separating the head from the tail, the
past from the future and breaking the continuous totality of time, conquering that dimension of plenitude and autonomy which only the instant
can confer. Zarathustra then relates how the shepherd laughed like he'd
never heard anyone laugh before.
The image of the serpent should be interpreted as a symbol of the idea
of a continuous circle. If the idea of Eternal Recurrence was conceived out
of the notion of circular totality, the serpent that doubles back on itself, it
leads to a worsening of the experience of temporality as exteriority, the
sphere of the involuntary. Each present moment is revealed as merely an
ineluctable return of the past, of the "was" in all its immutability. Conversely, if it arises as affirmation of the plenitude of each and every discrete
instant, as a real segmentation in the continuum of becoming, then it frees
man from this experience and reveals to him the plenitude and the
absolute actuality of each instant of his existence.
However, this new metaphysical status will be revealed only to those who
interrogate the totality of time starting from the Instant. Only he who has
already experienced time as a succession of minimal units (because time is
an infinite repetition of itself, to wit the Eternal Recurrence) will be able
to affirmatively interpret the idea of repetition and thus, mediated by this
idea, cosmologically re-affirm that primordial experience of plenitude,
123
which is the true identification between the will and the act. Only the idea
itself of Eternal Recurrence can focus the apprehension of time in the
dimension of the Instant. The representation of the idea of Return as a
cosmological doctrine creates - in circular fashion - the condition for the
possibility of its own revelation. This circularity is similar to that which is
already present in The Gay Science. While there it has to do with the reciprocal presupposition of an already configured existential posture and
with a representation of time that would allow for the empowerment of
that posture, in Thus Spoke Zarathustra such a shared dynamic (between the
existential posture and the representation of time) merely affects the
representation of the idea of Eternal Recurrence as a pure cosmological
doctrine in which the temporal whole has to be conceived of as the result
of an infinite series of atomic instants, even as the atomicity of these
instants is based solely on the thesis on the infinite character of the series
and, therefore, on the thesis of a limited totality.
This symmetrical deviation in the representation of the temporal whole
and of each one of the instants of which it is comprised, has been variously
described, particularly in those readings of Nietzsche that have been
influenced by the tradition of Husserl and Heidegger's phenomenologies
of temporality.52 Nevertheless, these readings are on shaky ground in
conceiving such a circle as a conflict between "intramundane" and
"extramundane" conceptions of time. For Eugen Fink, for example, this
circularity is a consequence of the fact that Nietzsche was only able to
conceive of the idea of the Eternal Recurrence out of the experience of
linear time, such as it was represented in the "intramundane" view of
things, that is, based on all of that which up until now has been part of the
temporal world, only to cancel out, in his explanation of the infinitude of
the past, this very same experience in the image of infinite repetition,
reducing time to a single, ecstatic dimension.53 The difficulty in ascending
to an "over-human" state lies in this very conflict. Nietzsche still needs to
resort to categories and concepts that derive from the all-too-human
experience of time with its past-future oppositions, thwarting by the way a
positive delineation of that which he was striving to explain. What is created, in Fink's view, is a true "negative hermeneutics of temporality," or
the self-dissolution of the temporal categories that serve to orient the
pathos of "the spirit of revenge." In the end, Fink's reading, rather than
revealing the necessary character of the hermeneutic circularity that
constitutes the idea of the Eternal Recurrence, reduces Nietszsche's
notion to a conceptual black hole. He concludes thusly: "what becomes
ambiguous and doubtful about the Nietzschean doctrine of Eternal
Recurrence in Thus Spoke Zarathustra is the opacity of his concepts of
eternity, of repetition, of the course of time and that which runs through
it. There is, in Nietzsche, no explicit concept of time."54 Heidegger sees
124
125
126
1. The functional nature of the will. The will in its entirety only acts
against other wills. It is always a gathering of dynamic relations:
*'every force can only expend itself on what resists."57
2. The thesis of the instantaneity of the will. The will exists solely as a
manifestation against another will. Wills confront each other in a
single instant. Their identity is changed by time since in the following
instant another will is already acting. As Nietzsche says: "Supposing
that the world had a certain quantum of force at its disposal, then it is
obvious that every displacement of power at any point would affect
the whole system."58 This is why there is no causal conditioning in
uninterrupted time, but always an absolute and instantaneous
reformulation of all relations offeree. 'Two successive states, the one
'cause/ the other 'effect': this is false. The first has nothing to effect,
the second has been effected by nothing. It is a question of a struggle
between two elements of unequal power: a new arrangement of
forces is achieved according to the measure of power of each of
them. The second condition is something fundamentally different
from the first (not its effect): the essential thing is that the factions in
struggle emerge with different quanta of power/'59
3. The relation between forces in each moment of their conflict is
governed by a "principle of the better," in which is grounded the
deterministic conclusion of each event in nature. The resultant of
this dynamic conflict is only aleatory from the perspective of each of
the forces present. Taken together, as the copossibility of a multiple, this perspective is absolutely necessary as each force, in its
essential instantaneity, extracts its final consequence from each
instant and so reaches its maximum power. As such, the necessity of
the physical event does not result in any conformity to universal laws
(which would mean that its essence would have to depend on a
transcendent instance), nor the inclusion of each event on the
wheel of Eternal Return. This necessity is now a process of internal
generation. "I take good care not to talk of chemical 'laws': that has
a moral aftertaste. It is rather a matter of the absolute establishment
of power relations: the stronger becomes master of the weaker to
the extent that the weaker cannot assert its degree of autonomy here there is no mercy, no forbearance, even less a respect for
'laws'!"60 Nietzsche adopts a localizing and instantaneous conception of determinism "There is no law: every power at every moment
draws its ultimate conclusion. It is precisely on the lack of a mezzo
termine that calculability rests."61
It is important to underline that these three dynamic principles upon
which Nietzsche would construct his doctrine of the will to power
127
presuppose a fundamental duality between the perspective of each individual will and that of the regulated relation of the multiplicity of wills in
conflict in each local morphology. From the perspective of singularity,
each will is radically unconditioned, spontaneous, and represents the pure
impulse, endowed by a free determination, of an immanent finality and
the struggle for the infinite increase of power. From the general perspective of morphology the resultant is always determined. Nietzsche's
problem is in conciliating this duality of perspectives while maintaining the
instantaneity of the will as a principle. They cannot be considered two
distinct moments, one in which the individual will begins to act in
unconditioned fashion and the other in which it achieves a regulated
resultant in the context of copossibility. It was precisely to solve this problem that Nietzsche established the difference between the concepts of will
and power.62 The first represents the interior and unconditioned face of
force while the second is the resultant in the context of local copossibility.
With the doctrine of the will to power, Nietzsche constructs a representation of action as pure present and complete in each instant without
requiring the instant to be derived from a temporal conception or from
any representation of a cosmological totality. Significantly, this doctrine
appears for the first time in 1886 in Beyond Good and Evil. There, in
aphorism 22 Nietzsche writes:
'nature's conformity to law/ of which you physicists talk so proudly, as
though - why, it exists only owing to your interpretation and bad
'philology' ... and somebody might come along who, with opposite
intentions and modes of interpretation, could read out of the same
'nature,' and with regard to the same phenomenon, rather the
tyrannically inconsiderate and relentless enforcement of claims of power
... but he might, nevertheless, end by asserting the same about this
world as you do, namely, that it has a 'necessary' and 'calculable' course,
not because laws obtain in it, but because they are absolutely lacking, and
every power draws its ultimate consequences at every moment.63
It is hardly strange, therefore, that in this same work, in the very next
aphorism, Nietzsche announces the creation of a new discipline: the
"morphology and the doctrine of the development of the will to power."64 This is
also the first book in which the idea of Eternal Return is entirely absent.
128
129
130
Now, morality protected life from despair and from the plunge into
nothingness for those men and classes who were violated and oppressed
by men: for powerlessness against men, not powerlessness against nature,
is what engenders the most desperate bitterness against existence.
Morality treated the despots, the men of violence, the "masters" in
general, as the enemies against whom the common man must be protected, i.e., first of all encouraged, strengthened. Consequently, morality
taught the deepest hatred and contempt for what is the rulers' fundamental trait: their will to power.
It is no longer powerlessness against nature and its essential temporality as Zarathustra had claimed - but powerlessness against men that provokes the
more desperate revolt against existence and which excites the moral
response. As Nietzsche tirelessly affirms in the Second and Third Essays of
The Genealogy of Morals, the result is a highly determined interpretation of
the relations of power that constitute every event. It is the weaker wills,
those who are violated and oppressed in relations of power, who give rise
to morality as a way of warding off their own despair.
Nietzsche's morphology of the will to power will eventually come to
reconfigure the typology of wills underlying the phenomenology of time
that was delineated in Thus Spoke Zarathustra. While in the earlier book this
typology was founded, as we have seen, on temporal categories and on the
opposition between remorse and nostalgia, now it is exclusively "physiological." However, here too it is essentially dualistic. Nietzsche considers
just two types: the "unfortunate" (die schlechtweggekommen) and the
"stronger ones" (die Stdrksten). The first are characterized by "the will to
destruction as the will of a still deeper instinct, the instinct for selfdestruction, the will into nothingness [des Willens ins Nichts]." The interpretation of the morality of existence is pursued only by the "unfortunate";
it is a form of self-justification, a way for them to transcend their "nihilizing" will. Opposed to them are the "stronger ones." They are defined
by Nietzsche in the following terms, as "The most moderate, those who
have no need of extreme articles of faith, who not only concede but even
love a good deal of contingency and nonsense, who can think of a man
with a considerable moderation of his value and not therefore become
small and weak: the richest in health, who are equal to the most misfortunes and therefore less afraid of misfortune"71 The overcoming of
morality does not demand that man be transfigured. It effects the selfperishing of those who engender morality and who find only there a
justification for their inferiority, for their "no" to existence. While in Thus
Spoke Zarathustra the overcoming of morality and the transformation
towards the over-human implies the adherence to an article of extreme
faith - the idea of the eternal repetition of the same - now the contrary is
131
132
The genius - but, perhaps for this reason, the great equivocation - of
Nietzsche's reading of the European cultural condition at the end of the
nineteenth century, consists in the fact that he condenses a multiplicity of
symptoms of the crisis of the models of rationality inherited from modernity in the figure of a single and decisive event: the advent of nihilism.
For Nietzsche, phenomena such as aesthetic romanticism, the success of
the mechanistic paradigm of the life sciences, philosophical pessimism or
the emergence of European socialist movements are hardly seen as timely
attempts by the West at internal reformulations of models of aesthetic,
epistemological, moral or political legitimization, but moments in a process of an absolute exhaustion of the possibility itself of legitimization in
general. This devaluation of all values and the radical loss of foundation is,
according to Nietzsche, not only a necessary process, but an irreversible
one. Nietzsche views this as an extreme consequence of the bankruptcy of
the very models of legitimization themselves.
Nihilism would encompass European consciousness in an inescapable
paradox: that of living in a moment ulterior to the dissolution of the
models of the legitimization of values, upon which it itself had been
constructed, without, however, the means to consider such an epochal
position as an expression of a privilege, as this would presuppose that the
final basis of such models still existed: notions of conscience, progress,
and overcoming.
Nietzsche presents the doctrine of nihilism as a description and, at the
same time, as a practical accomplishment of the exhaustion of this process
of delegitimization of Western values. Nihilism thus becomes the tide of a
general interpretation of Western culture and a political and aesthetical
manifesto for the subsequent centuries.
As historical narrative, the doctrine of nihilism is built upon the model
of negative dialectics. According to Nietzsche the decadence of values
originated with the earliest taking of positions in the West. It was with
Socratic ethics (and Christianity's reclamation of them) that, in the name
of equating happiness with knowledge, the foundations of civilization in
Art had shifted to foundations based on Knowledge. Ever since, life had
become the victim of reason with its self-destructive logic. Ironically,
134
Nietzsche fails to free himself from the fascination for historicism that he
so lucidly denounces in the second Untimely Meditation. To the extent that
he tries to describe nihilism as a unique event, it was impossible for his
reading of the West to avoid maintaining as well some of the logical
awkwardness to which the great nineteenth-century philosophies of history
had succumbed. Nietzsche was the victim of an excessive appreciation for
Hegelianism. He believes he can break with historicism simply by rejecting
the categories of progress and overcoming.
It was with this inverted Hegelianism that Nietzsche most clearly manifested himself, not only in his role as the son of his century, but as a
representative of the central categories of a culture against which he
would position himself. Indeed, more than a particular concept, the
notion of decadence is the historical and moral category par excellence by
which the West read the origin of its destiny. It was always as "a fall," or a
"period of degeneracy," that each epoch or people described their particular epochal place. Hesiod's myth of the five ages, upon which the
Greek tradition was built, is, in this respect, as eloquent as it is decisive in
the construction of the West's historical consciousness.
Nevertheless, it would be an error to reduce the doctrine of nihilism to a
negative teleology. Nietzsche's attachment to the category of decadence is
not exhausted simply in the inversion of the illuminist idea of "progress."
On the contrary, the very genesis of this doctrine derives from a fundamental reformulation of the notion of "decadence" as a historical category. From 1886 onwards (the year that marks the beginning of
Nietzsche's systematic reflection on the logic of self-dissolution of Western
values) the concept of "decadence" takes on a primordially anthropological meaning. Decadence designates, not the result of an historical
process, but the characterization of a determined psychological line. As
Nietzsche declares in The Twilight of the Idols:. "To choose what is harmful
to oneself, to be attracted by 'disinterested' motives, almost constitutes the
formula for decadence."1 This mutation of meaning, the shift from an
historical category to an anthropological one, with its adoption of
expressions such as decadence and decadent, which are inherited from the
more conceptual tradition of the French "psychologists" Taine and
Bourget, led Nietzsche to a different appreciation of the fundamental
evolution of the culture of his period. Decadence had nothing to do with a
logic of the development of humanity, or with a situation of minority when
faced with its origin. It should be seen more in the sense invoked by the
tide of Freud's famous work, Civilization and its Discontents, and the fact
that humanity had adopted values that were contrary to its self-affirmation,
which is to say, typologically "decadent" values. As such, the situation of
crisis in which humanity has put itself, by the bankruptcy of these same
values, seems, paradoxically, to be an expression of some new vigour, of
135
some vital growth. "The concept of decadence. - Waste, decay, elimination need not be condemned: they are necessary consequences of life, of
the growth of life. The phenomenon of decadence is as necessary as any
increase and advance of life: one is in no position to abolish it. Reason
demands, on the contrary, that we do justice to it."2 It is precisely to
designate the fundamental ambivalence in the process of the dissolution
of decadent values, for which the concept of decadence as an historical
category is no longer useful, that Nietzsche adopts, starting in 1886, the
concept of nihilism.
Nietzsche's reading of the genealogy of nihilism is constructed upon the
model of a negative dialectic. This is no longer the case in terms of the way
Nietzsche considers the possibility of overcoming nihilism. The devaluation of all values does not correspond to a single moment of determined
negativity that would permit, in and of itself, the dialectical construction of
a new basis, a new ground for new values. What it does do is to put
humanity in a situation of insecurity and essential danger. The West had
already experienced a similar internal dissolution of its axiological models.
But this undoing, instead of being translated into new modes of existence,
led to a worsening of decadence. According to Nietzsche, that was the
most decisive lesson of the Renaissance. In its excess, the culture of Dante
and Machiavelli had finally reached the point of a total reversal of
Christian morals. As Nietzsche says in The Antichrist, "Cesare Borgia as Pope
... Do you understand me? ... with this, Christianity was abolished! - What
happened? A German monk, Luther, came to Rome. This monk whose
body had all the vindictive instincts of a wounded priest, flew into a rage in
Rome against the Renaissance ... Instead of feeling the most profound
gratitude at the scale of what had taken place, the fact that Christianity
had been overcome at its source."3 The nihilist condition that, according
to Nietzsche, characterizes the culture of the end of the nineteenth century, corresponds, in its fundamental ambiguity, to a second "chance" for
decadence. Its essential feature is the result of the fact that European
consciousness is, for the first time, confronted with not only the selfdissolution of Christian morals, but with the bankruptcy of all ethical
categories which had found their paradigm in Christian morality.
