Derrida Envoi 2

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 18

Envoi

!"A"Qx

At the beginning of the twentieth century, in 1901, the French philosopher Henri Bergson made a remark about what he called "our word 'representation,'" our French word representation: (["word representation is
p"txrp{"word that, based on the etymology, ought never to designate
p"xt{{trp{"object presented to the mind for the first time. It ought to
wt"ttts"4("ps" so on.'
llor the moment I leave aside this remark of Bergson's. I shall let it wait
"wt"wtw{s" of an introduction that I propose to entitle simply envoi,
x"wt"xv{p6
cwt"simplicity and singularity of this envoi, this sending or dispatch,

will name perhaps what is ultimately at stake in the questions that I would
{xzt""psst"and submit to you for discussion.
Imagine that French were a dead language. I could just as well wpt
pxsF"attt"wp" to yourselves, French, a dead language. And in some
stone or paper archive, on some roll of microfilm, we could read a sentence. U"tps"it here, let it be the opening sentence of the introductory
address, the discours d'envoi, of this congress: "On dirait alors que nous
sommes en representation''; "One might say then that we are in represent at x6("I repeat: "One might say then that we are in representation."
'lit( of the lecture delivered in July 198o as the opening address at the (8th Annual (;otigress of the SocittS de Philosophic de Langue Francaise at the University of St rasbourg.

d67

95

Are we quite sure we know what this means today? Let us not be too
quick to think so. Perhaps we will have to invent it or re-invent, discover
it or produce it.
I have intentionally begun by allowing the word "representation" to appear already inserted in an idiom, set within the singularity of an expression ("titre en reprsentation"). Its translation into another idiom remains
problematic, which is another way of saying it could not be done without
remainder. I shall not analyze all the dimensions of this problem but will
limit myself to its most apparent outlines.
What do we ourselves know when we pronounce or listen to the sentence I just read? What do we know of this French idiom?
By saying "we," for the moment, I am designating first of all the community that relates to itself as subject of discourse, the community of
those who know their way around French, who know that they know
that, understand each other, and agree to speak, agree by speaking what
we call our language.
Now what we already know is that if we are here in Strasbourg, in
representation, then this event bears an essential relation to a double body,
whether you understand this word in the figure of a corpus, that is, a
body of work, or a corporation. I am thinking, on the one hand, of the
corps of philosophy that can itself be considered a corpus of discursive
acts or of texts but also as the corps or corporation of subjects, of institutions, and of philosophical societies. We are supposed to represent these
societies here, in one way or another, under some form or to some degree
u"legitimacy. We may be considered more or less explicitly mandated
representatives, delegates, ambassadors, emissaries; I prefer to say envoys.
N"on the other hand, this representation also maintains an essential
relation to the body or corpus of the French language. The agreement
wp"gave rise to this eighteenth congress was made in French between
philosophical societies "de langue francaise," whose very status refers to
wtx"linguistic affiliation, to a linguistic difference that does not coincide
with a national difference.
It goes without saying that, in this circumstance, we will not be able
"set aside the part of the philosophical or philosophico-institutional act
wp"belongs to language, to what is supposed to constitute the unity of a
language or a group of "Romance" languages, as they are called [langues

96

Envoi

dites latines]. It is all the more important not to do so in that the theme
chosen by this institution, representation, is more difficult than others to
detach or dissociate from its linguistic instantiation, even its lexical and
above all nominal instantiation, or, as others would be quick to say, from
its nominal representation.
I said I would not analyze all the idiomatic resources of the sentence
with which such a discourse would have begun ("One might say then
that we are in representation"), but let us retain at least this much more:
the sentence evokes the more or less representative representatives, the
envoys we are supposed to be, under the aspect and in the highly regulated time of a kind of spectacle, exhibition, or discursive, if not oratorical, performance, in the course of ceremonious, coded, ritualized exchanges. To be in representation, etre en representation, for an envoy, also
means in our language to show oneself, to-represent-oneself-on-behalfof, to-make-oneself-visible-for, on an occasion that is sometimes called a
manifestation so as to recognize, with this word, a certain solemnity. Appearing in this circumstance goes together with the apparatus of pomp,
and presentation or presence is suddenly remarkable there; it gives itself
to be remarked in representation. And what is remarkable makes for an
event, a consecrated gathering, a feast or ritual destined to renew the
pact, the contract, or the symbol. Well, allow me, as I thank our hosts,
to salute with some insistence the place of what is, right here, taking
place, the place of this taking-place. The event takes place, thanks to the
hospitality of one of our societies, in a city that, although it does not lie
outside of France, as was once, very symbolically, the case, is nevertheless not just any French city. This frontier city is a place of passage and
of translation, a margin, a privileged site for encounter or competition
between two immense linguistic territories, which are also two of the
most densely inhabited worlds of philosophical discourse. And it so happens, il se trouve (saying "il se trouve," I leave in reserve a chance of the
idiom hesitating between chance and necessity) that, if we are to treat
representation, we will not, as philosophers, be able to enclose ourselves
within latinity. It will be neither possible nor legitimate to overlook the
enormous historical stakes of the Latino-Germanic translation, of the
relation between repraesentatio and the Stellen of Vorstellung, Darstellung,
or Gestell. For centuries, as soon as a philosopher, regardless of which

