Morgan (2014) - Pragmatism As A Paradigm For Social Research
Morgan (2014) - Pragmatism As A Paradigm For Social Research
Morgan (2014) - Pragmatism As A Paradigm For Social Research
research-article2013
QIXXXX10.1177/1077800413513733Qualitative InquiryMorgan
Article
Qualitative Inquiry
2014, Vol. 20(8) 10451053
The Author(s) 2013
Reprints and permissions:
sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav
DOI: 10.1177/1077800413513733
qix.sagepub.com
David L. Morgan1
Abstract
Although advocates of mixed-methods research have proposed pragmatism as a paradigm for social research, nearly all
of that work has emphasized the practical rather than the philosophical aspects of pragmatism. This article addresses that
gap by connecting John Deweys work on experience and inquiry to current issues in the study of social research. In doing
so, it also addresses the political concerns that link pragmatism and social justice. As a new paradigm, pragmatism disrupts
the assumptions of older approaches based on the philosophy of knowledge, while providing promising new directions for
understanding the nature of social research.
Keywords
mixed-methods design, methodologies, pragmatism, methods of inquiry, John Dewey
Although the possibility of pursuing pragmatism as a paradigm for social research is not entirely new (e.g., Gage,
1989; Howe, 1988; Patton, 1988), its frequent linkage with
Mixed-Methods Research (MMR) has heightened the
awareness of pragmatism (e.g., Biesta, 2010; Hall, 2013;
Johnson & Onwuegbuzie, 2004; Maxcy, 2003; Morgan,
2007; Pearce, 2012; Tashakkori & Teddlie, 2010). There
are, however, legitimate questions about the extent to which
MMR has actually made use of the intellectual foundations
of pragmatism as a philosophy (Denzin, 2010, 2012). MMR
has emphasized the practical aspect of research methods in
ways that both introduced pragmatism as a paradigm for
social research, largely avoiding serious contact with the
philosophical foundations of pragmatism.
Does arguing for a broader application of pragmatism to
social research require a clarification of its specific relationship to MMR? At issue here is the idea that pragmatism is
somehow uniquely related to MMR. This confusion is reminiscent of some paradigmatic claims that qualitative methods must be connected to constructivism and quantitative
methods must be connected to post-positivism. In all of
these cases, there may be an affinity between paradigms and
methods, but there is no deterministic link that forces the
use of a particular paradigm with a particular set of methods. Although the recent resurgence of interest in pragmatism was indeed sparked by an attempt to resolve issues
Corresponding Author:
David L. Morgan, Department of Sociology, Portland State University,
Portland, OR 97207-0751, USA.
Email: [email protected]
1046
Pragmatism as a Philosophy
The crude summary of pragmatism as merely asking about
what works has been a perennial problem (Dewey,
1920/2008), so it is hardly surprising that it is occurring
once again. Of course, a similar kind of caricature also
exists for simplistic versions of constructivism, in which
social structure exists only in the imaginations of atomistic
individuals, and in retrograde summaries of post-positivism, which still insist on a one-to-one correspondence
between our observations and some external reality.
Fortunately, the ongoing discussions of the last decades
about paradigms (Guba, 1990) have created a more sophisticated understanding of constructivism and post-positivism
as paradigms for social research. Unfortunately, the omission of pragmatism from that debate has limited our understanding of it as a philosophical system. Hence, clarifying
the value of pragmatism as a philosophy for social research
requires getting past an emphasis on practicality.
The sheer difficulty of designing and carrying out MMR
helps explain the fields attraction to the portions of pragmatism that highlight workable approaches to problem
solving. MMR as a research community has a strong tendency to emphasize the how to aspects of research; however, this captures only part of the message of pragmatism,
which places more importance on questions about why to do
research in a given way. Following the path of classical
pragmatism (e.g., James, 1907/1995), we need to ask, What
difference does it makes to do our research one way rather
than another? When we ask why to questions, this points
to the importance of our choice of research goals. Yet even
the how to questions involve more than making technical
decisions about research methods because of the commitments we make when we chose one way rather than another
to pursue our goals. Thus, a limited emphasis on what
works is never enough, because it ignores choices about
both the goals to be pursued and the means to meet those
goals.