This is why it was so important to prevent the repetition of that process
of a mere axiological overcoming of decadence which asphyxiated the
world of possibilities opened by the Italian Renaissance. The paradox
which constitutes the nihilistic condition of our modernity cannot be
simply dissolved or got around by the recuperation of values whose
bankruptcy is at the very root of its origin. It has to be experienced in its
essence. "Why is the advent of nihilism now so necessary? It is because that
is where our very own values have found their final moment, because
nihilism is the logic of our highest values and ideas pushed to the extreme,
136
137
who have no need of extreme dogmas, those who not only concede but love
a good measure of chance and nonsense, those who can conceive of man
with a significant reduction in his value without thereby becoming small
and weak: the richest in health who can cope with the most misfortunes
and so have no great fear of misfortunes - men who are sure of their power
and represent with conscious pride the achievement of human strength"
(15). This text allows us to understand to what extent the Nazi recuperation of the ideal of the superior man was only made possible by sacrificing one of the profoundest ethical and anthropological theses of the
doctrine of the will to power. The European Nihilism confronts us, then, with
the theoretical nucleus of Nietzsche's final philosophy.
In spite of having been written exactly one century ago and of having
been the object of many editions, the text of The European Nihilism is
presented in the Colli and Montinari edition of 1980 in novel fashion. The
fact is that the history of the publication of Nietzsche's notebooks is
anything but happy. The complete version of this fragment was only
published once in the princeps edition (1901) of Nietzsche's posthumous
work, a work which, with its miscast title The Will to Power (Der Wille zur
Macht}, contained only 483 texts extracted from the notebooks. All later
editions, including the octavo edition of 1911, since then considered to be
the canonical version, derived from the "pocket edition" of 1906 (which
compiles, under the same title, 1067 fragments, and which, just as the first
one, was under the direction of Peter Cast and Elisabeth ForesterNietzsche), present The European Nihilism in four distinct fragments. The
first paragraph of the original version there corresponds to the 4th fragment, the second to the 5th, and the third to the 114th. Finally, the 4th
through the 16th correspond to the 55th. This adulteration cannot but
gravely compromise the intelligibility of this text. Not only because it
divides it into four false fragments, but it also inserts them into different
chapters of book I of this artificial work, known as The Will to Power. In this
particular editorial arrangement The European Nihilism loses the central
line of its argument and thus all that gives it its unique character, which is
the fact that it is the most systematic text ever written by Nietzsche about
the genealogy of nihilism.
It is only the recent critical edition, directed by the Italians Giorgio Colli
and Mazzino Montinari (1967), which has restored, with all due rigour,
The European Nihilism to its original format, just as Nietzsche had written it
on 10 June, 1887. We can therefore say that it has only been for a dozen
years that we have had access to this important document on the Nietzschean conception of Western civilizational decadence.
It is also important to underline that, as well as a philological reconstitution, the Colli and Montinari edition, by adopting a strictly chronological criterion for the organization of Nietzsche's works and, therefore,
138
giving us the chance to understand the place this text occupies in the
evolution of Nietzsche's thought, brings a new intelligibility to The European Nihilism. In fact, in light of this new edition, the Lenzer Heide text
can now be seen as a decisive moment in the formulation of Nietzsche's
final philosophy. It is an authentic turning point: it closes a cycle in his
work (which has at its centre the idea of Eternal Return) and initiates
another (that which is oriented by the doctrine of the will to power). Thus,
we understand today that this text, in which the idea of an infinite repetition is presented for the first time as the consequence of the logic itself
of the devaluation of the values produced by Christian morality, chronologically marks the definitive disappearance of the idea of Eternal Return
from Nietzsche's published works. While The Gay Science, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, and Beyond Good and Evil, that is, all works after 1881, display the
idea of a cyclical repetition of all events, The Genealogy of Morals, written
immediately following the stay in Lenzer Heide, as well as all the works
which are posterior to it, never again refer to this circular representation
of time, or, if they do, as in the case of Twilight of the Idols or Ecce Homo, it is
in a purely autobiographical context (when he refers to himself, he does
so with the designation he that taught Eternal Recurrence). Looked at
chronologically, The European Nihilism displays therefore a surprising isomorphism between its content and the place that it occupies in the evolution of Nietzsche's philosophy, that is, between, on one hand, the
theoretical gesture by which Nietzsche disengages himself from the idea of
the Eternal Recurrence and, on the other, the effective disappearance of
this same idea from the body of his texts.
Its '"typological" interpretation of the origin of value judgments also
marks the Lenzer Heide text as a turning point. This interpretation is to
be found in 9-15, which anticipate (though schematically) the principal
theses of The Genealogy of Morals. Here, for the first time, Nietzsche abandons that which we could call the ' "existential perspective" that oriented
his earlier works. The interpretation of action as a moral phenomenon no
longer results in a revolt against the essential temporality of human existence, as it did in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, nor in an illusion about the true
dimension of the will, as happened in Beyond Good and Evil. Now it is
merely an expression of a determined type of will. As Nietzsche affirms in
9 of the Lenzer Heide text, it is "the abused and oppressed classes of
men" who need morals, not only as a way to protect themselves "from
despair and the leap into nothingness" but as well as a weapon against the
"the powerful, the violent, the 'master' in general." We know the
importance that this typological conception of morality attains in The
Genealogy of Morals, it forms a basis there for the thesis on the reactive
origin of moral judgments as expression of the inversion of values on the
part of those who are "oppressed." In addition to this thematic
139
140
from despising himself as man, from taking against life, from despairing of
knowing [Erkennen]: it was a means of preservation" (1). He concludes this
first paragraph with the seemingly strange thesis "in sum: morality was the
great antidote against practical and theoretical nihilism." Nihilism is for
the first time conceived, not as an event of culture, not as the effect of the
irreversible dissolution of values, of practices and of interpretations, but as
a pure and primordial fact of existence as such. What Nietzsche calls
"practical and theoretical nihilism" would be inherent in the contingency
of life and of death; it would be the purest non-meaning of individual and
collective existence taken as whole. And morality, with its fictions and
values, its categories of truth and necessity, would be the principal
"antidote" against this absolute nothingness, against this primordial
nihilism.
The question confronting Nietzsche in the interior of this narrative is
that which has to do with the origin of a consciousness in revolt, and also
with the beginning of an understanding of a world and of man who says
"no" to life. If morals are, in their essence, an affirmation, an antidote
against despair and nothingness, from whence the negation, whence the
"no" to life and life's joys? Here Nietzsche also reformulates his diagnosis
put forth in Thus Spoke Zarathustra. The "no" to life is not evidence of a
moral interpretation of existence but, paradoxically, the effect of the
dissolution of this moral interpretation. The revolt is the consequence of
the dialectic of knowledge itself, or better, of the dimension of the truth
that all of fiction is based on.
In these first four paragraphs - which condense the epistemological
narrative - Nietzsche locates the inversion of the "yes" directly in the
sphere of values and their mechanisms of voluntary falsification. This
inversion is seen as a corollary to morality itself (to the principle of truth)
that, in questioning the basis for value judgments, had led to the discovery
of their origin in illusion. "But among the forces nurtured by morality was
truthfulness: this ultimately turns on morality, discovers its teleology, the
partiality of its viewpoint - and now the insight into this long-ingrained
mendacity, which one despairs of throwing off, acts precisely as a stimulus.
To nihilism" (2). The bankruptcy of this morality would thus be inscribed
in its own originating logic, in the antagonism between life and truth.
"This antagonism - not valuing what we know [erkennen], and no longer
being permitted to value what we would like to hoodwink ourselves with results in a disintegration process" (2).
Nietzsche therefore distinguishes two types of nihilism. That which he
calls the "first nihilism," is inherent to the very condition of existence and
its lack of meaning. The "second nihilism" is simply the consequence of
the self-dissolution of the strategies of resistance, of the sabotaging of that
antidote to the first nihilism, to wit morals. Its main characteristic is the
141
142
the same with freeing the will from this "spirit of vengeance." But within
the framework of Thus Spoke Zarathustra, this was only made possible by the
idea of the Eternal Recurrence. Via the infinite recurrence of each element of universal existence, nature revealed itself as the redeemer of
nature, redeemer of this "impotency" before the "this was," before time.
This is because morality was conceived as a consequence of the essential
feature of nature and time; the overcoming of morality imposed new
metaphors of the world and of time. And freeing the world of time itself,
freeing nature from its irrevocable temporality, was to free man from
himself, from his too-human nature, that is, from being condemned by
time - creating the over-man. And this new poetics, this vision of a new
experience of time, could only be declared in the context of prophecy, by
a gospel brought to men by someone beyond men and the gods, someone
like Zarathustra.
This is precisely the interpretation that the Lenzer Heide text abandons.
In 1887 Nietzsche comes to see that morality, in its sense of a revolt against
life, originates not in some impotency before nature, but in an impotency
before men. This change in perspective brings two fundamental consequences in its wake. The first is that morality is no longer an expression
of the human condition, it is no longer inscribed in the nature of the will
as a whole, but rather merely characterizes certain wills, infecting only
those men, those "people and classes who were violated and oppressed by
people." Morality therefore is the expression of a type of will. The second
consequence has to do with the object of revolt. Because it is only the
people who are violated and oppressed by other people who are driven to
revolt, their "spirit of vengeance" does not target life as a whole, or nature
as a temporal condition. The revolt, in the first instance, is against those
who oppress them. Morality is that interpretation which makes out of
affirmative people contemptible beings, which transforms those who are
the holders of power into enemies of humanity. It is only in this sense that
morality is converted into a general condemnation of nature, as a condemnation of the most intimate essence of everything that exists. In
condemning those who hold power, the violated and oppressed condemn
that which runs deepest in all of life: the tendency toward domination, the
will to power. As Nietzsche says: "Morality has treated the powerful, the
violent, the 'masters' in general as the enemies against whom the common
man must be protected, i.e., first of all encouraged, strengthened. Consequently morality has taught to hate and despise most profoundly what is the
fundamental characteristic of the rulers: their will to power" (9).
This new characterization of the origin of the morality is the same which
will come to organize The Genealogy of Morals, which Nietzsche begins
shortly after 10 June, 1887 and which would be sent to his publisher a
mere six weeks later. There we will find two absolutely new strategies. On
143
the one hand, Nietzsche seeks to explain the appearance of morality via a
description of a certain type of will: that of the weak, of the slaves, of the
oppressed. Morality is thus explained not by the "spirit of vengeance" which would target time and its "was" - but by "resentment" - which aims
to infect strong wills, the holders of power, with guilt. On the other hand,
the overcoming of morality no longer presumes a new cosmology, or a new
poetics of time and its eternal recurrence. This is why the idea of Eternal
Recurrence is completely absent from The Genealogy of Morals - as it will be
absent from all of the other books which Nietzsche will publish after 1887.
The destruction of the conditions for the possibility of morality now turns
to the presentation of the features that define the holders of power as
representative of those of the whole of will, of all living beings, in a word, it
now turns to the demonstration of the fact that everything is "Will to
Power."
The whole of this programme is announced in 9 of the Lenzer Heide
text:
To abolish, deny, break down this morality: that would mean providing
the most hated drive with an apposite sensation and evaluation. If the
sufferer, the oppressed man lost his belief in having a right to his contempt
for the will to power, he would enter the stage of hopeless desperation.
This would be the case if this trait were essential to life, if it turned out
that even that 'will to morality' was just concealing this 'will to power/
that even that hatred and contempt is still a power-will [Machwilk]. The
oppressed man would realize that he is in the same boat as the oppressor
and that he has no prerogative over him, no higher status than him.
The programme for the erosion of morality is essentially theoretical. The
battle against oppressed wills is worked out on a plane of representations
of the world, on a plane of beliefs. As Nietzsche says: "If the sufferer, the
oppressed man lost his belief in having a right to his contempt for the will to
power, he would enter the stage of hopeless desperation." And this
dimension of belief is underlined in 10: "Provided that the belief in this
morality collapses, those who turned out badly would no longer have their
consolation - and they would perish." This would be possible by demonstrating to the victim and to the oppressed that even their revolt against
the holders of power testifies to the hidden presence of the will to power,
which constitutes their own fundamental motivation. If, in Thus Spoke
Zarathustra, the new gospel brought with it the revelation of the Eternal
Return, in The Genealogy of Morals what is displayed - not revealed - is the
decisive argument against all moral belief: the world as will to power.
Yet, also within the typological narrative, the Lenzer Heide text maintains a dialectical understanding of this process of moral erosion. It is as
144
145
epistemological and typological are different as well in the way in which they
evaluate the constitutive ambivalence of the crisis produced by the bankruptcy of previous value judgments. The first aligns itself with a historicist
perspective. By identifying the logic of nihilism with the logic of knowledge, the dissolution of morals ends up by emerging as an expression of
progress, as a consequence of the development of a specific rationality,
not only critical but technical as well. The power with which critical reason
targets morality, with the sole aim of denouncing the falsity of its foundations, would be thus merely a corollary of the domination achieved by
technical reason over nature. According to Nietzsche it was this domination - which brought man greater confidence in his own power and destiny - that precluded the necessity for the foundation of the morals of
human existence. "In fact we no longer need an antidote against first
nihilism so much: life is no longer so uncertain, contingent, senseless in
our Europe. Such an immense multiplication of the value of man, of the
value of evil etc. is not so necessary now; we can stand a significant reduction
in this value and concede a good deal of nonsense and chance: the power
that man has achieved now permits a reduction in the disciplinary measures, of which the moral interpretation was the strongest. 'God' is much
too extreme a hypothesis" (3). Even if life is deprived of morality - with
the consequent loss of its metaphysical basis - the fact itself of being able
to dispense with morality is a sign of new vigour. Herein resides (in
accordance with the epistemological perspective) the ambiguity of the
nihilism of modernity. This is why a bankruptcy of values is not simply a
"collapse," or "degeneration," but a necessary event in the affirmation of
life. It is the specifically negative character, essential to the fundamental
recuperation of life, which lends nihilism its status as a negative dialectic
that comes very close to being an eschatology.
It is actually this understanding of a "dialectic" of the European cultural malaise that is present in the typological paradigm, even if, because of
the fact that it is formulated upon different postulates, its historical significance is questionable. Paragraph 14 affirms the "purifying" importance of the moral crisis. It is just that, here, it is not life in its entirety, or
Man, who come out strengthened by the crisis. The categories of "life" or
"humanity," which structure the epistemological narrative, do not play any
role here. "Purification" is now conceived as a process which internally
fractures life itself, which produces hierarchical effects among men. It
comes down to being a selection among powers, leading to the decay of
"the kind of people and classes who were violated and oppressed by people," and, in counterpoint, elevating the "strongest." The destruction of
morality based on a will to nothingness destroys the unfortunate themselves, "those who turned out badly" since they are only able to legitimize
their existence within the ambit of morality. "Nihilism as a symptom of the
146
fact that those who turned out badly have no consolation left: that they
destroy in order to be destroyed, that, relieved of morality, they no longer
have any reason to 'surrender themselves'" (12). Contrary to this, only
the ones who have no need of belief, no need of dogmas about the
absolute value of man, will be elevated by this crisis. "Who will prove to be
the strongest in this? The most moderate, those who have no need of
extreme dogmas, those who not only concede but love a good measure of
chance and nonsense, those who can conceive of man with a significant
reduction in his value without thereby becoming small and weak: the
richest in health who can cope with the most misfortunes and so have no
great fear of misfortunes - men who are sure of their power and represent
with conscious pride the achievement of human strength" (15). Because
they "are sure of their power," those who love chance and nonsense will
be prepared to resist the decay of morality and to reveal themselves as the
strongest. As such, since morality is no longer the expression of one of
life's necessities, the moral crisis has nothing to do with life in general, but
merely serves to close the cycle of reactive morality and, with it, to condemn the dissolution of the weak wills to which it had given rise.
The typological perspective also conceives the process of self-dissolution
of values as a moment of necessary negativity within a negative teleology.
By representing the destruction, not as the exhaustion of a determined
logic, but as the consequence of a "will to nothingness," negativity itself is
no longer just an abstract moment of the dialectic of morality, but takes on
an empirical dimension. Negativity embodies itself in the "those who turned
out badly." That is why only their true disappearance will allow for the
overcoming of negation and lead toward the exhaustion of morals. This is
where the negative dialectic of nihilism acquires a strangely selective
meaning, a strangely apocalyptic dimension.
Faced with this huge disparity in the views of nihilism we can perhaps
better understand what it was that actually led the editors of the fictitious
work, The Will to Power, to break up the text of The European Nihilism, which
we have discussed above. It was all about trying to erase its fundamental
contradiction. By separating the four first paragraphs from each other,
Nietzsche's sister and Peter Cast caused the epistemological narrative to
disappear; on the other hand, by beginning the rest of the text with 4,
they created the illusion of homogeneity between the culminating
moment in the epistemological narrative - the idea of the Eternal Recurrence - and the whole of the typological narrative. We do not know if this
was done deliberately, or simply in order to maintain consistency; we only
know that the result was, on one hand, the dissolution of the contradiction
between the epistemological perspective and the typology of nihilism
through the cancellation of the textual duality via which it was revealed,
147
and, on other hand, the promotion of the idea of the Eternal Recurrence
as the culminating topic of Nietzsche's reading of nihilism.