Envoi

97

language he belongs to, undertook an inquiry into repraesentatio, Vor- or


Darstellen, he has found himself, on both sides of the frontier, on both
banks of the Rhine, already caught up, surprised, preceded, anticipated
by the linked co-destination, the strange co-habitation, the contamination and the enigmatic co-translation of these two lexicons. The philosophicaland it is after all philosophical societies that send us here as
their representativescan no longer in this case allow itself to be shut
up within the closure of a single idiom, without thereby being set afloat,
neutral and disembodied, far from every body of language. The simply
philosophical finds itself caught up in advance in a multiple body, a linguistic duality or duel, in the zone of a bilingualism that it can no longer
efface without effacing itself. And one of the numerous supplementary
folds of the enigma follows the line of this translationand of this task
of the translator. We are not "in representation" only as representatives,
as delegates or placeholders sent to an assembly determined to discuss
representation; the problem of translatability that we shall not be able to
avoid will also be a problem of representation. Is translation of the same
order as representation? Does it consist in representing a sense, the same
semantic content, by a different word in a different language? If so, is it
a matter of a substitution that has a representative structure? And as a
privileged example, both supplementary and abyssal, do Vorstellung and
Darstellung play the role of German representations of French (or more
generally Latin) representation or vice versa, is "representation" the pertinent representative of Vorstellung, indeed, of Darstellung? Or does the
so-called relation of translation or of substitution already escape the orbit
of representation, and in that case how should we interpret representation? I shall come back to this exemplary question, which I am merely
situating at the moment. More than once, so as to send things off while
acquitting myself badly of the task with which I am honored, I will have
to proceed in this fashion and limit myself to just recognizing, no more,
certain topoi that today, it seems to me, we should not avoid.
Let us suppose that French were a dead language. We believe we know
how to identify a dead language and have at our disposal a set of fairly rigorous criteria. Trusting in this very nave presumption, represent to yourselves the following scene of decipherment under this condition: Some
philosophers, who are busying themselves with a written corpus, a library

98

Envoi

or a mute archive, would have not only to reconstitute a French language


but by the same token to fix the sense of certain words, to establish a
dictionary or at least some entries for a dictionary. For example, for the
word representation, whose nominal unity would at some point have been
identified. Without any context other than that of written documents, in
the absence of subjects who are called living and intervening in this context, the lexicologist would have to elaborate a dictionary of words (as you
know, the distinction is made between dictionaries of words and dictionaries of thingsmore or less as Freud distinguished word representations
[W ortvorstellungen] from thing representations [Sach- or Dingvorstellungen]). Confident in the unity of the word and in the double articulation
of language, such a lexicon would have to classify the different items of
the word "representation" by their meanings and by their functioning in
a certain state of the language, while taking account of a certain richness
or diversity of corpuses, codes, and contexts. One must thus presuppose
both a profound unity of these different meanings and a law regulating
this multiplicity. A minimum and shared semantic kernel would justify
each time the choice of the "same" word "representation" and would allow itself, precisely, "to be represented" by it, in the most diverse contexts.
In the political domain, we can speak of parliamentary, diplomatic, or
union representation. In the aesthetic domain, we can speak of representation in the sense of mimetic substitution, notably in the so-called
plastic arts, and, in a more problematical manner, of a theatrical representation in a sense that is not necessarily or uniquely reproductive or
repetitive but in order to name in this case a presentation (Darstellung),
an exhibition, a performance. I have just evoked two codes, the political and the aesthetic, leaving aside for the moment the other categories
(metaphysics, history, religion, epistemology) inscribed in the program
of our congress. But there are also all sorts of subcontexts and subcodes,
all sorts of uses of the word "representation" where it seems to mean image, perhaps nonrepresentative, nonreproductive, nonrepetitive, simply
presented and placed before our eyes, before our sensible or intelligible
gam, according to the traditional metaphor that can also be interpreted
and overdetermined as a representation of representation. More broadly,
one can also look for what there is in common between the nominal occurrences of the word "representation" and so many idiomatic locutions
in which the verb "to represent," indeed, "to represent oneself," does not

Envoi

99

appear simply to modulate, in the mode of the "verb," a semantic kernel


that one could identify according to the nominal model of (singular absolute) "representation." If the noun "representation," the adjectives "representing," "representable," "representative," the verbs "to represent" or, in
the pronominal mode in French, se representer [to represent to oneself] are
not only the grammatical modulations of one and the same meaning, if
kernels of different meanings are present, at work in or produced by these
grammatical modes of the idiom, then the lexicologist, the semanticist,
indeed, the philosopher who would try to classify different varieties of
"representation" and of "representing," to give account of the variables
or the divergences from the identity of an invariant meaning, is going to
have a rough time of it.
I am using the hypothesis of the dead language only as a telltale sign.
It draws attention to a situation in which a context cannot be saturated
so as to permit the determination and identification of a sense. Now in
this respect a so-called living language is structurally in the same situation. If there are two conditions for fixing the meaning or overcoming the
polysemy of a wordnamely, the existence of an invariant beneath the
diversity of semantic transformations, on the one hand, and the possibility of determining a saturable context, on the otherthese two conditions seem to me in any case as problematical for a living language as for
a dead one.
And this is more or less, here and now, our situation, we who are in
representation. Whether or not one lays claim to a philosophical use of
so-called natural language, the word representation does not have the same
semantic field and the same mode of functioning as an apparently identical word ("representation" in English, Repriisentation in German) or as the
different words that people take to be its equivalents in current translations (once again, and I shall return to this point, Vorstellung is not just
one example here among others). If we want to understand one another,
to know what we are talking about around a theme that is truly common to us, we have before us two types of large problematics. We can
ask ourselves, on the one hand, what discourse based on representation
means in our common language. And then we will have a task that is not
fundamentally different from that of the semanticist-lexicologist who is
projecting a dictionary of words. But, on the other hand, presupposing
an implicit and practical knowledge on this subject, basing ourselves on