Denzin (2012) summarizes the importance of these
issues as follows:
The MMR links to the pragmatism of Dewey, James, Mead,
and Peirce are problematic. Classic pragmatism is not a
methodology per se. It is a doctrine of meaning, a theory of
truth. It rests on the argument that the meaning of an event
cannot be given in advance of experience. The focus is on the
consequences and meanings of an action or event in a social
situation. This concern goes beyond any given methodology or
any problem-solving activity. (p. 81)
1047
Morgan
1048
Pragmatism as a Paradigm
Much of Deweys philosophical agenda is highly relevant
for social research today, because he sought to break down
the dualism between realism and idealism. This contrast is
very close to the separation between post-positivism and
constructivism, in which differentiation of these two paradigms has been a central feature in applying the philosophy of knowledge to social research (e.g., Guba & Lincoln,
2005). In this philosophical system, post-positivists claim
that the world exists apart from our understanding of it,
while constructivists insist that the world is created by our
conceptions of it. For Dewey (1925a/2008), these two
assertions are equally important claims about the nature of
human experience. On one hand, our experiences in the
world are necessarily constrained by the nature of that
world; on the other hand, our understanding of the world is
inherently limited to our interpretations of our experiences.
We are not free to believe anything we want about the world
if we care about the consequences of acting on those beliefs.
Within Deweys pragmatism and its emphasis on experience, ontological arguments about either the nature of the
outside world or the world of our conceptions are just discussions about two sides of the same coin.
1049
Morgan
Deweys rejection of arguments about the nature of reality is not the same, however, as denying the differences
between post-positivism and constructivism as approaches
to research. Researchers from these traditions have very
difference experiences in the world of research, and these
experiences lead to different beliefs and different actions.
The point here is that any attempt to produce knowledge
occurs within a social context. Morgan (2007) interprets
Kuhns (1996) concept of paradigms in terms of the importance of shared beliefs within a community of researchers
who share a consensus about which questions are most
meaningful and which methods are most appropriate for
answering those questions (2007, p. 53). Paradigms are
thus social worlds where research communities exert a
powerful influence over the beliefs we consider to be
meaningful and the actions we accept as appropriate.
Using a conception of paradigms as shared beliefs within
a community of researchers, what we know as and post-positivism and constructivism easily fit within this definition due
to the distinctive research experiences that they define and
promote. Rather than assigning post-positivism and constructivism a priori to different ontological and epistemological camps, a pragmatist would focus on their characteristic
approaches to inquiry. Each of them creates its own world of
researchdifferent contexts with different feelings about
and different standards for the nature of inquiry.
For metaphysical versions of the philosophy of knowledge, assumptions about the nature of reality determine the
kinds of knowledge that are possible. For pragmatism, this
abstraction is replaced by an emphasis on experience as the
continual interaction of beliefs and action. This leads to
questions about what difference it makes not only to acquire
knowledge one way rather than another (i.e., the procedures
we use), but to produce one kind of knowledge rather than
another (i.e., the purposes we pursue). Knowledge is not
about an abstract relationship between the knower and the
known; instead, there is an active process of inquiry that
creates a continual back-and-forth movement between
beliefs and actions.
The key point here is that pragmatism as a paradigm can
account for one of the most distinctive features of the previous paradigmthe importance of distinguishing between
post-positivism and constructivismwithout relying on
metaphysical assumptions about ontology and epistemology. Pragmatism not only replaces arguments about the
nature of reality as the essential criterion for differentiating
approaches to research, it also recognizes the value of those
different approaches as research communities that guide
choices about how to conduct inquiry. Thus, pragmatism
acts as a new paradigm to replace an older way of thinking
about the differences between approaches to research by
treating those differences as social contexts for inquiry as a
form of social action, rather than as abstract philosophical
systems.
Dewey and other classic pragmatists felt that the longstanding debates in traditional metaphysics were seriously
misguided. By ignoring the centrality of human experience,
these debated simply asked the wrong questions. Of course,
this dismissal of metaphysical issues will not sit well with
those who advocate for their importance in understanding
social research. Accordingly, Yvonna Lincoln (2010) complains, The mixed-methods pragmatists tell us nothing
about their ontology or epistemology (p. 7). This demand
that pragmatism pay attention to metaphysics is hardly new,
and as noted above, Dewey himself saw his version of pragmatism as what we would now call a new paradigm within
his home discipline of philosophy. Thus, in a passage from
his work on evolution that sounds very much like Thomas
Kuhn (1996), Dewey claims that rather than solving the traditional philosophical problems, we need to get over them.
Intellectual progress usually occurs through sheer abandonment
of questions together with both of the alternatives they
assumean abandonment that results from their decreasing
vitality and a change of urgent interest. We do not solve them:
we get over them. Old questions are solved by disappearing,
evaporating, while new questions corresponding to the changed
attitude of endeavor and preference take their place. (Dewey,
1910/2008, p. 14)
1050
As the preceding discussion indicates, these same defining characteristics also underlie pragmatism as a philosophy.