But the contradictions in Nietzsche must be understood and not artificially dissolved. It is an undeniable fact that, given the way in which these
contradictions are included in the June 1887 text, he conceived of the two
perspectives on nihilism, if not as univocals, at least as convergences.
Understanding this text implies understanding how those narratives could
occur to Nietzsche as unified.
It is our view that producing this unity would have been the function of
that which we can consider the third of these narratives of nihilism present
in the Lenzer Heide text. This can be found in 5-8, and has at its centre
the idea of the Eternal Recurrence. In these paragraphs Nietzsche seems to
set out his "metaphysics," that is, his thesis on the condition of the possibility for a non-moral meaning of existence. As such, this metaphysical
narrative appears to be the positive opposite of the other two. Both the epistemological perspective and thetypologicalface the question of the meaning
of existence solely from the logic of its exhaustion. They try to describe the
process of the conversion of the theological thesis (according to which
everything has a basis, that is, is part of a creator's plan, including evil) into
the thesis of nihilism, or of the absolute absence of basis, of a total "in
vain." They are therefore framed negatively according to their dialectic. Yet
the function of the idea of the Eternal Recurrence seems, on the contrary,
to permit the revelation of existence as positive, as an absolute fact, beyond
the absence of all interpretations, all moral beliefs. Nevertheless, it is
important to underline the fact that the revelation of the positive fact of a
senseless existence is not the result of a simple negation of moral sense.
Nietzsche does not limit himself to opposing a new interpretation of the
world to the bankruptcy of all previous interpretations - which would be to
ignore the truth and the historical breadth of the phenomenon of nihilism.
The overcoming of nihilism, the overcoming of the belief that everything is
"in vain," will have to be achieved on the basis of maximization, of an
absolute furthering of the process itself of the bankruptcy of all interpretations. The decisive importance that Nietzsche attributes to the idea of
the Eternal Recurrence is precisely the result of this cosmological idea
being a representation of a radically silent, unspoken world, that is, of its
being the most "paralyzing" negation of the meaning of existence because
of the denial of all finality. Paragraphs 5 and 6, which deliberate over the
terminal moments of the mockery of knowledge, present the idea of the
Eternal Recurrence as the terminal point in this process. "Let us think this
thought in its most terrible form: existence as it is, without sense or aim,
but inevitably returning, without a finale in nothingness: 'the eternal
return.' This is the most extreme form of nihilism: nothingness (the
'senseless') eternally! [das Nichts (das 'Sinnlose9) ewig]. European form of
148
Buddhism: energy of knowledge [ Wissen] and strength forces one into such
a belief. It is the most scientific of all possible hypotheses. We deny final
goals: if existence had one, it would have to have been reached" (6). The
idea of the Eternal Recurrence thus terminates, according to the epistemological perspective, Christian morality in and of itself: if Christianity
depends upon an eschatological representation of the world, the thesis of
the infinite cycle undermines its roots at their profoundest
The Eternal Recurrence plays an identical role in creating the effect of
mockery in the typological narrative. The representation of an Eternal
Recurrence of all things is also seen as the final moment in the bankruptcy
of morality, although here, as one would expect, the impact is selective. It
is the unfortunate, the oppressed man, Nietzsche tells us in 14, who will
face the Eternal Recurrence as the ultimate form of self-destruction. "The
unhealthiest kind of man in Europe (of all classes) is the ground of this
nihilism: they will feel that belief in the eternal recurrence is a curse which,
once you are struck by it, makes you no longer baulk at any action; not
being passively extinguished, but making everything that is so senseless and
aimless be extinguished: although it is only a spasm, a blind rage on
realizing that everything has existed for eternities - including this moment
of nihilism and lust for destruction." The oppressed man will then try to
destroy everything that is revealed in this idea to be meaningless and
endless, including his own existence.
It is now necessary to raise the important question. Beyond its appalling
and despair-inspiring significance, does the idea of the Eternal Recurrence contain within it some redemptive importance? Is there some
dimension - cosmological, ethical, or aesthetic - in the idea of infinite
recurrence that might lead to a will beyond the will to destruction? Where
is the affirmative face of this idea in which Nietzsche now discovers the
final chapter in the story of the will in revolt?
Such ambivalence, such a fusion between an abyssal, negative interpretation and an affirmation of the infinite was, as we have seen, the
nucleus of the ethical impact of the idea of the Eternal Recurrence, as
much in The Gay Science as in Thus Spoke Zarathustra. The idea was always
presented there as the condition of something that imposed a decision,
that obliged a radical cut between significations. In 1883, in The Gay Science, it took the form of a demon that had invaded our midnight dreams.
In 1884, in Zarathustra's words, it appeared as an enigma, as an image
that needed to be deciphered, not because it was obscure, vague or
indeterminate, but because it demanded a decision be made, a choice
between the Dwarfs perspective, for whom time was circular and everything was equal, and the shepherd's perspective, who had cut off the head
of the serpent of time and laughed before the eternity of each instant. In
all of his writings on the Eternal Recurrence Nietzsche explores this
149
150
finale in nothingness" lead not to nothingness, but rather to the liberation of an absolute "yes"?
A first reading of the text leaves us with the impression that it is the idea
of the Eternal Recurrence that, by itself alone, can force a second inversion: the negation of a model of meaning in favour of affirming a new
paradigm which it alone, through its formulation, can reveal - the concept
of a meaning as absolute immanence, that is, with the immediate coincidence of each event with its own essence as pure act. The idea of the
Eternal Recurrence would thus absorb all of transcendence, even in its
most insignificant immanencies - each instant - thereby revealing the
source of the meaning of existence.
Apparently, this is the meaning that comes out of paragraph 7.
Nietzsche asks: "If we remove finality from the process, can we nevertheless
still affirm the process? This would be the case if something within that
process were being achieved at its every moment - and always the same"
(7). The impression is given here that Nietzsche is describing the affirmative face of the idea of the Eternal Return. The nihilist version could be
reduced to the despair felt when facing the lack of any end whatsoever of
the whole of the cosmological process. The affirmative version will consist
in, in spite of this, accepting this process. The "yes" to this process would
only require that we presuppose "something within that process were
being achieved at its every moment - and always the same." There seems to
be no doubt that this "something" within the process goes back to the
idea of the Eternal Return. It seems that only in the context of the idea of
the eternal repetition of all things can there exist something that is always
attained in each moment, and is "always the same." Indeed, conceiving
existence as infinite duration without an object or finality, the idea of
Eternal Return causes each instant to arise as an absolute immanence, as
the centre of time in its totality. Each moment in the process returns, not
to an origin or finality, but simply to a series of identical instants of which
it is the repetition. Each event is a pure act, an absolute coincidence
between itself and its essence. The instant is no longer a mark of the
ephemeralness of human existence "in the flux of becoming and passing
away" (1), but has been converted into a basis for itself and for the
totality of becoming.
However, a more attentive reading of the Lenzer Heide text will completely subvert this interpretation. Nowhere does Nietzsche ever say that it
is the idea of the Eternal Recurrence that contains the "yes" to each
moment of the process. On the contrary, he shows that such a "yes" had
already been enunciated at a certain moment in the history of ideas - and
quite independently of the idea of the Eternal Recurrence. Let us look
once again at the previously cited passage: "If we remove finality from the
process, can we nevertheless still affirm the process? - This would be the case
151
if something within that process were being achieved at its every moment and always the same. Spinoza reached such an affirmative position, to the
extent that every moment has a logical necessity: and with the logicality of
his fundamental instinct he was triumphant that the world was constituted
in such a manner" (7). The "yes" to each moment in the process, in spite
of there being no finality for the whole, had already been formulated by
Spinoza. Spinoza inverted the concept of meaning by absorbing it within
existence itself. In affirming a metaphysical likeness between the essence
of each of the existents in the univocality of God and his modes, Spinoza
would discover the immanent necessity of each event, the reason for its
being such as it is and not any other way. Spinoza was able to arrive at the
supreme position of saying "yes" to all things. However, Nietzsche considered the kind of affirmation arrived at by Spinoza too particular. "But
his case is just an individual case" (8). Nietzsche never recognized the
pantheism that supports this way of conceiving the immanent character of
the meaning of each event. The likeness between essence and existence,
according to Nietzsche, should be conceived, not as the singularity of the
whole and each of its modes, but as the univocality of each event in and of
itself, in the fullness of instants. The likeness between the thing and its
basis, beyond any teleology, is the likeness between that which each instant
wants to reach and the act of reaching it. Yet, is this notion that the idea of
the Eternal Recurrence is a representation of each instant still not too
pantheistic? To absolutely affirm the "something" that is reached within
the process and in each of its moments, which "is always the same," simply
because this "something" is integrated into the whole, because this
something belongs to an immense cycle of things and happenings, is this
not to say that it is one more experience of the divine, now cast in the
figure of an eternal whole? And yet, could we still say "yes" to each instant
of existence without adopting either Spinoza's model of pantheist univocality, or the idea of the Eternal Recurrence?
What is most revealing in the Lenzer Heide text is that this is precisely
what Nietzsche does do. Let us go back to that moment in which Spinoza's
"yes" is invoked:
Spinoza reached such an affirmative position, to the extent that every
moment has a logical necessity: and with the logicality of his fundamental instinct he was triumphant that the world was constituted in such
a manner. But his case is just an individual case. Every fundamental
characteristic at the basis of every event, as expressed in every event, would
need to impel any individual who felt it was his fundamental characteristic to welcome triumphantly every moment of existence in general. It would need this fundamental characteristic in oneself to be felt
precisely as good, valuable, with pleasure (7,8).
152
Spinoza's response is too particular. And, as such, too artificial. It presupposes an immense conceptual machinery, a terribly complex ontological and teleological system. For Nietzsche this is completely unnecessary.
The "yes" that he now wants to express is much simpler. There are just
two necessary conditions: (a) the knowledge of what is fundamental in
each event, the knowledge of the essential structure of each moment in
progress; and (b) the feeling of pleasure provoked by this essential
"something" which underlies each event.
This is what comes across in paragraph 8. It is enough, in the first
instance, that each individual feels that his fundamental characteristic is
exactly that which underlies each event so that, if he feels this fundamental characteristic in himself as pleasure, as something good and
valuable, he will "welcome triumphantly every moment of existence in
general."
Where is the idea of the Eternal Recurrence in this "yes"? The individual triumphantly approves each instant of universal existence only if he
feels with pleasure, as good and valuable, the "fundamental characteristic" that underlies each moment. The great question of the Lenzer
Heide text therefore shifts from the idea of the Eternal Recurrence which is always presented as the final chapter of the history of nihilism - to
an understanding of what this "fundamental characteristic" might be.
And, directly in the second paragraph, where the narrative on the origin
of morality we have referred to as typological begins, Nietzsche explains
what the significance of this Grundcharakterzug is. Let us cite the passage
once again. "Consequently morality has taught to hate and despise most
profoundly what is the fundamental characteristic of the rulers [der
Grundcharakterzug der Herrschenden]: their will to power" (9). This is where
the theory of the will to power begins to constitute the basis for the new
"yes" to each moment of universal existence. The one who recognizes in
himself this manifestation of the will to power will be able to triumphantly
sanction each instant, affirm that "something," always the same, which is
produced in each moment of the process.
We will find as well that the theory of the will to power is not merely a
substitute for the idea of the Eternal Recurrence in its role as the idea that
forms a basis of the new "yes" to all things. It also takes on the status of a
truly decisive idea in terms of wills. The concept of the will to power, as the
fundamental characteristic that underlies each action and each event,
allows us to understand, in one and the same moment: (a) the origin of
morality, (b) the erosion of morality, and (c) the new "yes" to universal
existence. This simultaneity is the sense in which the will to power itself
contains, in its essence, the fundamental ambivalence of existence. It leads
as much to the invention of morality (as the revolt of the oppressed
against the holders of power), as it elevates affirmative wills to the
153
154
155
156
of the idea of the Eternal Recurrence. They are those who are "sure of
their power," that is, who recognize in each of their actions, and underlying each moment of their existence, this fundamental characteristic
which is their will to power. It is the doctrine of the will to power, and not
the idea of the Eternal Recurrence, which will come to explain the affirmative conclusions that are possible in the crisis of nihilism, that nihilism
which finds its end with the idea of the Eternal Recurrence. It is the
doctrine of the will to power that not only explains how morality arose in
the first place, but how the idea of the Eternal Return arose as a paradoxical consequence of morality, and, finally, that explains how the crisis
created from the appearance of nihilism - and, with it, the idea of the
Eternal Recurrence - creates another crisis internally, a process of the
cleansing of wills, freeing those stronger wills from the spirit of resentment
and directing them towards the affirmation of each event in universal
existence. It is only because these strong wills, these superior men - who
not only "concede but love a good measure of chance and nonsense" are raised to the level of conscious pride in their strength, that they are
able to affirm the whole of existence.
It should be clear how the doctrine of the Eternal Recurrence came to
subtly link various narratives of the genesis of non-sense. The analogous
status, which the idea of the Eternal Recurrence has in the epistemological
and the typological narrative, produces, between them, the appearance of
univocality. The epistemological narrative actually seems to serve as the
historical introduction to the typological; as though the logic of science
were nothing more than the development of a "will to nothingness."
Nietzsche leaves open the hypothesis that the dialectic of knowledge
might be the trap used by the will to destruction to orchestrate its own
demise via the curse that it itself produced.
In the ambivalence that structures The European Nihilism, it is the fundamental duality that runs through the doctrine of nihilism (the parallel
adoption of historicist and vitalist postulates) that, through the idea of the
Eternal Recurrence, finds a precarious overcoming. The final paragraph
reinforces this mechanism: "How would such a man think of the eternal
recurrence?" (16) asks Nietzsche.
For those men who will revel in the crisis of nihilism, like "the strongest," for those who "have no need of extreme dogmas" (15), what
would be the meaning of this idea of the exact repetition of all events and,
therefore, the repetition of the process of the crisis itself and its effects of
"cleansing?" Nietzsche does not respond. Nor does he have to respond.
The destiny of these stronger men no longer depends on the way in which
they conceive of the idea of the Eternal Recurrence, but solely on how they
feel, with pleasure and lust after, as though it were something of value, this
most "fundamental characteristic" which is their will to power. This is why
157
the idea of the Eternal Recurrence is left out of The Genealogy of Morals, and
of all other books after this text of 10 June, 1887. If Nietzsche refers to it
again, it is only as a biographical reference, as happens in Ecce Homo, when
he explains the genesis of Thus Spoke Zarathustra.
Shall we then continue to consider the idea of the Eternal Recurrence
as the culminating idea of Nietzsche's final philosophy, as the main subject of Nietzsche's late works?
Notes
Translator's Preface
1
The Birth of Tragedy: The Basic Writings of Nietzsche, edited and translated by
Walter Kaufmann, New York: Random House, 2000, p. 60. (Translator's note: I
wish to thank Filipe Ferreira for bibliographic assistance).
2
"Kant labored energetically to define the distinctive character of the aesthetic
domain. His point of departure here was the analysis of the judgment of taste,
which is certainly directed towards something subjective, namely the free play of
the imagination, but which manifests more than mere preference, being orientated rather towards intersubjective agreement. Although aesthetic objects belong
neither to the sphere of phenomena knowable by means of the categories of the
understanding, nor to the sphere of free acts subject to the legislation of practical
reason, works of art (and those of natural beauty) are accessible to objective judgment" ]. Habermas, "Die Moderne - ein unvollendetes Projekt" in Die Moderne ein unvollendetes Projekt. Philosophisch-folitischeAufsdtze, Reclam Verlag: Leipzig, 1990,
p. 44. English translation: "Modernity: An Unfinished Project" in Habermas and the
Unfinished Project of Modernity: Critical Essays on the Philosophical Discourse of Modernity,
ed. Maurizio Passerin d'Entreves and Seyla Benhabib, MIT Press: Cambridge,
Massachusetts, 1997. Habermas's references to the Kantian aesthetic occur regularly. For an overview of the connection between Habermas's programme of the
communication act and the aesthetic theory see Rainer Rochlitz, "De 1'expression
au sens. Perspectives Esthetiques chez Habermas" in Revue Internationale de Philosophie 4/1995, n. 194, pp. 405-435.