100

Envoi

a living contract or consensus, we can believe that in the end all subjects competent in our language understand one another about this word,
that the variations are only contextual, and that no essential obscurity
will obfuscate discourse about representation; we would then try to give
an account, as they say, of representation today, the thing or the things
named "representations" rather than of the words themselves. We would
have in mind a sort of philosophical dictionnaire raisonne of things rather
than words. We would presuppose that no irreducible misunderstanding is possible as to the content and the destination of the message or
the envoi named "representation." In a "natural" situation (as we also say
a natural language), one could always correct the indeterminacy or the
misunderstanding; and it is at bottom with philosophy that one would
correct philosophy, I mean, the bad effects of philosophy. These would
follow from a gesture that is very common and apparently profoundly
philosophical: to think what a concept means in itself, to think what representation is, the essence of representation in general. This philosophical
gesture first transports the word to its greatest obscurity, in a highly artificial way, by abstracting it from every context and every use value, as if
a word were regulated by a concept independently of any contextualized
function, and even independently of any sentence. You will recognize in
this a type of objection (let us call it roughly "Wittgensteinian," and if
we wish to develop it during the colloquium let us not forget that it was
accompanied for Wittgenstein, at a given stage of his career, by a theory
of representation in language, a picture theory that should be significant
for us here, at least as regards what is "problematical" about it). In this
situation, a colloquy of philosophers always tries to stop the philosophical vertigo that overtakes them very close to their language, and to do
so with a gesture that I said a moment ago was philosophical (philosophy against philosophy), but in fact it is prephilosophical, because one
is then behaving as if one knew what "representation" means and as if
one had only to adjust this knowledge to a present historical situation,
to distribute the articles, the types, or the problems of representation in
different regions, but belonging to the same space. A gesture at once very
philosophical and prephilosophical. One can understand the legitimate
concern of the organizers of this congress, more precisely of its organizing committee Conseil scientifiquel, who in order to avoid, and I quote,
"too great a dispersion" propose to distribute the theme among different
set lions (Aesthetics, Politics, Metaphysics, I listory, Religion, Epistemol-

Envoi

IOI

ogy). "To avoid too great a dispersion": this accepts a certain polysemy,
provided that it is not excessive and recognizes a rule, provided that it
can be measured and governed in this list of six categories or in this encyclopedia, this circle of six circles or six jurisdictions. Nothing is more
legitimate, in theory and practically, than this concern of the organizing
committee. Nevertheless, this list of six categories remains problematic,
as everyone knows. They cannot be spread out upon the same table, as
if one did not imply or never overlapped another, as if everything were
homogeneous inside each of the categories, or as if this list were a priori
exhaustive. And one can imagine [vous vous representez] Socrates arriving
in the early dawn of this Symposium, tipsy, late, and posing his question:
"You tell me there is aesthetic and political and metaphysical and historical and religious and epistemological representation, as if each were one
among others, but in the end, aside from the fact that you have forgotten
some and that you are enumerating too many or too few, you have not
answered the question: what is representation itself and in general? What
makes of all these representations representations to be called by the same
name? What is the eidos of representation, the being-representation of
representation?" As for this well-known schema of the Socratic question,
the possibility of this fiction is limited because for essential reasons
questions of language that do not allow of being assigned to a simple and
limited placeSocrates would never have been able to ask this kind of
question about the word "representation." I think we must begin with the
hypothesis that the word "representation" translates no Greek word in any
transparent way, without remainder, without reinterpretation and deep
historical reinscription. This is not a problem of translation, it is the problem of translation and of the supplementary fold I pointed to a moment
ago. Before knowing how and what to translate by "representation," we
must interrogate the concept of translation and of language that is so often dominated by the concept of representation, whether it be a matter of
interlinguistic, intralinguistic (within a single language), or even, to revert
for convenience to Roman Jakobson's tripartite distinction, intersemiotic
translation (between discursive and nondiscursive languages). Each time
we again come upon the presupposition or the desire for an invariable
identity of sense already present behind all the uses and regulating all the
variations, all the correspondences, all the inter-expressive relations (I use
this Leibnizian language deliberately, and recall that what Leibniz refers
to as the "representative nature" of the monad constitutes this constant