1051
Morgan
The difference is that these principles flow directly from
pragmatisms core assumptions about the nature of inquiry
without any need to add axiology as a separate element.
While there is no doubt that metaphysical discussions about
the nature of reality and truth can be extended to handle the
political and ethical aspects of research, pragmatism as a
philosophical paradigm has the advantage of naturally
assigning a central role of politics and ethics in every aspect
of human experience.
Once again, the larger point is that pragmatism as a
broad paradigm for social research can account for the
accomplishments of the previous paradigm without the
need for metaphysical assumptions. In this case, pragmatism can stand outside the previous assumptions and still
provide at least as strong a bond to social justice goals. Both
social justice and pragmatism treat our actions as researchers as located within belief systems, in which those beliefs
are subject to change by our conscious actions. Furthermore,
both the experiences we bring to research and the changes
we hope to produce are context bound, embodied and emotional, and thoroughly social in nature. Taken together,
these strengths point to both the value of classical pragmatism as an orientation toward social justice and the potential
for current work on social justice to continue pragmatisms
development in this direction.
Conclusion
In considering the increased interest in pragmatism as a
paradigm for social research, it is essential to recognize that
paradigms are more than simple statements about future
directions for research. From the perspective of pragmatism, new paradigms create new sets of beliefs that guide
new kinds of actions. At a fundamental level, paradigms
create new worldviews and social contexts that have widespread impacts on the conduct of inquiry.
Understanding the shift toward pragmatism as a paradigm begins with the recent history of social research methodology, from which interest in pragmatism emerged
through its association with MMR. MMR, in turn, arose in
a period when it was expected that any approach to social
research would have a metaphysical paradigm explicitly
based on the philosophy of knowledge. Yet, MMR did not
fit comfortably within that context. In particular, most of
the focus in MMR was on practical, procedural issues about
how to combine the strengths of qualitative and quantitative
methods rather than philosophical claims. Thus, for most of
the researchers operating within the field of MMR, the
appeal of pragmatism was more about its practicality than
in its broader philosophical basis.
That is the setting for this articlea moment when pragmatism has been proposed as a new paradigm for social
research, yet its potential in this regard has remained underdeveloped. The time has come for social research to dig
1052
Funding
The author(s) received no financial support for the research,
authorship, and/or publication of this article.
References
Biesta, G. (2010). Pragmatism and the philosophical foundations
of mixed methods research. A. Tashakkori & C. Teddlie
(Eds.), Handbook of mixed methods research for the social
& behavioral sciences (2nd ed. pp. 95-118). Thousand Oaks,
CA: SAGE.
Biesta, G., & Barbules, N. (2004). Pragmatism and educational
research. New York, NY: Rowman & Littlefield.
Denzin, N. (2010). Moments, mixed methods, and paradigm dialogs. Qualitative Inquiry, 16, 419-427.
Denzin, N. (2012). Triangulation 2.0. Journal of Mixed Methods
Research, 6, 80-88.
Dewey, J. (2008). How we think. In J. Boydston (Ed.), The middle
works of John Dewey, 1899-1924 (Vol. 11, pp. 105-353).
Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press. (Original
work published 1910a)
Dewey, J. (2008). The influence of Darwinism on philosophy.
In J. Boydston & L. Hahn (Eds.), The middle works of John
Dewey, 1899-1924 (Vol. 4, pp. 1-215). Carbondale: Southern
Illinois University Press. (Original work published 1910b)
Dewey, J. (2008). Reconstruction in philosophy. In J. Boydston
& R. Ross (Eds.), The middle works of John Dewey, 18991924 (Vol. 12, pp. 77-202). Carbondale: Southern Illinois
University Press. (Original work published 1920)
Dewey, J. (2008). Human nature and conduct. In J. Boydston & G.
Murphy (Eds.), The middle works of John Dewey, 1899-1924
(Vol. 14, pp. 1-227). Carbondale: Southern Illinois University
Press. (Original work published 1922)
Dewey, J. (2008). Experience and nature. In J. Boydston & S.
Hook (Eds.), The later works of John Dewey, 1925-1953
(Vol. 1, pp. 1-437). Carbondale: Southern Illinois University
Press. (Original work published 1925a)
Dewey, J. (2008). The public and its problems. In J. Boydston &
J. Gouinlock (Eds.), The later works of John Dewey, 19251953 (Vol. 2, pp. 235-372). Carbondale: Southern Illinois
University Press. (Original work published 1925b)
Dewey, J. (2008). Creative democracy. In J. Boydston & J.