3
"[T]he aesthetic for him [Habermas] has remained an aesthetic of the
beautiful." Lyotard, "Response a la question: qu'est-ce que le postmoderne?" in
Critique, 419, April 1982, p. 365. (My translation.)
4
"In his Critique of Judgment Kant outlines, rapidly and almost without realizing
it, another solution to the problem of sublime painting. One cannot, he writes,
160
Notes
represent the power of infinite might or absolute magnitude within space and time
because they are pure Ideas. But one can at least allude to them, or 'evoke' them by
means of what he baptizes a 'negative presentation.* As an example of this paradox
of a representation which represents nothing, Kant cites Mosaic law which forbids
the making of graven images." J.F. Lyotard L'Inhumain, Galilee: Paris, 1988, p. 96.
English translation: The Inhuman: Reflections on Time, translated by Geoffrey Bennington and Rachel Bowlby, Polity Press: Cambridge, 1991, p. 85.
5
"This is only an indication, but it prefigures the Minimalist and abstractionist
solutions painting will use to try to escape the figurative prison." Ibid.
6
"Avant-garde art abandons the role of identification that the work previously
played in relation to the community of addressees. Even when conceived, as it was
by Kant, as a dejure horizon or presumption rather than a de facto reality, a sensus
communis (which, moreover, Kant refers to only when writing about beauty, not the
sublime) does not manage to achieve stability when it comes to interrogative works
of art." Lyotard, Ulnhumain, p. 115. English translation: p. 104. For a well-founded
discussion on the lack of a "sensus communis" in Kant associated with the sublime, see Paul Crowther, "The Kantian Sublime, the Avant Garde and the Postmodern: A Critique of Lyotard." New Formations, Spring 1989, 7: 67-75.
7
J. F. Lyotard and Jacob Rogozinski, L'Autre Journal, December 1985, p. 34. [My
translation.]
8
Lyotard, Ulnhumain, p. 149. English translation: p. 137.
9
Those interested in a more in-depth analysis of the debate between Lyotard
and Habermas can turn to a large body of literature. I would draw your attention to
the most important presentation of this theme, a work by Albrecht Wellmer, Zur
Dialektik von Modeme und Postmoderne nach Adorno, Suhrkamp Frankfurt am Main,
1988, as well as to the small book by Manfred Frank, Die Grenzen der Verstdndigung.
Ein Geistergesprdch zwischen Lyotard und Habermas, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main,
1988, and to an article by Richard Rorty, "Habermas, Lyotard et la Postmodernite"
in Critique no. 442, March 1984, pp. 181-197. Wellmer is available in English in:
"The Dialectic of Modernism and Postmodernism: The Critique of Reason since
Adorno" in The Persistence of Modernity: Essays on Aesthetics, Ethics and Postmodernism,
translated by David Midgley, Polity Press: Cambridge, 1991.
10
Critique of Judgment, translated by Werner S. Pluhar, Hackett Publishing
Company: Indianapolis, 1987, p. 159.
11
Ibid., p. 79.
12
Schiller, English translation: On the Aesthetic Education of Man: In a Series of
Letters, translated by Elizabeth M. Wilkinson and LA Willoughby, Clarendon Press:
Oxford, 1983, p. 215.
13
"It is, therefore, one of the most important tasks of education to subject man
to form even in his purely physical life, and to make him aesthetic in every domain
over which beauty is capable of extending her sway; since it is only out of the
aesthetic, not out of the physical state that the moral can develop. If man is, in
every single case, to possess the power of enlarging his judgment and his will into
the judgment of the species as a whole ... if he is to be fit and ready to raise himself
out of the restricted cycle of natural ends towards rational purposes, then he must
already have prepared himself for the latter within the limits of the former, and
Notes
161
have realized his physical destiny with a certain freedom of the spirit, that is, in
accordance with the laws of beauty." Schiller, ibid., p. 215. In another passage
Schiller goes on to affirm: "Though it may be his needs which drive man into
society, and reason which instils within him the principles of social behavior,
beauty alone can confer upon him a social character. Taste alone brings harmony
into society, because it fosters harmony in the individual. ... All other forms of
communication divide society, because they relate exclusively either to the private
receptivity or to the private proficiency of its individual members, hence to that
which distinguishes man from man; only the aesthetic mode of communication
unites society, because it relates to that which is common to all." Ibid.
14
J. Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, MIT Press: Cambridge,
Massachusetts, 1987, p. 45.
15
"Die Moderne - ein unvollendetes Projekt," p. 52. English translation: p. 53.
16
The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, p. 49.
17
"With Nietzsche's entrance into the discourse of modernity, the argument
shifts, from the ground up. To begin with, reason was conceived as a reconciling
self-knowledge, then as a liberating appropriation, and finally as a compensatory
remembrance, so that it could emerge as the equivalent for the unifying power of
religion and overcome the bipartitions of modernity by means of its own driving
forces. Three times this attempt to tailor the concept of reason to the programme
of an intrinsic dialectic of enlightenment miscarried. In the context of this constellation, Nietzsche had no choice but to submit subject-centred reason yet again
to an immanent critique - or to give up the programme entirely. Nietzsche opts for
the second alternative." The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, pp. 85-6.
18
The emblematic work of French Nietzscheanism is Nietzsche aujourd'huif, 2
vols, Col. 10/18, UGE: Paris, 1973, which contains the talks and debates from the
Cerisy-la-Salle International Colloquium on Nietzsche, held in June 1972. There is
now a significant grouping of studies of this philosophical movement. See especially: David B. Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche: Contemporary Styles of Interpretation,
MIT Press: Cambridge, Massachusetts and London, 1985; Keith Ansell-Pearson and
Howard Caygill, eds, The Fate of the New Nietzsche, Avebury: Aldershot, 1993; Ernst
Behler, "Nietzsche and Deconstruction," in Volker Durr, Reinhold Grimm and
Kathy Harms, eds, Nietzsche: Literature and Values, University of Wisconsin Press:
Madison, 1988 (pp. 180-98); Michael Allen Gillespie and Tracy B. Strong, eds,
Nietzsche's New Seas: Explorations in Philosophy, Aesthetics, and Politics, University of
Chicago Press: Chicago and London, 1988; David Farrell Krell and David Wood,
eds, Exceedingly Nietzsche: Aspects of Contemporary Nietzsche-Interpretation, Routledge:
London and New York, 1988.
19
Cf. Du Sublime by Jean-Luc Nancy and Michel Deguy, Belim: Paris, 1988 and
also J. Derrida, Ph. Lacoue-Labarthe, J.L. Nancy, J.F. Lyotard et al, La Faculte de
juger, Minuit: Paris, 1985. But the most important study continues to be Lecons sur
I'Analytique du sublime, by J.F. Lyotard, Galilee: Paris, 1991. Here, over more than
three hundred pages, Lyotard gives us an exhaustive commentary on 23-29 of the
Critique of Judgment, precisely those sections which make up the "Analytic of the
Sublime." English translations: Jean-Francois Courtine et al., Of the SubUme: Presence
in Question, translated by Jeffrey S. Librett, SUNY Press: New York, J.F. Lyotard,
162
Notes
1993, Lessons on the Analytic of the Sublime: Kant's Critique of Judgment [sections 2329], translated from the French by Elizabeth Rottenberg, Stanford University Press:
California, 1994.
20
Alain Boyer, Andre Comte-Sponville, Vincent Descombes, Luc Ferry, Robert
Legros, Philippe Raynaud, Alain Renaut, Pierre Andre Taguieff, Pourquoi nous ne,
sommes pas nietzscheens, Grasset: Paris, 1991. English translation: Why We Are Not
Nietzscheans, translated by Robert de Loaiza, University of Chicago Press: Chicago,
1997.
21
The most significant cases of this absence is represented by two collections of
recent studies dedicated to the sublime: Du Sublime, already referred to and Das
Erhabene. Zwischen Grenzerfahrung und Grossenwahn, by Christine Pries, Weinheim,
1989. Jean-Luc Nancy, in his study "L'offrande sublime" in which, along with a
commentary on the "Analytic of the Sublime" in the Critique of Judgment, he traces
one story of the meditation on the sublime in contemporary thought, which
includes references to Benjamin, Heidegger, Adorno, and Bataille, makes the
following comment in a footnote: "I must not omit to mention at least once the
name of Nietzsche, who thought, in one sense or several, something of the sublime, even if he hardly thematized it as such." Du Sublime, p. 39, n.3. But nowhere is
this "sublime in a certain sense" which Nietzsche would have pondered mentioned, nor is it ever shown that he worked systematically at this theme. Nietzsche's
aesthetic is a permanent fixture in both of these volumes, albeit only at an implicit
level. And when it appears more explicitly, as in Erhabene, in "Die Verwindung der
Erhabenen - Nietzsche" by Norbert Bolz, the sublime is only referred to - and
always in the vaguest of ways - in reference to The Gay Science and Thus Spoke
Zarathustra, especially in the commentary on the chapter "Von den Erhabenen"
(cf. pp. 16517). Likewise, in a recent work, Marc Richir reconstructs the place of
the aesthetic of the sublime in political thought from Kant onwards - including
considerations of Fichte, Hegel, Schelling, Michelet, and Heidegger. In his
introduction he says "the largest gap in our considerations of the philosophers is
Nietzsche. But ... to consider him thoroughly we would need a whole book."
English translations of two of these works can be found in: Jean-Luc Nancy, "The
Sublime Offering" in Of the Sublime: Presence in Question, pp. 25-53.
22
Among the studies of Nietzsche's aesthetic, the only ones that refer to the
category of the sublime in The Birth of Tragedy are Aesthetische Lebensformen bei
Nietzsche by Rudolf Reuber, Willhelm Fink Verlag: Munich, 1989, and Bertram
Schmidt, Der ethische Aspekt der Musik. Nietzsches Geburt der Tragoedie und die Weiner
Klassische Musik, Konigshausen & Neumann: Wurzburg, 1991. However, in both
cases, there is a failure to understand the link between the Nietzschean theory and
the Kantian tradition of the sublime. While Reuber locates the tradition of the
sublime, in its opposition to the beautiful, in the tradition of the aesthetic of the
ugly - inaugurated by Karl Rosenkranz in his Asthetick des Hdsslichen (1853) (cf.
Reuber, pp. 76-96), Schmidt simply suspends an analysis of the consequences of
his discovery that the Dionysian originates in Schiller's Sublime. After affirming
that "his [Nietzsche's] concept of Dionysian is similar to the concept of Schiller's
Sublime: the pleasure in suffering, the 'marvelous mixture and duplicity of affections' is analogous to the 'mixed feeling' of the Sublime in the Schillerean sense"
Notes
163
(p. 50), Schmidt adds that "an analysis of this analogy would outstrip the reach of
the present work" (ibid.). Only after 1991 did systematic interpretations of The
Birth of Tragedy based on the aesthetic of the sublime appear. One example is John
Sallis's Crossings, Nietzsche and the Space of Tragedy, University of Chicago Press:
Chicago and London, 1991, and another is Michael Hair's Nietzsche et la Metaphysique, Gallimard, Paris, 1993. Though neither book makes any references to Lyotard's recent readings of the "Analytic of the Sublime," they do, however, bespeak
a consciousness of the theme's, let's say, "postmodern" plots. Nevertheless, in
both cases, the reading is based exclusively on maintaining a parallelism between
Kant and Nietzsche. This creates two important limitations: (a) the task of determining the history of the reception of the Critique of Judgment within Nietzsche's
work is neglected; that is, the transformation of the Kantian sublime into Schopenhauer's metaphysic and thus into Wagner's expressionist aesthetic is not
reconstructed; (b) there is a total absence of hermeneutical reservations in the
establishment of the Kant/Nietzsche parallel. Neither Sallis nor Harr ever suspected the possibility that their interpretation of the Kantian theory of the sublime
is already contaminated by the Nietzschean tonalities which underlie the renaissance in interest in the "Analytic of the Sublime." English Translation: Michael
Harr, Nietzsche and Metaphysics, translated from the French by Michael Gendre,
SUNY Press: New York, 1996.
23
This process of transferring the effects of an aesthetic mockery of the real,
which had originated in The Birth of Tragedy, to the Kantian theory of the sublime,
without any examination of Nietzsche's own return to Kant via this same theory of
the sublime, truly began in 1978 with Jacques Derrida's La Verite en Peinture,
Flammarion: Paris, 1978. Through a rigorous reading of the theory of the sublime
in the Critique of Judgment in the chapter entitled "Le Colossal," Derrida showed
how Kant had first described the experience of the representation of the irrepresentable, the impossible presence of presence. Yet, his discovery is informed
solely by the theories of art put forth by Benjamin and Heidegger. Nietzsche is
there, always present, but only in the epochal plots of the theory of the sublime
and never as a moment in the history of the metaphysic of the irrepresentable
constructed around the polarity beautiful/sublime. As such, those hesitations that,
in the tradition of the aesthetic of the sublime, run through the entirety of this
experience of a presentification of the irrepresentable - for example, as Derrida
shows in the Hegelian interpretation of Kant, the hesitation between "knowing, or
rather of thinking, whether one must think (as Hegel thinks) sublimity, set out
from the thought of sublimity, or on the contrary (as Kant figures) from presentation, inadequate to this thought, of the sublime, etc." - never affect Nietzsche's text. (English translation: Derrida, J., The Truth in Painting, translated from
the French by Geoff Bennington and Ian MacLeod, University of Chicago Press:
Chicago, 1987, p. 134.) He does not belong to this history; he merely furnishes it
with its untouchable horizon. To read The Birth of Tragedy through the theory of the
sublime would be to upset the veracity of the absolute eccentricity of Nietzsche's
aesthetic in a tradition that, in the final analysis, finds its line of escape in the
sublime.
164
24
Notes
Notes
165
representation, both as a whole and in its parts, the objectivity of the will, which
accordingly means the will become object, i.e., representation." Ibid., p. 169.
34
Ibid., p. 170.
35
"[I]n so far as the subject knows as an individual, the Ideas will also lie quite
outside the sphere of its knowledge as such. Therefore, if the Ideas are to become
object of knowledge, this can happen only by abolishing individuality in the
knowing subject." Ibid., p. 169.
36
"[T]he transition that is possible, but to be regarded only as an exception,
from the common knowledge of particular things to knowledge of the Idea takes
place suddenly, since knowledge tears itself free from the service of the will
precisely by the subject's ceasing to be merely individual, and being now a pure
will-less subject of knowledge. Such a subject of knowledge no longer follows
relations in accordance with the principle of sufficient reason; on the contrary, it
rests in fixed contemplation of the object presented to it out of its connexion with
any other, and rises into this." Ibid., p. 178.
37
Ibid., p. 202.
38
Ibid., p. 205.
39
Ibid.
40
This moral destiny of the aesthetic of the sublime is well presented by Leonel
Ribeiro dos Santos in his study "Sentiment of the Sublime and Moral Experience."
As he writes: "If... we go on to examine that which Kant considers to be sublime
and the conditions to which this sentiment is submitted, the more the aesthetic
nature of this sentiment will seem to be implicated. What is even more patent is its
intimate connection with ideas of reason and with moral feeling or disposition." A
razdo sensivel, Colibri: Lisbon, 1994, p. 94. [My translation.]
41
The World as will and Representation, I, p. 205.
42
Ibid.
43
Ibid., p. 207.
44
Ibid., p. 252.
45
Ibid., pp. 252-3.
46
Ibid., p. 207.
47
Ibid., p. 253.
48
The World as Witt and Representation II, SW II, p. 433.
49
Perhaps it is in this link between the aesthetic of the sublime and the theory of
the tragedy that the metaphysics of pessimism most closely approaches the
inheritance of Schiller, Lessing, and Schelling. For an analysis of the place of
tragedy as figure of the sublime within Romantic dramaturgy, see "Tragedie et
sublimite. L'interpretation speculative de VOedipe Roi au seule de 1'idealisme allemand" by Jean-Francois Courtine, in his Exstase de la Raison. Essais sur Schelling,
Galilee: Paris, 1990, pp. 75-111.
50
The World as Witt and Representation, II, p. 433.
51
As George Steiner has shown, in this use of tragedy as metaphor for the
absolute of existence, Schopenhauer repeats the basis of the aesthetics of the tragic
of German Idealism. See Antigpnes, Clarendon Press: New York, 1986.