102

Envoi

and regulated relation of inter-expressivity). Such a representative relation


would organize not only the translation of a natural or a philosophical
language into another but also the translatability of all the regions, for
example, also of all the contents distributed in the sections arranged by
the organizing committee. And the unity of this table of sections would
be assured by the representative structure of the table.
This hypothesis and this desire would be precisely those of representation, of a representative language whose destined aim is to represent
something (to represent in all the senses of the delegation of presence,
of reiteration rendering present once again, by substituting a presentation for another in absentia and so on). Such a language would represent
somethinga sense, an object, a referent, indeed, already another representation in whatever sensethat is supposed to be anterior and exterior to it. Beneath the diversity of words from diverse languages, beneath
the diversity of uses of the same word, beneath the diversity of contexts
or of syntactic systems, the same sense or the same referent, the same
representative content would keep its inviolable identity. Language, every language, would be representative, a system of representatives, but
the content represented, the represented of this representation (meaning,
thing, and so on) would be a presence and not a representation. As for the
represented (the represented content), it would not have the structure of
representation, the representative structure of the representing. Language
would be a system of representatives or also of signifiers, of placeholders, substituted for what they say, signify, or represent, and the equivocal
diversity of the representatives would not affect the unity, the identity,
indeed even the ultimate simplicity of the represented. Now, it is only on
the basis of these premisesthat is to say, a language as a system of representationthat the problematic in which we are tangled up would be
set in place. But to determine language as representation is not the effect
of an accidental prejudice, a theoretical fault or a manner of thinking, a
limit or a closure among others, a form of representation, precisely, that
Came about one day and that we could get rid of by a decision when the
time comes. Today, many people set their thinking against representation.
In a more or less articulated or rigorous way, this thinking gives in facilely
to an evaluation: representation is bad. And this without being able to
assign, in the final analysis, the place and the necessity of the evaluation.
We should ask ourselves what this place is and, above all, what the various risks (in particular political ones) may be of such a prevalent evalu-

Envoi

103

ation, prevalent in the world at large but also among the most diverse
fields, from aesthetics to metaphysics (to return to the distinctions of our
program), and passing by way of politics, where the parliamentary ideal,
to which the structure of representation is so often attached, is no longer
very inspiring [mobilisateur] in the best of cases. And yet, whatever may
be the strength and the obscurity of this dominant current, the authority
of representation constrains us, imposes itself on our thought through
a whole dense, enigmatic, and heavily stratified history. It programs us,
precedes us, and predisposes us too much for us to make a mere object of
it, a representation, an object of representation confronting us, set before
us like a theme. It is even rather difficult to pose a systematic and historical question on the topic (a question of the type: "What is the system and
the history of representation?"), given that our concepts of system and of
history are essentially marked by the structure and the closure of representation.
When one tries today to think what is happening with representation,
at once the extension of its domain and its being called into question, one
cannot avoid (regardless of the importance one finally grants it) this central motif of the Heideggerian meditation when it attempts to determine
an epoch of representation in the destiny of Being, a post-Hellenic epoch
in which the relation to Being would have been arrested as repraesentatio
and Vorstellung, in the equivalence of the one to the other. Among the
numerous texts of Heidegger that we ought to reread here, I will have
to limit myself to a passage from "Die Zeit des Weltbildes" in Holzwege.
Heidegger there inquires into what best expresses itself, the sense [Bedeurung] that comes best to expression [Ausdruck] in the word repraesentatio,
as well as in the word Vorstellung. This text dates from 1938, and I would
like first to draw your attention to one of the particularly timely features
of this meditation. It has to do with publicity and publication, the media,
the accelerating pace at which intellectual and philosophical production is
becoming technical (in short, its becoming productive), in a word, everything that could be included today under the heading of a society of productivity, of representation, and of spectacle, with all the responsibilities it
demands. Heidegger initiates in this place even an analysis of the research
institution, of the university and of publication in connection with the
dominant installation of representative thought, of the determination of
appearance or presence as an image-before-one or the determination of
the image itself as an object installed before [vorgestalld a subject. I reduce

104

Envoi

and oversimplify a train of thought pursued on the side of the determination of what-is [l'etant] as object and of the world as a field of objectivity
for a subjectivity, the institutionalization of knowledge being unthinkable
unless it is put into this setting of objective representation. In passing,
I leidegger evokes, moreover, the life of the intellectual who has become
a "researcher" and has to participate in programmed congresses, of the
researcher tied to "commissions with publishers. The latter now determine along with him which books must be written." 2 Heidegger adds a
note here that I want to read because of its date and because it belongs so
clearly to our reflection on the epoch of representation:
The growing importance of the publishing business is not based merely on the

fact that publishers (perhaps through the process of marketing their books)
come to have the best ear for the needs of the public or that they are better
businessmen than are authors. Rather their peculiar work takes the form of
a procedure that plans and that establishes itself with a view to the way in
which, through the prearranged and limited publication of books and periodicals, they are to bring the world into the picture for the public and confirm
it publicly. The preponderance of collections, of sets of books, of series and
pocket editions, is already a consequence of this work on the part of publishers, which in turn coincides with the aims of researchers, since the latter not
only are acknowledged and given consideration more easily and more rapidly
through collections and sets, but, reaching a wider public, they immediately
achieve their intended effect.'

I fere now is the most palpable articulation, which I lift out of a long
and difficult development that I cannot reconstitute here. If we follow
leidegger, the Greek world did not have a relation to the what-is as to
a conceived image or representation (here Bild). For them, the what-is is
presence; and this did not, originally, derive from the fact that man would
look at what-is and have what is called a representation [Vorstellung] of it
as the mode of perception of a subject. In a similar way, in another age
(and it is about this sequence of ages or epochs, Zeitalter, arranged to he
sure in a nonteleological fashion but grouped under the unity of a destiny
of Being as sending, envoi, Geschick, that I would like to raise a question
later on), in the Middle Ages one relates essentially to being as to an ens
erratum. ""li) he something that-is rtre-un-etand" means to belong to the
order of the created. This thus corresponds to God according to the analogy of what-is [analogia entis], hut, says Heidegger, the being of what-k