Gouinlock (Eds.), The later works of John Dewey, 19251953 (Vol. 14, pp. 224-230). Carbondale: Southern Illinois
University Press. (Original work published 1939)
Dewey, J. (2008). Propositions, warranted assertibility and truth.
In J. Boydston (Ed.), The later works of John Dewey, 19251953 (Vol. 14, pp. 168-188). Carbondale: Southern Illinois
University Press. (Original work published 1941)
Gage, N. L. (1989). The paradigm wars and their aftermath: A
historical sketch of research and teaching since 1989.
Educational Researcher, 18, 4-10.
Guba, E. (1990). The paradigm dialog. Newbury Park, CA: SAGE.
Guba, E., & Lincoln, Y. (2005). Paradigmatic controversies, contradictions, and emerging confluences. In N. Denzin & Y.
Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualitative research (3rd ed., pp.
191-215). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.
Hall, J. (2013). Pragmatism, evidence, and mixed methods evaluation (Special Issue: Mixed methods and credibility of evidence
in evaluation). New Directions for Evaluation, 2013(138), 1526.
Hesse-Biber, S. (2012). Feminist approaches to triangulation:
Uncovering subjugated knowledge and fostering social
change in mixed methods research. Journal of Mixed Methods
Research, 6, 137-146.
Hesse-Biber, S., & Leavy, P. (2008). Introduction: Pushing on the
methodological boundaries: The growing need for emergent
methods within and across the disciplines. In S. Hess-Biber &
P. Leavy (Eds.), Handbook of emergent methods (pp. 1-15).
New York, NY: Guilford Press.
Howe, K. R. (1988). Against the quantitative-qualitative incompatibility thesis or dogmas die hard. Educational Researcher,
17, 10-16.
James, W. (1995). Pragmatism. Mineola, NY: Dover Publications.
(Original work published 1907)
Johnson, B., & Onwuegbuzie, A. (2004). Mixed methods research:
A research paradigm whose time has come. Educational
Researcher, 33(7), 14-26.
Kuhn, T. (1996). The structure of scientific revolutions (3rd ed.).
Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Lincoln, Y. (2010). What a long, strange trip its been:
Twenty-Five years of qualitative and new paradigm research.
Qualitative Inquiry, 16, 3-9.
Maxcy, S. (2003). Pragmatic threads in mixed methods research
in the social sciences: The search for multiple modes of
inquiry and the end of the philosophy of formalism. In A.
Tashakorri & C. Teddlie (Eds.), Handbook of mixed methods in social & behavioral research (pp. 51-90). Thousand
Oaks, CA: SAGE.
Mertens, D. M. (2003). Mixed methods and the politics of human
research: The transformative-emancipatory perspective. In A.
Tashakkori & C. Teddlie (Eds.), Handbook of mixed-methods
in social and behavioral research (pp. 135-166). Thousand
Oaks, CA: SAGE.
Mills, C. (1964). Sociology and pragmatism: The higher learning
in America. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Morgan, D. L. (2007). Paradigms lost and pragmatism regained:
Methodological implications of combining qualitative and
quantitative methods. Journal of Mixed Methods Research,
1, 48-76.
Morgan, D. L. (2013). Integrating qualitative and quantitative
methods: A pragmatic approach. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.
Patton, M. (1988). Paradigms and pragmatism. In D. Fetterman
(Ed.), Qualitative approaches to evaluation in educational
research (pp. 116-137). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.
Pearce, D. 2012. Mixed methods inquiry in sociology. American
Behavioral Scientist, 56, 829-848.
Seigfried, C. (1996). Pragmatism and feminism: Reweaving the
social fabric. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Seigfried, C. (2002a). Feminist interpretations of John Dewey.
University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.
1053
Morgan
Seigfried, C. (2002b). John Deweys pragmatist feminism. In
C. Seigfried (Ed.), Feminist interpretations of John Dewey
(pp. 47-77). University Park: Pennsylvania State University
Press.
Strubing, J. (2007). Research as pragmatic problem solving. In
A. Bryant & K. Charmaz (Eds.), Sage handbook of grounded
theory (pp. 580-601). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.
Sullivan, S. (2001). Living across and through skins. Bloomington:
Indiana University Press.
Tashakkori, A., & Teddlie, C. (2010). Overview of contemporary
issues in mixed methods research. In A. Tashakkori & C.
Teddlie (Eds.), Handbook of mixed methods research for the
Author Biography
David L. Morgan is a professor of sociology at Portland State
University. His work concentrates on focus groups and mixed
methods research. His most recent book is Integrating Qualitative
and Quantitative Research: A Pragmatic Approach from SAGE.