52
Early in paragraph 16 Schopenhauer resorts to the metaphor of the stage to
illustrate the ambivalent condition of human existence, which is simultaneously
166
Notes
concrete and abstract. "In the former he is abandoned to all the storms of reality
and to the influence of the present; he must struggle, suffer, and die like the
animal. But his life in the abstract, as it stands before his rational consciousness, is
the calm reflection of his life in the concrete, and of the world in which he lives;...
In respect of this withdrawal into reflection, he is like an actor who has played his
part in one scene, and takes his place in the audience until he must appear again.
In the audience he quietly looks on at whatever may happen, even though it be the
preparation of his own death (in the play); but then he again goes on the stage,
and acts and suffers as he must." The World as Witt and Representation, I, p. 85.
53
The World as Witt and Representation, II, p. 433.
54
It is this complete annulment of the gift that truly marks the transcendental
category of tragedy. Even though he does not consider the link between the theory
of tragedy and the aesthetic of the sublime, Philonenko gives us an excellent
description of this ontological, as well as moral, cancellation in the metaphysics of
pessimism and in the constitution of tragedy as a transcendental figure. "Schopenhauer wants ideality of time and space to have some effect on the real and
moral nullity of all phenomena manifested therein. First the real nullity: all phenomena is nothing more than a simulacrum of being, and Schopenhauer reduces
the Erscheinung to the Kantian sense of Schein. Secondly, moral nullity: the simple
Schein which develops on the last level of reality as it is defined by Plato cannot even
attempt to have an ethical meaning, as its consistency is null. The ontological and
moral nullity of the experience of the world is the founding moment of the
transcendental category of tragedy: there is no meaning to birth, there is no
meaning in living and death is simply what it is, a nothing. But this moment, in and
of itself, reveals its consequence: conceived in this way, the transcendental category
of tragedy justifies and insures pessimism." [My translation.] "Breve meditation
sur la philosophic de la tragedie de Schopenhauer" in Le transcendental et la pensee
moderne, PUF: Paris, 1990, p. 296.
55
The World as Witt and Representation, I, pp. 255-6.
56
Ibid., p. 257.
57
We know that the characterization of music as a condition of objectless
representation, in spite of being paradoxical in its dependence upon Western art's
mimetic tradition, would be fulfilled in the musical aesthetic of the nineteenthand the early twentieth-century works of Mahler, Strauss, Schoenberg and Berg.
See Michelle Biget, "Compositeurs allemands lecteurs de Schopenhauer, 18501920" in Roger-Pol Droit, ed., Presences de Schopenhauer, Grasset: Paris, 1989, pp.
174-86.
58
For example, Wagner always said that Der Ring des Nibelungen was finished
before he had discovered Schopenhauer in 1854. Nevertheless, as Richard Hollindrake shows us, even though in the 1853 edition the last scene makes an apology
for Woltan's power, the edition of GesammeUe Schriften und Dichtung of 1873 substitutes the concept of "power" for "love," and Woltan embodies the experience
of negation of the world. See Nietzsche, Wagner and the Philosophy of Pessimism,
George Allen & Unwin: London, 1982, especially pp. 57-8.
59
For a historico-philological reconstitution of the relationship of reciprocal
Notes
167
influence between Nietzsche and Wagner see Mazzino Montinari, "Nietzsche und
Wagner vor hundert Jahren" in Nietzsche - Studien, 7 (1978), pp. 288-307.
60
Wagner, Beethoven, in Jubilaeumsausgabe, Band 9, Insel Verlag: Frankfurt am
Main, 1983, pp. 56-7. English translation: Beethoven, by Richard Wagner, trans.
Edward Dannreuthe, ed. William Reeves, London, 1903 (3rd edn) pp. 23-30.
61
For an understanding of the place of Eduard Hanslick and his formalist
model in the history of the aesthetics of music, see Dahlhaus, C. Aesthetics of Musk,
translated from the German by William W. Austin, Cambridge University Press:
Cambridge (1982).
62
"To the question - what is to be expressed with all this material? The answer
will be: musical ideas. Now, a musical idea, reproduced in its entirety, is not only an
object of intrinsic beauty, but also an end in itself, and not a means for representing feelings and thoughts. The essence of music is sound and motion" Vom
Musicalisch-Schonen. Ein Beitrag zur Revision der Asthetik der Tonkunst, Breitkopf &
Hartel: Wiesbaden, 1989, p. 59. (1st edn, Leipzig, 1854). English translation:
Eduard Hanslick, Beautiful in Music. A contribution to the revisal of Musical Aesthetics,
trans. Gustav Cohen, Novello, Ewer & Co: London and New York, 1891.
63
Jean-Jacques Nattiez summarizes the theses of this work in the following
fashion: (a) music awakens the senses; (a) therefore the senses are not contained
in the music; and (c) the beautiful in music does not reside in the feelings of the
composer, or the listener, but in the pure contemplation of the form: the composer should not try to excite feeling. Nattiez comes to the following conclusion:
"With this essay, Western aesthetics seesaws. It is no longer concerned with the
study of sensations produced by a form - and Hanslick reminds us of the meaning
of the word aesthesis-but of the form itself." Jean-Jacques Nattiez, "Hanslick ou les
apories de 1'immanence" in Le Combat de Chronos et d'Orphee, Christian Bourgois
Editeur: Paris, 1993, p. 59. [My translation above.]
64
Vom Musikalisch-Schonen, p. 7. [My translation.]
65
In the 1854 edition Hanslick only discusses Wagner's Work of the Art of the
Future (1850) and the theses presented therein about the heart as the organ of
sound. In later editions Hanslick takes to task the definition of music as the "art of
expression" [Kunst des Ausdrucks], as well as the thesis that would see music as a
means for the immediate apprehension of the world's essence. Here he is looking
precisely at Wagner's essay Beethoven (1870). It is surprising that in criticizing
Wagner's text, he fails to understand that it represents a response to his own
formalist notions. In fact, Hanslick does not consider the distinction made here for
the first time by Wagner between an aesthetic of the beautiful, as an aesthetic of
forms, and an aesthetic of the sublime, as an aesthetic of the senses. Nor does he
see that via this distinction Wagner is able to save his expressionist definition of
music.
66
Beethoven, p. 83. English translation: pp. 71-71.
67
Ibid., p. 73. English translation: pp. 55-6.
68
Nietzsche had always been tormented by Wagner's aesthetic correlation
between the sublime, the ineffable, and the divine. But only in 1888, in The Wagner
Case, did he really let it be understood to what extent he was conscious of the fact
the it was the beautiful/sublime opposition that functioned in Wagner as the
168
Notes
Werke, Kritische Studienausgabe (hereafter KSA), eds, Georgio Colli and Mazzino
Montinari, Verlag de Gruyten Berlin/New York, 1967, XII, 9 (84); The Witt To
Power, ed. by W. Kaufmann, translated by W. Kaufmann and R.J. Hollingdale,
Vintage: New York, 1967, 379. (Translator's note: All further references for The
Witt to Power are to the Kaufmann ed. and will be indicated by WP. "The Individual
and Individuality in Nietzsche" was first translated into English by Christopher
Rollason, for Pli, 12 (2001). For the present translation of this chapter, I have
relied heavily on Rollason's superb translation of the Nabais text. Rollason's version has been recently re-published in A Companion to Nietzsche, Keith Ansell
Pearson (ed), Blackwell: London, 2006. The version published in PU (and later in
the Blackwell book) underwent heavy editing by the editor [s] of that magazine and
certain crucial passages that were in the original Portuguese version were omitted
from the published, English versions, thereby eliminating the central thesis of the
Notes
169
article concerning the disappearance of the idea of the Eternal Recurrence after
1885. The present translation restores these passages and, in doing so, will significantly challenge the canonical sanctification of the doctrine of the Eternal
Return in, especially, Anglo-American Nietzsche studies.
2
KSA, IX (158). (Translator's note: many of the citations in the present chapter
are from Nietzsche's posthumous writings. This is the case where only the KSA
reference is provided. Where no translator is indicated the passage was translated
by the editors of Pli).
3
G.W. Leibniz, letter to Arnauld of 30 April 1687, Philosophische Schrifien, ed.
Gerhardt, vol. II, p. 97.
4
The lack of a specific description of the concept of the individual in Nietzsche
has lead some scholars to see a negation of the individual in his theory of the will to
power, and the predominance of an undifferentiated continuum. In the words of
Eugen Fink in Nietzsches Philosophie (French trans., Hildenberg, Minuit: Paris,
1965): "The world is not composed of things, it is a single flux of life, a 'sea' in
which there are waves but nothing is permanent" (p. 207) and, again: "Starting
out from a basic conception of being as becoming, Nietzsche denies the individual,
finite being. There is no such thing as being because, in the end, there is no such
thing as individuation" (p. 210).
5
The World as Will and Representation, I, p. 113.
6
cf. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason (Kritik der reinen Vernunft), AK B 473/
A 445 and ff.
7
"The solution to the third antinomy, whose subject was the idea of freedom,
merits special consideration insofar as for us it is very remarkable that Kant is
obliged precisely here, in connection with the Idea of Freedom, to speak in greater
detail about the thing in itself." The World as Will and Representation, p. 501.
8
Schopenhauer, Parerga und Paralipomena I, S.W., V. p. 270.
9
Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, IV, 63, S.W., I, p. 674. [My
translation.]
10
KSA, I, pp. 26-7. English translation: The Birth of Tragedy and Other Writings,
translated by Ronald Speirs, Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, 1999, p. 15.
11
"We, however, who consist of and are completely trapped in semblance, are
compelled to feel this semblance to be that which truly is not [WahrhaftNichtseiende}, i.e. a continual Becoming in time, space, and causality - in other
words, empirical reality." Ibid., KSA, I, pp. 38-9. English translation: Speirs, 1999,
p. 26.
12
"If we add to this horror the blissful ecstasy which arises from the innermost
ground of man, indeed of nature itself, whenever this breakdown of the principium
individuationis occurs, we catch a glimpse of the essence of the Dionysiac, which is
best conveyed by the analogy of intoxication. ... Now, hearing this gospel of universal harmony, each person feels himself to be not simply united, reconciled or
merged with his neighbor, but quite literally one with him, as if the veil of maya
had been torn apart, so that mere shreds of it flutter before the mysterious primordial unity [das Ur-ein]." Ibid., KSA, I, p. 30. English translation: Speirs, 1999,
p. 17-18.
13
"One might even describe Apollo as the magnificent divine image of the
170
Notes
principium individuationis, whose gestures and gaze speak to us of all the intense
pleasure, wisdom and beauty of 'semblance'." Ibid., KSA, I, p. 28. English translation: p. 17.
14
"As an ethical divinity Apollo demands measure from all who belong to him
and, so that they may respect that meaure, knowledge of themselves." Ibid., KSA, I,
p. 40. English translation: Speirs, 1999, p. 27.
15
"But how do we regain ourselves? How can man know himself? He is a dark
and concealed thing. ... The young soul looks back upon life with the question:
what have you until now truly loved? What does your soul have to do with the series
of these venerated objects in front of you? Perhaps through their essence and their
sequence they give you a law, the fundamental law of your proper self." Schopenhauer as Educator, KSA, I, p. 340.
16
Ibid., KSA, I, p. 338.
17
It is significant that it should be through the figure of Apollo that Nietzsche
distinguishes himself from Schopenhauer. Dionysus will only return after 1885,
with the theory of the Will to Power, in which the universal Whole no longer
opposes the principium individuationis, but rather becomes its expression.
18
"Here, at this moment of supreme danger for the will, art approaches as a
saving sorceress with the power to heal. Art alone can re-direct those repulsive
thoughts about the terrible and the absurd nature of existence into representations with which man can live." KSA, I, p. 57. English translation: Speirs, 1999,
p. 40.
19
Schopenhauer as Educator, KSA, I, pp. 374-5.
20
KSA, II, p. 29. English translation: Human, Att-too-Human, translated by RJ.
Hollingdale, Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, 1995, p. 15.
21
Ibid., KSA, II, p. 30. English translation: Hollingdale, 1995, p. 16.
22
KSA, IX, 6 (158).
23
Nietzsche was inspired by Jacob Burckhardt's The Civilization of the Renaissance
in Italy (1860), especially the second part with its description of the development of
the individual as a self-sufficient individuality. See the second part, entitled "The
Development of the Individual."
24
Human, Att-too-Human, KSA, II, p. 103. English translation: Hollingdale, 1995,
p. 57.
25
KSA, IX, 6 (80).
26
KSA, IX, 6 (158).
27
KSA, IX, 6 (293).
28
KSA, IX, 7 (62); WP 331.
29
KSA, IX, 7 (62); WP 331.
30
"[A]ll is eternal, unbecome [ungeworden}" KSA, IX, 11 (157).
31
KSA, IX, II (202).
32
KSA, IX, 11 (156).
33
"All becoming moves itself in the repetition of a determinate number of
absolutely identical states," KSA, IX, 11 (245).
34
KSA, IX, 11 (148).
35
KSA, IX, 18 (3). [My translation.]
36
KSA, III, p. 570.
Notes
37
171
172
Notes
volition, as if then [after separation] volition would still be left over." KSA, XI, 38
(8).
67
KSA, XII, 5 (64).
68
KSA, XI, 11 (32). [My translation.]
69
KSA, XIII, 11 (83); WP 674.
70
KSA, XII, 2 (143).
71
KSA, XII, 2 (175). Nietzsche's criticism of Darwinism touches precisely on the
inversion of perspectives in its explanation of external/internal relations in the
genesis of living forms. "The influence of 'external circumstances' is overestimated
to the point of nonsense by Darwin; what is essential about the life-process is just
the gigantic creative power which produces forms working from within while using
and exploiting 'external circumstances'." KSA, XII, 7 (25).
72
Nietzsche is able to deny his own notion of "cause" based on the model of
copossibility among individuals. As he says: " 'Cause' and 'effect' ... That means:
the separation of the event into action and passion." KSA, XII, 7 (1). All individuals are absolutely active. ''What is 'passive'? To resist and react. To be hampered
in forward-grasping movement: thus an act of resistance and reaction. What is
'active'? Striding towards power." KSA, 5 (64).
73
KSA, XIII, 14 (113). [My translation.]
74
KSA, XII, 5 (71).
75
It is also the model of copossiblity that allows Nietzsche to conceive the tie
between the spontaneous nature of each individual and the regulated character of
each and every one of the events that comprise his biography. ' 'Let us here dismiss
the two popular concepts 'necessity' and 'law': the former introduces a false
constraint into the world, the latter a false freedom. Things' do not behave regularly, according to a rule... There is no obedience here: for that something is as it
is, as strong or as weak, is not the consequence of an obedience to a rule or a
compulsion - The degree of resistance and the degree of superior power - this is
the question in every event: if, for our day-to-day calculations, we know how to
express this in formulas and 'laws', so much the better for us! ... There is no law:
every power draws its ultimate consequence at every moment, Calculability exists
precisely because things are unable to be other that they are." KSA, XIII, 14 (79);
WP634.
76
This fragment (the Lenzer Heide text of 1887) is dealt with extensively in the
last chapter of this book.
77
KSA, XII, 7 (38); WP 1032.
EcceHomo, KSA, VI, p. 296. English translation: The Genealogy of Morals andEcce
Homo, translated by Walter Kaufmann, Random House: New York, 1989, p. 258.
2
Dithyrambs of Dionysus, translated by R.J. Hollingdale, Black Swan Books: Redding Ridge, 1984.
3
These essays (like everything that Nietzsche wrote before the autumn of 1869)
are not included in the Colli and Montinari critical edition, our principal source of
Notes
173
Nietzsche's works in this study. This edition begins with the published writings
from the Basel period. For this reason the works spoken about here are taken from
the five-volume edition Friedrich Nietzsche. Werke und Briefe. Historisch-Kritische
Gesamtausabe, edited by Hans Joachim Mene, Carl Koch, and Karl Schlechta, C.H.
Beck'sche Verlagsbuchhandlung: Munich, 1933-40.
4
English translation: "Fate and History: Thoughts," in Keith Ansell Pearson
and Duncan Large, eds, The Nietzsche Reader, Blackwell: London, 2006, p. 13.
Translated by Duncan Large.
5
Ibid., p. 13.
6
Ibid,, p. 14.
7
Ibid., p. 14.
8
Ibid., p. 15.
9
Freedom of Will and Fate, in ibid., p. 17.
10
Ibid., p. 17.
11
Ibid.
12
13
14
Ibid. p. 14.
Ibid.
On this confusion in Thus Spoke Zarathustra see Chapter 5 below, especially the
sections entitled "Time and Morality" and "The Typological Perspective in Thus
Spoke Zarathustra."