Envoi

105

never consists in an object [Gegenstand] brought before man, fixed, ar-

rested, available for the human subject who would possess a representation of it. This will be the mark of modernity. "The fact that whatever is
comes into being in and through representedness [literally, in the beingrepresented, in der V orgestelltheit] transforms the age [Zeitalter] in which
this occurs into a new age in contrast with the preceding one." 4 It is thus
only in the modern period (Cartesian or post-Cartesian) that what-is is
determined as an ob-ject present before and for a subject in the form of
repraesentatio or Vorstellen. So Heidegger analyzes the Vorgestelltheit des
Seienden. What do Stellen and V orstellen mean? I translate, or rather for
essential reasons I couple the languages:
In distinction from Greek apprehending, modern representing [das neuzeitliche Vorstellen], whose meaning [Bedeutung] the word repraesentatio first brings
to its earliest expression [Ausdruck], intends [meint] something quite different.
Vorstellen bedeutet bier, here "to represent" means: das Vorhandene als ein Entgegenstehendes vor sich bringen, auf sich, den Vorstellenden zu, beziehen and in
diesen Bezug zu sich als das massgebenden Bereich zuruckzwingen, to bring what
is present at hand [which is already before one: Vorhandene] before oneself as
something standing over against, to relate it to oneself, to the one representing it, and to force it back into this relationship to oneself as the normative
realm.'

It is the self, here the human subject, that is the field in this relation, the
domain and the measure of objects as representations, its own representations.
Heidegger thus uses the Latin word repraesentatio and settles at once
into the equivalence between repraesentatio and Vorstellung. This is not
illegitimate, quite the contrary, but it does require some explanation. As
"representation," in the philosophical code or in ordinary language, Vorstellung does not immediately seem to imply the meaning that is conveyed
by the re- of repraesentatio. Vorstellen seems to mean simply, as Heidegger
emphasizes, to pose, to dispose before oneself, a sort of theme on the
theme. But this sense or value of being-before is already at work in "present." Praesentatio signifies the fact of presenting and repraesentatio that
of rendering present, of summoning as a power-of-bringing-back-to-presence. And this power-of-bringing-back, in a repetitive way, while keeping the disposition to this recall, is marked simultaneously by the re- of
representation and in this positionality, this power-of-posing, disposing,

to6

Envoi

putting, placing, which is to be read in Stellen and at the same time refers
hack to the self, that is, to the power of a subject who can bring back to
presence and make present, make something present to itself, indeed, just
make itself present. Making-present can be understood in two senses at
least, and this duplicity is at work in the term "representation." On the
one hand, to render present would be to bring to presence, into presence,
cause or allow to come by presenting. On the other hand, but this second
sense inhabits the first, because to cause or to allow to come implies the
possibility of causing or allowing to return, then to render present, like
all "rendering" and like all restitution, would be to repeat, to be able to
repeat. Whence the idea of repetition and return that inhabits the very
meaning of representation. Concerning a word, which to my knowledge
is never used thematically in this context, I will say that it is the "render"
that splits: sometimes it means, as in "to render present," simply to present, to allow or cause to come to presence, into presentation; sometimes it
means to cause or allow to return, to restore for the second time to presence, perhaps in effigy, ghost, sign, or symbol, what was not or no longer
there, this not or no-longer having a very great diversity of possible modes.
Now, whence comes, in philosophical or more or less scientific language,
this semantic determination of repraesentatio as something whose place
is in and for the mind, within the subject and facing it, in it and for it,
object for a subject? In other words, how could this meaning of repraesentatio he contemporary, as Heidegger claims, with the Cartesian or Cartesian-Hegelian epoch of the subjectum? In re-presentation, the present,
the presentation of what presents itself comes back, returns as a double,
effigy, image, copy, idea in the sense of picture of the thing henceforth
at hand, in the absence of the thing, available, disposed and predisposed
lin., by, and in the subject. For, by, and in, the system of these prepositions
marks the place of representation or of the Vorstellung. The re- marks the
repetition in, fir, and by the subject, a parti subjecti, of a presence that
otherwise would present itself to the subject without depending upon it
or without having its proper place in the subject. Doubtless the present
that returns in this way already had the form of what is for and before the
subject but was not at its disposition in this preposition itself. Whence the
possibility of translating repraesentatio by Vorstellung, a word that, in its
literality and here as a metaphor (to put it rather hastily, but I am setting
this problem aside) marks the gesture that consists of posing, of causing
to stand up befOre the self, of installing in front of oneself, of keeping at

Envoi

1o7

one's disposal, of localizing within the disposability of the preposition.


And the ideality of the idea as a copy in the mind is precisely what is most
readily available, most repeatable, apparently most docile to the reproductive spontaneity of the mind. The value "pre-," "being-before," was
certainly already present in "present"; it is only the putting at the disposal
of the human subject that gives rise to representation, and this putting at
one's disposal is the very thing that constitutes the subject as a subject.
The subject is what can or believes it can offer itself representations, disposing them and disposing of them. When I say "offer itself representations," I could just as easily say, changing the context only barely, offer
itself representatives (political ones, for instance) or even, and I will come
back to this, offer itself in representation or as a representative. We see
this positional initiativewhich will always be related to a certain highly
determined concept of freedommarked within the Stellen of Vorstellen.
And I must content myself with situating here, in this precise place, the
necessity of the whole Heideggerian meditation on the Gestell and the
modern essence of technics.
If rendering present is understood as the repetition that restitutes thanks
to a substitute, we come once again upon the continuum or the semantic
coherence between, on the one hand, representation as idea in the mind
pointing to the thing (for instance, as "objective reality" of the idea), as
picture in place of the thing itself, in the Cartesian sense or in the sense of
the empiricists, and, on the other hand, aesthetic representation (theatrical, poetic, literary, or visual) or, finally, political representation.
The fact that there is representation or Vorstellung is not, according to
Heidegger, a recent phenomenon, characteristic of the modern epoch of
science, of technique, and of subjectivity of a Cartesian-Hegelian type.
But what would be characteristic of this epoch is rather the authority, the
dominant generality of representation. It is the interpretation of the essence of what is as an object of representation. Everything that becomes
present, everything that is, which is to say, is present or presents itself is
apprehended in the form of representation. Representation becomes the
most general category for determining the apprehension of whatever it is
that is of concern or interest in any relation at all. All of post-Cartesian
and even post-Hegelian discourse, if not in fact the whole of modern discourse, has recourse to this category to designate the modifications of the
subject in its relation to an object. The great question, the matrix question, thus becomes, for this epoch, that of the value of representation, of

108

Envoi

its truth or its adequation to what it represents. And even the criticism
of representation, or at least its de-limitation and there where it is most
systematically exceededat least in Hegelseems not to call again into
question the very determination of experience as subjective, that is to say,
representational. I believe this could be shown in Hegel, who nevertheless
reminds us regularly of the limits of representation insofar as it is unilateral, only on the side of the subject ("it is still only a representation," he
always says at the moment of proposing a new A ufhebung). I will come
back to this in a moment. Mutatis mutandis, Heidegger would say the
same of Nietzsche, who nevertheless was dogged in his opposition to representation. If he had read him, would he have said the same of Freud,
for whom the concepts of representation, under the names Vorstellung,
Reprsentanz, and even Vorstellungsreprasentanz, play such a strongly organizing role in the obscure problematics of drive and of repression, and for
whom, in more roundabout ways, the work of mourning (introjection,
incorporation, interiorization, idealization, so many modes of Vorstellung
and of Erinnerung), the notions of phantasm, and of fetish all retain a
strict relation with a logic of representation or of representativeness? Once
again, I set this question aside for the moment.
Of course, Heidegger does not interpret this reign of representation
as an accident, still less as a misfortune in the face of which we must
fall back shivering. The end of "Die Zeit des Weltbildes" is very clear in
this respect, at the point where Heidegger evokes a modern world that is
beginning to withdraw from the space of representation and of the calculable. We might say in another language that a criticism or even a deconstruction of representation would remain weak, vain, and irrelevant if it
were to lead to some rehabilitation of immediacy, of original simplicity, of
presence without repetition or delegation, if it were to induce a criticism
of calculable objectivity, of science, of technics, or of political representation. The worst regressions can put themselves at the service of this antirepresentative prejudice. Reverting to the Heideggerian position itself, I
will specify a point that will prepare from afar a question in its turn about
I leidegger's path or procedure: If it is not the accident of a faux pas, this
reign of representation must have been destined, predestined, geschickte,
that is to say, literally sent, dispensed, assigned by a destiny as the gathering of a history (Geschick, Geschichte). The advent of representation must
have been prepared, prescribed, announced from far off, emitted, I will
say trlesigned, in a world, the Greek world, where nevertheless representa-

Envoi

109

tion, the Vorstellung or the Vorgestelltheit des Seienden had no dominion.


How so? Representation is to be sure an image, or an idea as an image in
and for the subject, an affection of the subject in the form of a relation to
the object that is in it as a copy, a picture or a scene, an idea, if you like,
in a more Cartesian sense than a Spinozoistic one, and (a passing remark)
that is probably why Heidegger always refers to Descartes without naming Spinozaor perhaps othersto designate this epoch. Representation
is not merely this image, but to the extent that it is, supposes a world previously constituted as visible. As visible, which is to say as image, not in
the sense of reproductive representation, but in the sense of manifestation
in the visible form, of the formed, informed spectacle, as Bild.
Now, if for the Greeks, according to Heidegger, the world is not essentially Bild, an available image, a spectacular form offered to the gaze
or to the perception of a subject; if the world were first of all presence
(Anwesen) that grabs or attaches itself to man rather than being seen, intuited (angeschaut) by him; if it is rather man who is invested and regarded
by what-is, it was nevertheless necessary for the world as Bild, and then
as representation, to have declared itself already among the Greeks, and
this was nothing less than Platonism. The determination of the being of
what is as eidos is not yet its determination as Bild, but the eidos (aspect,
look, visible figure) would be the distant condition, the presupposition,
the secret mediation that would one day permit the world to become
representation. Everything happens as if the world of Platonism (and in
saying the world of Platonism, I also exclude the idea that something like
Platonist philosophy might have produced a world, or that, inversely, it
might have been the simple representation, as reflection or as symptom,
of a world that sustains it) had prepared, dispensed, destined, sent, put
on its way and on its path the world of representationall the way down
to us, passing through the relay of the positions or posts of Cartesian,
Hegelian, Schopenhauerian, even Nietzschean types, and so on, that is to
say, the whole of the history of metaphysics in its unity presumed to be the
indivisible unity of a sending.
In any case, there is no doubt that for Heidegger, Greek man before
Plato did not inhabit a world dominated by representation; and it is
with the world of Platonism that the determination of the world as Bild
announces itself and is sent on its way, a determination that will itself
prescribe and send on the predominance of representation. "Yet, on the
other hand IDagegen], that the beingness of whatever-is [die Seiendheit des