15
"The solution of the third antinomy, whose subject was the Idea of freedom,
merits special consideration ... In general, this is the point where Kant's philosophy leads to mine, or mine springs from his as its parent stem." (The World as Will
and Representation, I, p. 501.)
16
"For us it is very remarkable that Kant is obliged precisely here, in connexion
with the Idea of freedom, to speak in greater detail about the thing-in-itself, hitherto
seen only in the background. This is very easy for us to understand after we have
recognized the thing-in-itself as the will. ... For the rest, it is just this intended
solution of the sham third antinomy that gives Kant the opportunity to express very
beautifully the profoundest ideas of his whole philosophy ... but above all, the
discussion of the contrast between the empirical and intelligible characters which I
number among the most admirable things ever said by man." (Ibid., pp. 501-5.)
17
"Every efficient cause, however, must have a character, that is, a rule according
to which it manifest its causality, and without which it would not be a cause.
According to this we should have in every subject of the world of sense, first, an
empirical character, through which its acts, as phenomena, stand with other phenomena in an unbroken connection, according to permanent laws of nature, and
could be derived from them as their conditions, and in connection with them form
the links of one and the same series in the order of nature. Secondly, we should
have to allow to it an intelligible character also, by which, it is true, it becomes the
cause of the same acts as phenomena, but which itself is not subject to any conditions of sensibility, and never phenomenal. We might call the former the character of such a thing as a phenomena, in the latter the character of the thing by
itself. According to its intelligible character, this active subject would not depend
on conditions of time, for time is only the condition of phenomena, and not of
things by themselves. In it no act would arise or perish, neither would it be subject
174
Notes
therefore to the law of determination in time and of all that is changeable, namely,
that everything which happens must have its cause in the phenomena (of the previous
state). In one word its causality, so far as it is intelligible, would not have a place in
the series of empirical conditions by which the event is rendered necessary in the
world of sense." Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, translated by F. Max Muller, Anchor
Books: New York, 1966, p. 370.
18
"For we are speaking here of the absolutely first beginning, not according to
time, but according to causality. If, for instance, at this moment I rise from my
chair with perfect freedom, without the necessary determining influence of natural
causes, a new series has its absolute beginning in this event, with all its natural
consequences ad infinitum, although, with regard to time, this event is only the
continuation of a preceding series. For this determination and this act do not
belong to the succession of merely natural effects, nor are they a mere continuation of them, but the determining natural causes completely stop before it, so far as
this event is concerned, which no doubt follows them, and does not result from
them, and may therefore be called an absolutely first beginning in a series of
phenomena, not with reference to time, but with reference to causality." Ibid., p.
322.
19
S. W., Ill, p. 707. English translation: On the Basis of Morality, translated by
E.FJ. Payne, Berghahm Books: Providence, 1995, p. 112.
20
KSA I, pp. 374-5. English translation: "Schopenhauer as Educator" in Untimely Meditations, translated by RJ. Hollingdale, Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, 1997, p. 155.
21
Ibid., p. 127.
22
KSA, I, 56. English translation: in The Basic Writings of Nietzsche, edited and
translated by Walter Kaufmann, Random House: New York, 2000 (first ed. 1967),
p. 60.
23
KSA, I, p. 257. English translation: "On the Uses and Disadvantages of History
for Life," in Untimely Meditations, translated by RJ. Hollingdale, p. 67.
24
Ibid., p. 59.
25
Ibid.
26
Ibid., p. 67.
27
"History belongs above all to the man of deeds and power, to him who fights a
great fight, who needs models, teachers, comforters and cannot find them among
his contemporaries." (Ibid. p. 67) ... "He learns from it that the greatness that
once existed was in any event once possible and may thus be possible again." (Ibid.
p. 69.)
28
Ibid., p. 70.
29
Ibid., p. 74.
30
Ibid., pp. 75-6.
31
Ibid., p. 76.
32
Ibid., p. 66.
33
The World As Witt and Representation, I, pp. 182-3.
Notes
175
KSA, VI, p. 274; English translation: in The Basic Writings of Nietzsche, edited and
translated by Walter Kaufmann, Random House: New York, 2000, p. 688.
2
Ibid., p. 688.
3
Because Nietzsche and not the philosophy of the Portico is the object of this
chapter, in which we will try to analyse the way in which Nietzsche conceived of
Stoicism, we recommend that the reader refer to one of the most important books
dedicated to all of the central aspects of Stoicism, especially for an analysis of the
ethical programme of the Stoics. See Victor Goldschmidt, Le systeme stoicien et Videe
de temps, Vrin: Paris, 1977.
4
See the commentary on this aphorism at the end of this chapter.
5
On the importance of the influence of Stoicism, it is worth reading Michel
Spanneut's classic, Permanence du stowisme, de Zenon a Malraux, ed., J. Duculot, S. A:
Gembloux, 1973. There you will find two pages dedicated to Nietzsche. In addition
to the diverse and contradictory ways in which Nietzsche appreciated Stoicism,
Spanneut lays out Nietzsche's most important points of affinity, that is, (a) the idea
of the Eternal Recurrence, (b) the programme for the assent to destiny as the basis
for the autonomous ideal of the will, and (c) the model for the world as Will (cf.
pp. 352-3).
6
Charles Andler, Nietzsche, sa vie et sa pensee, Gallimard: Paris, 1958, vol. II, pp.
406-8.
7
Georges Morel, Nietzsche, Introduction a une premiere lecture, Aubier-Montaigne:
Paris, 1971, vol. II, pp. 284-5.
8
Cf. Jean Granier, Le probleme de la Verite dans la philosophie de Nietzsche, Seuil:
Paris, 1966, pp. 414-15.
9
See Gilles Deleuze, Logique du Sens, Minuit: Paris, 1969.
10
Gilles Deleuze, Nietzsche et la philosophie, P.U.F.: Paris, 1962, p. 20. English
translation: Nietzsche and philosophy, translated by High Tomlinson, Athlone: London, 1983.
11
Because Nietzsche's essay was not included in the Colli and Montinari edition,
we have used the Hans Joachim Mette and Karl Schlechta edition. Both the German and the Latin version of De Laertii Diogenis fontibus are published in volume IV,
pp. 217-359. An exposition of the theses according to which Diocles of Magnesia
had been the source of the whole of book VII on the Portico occupy pp. 223-5.
12
Nietzsche's argument (ibid., pp. 229-36) is based almost exclusively on a
passage at the beginning of the 10th Book of Diogenes Laertius. It can be summed
up as follows: Diocles of Magnesia, who, according to what we know via Diogenes,
so praised Epicurus in the book III of his lost work, would be the same author,
also referred to by Diogenes, indicated in the work Twenty-Four Proofs to Diocles in
Twelve Books by the Stoic, Socio, (whom Nietzsche demonstrates as being the one
who was known to be Seneca's teacher). Furthermore, according to Diogenes, this
work which refutes Diocle also defames Epicurus. This being the case, Nietzsche
concludes, Diocles of Magnesia can only be the enemy of the Portico and its
detractor.
13
Pindar, Pythian Odes II, v. 73, cited by Nietzsche, ibid., p. 222. On the
176
Notes
Notes
25
177
178
33
Notes
See the beautiful hymn to eternity and the wholeness of the Universe, or as
Nietzsche calls it das Ja - und Amen-Lied in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, III. The Seven
Seals, KSA, IV, pp. 287-91. English translation in The Portable Nietzsche, p. 340.
34
"The doctrine of the 'eternal recurrence,' that is, of the unconditional and
infinitely repeated circular course of all things - this doctrine of Zarathustra might
in the end have been taught already by Heraclitus. At least the Stoa has traces of it,
and the Stoics inherited almost all of their principal notions from Heraclitus." Ecce
Homo, KSA, VI, p. 313. English translation: pp. 729-30.
35
Cf. Emile Brehier, Chrysippe, Felix Alcan, Paris, 1910, p. 158.
36
For an exhaustive analysis of the cosmological, logical, and ethical reach of
the doctrine of the Eternal Recurrence in the Stoa see Jonathan Barnes "La
doctrine du Retour Eternel," in Les Stoiciens et leurLogique, Vrin: Paris, 1978, pp. 320. The bibliography on this subject is nearly unlimited; see Joan Stambaugh,
Nietzsche's thought of Eternal Return, the Johns Hopkins University Press: Baltimore
and London, 1972. Karl Lowith, Nietzsches Philosophie der ewigen Wiederkehr des Gleichen, Kohlhamer: Stuttgart, 1956, and Pierre Klossowski, Nietzsche et le cercle vicieux,
Mercure de France: Paris, 1969.
37
KSA, IX, 12 (141). [My translation.]
38
"... hence I, too, shall say what it is that I wish from myself today, and what was
the first thought to run across my heart this year - what thought shall be for me the
reason, warranty, and sweetness of my life henceforth. I want to learn more and
more to see as beautiful what is necessary in things; then I shall be one of those
who make things beautiful. Amor fati: let that be my love henceforth!" The Gay
Science, aphorism 276; KSA, III, p. 521. English translation: p. 223.
39
Cf. The Gay Science, aphorism 341; KSA, III, p. 570. English translation: p. 274.
40
KSA, III, p. 544. English translation: p. 245.
41
KSA, III, p. 383. English translation: pp. 85-6. With respect to this, aphorism
326 is also worth citing: "Is our life really painful and burdensome enough to make
it advantageous to exchange it for a Stoic way of life and petrification? We are not so
badly off that we have to be as badly off as Stoics." (English translation: p. 257).
42
Nietzsche is a victim of that same confusion that Victor Goldschmidt exposed,
between the general and permanent imperturbability of primitive scepticism in
Stoicism and the active readiness for correct action at opportune moments.
Goldschmidt, Le systeme stotcien et Uidee de temps, p. 135. See chapter 5, "La theorie
de 1'action," as well as chapter 6, "La morale en acte," pp. 125-210.
43
Beyond Good and Evil 227, KSA, V, p. 162. English translation: in The Basic
Writings of Nietzsche, p. 345.
44
This principle, as is well known, underwent various formulations; cf. Hans von
Arnim, Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, III, Teubner: Stuttgart, 1964, p. 4 and following. Nietzsche refers only to its trivial form, as moral naturalism, that is, as though
he were expressing the principle of living according to moral laws that had
emerged out of nature.
45
Beyond Good and Evil, 9, KSA, V, pp. 21-2. English translation: Basic Writings of
Nietzsche, p. 205.
46
Hans von Arnim, Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, III, 5,14.
47
Ibid., Ill, 4,12.
Notes
179
48
180
Notes
of the 'Revaluation'," the editors write, commenting on the letter cited above.
KSA, XV, p. 186.
6
See for example the following passage from a letter to Paul Deussen dated 26
November, 1888: "My 'Revaluation of All Values', whose principal tide [Haupttitel\
is 'The Antichrist', is finished. In the next years, I must occupy myself with the
translation of this work into seven languages: the first edition in each of these
languages, about a million copies." Git. in KSA, XV, p. 187. (Translator's version.)
7
2 KSA, XIII, 25 [11]. [My translation.]
8
"The uncovering of Christian morality is an event without parallel, a real
catastrophe." (KSA, VI, p. 373.) English translation: Kaufmann, 1989, p. 333.)
Nietzsche wrote at the end of Ecce Homo, referring to The Antichrist. "He that is
enlightened about that, is a force majeure, a destiny - he breaks the history of
mankind in two. One lives before him, or one lives after him." (Ibid.) In the same
notebook of 1886, where for the first time he mentions "the revaluation of all
values," he writes: "Starting point: it is an error to point to 'social hardship' or
'physiological degeneration' or even corruption as the cause of nihilism. These can
still be interpreted in very different ways. Instead, it's in a very particular interpretation, the Christian-moral one, that nihilism is found." (KSA, XII, 2 [127]).
English translation: Writings from the Late Notebooks, trans. Kate Sturge, Cambridge
University Press: Cambridge, 2003, p. 83.
9
The paradigmantic works are by Klossowski, Nietzsche el le cercle vicieux, Deleuze,
Nietzsche et la Philosophic, Wolfgang Muller-Lauter, Nietzsche Seine Philosophic der
Gegensatze und seiner Philosophic, Walter de Gruyten Berlin/New York, 1971, Karl
Lowith, Nietzsches Philosophic der cwigcn Wiederkchr dcs Gleichen, Kohlhammer: Stutgart, 1956, Joan Stambaugh, Nietzsche's thought of eternal return, Bernd Magnus,
Nietzsche's Existential Imperative, Indiana University Press: Bloomington & London,
1978. And most recently Gunter Abel, Nietzsche, DieDynamik der Willen zurMacht und
die ewige Wiederkehr, Walter de Gruyter: Berlin/New York, 1984.
10
This is the central thesis of Heidegger's Was Heisst Denkenf, Max Niemeyer
Verlag: Tubingen, 1954. For Heidegger, revaluing all values would be to cancel the
condition for the possibility of the whole moral devaluation of existence. Not only
this, but, according to Heidegger, Nietzsche would have seen such a basis in the
existential figure of the "spirit of revenge" (der Geist der Roche) - which is defined
as a revolt again the irrevocability of the past To unleash the consciousness of
revolt against the past and, thus, the revolt against existence in general, would
therefore imply the acceptance of the idea of the Eternal Recurrence, that is to say,
the revaluation of man in the over-human.
11
Deleuze's reading of the way Nietzsche prepares Foucault's fundamental
theses is significant "What does Foucault mean when he says there is no point in
crying over the death of man?" ... "Foucault, like Nietzsche, can only sketch in
something embryonic and not yet functional. Nietzsche said that man imprisoned
life, but the superman is what frees life within man himself, to the benefit of another
form, and so on" ... "And is this unlimited finity or superfold not what Nietzsche
had already designated with the name of eternal return?" Gilles Deleuze, Foucault,
Minuit Paris, 1986. English translation: Foucault, translated by Sean Hand, University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, 1988, pp. 130-1. The link between the
Notes
181
reflection on "the death of man" - identified certainly by Heidegger with the end
of the metaphysics of the subject- and the basis of the philosophy of Nietzsche can
also be found in the programmatic text, "Les fins de Thomme," by Jacques Derrida, in Marges de la Philosophie, Minuit: Paris, 1972. English translation: Margins of
Philosophy, translated by Alan Bass, University of Chicago Press: Chicago, 1982. See,
as well, Gianni Vattimo's Al di la des soggetto. Nietzsche, Heidegger and rhermeneutica,
Feltrinelli: Milano, 1981, where this link between Nietzsche and Heidegger is taken
up precisely around this theme of the "death of man."
12
Gianni Vattimo comes to the same conclusion: "Indeed, the scattered and
often incoherent theories of post-modernity acquire rigor and philosophical
credibility when seen in relation to the Nietzschean problematic of the overcoming
of metaphysics." La fine della modernita, Garzanti: Milan, 1985, p. 9. Translated into
English as: The End of Modernity: Nihilism and hermeneutics in post-modern culture,
translated by Jon R. Snyder, Polity: Cambridge, 1988, p.l.
13
This is Habermas's interpretation in the chapter dedicated to Nietzsche in Der
philosophische Diskurs der Moderne, Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main, 1985.
14
"Now I shall relate the history of Zarathustra. The fundamental conception of
this work, the idea of the eternal recurrence, this highest formula of affirmation
that is at all attainable, belongs in August 1881: it was penned on a sheet with the
notation underneath, "6000 feet beyond man and time." That day I was walking
through the woods along the lake Silvaplana; at a powerful pyramidal rock not far
from Surlei I stopped. It was then that this idea came to me." Ecce Homo, KSA, VI,
335. English translation: Kaufmann, 1989, p. 295.
15
Cited in Chronik zu Nietzsches Leben, KSA, XV, p. 139.
16
See fragments 27 [80], 27 [82], 29 [40], 29 [66], among many others, all of
them included in volume 11 of the KSA.
17
Cf. supra, p. 177 note 1.
18
KSA, VI, p. 160.
19
Cf. KSA, VI, p. 335. English translation: The Basic Writings of Nietzsche, p. 751.
20
The only exceptions are fragments 5 [54] ,5 [71] (which we speak about at the
end of this work), and 7 [54] in volume 12 of the KSA, and fragment 10 [13] in
volume 13.
21
KSA, XIII, 22 [14].
22
"If I reckon back a few months from this day, I find as an omen a sudden and
profoundly decisive change in my taste, especially in music." Ecce Homo, KSA, VI,
335. English translation: Kaufmann, 1989, p. 295.
23
Cf. KSA II, pp. 67, 70, 75.