110

Envoi

Seienden] is defined for Plato as eidos [aspect, sight, A ussehen, A nblick] is


the presupposition, destined far in advance [sent: die weit voraus geschickte
Voraussetzung] and long ruling indirectly in concealment [lang in Verborgenen mittelbar waltende Voraussetzung] for the world's having to become a
picture [BiLd]." 6 The world of Platonism would thus have given the sendoff for the reign of representation; it would have destined there, it would
have destined it without itself being subjected to it. It would have been,
at the limit of this sending, like the origin of philosophy. Already and not
yet. But this already-not-yet should not be the dialectical already-not-yet
that organizes the whole Hegelian teleology of history and, in particular,
the moment of representation [Vorstellung] that is already what it is not
yet, its own overflowing. The Geschick, the Schicken, and the Geschichte of
which Heidegger speaks are not sendings of the representative type. The
historiality they constitute is not a representative or representable process,
and in order to think it, we need a history of Being, of the envoi of Being
that is no longer regulated or centered on representation.
What remains then to think here is a history that would no longer be
of a Hegelian or dialectical type in general. For Hegelian, even neo-Hegelian, criticism of representation [Vorstellung] seems always to have been a
sublation (Aufhebung) [releve] of representation that keeps it at the center
of becoming, as the very form, the most general formal structure of the
relay from one moment to the next, and this once again in the present
form of the already-not-yet. Thusbut one could add many other examplesbetween aesthetic and revealed religion, between revealed religion
and philosophy as absolute knowledge, it is always the Vorstellung that
marks the limit to be sublated [a relever]. The typical syntagma is thus
the following: it is still only a representation, it is already the following
stage but that remains still in the form of the Vorstellung, it is only the
subjective unilaterality of a representation. But the "representative" form
of this subjectivity is only sublated [relevee], it continues to inform the
relation to being after its disappearance. It is in this sense and following
this interpretation of Hegelianismat once strong and classicthat the
latter would belong to the epoch of subjectivity and of representationality
(Vorgrstelltheit) of the Cartesian world.
What I retain from the last two points I have just evoked all too superficially is that in order to begin to think the multiple bearings of the
word "representation" and the history, if there is one that really is one, of
Vorgestelltheit, the minimal condition would he to raise two presupposi-

Envoi

OOO

tions, that of a language whose structure is representative or representational, and that of a history as a process scanned according to the form or
rhythm of Vorstellung. One should no longer try to represent to oneself the
essence of representation, Vorgestelltheit. The essence of representation is
not a representation, it is not representable, there is no representation of
representation. Vorgestelltheit is not just a Vorstellung. And it does not lend
itself to this. It is in any case through a gesture of this type that Heidegger
interrupts or disqualifies, in different domains, specular reiteration or infinite referral [renvoi a l'infini].
This move on Heidegger's part does not only lead us to think of representation as having become the model of all thinking of the subject, of
every idea, of all affection, of everything that happens to the subject and
modifies it in its relation to the object. The subject is no longer defined
only in its essence as the place and the placing of its representations; it is
also, as a subject and in its structure as subjectum, itself apprehended as a
representative. Man, determined first and above all as a subject, as beingsubject, finds himself interpreted through and through according to the
structure of representation. And in this respect, he is not only a subject
represented in the sense in which one can, in one way or another, still say
of the subject today that it is represented, for example by a signifier for
another signifier: "The subject," Lacan says, "is what the signifier represents . . . for another signifier." C The whole Lacanian logic of the signifier
works also with this structuration of the subject by and as representation:
an "entirely calculable" subject, Lacan says, as soon as it is "reduced to
the formula of a matrix of significant combinations."' What brings the
reign of representation into accord with the reign of the calculable in
this way is precisely Heidegger's theme; he insists on the fact that only
calculability (Berechenbarkeit) guarantees the certainty in advance of what
is to be represented (des Vorzustellenden), and it is in the direction of the
incalculable that the limits of representation can be overrun. Structured
by representation, the represented subject is also a representing subject.
A representative of the what-is and thus also an object, Gegenstand. The
trajectory that leads up to this point is roughly the following: By "modern" Vorstellung or repraesentatio, the subject causes the what-is to come
back before it. The prefix re-, which does not have necessarily the value
of repetition, signifies at least the availability of the causing-to-come or
to-become-present as what-is-there, in front, placed-before Vre-posel. The
Stellen translates the re- insofar as it designates the making available or the