24
Ueber die Grundlage der Moral, Arthur Schopenhauer Samtliche Werke, Wissenschaftliche Buchgessellschaft, Darmstadt, 1980, Band 3:708. English translation:
On the Basis of Morality, translated by E.F J. Payne, Berghahm Books: Providence,
1995, p. 110.
25
Kant, Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, translated by Allen W. Wood,
Yale University Press: New Haven, 2002, p. 66.
26
Human, All-too-Human, KSA, II, p. 64. English Translation: Human All-tooHuman, RJ. Hollingdale, Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, 1999, pp. 34-5.
27
Ibid.
182
28
Notes
Ibid.
Ibid., p. 58.
30
Heidegger makes various comments about this chapter in Thus Spoke Zarathustra: in Nietzsche metaphysische Grundstellung im abendldndischen Denken: Die ewige
Wiederhehr des Gleichen (Sommersemester 1937), Gesamtausgabe XLJV, in Was Heisst
Denken?, Max Niemeyer Verlag: Tubingen, 1954, and expecially in the essay on
Zarathustra in Vortrage und Aufsatze, Gesamtausgabe VII. English translation:
What is Called Thinking, translated by J. Glenn Gray, Harper & Row: New York,
1968. An important study of Heidegger's meditation on Nietzsche about the interpretation of time as irreversible and as a revelation of the fundamentally temporal
condition of human existence can be found in "La presence de Nietzsche dans
Sein und Zeit" byJacques Taminiaux, in Lectures de lontologiefondamentale. Essais sur
Heidegger, Jerome Millon: Grenoble, 1989.
31
Thus Spoke Zarathustra, II, KSA, IV, p. 180. English translation: in The Portable
Nietzsche, pp. 251-2.
32
Ibid., p. 252.
33
Ibid.
34
Ibid.
35
Jankelevitch, L'irreversible et le nostalgie, Flammarion: Paris, 1974, p. 273. (My
translation)
36
Thus Spoke Zarathustra, II, KSA IV, pp. 179-80. English translation: The Portable
Nietzsche, p. 251.
37
Ibid., 252.
38
It was Gilles Deleuze who made the idea of typology in Nietzsche central and
under the rubric of which all of the theses of the theory of the will are brought
together. He distinguishes active types, whose will to power is expressed through
affirmation, and reactive types, which rest in the principle of negation, and creates
a framework in which all of the typological figures of Thus Spoke Zarathustra and The
Genealogy of Morals are represented. The first group includes the artist, the aristocrat,
the sovereign individual and the legislator. Among the reactive types are the man who
never finishes anything, the perpetual accuser, the man who multiplies his pain, the guilty
man, the domesticated man, the aesthetic man and the non-artist. Cf. Nietzsche et la Philosophie, p. 166. The weakness of Deleuze 's reading is in the blurring of the difference between the various works of the 1881-5 period, that is The Gay Science and
Thus Spoke Zarathustra, and those which are organized around the theory of the will
to power, posterior to 1885, of which The Genealogy of Morals is the most important
and paradigmatic. This blurring hinders our understanding of the basic ambivalence in Nietzsche's analysis of time in Thus Spoke Zarathustra. As we have tried to
point out here, this work already contains a typological understanding of time,
even if, simultaneously, time is conceived as a universal determination. Nietzsche
will abandon the phenomenological perspective. And this abandonment will lead
to the immense typology which is The Genealogy of Morals.
39
Deleuze defines reactive forces precisely as those "that are separated from
that of which they are capable." Nietzsche et la Philosophie, p. 140.
40
See, for an excellent balance of the exegetical problems born of the attempts
to conceive of the idea of the Eternal Return as the fundamental substance of
29
Notes
183
Nietzsche's final philosophy, M.C. Sterling, "Recent discussions of eternal recurrence: some critical comments" in Nietzsche-Studien, Band 6, Walter de Gruyter:
Berlin/New York, 1977, pp. 261-91.
41
KSA, IX, 11 [338]. Cf. tb. 11 [203] ou 11 [160]. English translation by Keith
Ansell Pearson and Duncan Large in The Nietzsche Reader, p. 241.
42
KSA, III, p. 570. English translation: The Portable Nietzsche, pp. 101-2.
43
Ibid.
44
KSA, IX, II [165]. English translation by Diane Morgan, Keith Ansell Pearson
and Duncan Large in The Nietzsche Reader, p. 241.
45
KSA, IX, 11 [163]. English translation by Keith Ansell Pearson and Duncan
Large in ibid., p. 241.
46
Cf. tb. KSA, IX, 11 [161], 11 [160], 11 [203].
47
Thus Spoke Zarathustra, III, KSA, IV, p. 249. English translation: The Portable
Nietzsche, p. 310.
48
KSA, IV, p. 181. English translation: The Portable Nietzsche, p. 253.
49
KSA, IV, p. 278. English translation, The Portable Nietzsche, p. 333.
50
KSA, IV, pp. 199-200. English translation: Thus Spoke Zarathustra, ed. and
trans, by R.S. Hollingdale, Penguin: London, 1961, pp. 178-9.
51
Ibid., 179.
52
Cf. works of Stambaugh and Lowith cited above.
53
Nietzsche Philosophie, Kohlhammer Verlag: Stuttgart, 1960, p. 146.
54
Ibid., p. 103. [My translation.]
55
Nietzsche I, Gunther Neske Verlag: Tubingen, 1961, p. 273. [My translation.]
56
For a more complete understanding of the doctrine of the will to power, see
Chapter 2, above.
57
KSA, XIII, 11 [77], English translation: Kate Sturge, Writings from the Late
Notebooks, Cambridge University Press: Cambridge 2003, p. 214.
58
KSA, XI, 36 [20], English translation: Walter Kaufmann and RJ. Hollingdale,
The Will to Power, Random House: New York, 1967, p. 340.
59
KSA, XIII, 14 [95], English translation: The Witt to Power, Random House: New
York, 1967, p. 337.
60
KSA, XI, 36 [18], English translation: Sturge, Writings from the Late Notebooks, p.
24.
61
KSA, XIII, 14 [79], English translation: Sturge, Writings from the Late Notebooks,
p. 216.
62
See Volker Gerhardt, "Da Vontade de Poder: para a Genese e Interpretacao
da Filosofia do Poder em Nietzsche" in Antonio Marques, ed., Cem anos apos o
Projecto "Vontande de Poder - Transmutagao de todos ofValores," Verga: Lisbon, 1989,
pp. 11-32.
63
The Basic Writings of Nietzsche, p. 220.
64
Ibid. p. 221.
65
In Ansell Pearson and Large, eds, The Nietzsche Reader For a more detailed
commentary on this important fragment, see the following chapter.
66
KSA, XII, p. 5. 71.
67
This is Gianni Vattimo's interpretation in his commentary on the Lenzer
Heide fragment in his Introduzione a Nietzsche, Laterza: Roma, 1985, pp. 94-100.
184
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
Notes
Lenzer Heide
Lenzer Heide, paragraph 9.
Ibid., para. 11.
Ibid., para. 15.
Ibid.
Ibid., para. 9.
Ibid., para. 14.
KSA, VI, p. 135. English translation: Twilight of the Idols, translated by RJ.
Hollongdale, Penguin Books: London, 2003, p. 98.
2
KSA, XIII, pp. 255-6. The Witt to Power p. 25.
3
The Anti-Christ, Ecce Homo, Twilight of Idols and other writings, ed. Aaron Ridley
and Judith Norman, translation by Judith Norman, Cambridge University Press:
Cambridge, p. 64.
4
Nachgelassene Fragmente, 11 [411], Band XIII, p. 190. [My translation.]
5
European Nihilism, English transl. by Duncan Large in Keith Ansell-Pearson and
Duncan Large (eds) The Nietzsche Reader, Blackwell: London, 2006, pp. 385-9.
(Translator's note: all further paragraph references in this chapter refer to the
Blackwell Ansell-Pearson/Large edition of European Nihilism - also referred to as
the Lenzer Heide fragment.)
Bibliography
Friedrich Nietzsche
Werke, Kritische Studienausgabe (KSA), eds, Georgio Colli and Mazzino
Montinari, 15 vols, de Gruyter, Berlin and New York, 1967-77.
For the texts written before The Birth of Tragedy: Hans Joachim Mette and
Karl Schlechta edition, Friedrich Nietzsche, Werke und Briefe, HistorischKritische Gesamtausgabe (HKW), C.H. Beck'sche Verlagsbuch, Munich,
1937.
Sdmtliche Briefe: Kritische Studienausgabe, eds, Giorgio Colli and Mazzino
Montinari, 8 vols, de Gruyter, Berlin and New York, 1986.
Fatum und Geschichte, HKW, II. English translation: "Fate and History:
Thoughts," by George, J. Stack, in Keith Ansell Pearson and Duncan
Large, eds, The Nietzsche Reader, Blackwell, London, 2006.
Die Geburt der Tragodie, KSA, I. English translation: The Birth of Tragedy, by
Walter Kaufmann, in The Basic Writings of Nietzsche, Modern Library, New
York, 2000.
Vom Nutzen und Nachteil der Historiefur das Leben, KSA I. English translation:
"On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life." in Untimely Meds,
RJ. Hollingdale, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1997.
Schopenhauer als Erzieher, KSA, I. English translation "Schopenhauer as
Educator," in R. J. Hollingdale, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1997.
Menschliches, Allzumenschliches I & II, KSA, II. English translation: Human,
All-too-Human, by RJ. Hollingdale, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1995.
Morgenrote, KSA, III. English translation: Daybreak, by RJ. Hollingdale,
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1997.
Die frohliche Wissenschaft, KSA, III. English translation: The Gay Science, by
Josefine NauckhofF, edited by Bernard Williams, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge, 2001.
Also sprach Zarathustra, KSA, IV. English translation: Thus Spoke Zarathustra,
by Walter Kaufmann in The Portable Nietzsche, Viking Books, New York,
1976.
186
Bibliography
Jenseits von Gut und Bose, KSA, V. English translation: Beyond Good and Evil,
by Marion Faber, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1998.
Gotzen-Ddmmerung, Der Antichrist, Ecce Homo, KSA, VI. English translation:
The Anti-Christ, Ecce Homo, Twilight of Idols and other writings, ed. Aaron
Ridley and Judith Norman, translated by Judith Norman, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge, 1999.
Dionysos-Dithyramben, KSA, VI. English translation: Dithyrambs of Dionysus, by
R.J. Hollingdale, Black Swan Books, Redding Ridge, 1984.
For the posthumous work:
The Will to Power, translated by Walter Kaufman and RJ.Hollingdale, Vintage Books, New York, 1967.
Writings from the Late Notebooks, translated by Kate Sturge, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge, 2003.
"Notes from 1881," translated by Duncan Large, Keith Ansell-Pearson,
Diane Morgan, in Keith Ansell-Pearson and Duncan Larghe (eds) The
Nietzsche Reader, Blackwell, London, 2006, pp. 238-41.
"European Nihilism," translated by Duncan Large, in Keith Ansell-Pearson and Duncan Large, eds, The Nietzsche Reader, Blackwell, London,
2006, pp. 385-389.
Secondary Works
AAW. Nietzsche aujourd'huif, 2 vols, Col 10/18, UGE, Paris, 1973.
Abel, Gunter, Nietzsche, Die Dynamik der Willen zur Macht und die ewige Wiederkehr, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin and New York, 1984.
Allen Gillespie, Michael and Strong, Tracy B., eds, Nietzsche's New Seas:
Explorations in Philosophy, Aesthetics, and Politics, University of Chicago
Press, Chicago and London, 1988.
Allison, David B., ed., The New Nietzsche: Contemporary Styles of Interpretation,
MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts and London, 1985.
Andler, Charles, Nietzsche, sa vie et sa pensee, Gallimard, Paris, 1958.
Ansell Pearson, Keith, Viroid Life: Perspectives on Nietzsche and the Transhuman Condition, Routledge, London, 1997.
Ansell Pearson, Keith and Caygill, Howard, eds, The Fate of the New Nietzsche,
Aldershot, Avebury, 1993.
Barnes, Jonathan, "La doctrine du Retour Eternel," in Les Stoiciens et leur
Logique, Vrin, Paris, 1978, pp. 3-20.
Behler, Ernst, "Nietzsche and Deconstruction," in Volker Durr, Reinhold
Grimm, and Kathy Harms, eds, Nietzsche: Literature and Values, University
of Wisconsin Press, Madison, 1988.
Bibliography
187
Boyer, Alain, Comte-Sponville, A., Descombes, V., Ferry, L., Legros, R.,
Raynaud, Ph., Renaut, A., Taguieff, P.A. Pourquoi nous ne sommes pas
nietzscheens, Grasset, Paris, 1991. English translation: Why We Are Not
Nietzscheans, translated by Robert de Loaiza, University of Chicago Press,
Chicago, 1997.
Brehier, Emile, Chrysippe, Felix Alcan, Paris, 1910.
Burckhardt, Jacob, The Civilization of the Renaissance in Italy (1860), translated by Peter Murray, Penguin, London, 1990.
Colli, Giorgio, Dopo Nietsche, Adelphi, Milan, 1974.
Scritti su Nietzsche, Adelphi Editore, Milan, 1980.
La ragione errabonda. Quaderni postumi, a cura di Enrico Colli, Adelphi,
Milan, 1990.
Courtine, Jean-Frangois, Extase de la Raison. Essais sur Schelling, Galilee,
Paris, 1990.
Cox, Christoph, Nietzsche: Naturalism and Interpretation, University of California Press, Berkeley, Los Angeles and London, 1999.
Crowther, Paul, "The Kantian Sublime, the Avant Garde and the Postmodern: A Critique of Lyotard," New Formations, Spring 1989, 7: 67-75.
Dahlhaus, Carl, Musikdsthetik, Laaber Verlag, Laaber, 1979. English translation: Aesthetics of Music, translated by William W. Austin, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge, 1982.
Deleuze, Gilles, Nietzsche et la Philosophie, PUF, Paris, 1962. English translation: Nietzsche and Philosophy, translated by Hugh Tomlinson, Athlone
Press, London, 1983.
Difference et Repetition, PUF, Paris, 1969. English translation: Difference
and Repetition, translated by Paul Patton, Columbia University Press, New
York, 1994.
Logique du Sens, Minuit, Paris, 1969. English translation: The Logic of
Sense, translated by Mark Lester and Charles Stivale, Columbia University Press, New York, 1990.
Mille Plateaux, Minuit, Paris, 1980 (with Felix Guattari). English
translation: A Thousand Plateaus - Capitalism and Schizophrenia, translated
by Brian Massumi, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1987.
Foucault, Minuit, Paris, 1986. English translation: by Sean Hand,
University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1988.
-Pourparlers, Minuit, Paris, 1990, English translation: Negotiations,
translated by Martin Joughin, Columbia University Press, New York,
1995.
Qu'est-ce que le Philosophie?, Minuit, Paris, 1991 (with Felix Guattari).
English translation: What is Philosophy? translated by Hugh Tomlinson
and Graham Burchell, Columbia University Press, New York, 1994.
Critique et Clinique, Minuit, Paris, 1993. English translation: Essays
188
Bibliography
Bibliography
189
190
Bibliography
Love, Frederick R., Young Nietzsche and the Wagnerian Experience, University
of North Carolina Press, Chapel Hill, 1963.
Lowith, Karl, Nietzsches Philosophie der ewigen Wiederkehr des deichen, Kohlhamer, Stuttgart, 1956. English translation: Nietzsche's Philosophy of the
Eternal Recurrence of the Same, translated byj. Harvey Lomax, University of
California Press, Berkeley, Los Angeles and London, 1997.
From Hegel to Nietzsche: The Revolution in Nineteenth-Century Thought,
translated by David E. Green, Rinehart & Winston, New York, 1964.
Lyotard, Jean-Francois, L'Inhumain. Causeries sur le temps, Galilee, Paris,
1988. English translation: The Inhuman: Reflections on Time, translated
by Geoffrey Bennington and Rachel Bowlby, Polity Press, Cambridge,
1991.
Lemons sur I'Analytique du sublime, Galilee, Paris, 1991. English translation: Lessons on the Analytic of the Sublime: Kant's Critique of Judgment
[sections 23-29], translated by Elizabeth Rottenberg, Stanford University Press, California, 1994.
-"Reponse a la question: qu'est-ce que le postmoderne?" in Critique,
419, April 1982.
Magnus, Bernd, Nietzsche's Existential Imperative, Indiana University Press,
Bloomington and London, 1978.
Martin, Nicholas, Nietzsche and Schiller: Untimely Aesthetics, Oxford University Press, Oxford and New York, 1996.
May, Keith M., Nietzsche and the Spirit of Tragedy, St Martin's Press, New
York, 1990.
Moles, Alistair, Nietzsche's Philosophy of Nature and Cosmology, Lang, New
York, 1990.
Montinari, Mazzino, "Nietzsche und Wagner vor hundert Jahren," in
Nietzsche - Studien, 7 (1978), pp. 288-307.
Che cosa ha veramente ditto Nietzsche, Casa Editrice Astrolabio-Ubaldini
Editore, Rome, 1975.
Nietzsche, Editori Riuniti, Rome, 1996.
Morel, Georges, Nietzsche, Introduction a une premiere lecture, Aubier-Montaigne, Paris, 1971.
Morrison, Robert G., Nietzsche and Buddhism: A Study in Nihilism and Ironic
Affinities, Oxford University Press, Oxford and New York, 1997.
Nancy, Jean-Luc and Deguy, Michel, eds, Du Sublime, Belim, Paris, 1988.
English translation: Of the Sublime: Presence in Question, translated by
Jeffrey S. Librett, SUNY Press, New York, 1993.
Nattiez, Jean-Jacques, Le Combat de Chronos et d'Orphee, Christian Bourgois
Editeur, Paris, 1993.
Nehamas, Alexander, Nietzsche: Life as Literature, Harvard University Press,
Cambridge, Massachusetts and London, 1985.
Philonenko, Alexis, Le transcendental et la pensee moderne, PUF, Paris, 1990.
Bibliography
191
192
Bibliography
Bibliography
193
Index
Abel, Gunter 190
actual, the
distinction between empirical and
intelligible character 39-42, 46,
51, 54, 72-6, 106
as phenomenal manifestation of
eternity 26, 34, 83
Adorno, Theodor 5, 7
aesthetics
aesthetic education and political
Utopia 3-6
aesthetic of nostalgia 117
aesthetic of pessimism 12, 22, 29
of the beautiful 2, 10
consciousness of finitude of the
aesthetic subject 19
Dionysian see Dionysus and the
Dionysian
of existence 87
formalist aesthetic 31
individuation between the aesthetic
and the ethical 40-3
justification of existence 42
Kantian concept of aesthetic
judgment 1-6
Kantian concept of ethical judgment
3,5
negative representation 2-3
in postmodern debate 1-10
Schopenhauerian transformation of
Kantian 13-20, 26
sensus communis as aesthetic
foundation to ethical judgment
in Kant 3, 5
of the sublime see sublime, the
theological interpretation of 33
of the transcendental-pragmatic 2
universality of the aesthetic 2, 4,
14-15
of the unrepresentable 9, 10
am&rfati 66, 85-7, 91, 94
Andler, Charles 86
Antichrist, The 99, 100, 101, 103
Apollo and the Apollonian
Apollo as an ethical divinity 77
Dionysian/Apollonian polarity 10,
34,77
individuation 41, 42
justification of appearance 34
art
Dionysian 10
Kantian aesthetic and the
interpretation of 2-3
Schopenhauerian cartography of
forms of 23, 27
theophanic condition of 33
atomism 52, 53-4, 56
Attempt at the Revaluation of All Values,
The 99
Bataille, G. 7
Baumgarten, Alexander 14
beauty
the beautiful and the sublime 1-3,
10-11, 12-15, 18,26,30-2
Kantian aesthetic judgment and 1-6
Kantian aesthetic of the beautiful 2,30
as manifestation of an Idea
(Schopenhauer) 12-16
musical 31
Schopenhauerean aesthetic of the
beautiful 14-15, 18, 21-2, 26
196
Index
individuation in 40-2
oblique treatment of sublime
condition of music 29-30
postmodern reading of 5-11
premises of postmodern aesthetic
theory 7
Schopenhauerian roots to aesthetic
of 11-12, 16
the sublime and the beautiful in 9,
10-11
tragedy as musical drama 29, 30, 34
Brehier, Emile 93
Buddhism 147, 153-4
calculability in nature 126, 127
causality, principle of 17, 45-6
individual as origin and end of chain
of causation 49
chance 68
Christian morality 89-93, 100,128,132,
148
self-dissolution of Christian morals
135
Chrysippus 88, 95
Cicero 96
and Montinari, Mazzino 99, 137
Comte-Sponville, A. 8
contemplation
disinterested contemplation of forms
2, 18
intuitive contemplation of Ideas 18, 32
pure contemplation 21-2, 28
contingency 68
Dawn, The 44, 105
Daybreak 91
decadence 86, 132, 133-5, 137
Deleuze, G.
in Nietzsche's legacy 7
on Nietzsche's relationship to
Stoicism 86-7
Derrida, Jacques
"artist's metaphysics" 5
as French Nietzschean 7
Descombes, V. 8
determinism 73, 91-2
see also necessity
Diocles of Magnesia 88
Diogenes Laertius, essay on 88, 93, 95,
98
Dionysus 99
Dionysus and the Dionysian
Dionysian/Apollonian polarity 10.
34,77
Dionysian ecstasy 41-2, 77, 82
Dionysian experience 29, 64
Eternal Return and 103
as the experience of the sublime
8-11, 34
as symbol of unity of the will
(Schopenhauer) 41, 77
Yes to all existence 64, 86
Dithyrambs of Dionysus 66
drama
musical 9, 29-34
tragic 24, 33, 42
dreams 16, 25
Ecce Homo
amorfati 97
197
Index
Eternal Return 93, 103, 104, 138, 157
revaluation of all values 99, 100, 139
tragedy xii, xiii
ecstasy, Dionysian 10, 34, 41-2, 77, 82
energy-quantum, will to power 53-4,
60-1, 126, 129
Epictetus 90-1, 92
maxims 86, 87
Epicurus 88
Eternal Return/Recurrence
ambiguity and decision 116-18
anthropological perspective 118, 124
demon's message 115
eternity and 66
as an experience of nostalgia 110-11,
117, 120
as an experience of remorse 108-15
genesis of the idea 80, 91, 92-3,
102-3
individuality and 46-50
the instant as the true perspective to
idea of 120-5
necessity and 65-7, 72
nihilism and xiv, 101, 128-32, 147-57
and the over-human 115, 118-23
phenomenal consciousness and 124
place in project of revaluation of all
values 99-104, 125-32, 138
reformulation of Stoic idea of 65, 86,
92-4
selectivity and 131
spirit of revenge and 71
strange disappearance of idea xiv,
102-4, 124, 138
and the tragic xii-xiv, 122
typological perspective 124
will to power and 63, 126-9
eternity
as ever present 68, 75, 82
as fatum 66
as ideality (Schopenhauer) 26
as immutability of character 39-40,
73-5
individuality and 62-4
as infinite repetition 48-50
as intemporality 77-83
fragment
fate
fatum 67-82, 97
love of (amor fati) 66, 85-7, 91, 94
Fate and History 67, 77
Ferry, Luc 8
Fink, Eugen 123, 124
force 57-62
hierarchy of forces 59-62, 136, 144-6
Foucault, Michel 5, 7, 87
free will
error of 1056
fatum and 67-73, 75-6
freedom 66, 69, 72, 73
defined by actuality and immutability
75,83
guilt and the intuitive condition of
106
morality and 105-7
Freedom of the Witt and Fate 67
French Nietzscheanism 7
Cast, Peter 137, 146
Gay Science, The
198
Index
5, 6, 7-8
postmodern debate 1-12
return to Kant 6-7, 9
the "transcendental-pragmatic" 1-2
Hanslick, Eduard 31-2
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 37, 85,
87
inverted Hegelianism 134
Heidegger, Martin
hermeneutical ontology of time
108-9, 123-4
the over-human and end of
humanism 101
postmodern debate 5, 7
hierarchy offerees 59-62, 136, 144-6
history
antiquarian 80-1
critical 81
fate and 67-8, 77-8
life and 77-82
monumental 79-80
supra-historical awareness 82
Human, All Too Human
break with Schopenhauer 44-7, 112
individuation 44
individuality
essence of world within the individual
51-3, 54
essential relations of the individual
57-9
eternity and 62-4
hierarchy of 61-2
as identity in repetition 46-50 see also
Eternal Return/Recurrence
imaginary and real individuals 53-4
immanent quest for 37-8
the individual without qualities 44-6
individuals as only real beings 38
in Kant 106-8
nomadic individualities 54-5
perception and 57-9
perspective and 59-61
in Schopenhauer 39-40
spontaneity and 55-7, 62, 63
in the theory of the will to power 5064
individuation 38, 39-46, 51-5
innocence 108
chance as the innocence of
becoming 68
Nietzsche's naturalism and the access
to innocence of nature 65-7, 912,94
intelligible character 39-40, 73-6, 77
distinction between empirical and
Index
intelligible character 39-42, 46,
51, 54, 72-6, 106
intuition
of the beautiful 26
of freedom 106
of the sublime 26
understanding and 16-18, 51
Jankelevitch, Vladimir 111
Kant, Immanuel
concept of freedom 106-7
Critique of Judgment 1-10, 13, 25, 30
Critique of Pure Reason 74, 106
distinction between beautiful and
sublime 1-3, 10, 13-15
empirical and intelligible character
39-40, 73-6
formalism of Kantian morality 87
individuality 106-8
as target in Nietzsche's "practice of
war" 85
theory of the sublime 2-3, 7, 8, 9, 13,
19-20
vicious circle in foundation of
morality through freedom 106-7
Klossowski, Pierre 7
knowledge
converted into pure contemplation 28
decried by life 82
innocence and 108
Nietzsche's naturalism and the access
to innocence of nature 65-7, 912,94
nullified will as pure subject of 40
Schopenhauerean aesthetic and
theory of 16-18
self-destruction of nihilism and 144-5
serving life 78-9
the sublime and 10-11
Kofman, Sarah 7
Lacoue-Labarthe, Philippe 7, 8
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm 38
Lenzer Heide fragment ( The European
Nihilism) 128-30, 132, 136-57
199
life
beauty and the intensification of 13
cursed 105
evocation of nostalgia through events
of 117
history and 77-82
individuals as systems of 52, 53, 55
nature and 96
remorse as revolt of life against itself
105
saying Yes to existence 64, 86, 129,
152
tragedy of 24-5
as will to power 96
Luther, Martin 135
Lyotard, Jean-Francois
"artist's metaphysics" 5
controversy with Habermas 5, 6-7, 8-9
as French Nietzschean 7, 9
"negative representation" 1, 2-3
and the sublime 1-3, 7-9
Mahler, Gustav xii
man
as analogy of world in itself 51-2
between automaton and God 70, 72
death of 101
the Stoic wise man vs. the Christian
religious man 89-93
supra-historical 82
metaphysics
of the artist 5, 8
in Birth of Tragedy 34, 40-2
Dionysian ecstasy as metaphysical
experience 34, 40-2
duality of atemporal essence and
existence in time 77-80
Kantian concept of metaphysics and
the limits of human knowledge
26-7, 105-7
naturalist see naturalism
Nietzsche's critique and return to
Kant's theory of knowledge 44-5
Nietzsche's philosophy as last
modern metaphysics of necessity
65 see also necessity
200
Index
as response to Kantian/
Schopenhauerean duality 44-5
as revelation of the innocence of the
world 65-7, 91-2, 94, 108
nature, living by 958
necessity
as determinism 73, 91-2
as eternal repetition 65-7, 72
eternity as mode of 66, 75-7
as fatum see fate
as immutability of character 73-5
as irrevocability of the past 108-15
life and 77-8
as local and instantaneous
copossibility 125-7
of nature 94
will to power 126, 149-51
negative representation 1, 2-3, 25
converted into representation
without an object 28
see also unrepresentable, the
Nietzsche's works
The Antichrist 99, 100, 101, 103
The Attempt at the Revaluation of All
Values 99
Beyond Good and Evil see Beyond Good
and Evil
The Birth of Tragedy see Birth of Tragedy,
The
The Dawn 44, 105
Daybreak 91
Dionysus 99
Ecce Homo see Ecce Homo
The European Nihilism (Lenzer Heide
fragment) 128-30, 132, 136-57
Fate and History 67, 77
Freedom of the Witt and Fate 67
The Gay Science see Gay Science, The
The Genealogy of Morals see Genealogy of
Morals, The
Human, Att Too Human 44-7, 86,
105-8, 112, 114
The Immoralist 99
Lenzer Heide fragment ( The
European Nihilism) 128-30, 132,
136-57
Index
Mixed Opinions and Maxims 44, 105
poems 66
Thus Spoke Zarathustra see Thus Spoke
Zarathustra
Twilight of the Idols 100, 103, 134, 138,
139
Untimely Meditations 41-3, 76, 77-83,
134
The Wanderer and His Shadow 44, 105
We That Say Yes 99
The Will to Power 63-4, 99-101, 137-9
nihilism
decadence and 132, 133-5, 137
Eternal Return and xiv, 101, 128-32,
147-57
forms of 37, 139-42, 144-8
Lenzer Heide fragment 136-57
Lvotard's nihilistic sublime 1
as a negative dialectic 145-6
overcoming of 101, 132, 143-6
in The Will to Power 99-101, 137-9
will to power and 103, 104, 124, 127-9
nostalgia 110-11, 115-20
On the Genealogy of Morality see Genealogy
of Morals, The
over-human, the (Ubermensch)
anthropological description of time
as ground of concept 108-15
disappearance of idea 101, 115,
118-23
and the end of humanism 101
Pautrat, Bernard 7
perception
as appearance 14, 27, 29
as property of every force 57-60
perspectivism
as ground for individuality of every
force 57, 59-62
as typology 142-7
pessimism
aesthetic of 12, 22, 29
ethic of 11, 74
and metaphysical condemnation of
individuated life 39-40
201
202
Index
appearance of 15-16, 46
experience of absolute absence of 10
metaphysical world and world of
representation 44
music as the representation of the
unrepresentable 27-8
negative representation see negative
representation
the sublime as a representation of the
unrepresentable 25-6, 33
Utopian 3
will and 16-18
see also unrepresentable, the
revaluation of all values
amorfati 87
in Birth of Tragedy xiii
eternal return xiv, 103-4, 115, 12732, 148-57
genesis of the project 99-101, 103
nihilism 133-6, 141-8
will to power 125-32
Key, Jean-Michel 7
Romanticism 5, 9, 10, 74
Schiller, Friedrich
On the Aesthetic Education of Man 3-5,
6
Schillerean romanticism 10 see also
romanticism
Schopenhauer, Arthur
"Aesthetics of Poetry" 24
On the Basis of Morality 75, 105
cartography of the forms of art 23, 27
"Critique of Kantian Philosophy" 14
eternity as ever present 75, 82
experience of remorse as evidence
for morality 105-7
freedom as immutability of character
73-5
individuation 39-40
model of necessity 73-5
morality of compassion 87
music 27-9
Nietzsche's break with 44-5, 105-8
One Witt 37
paradox of individuality 39-40
203
Index
theodicy 68
theology
rejection of theological perspective
68
theological interpretation of
aesthetics 33
see also Christian morality
thing-in-itself
fatum as 72-3, 75
Kantian 10, 72-3, 74
in ontology of music 27-9
reification of 39-40
Universal as 37
as will (Schopenhauer) 31, 34, 39-40,
73-5
as will to power 50-1
see also individuality
Thus Spoke Zarathustra
anthropological understanding of
time 118, 124
chance as the innocence of
becoming 68
Eternal Return 66, 101, 102-3, 1 OSIS, 118-25
irrevocability and irreversibility 11120
the over-human 114-15, 123, 130
spirit of revenge 71, 109-15
time
the ahistorical instant 77-83
anthropology of 118, 124
duality of atemporal essence and
existence in time 77-80
fatum as a figure of the past 71
the instant as the true perspective to
idea of Eternal Return 120-5
irreversibility of 71, 111-12
morality and 108-10
nostalgia and 111, 115-20
phenomenology of 123-5
as real property of things in
becoming 44-50
revolt against the irrevocability of the
past 71, 108-15
and space as appearances 19-21, 32
decadence 134
Eternal Return 103, 138
genesis of the project of revaluation
of all values 100, 139
understanding, intuitive 16-18
unrepresentable, the
aesthetic of 9, 10
God and 33
moral law and 3, 33
music and 27-8, 33-4
the sublime and 25-7, 33
Untimely Meditations
Eternal Return 80
historicism 134
individuality 41-3
metaphysical hierarchy 76
time 77-83
utilitarianism 87
Utopia, political 3-6
values
inversion of 37
revaluation of see revaluation of all
values
universal validity of value judgments
5
Wagner Case, The 85, 139
204
Index