Envoi

112

putting in place, whereas the vor translates the prae of praesens. According
to Heidegger, neither Vorstellung nor repraesentatio can translate a Greek
thought without diverting it elsewhere, which, moreover, all translation
does. It has happened, for example, that phantasia or phantasma has been
translated in French by representation; one finds this in a Plato lexicon, for
instance, and the phantasia kataleptik of the Stoics is frequently translated as "comprehensive representation." But this anachronistically supposes the subjectum and the repraesentatio to be possible and thinkable for
the Greeks. Heidegger contests that supposition, and appendix 8 of "Die
Zeit des Weltbildes" tends to demonstrate that subjectivism was unknown
in the Greek world, even to the Sophists; Being, he maintains, is apprehended there as presence, and appearing is apprehended in presence and
not in representation. Phantasia names a mode of this appearing that is
not representative. "In unconcealment [Unverborgenheid, ereignet sich die
Phantasia, phantasia comes to pass; the coming-into-appearance [das zum
Erscheinen-Kommen], as a particular something, of that which presences
as such [des Anwesenden als eines solchen] for man, who himself appears
toward what appears."' This Greek thought of phantasia (whose fate we
should follow here in all its displacements, up to the allegedly modern
problematic of "fiction" and "phantasm") addresses itself only to some
presence, the presence of the what-is for the presence of man, its sense unmarked by the values of representative reproduction or of the imaginary
object (produced or reproduced by man as representation). The enormous
philosophical question of the imaginary, of the productive or reproduct ive imagination, even when it assumes once more, for example, in Hegel,
the Greek name of Phantasie, does not belong to the Greek world but
conies up later, in the age of representations and of man as a representing
"subject: Der Mensch als das vorstellende Subjekt jedoch phantasiert. Man as
representing subject, however, fantasizes, that is, he moves in imaginatio
the L atin word always marks the access to the world of representation],
in that his representing [sein Vorstellen] imagines, pictures forth, whatever
is, as the objective, into the world as picture [the German is still indispensable here: insole' rn sein Vorstellen das Seiende als das Gegenstandliche in
the W elt air Bild einbildet].""
I low is man, having become a representative in the sense of Vorstellend,
also and at the same time a representative in the sense of Repriisentant, in
other words, not only someone who has representations, who represents
himself, but also someone who himself represents something or some
)

Envoi

113

other? Not only someone who sends himself or gives himself objects but
who is the envoy of something else or of the other? When he has representations, when he determines everything that is as representable in a
Vorstellung, man fixes himself by giving himself an image of what is, he
makes of it an idea for himself, he is there ("Der Mensch setzt uber das
Seiende sich ins Bild," Heidegger says). From that point on he puts himself on stage, Heidegger says literally, "setzt er sich selbst in die Szene,"
that is to say, in the open circle of the representable, of shared and public
representation. And in the following sentence, the expression of staging
is displaced or folded into itself; and, as in the translation, Ubersetzen,
the placing (Setzen) is no less important than the stage. Putting himself
forward or putting himself on stage, man poses, represents himself as/like
the scene of representation ("Damit setzt sich der Mensch selbst als die
Szene, in der das Seiende fortan sich vor-stellen, ptxtt4"d.h. Bild
sein muss"): in that way, man puts himself forward as the stage on which
what-is must from now on re-present itself, present itself, that is to p"4"be
an image. And, Heidegger concludes: "Man becomes the representative
[this time Reprasentant, with all the ambiguity of the Latin word] of that
which is, in the sense of that which has the character of object [im Sinne
des Gegensandigen].""
We thus see the reconstitution of the chain of consequences that sends
us back from representation as idea or as the objective reality of the idea
(relation to the object), to representation as delegation, perhaps political,
therefore to the substitution of subjects identifiable with one another and
all the more replaceable in that they are objectifiable (and here we have
the other side of the democratic and parliamentary ethics of representation, that is to say, the horror of calculable subjectivities, innumerable but
that can be numbered, computed, the crowds in concentration camps or
in the computers of the police or other agencies, the world of the masses
and of the mass media, which would also be a world of calculable and representable subjectivity, the world of semiotics, of computer science, and
of communications). The same chain, if we assume that its consequences
hang together and if we follow the development of the Heideggerian motif, traverses a certain system of political, pictorial, theatrical, or aesthetic
representation in general.
Some of you may perhaps consider this reverential reference to Heidegger excessive, and above all that German is becoming rather invasive
for the opening of a congress on French-language philosophy. Before pro-

1?

Envoi

posing some types of question for the debates that are about to begin, I
would like to justify this recourse to Heidegger and to the German of
Heidegger in three ways.
First justification. The problematic opened up by Heidegger is to my
knowledge the only one today to treat representation as a whole, an ensemble [clans son ensemble]. And already I must go beyond even this formula: the procedure or the step taken, the path of thought called Heideggerian is here more than a problematic (a problematic or a Fragestellung
still owing too much to representative pre-positionality; it is the very
quality of problem that gives us something to think about here). We have
more than a problematic here, and it concerns more than an "ensemble";
in any case, it is not concerned with the ensemble or the assembling only
as system or as structure. This path of Heideggerian thought is the only one
to refer the gathering or assembling of representation back to the world
of language and of languages (Greek, Latin, and Germanic) in which it
unfolded, and to make of languages a question, a question not predetermined by representation. What I shall try to suggest in a moment is that
the force of this gathering in the path of Heideggerian thought opens
another type of problem and still leaves room for thought, but I think it
is not possible today to remain unaware, as is too often the case in francophone philosophic institutions, of the space cleared by Heidegger.
Second justification. If in pointing outand I have not been able to
do more than thatthe necessity of the reference to Heidegger, I have
often spoken German, it is because, when addressing the question of representation, French-speaking philosophers have to feel the philosophical
necessity of exiting from latinity in order to think the event of thought
that takes place under the word repraesentatio. Not exiting just to exit, to
disqualify a language, or to go into exile, but in order to think the relation
to one's own language. To indicate only this point, which is an essential
one to be sure, what Heidegger situates "before," so to speak, the repraesentatio or the Vorstellung, is neither a presence, nor a simple praesentatio,
nor praesentatio period. A word that is often translated by "presence" in
this context is Anwesen, Anwesenheit, whose prefix in this context (I must
insist on this point) announces a coming to disclosure, to unconcealing,
to patency, to plienomenality rather than the prepositionality of an objective being-in-front-of. And we know how since Being and Time, the
questioning concerning the presence of Being is referred hack radically to
the quest ioning of temporality, a movement that the latinate problematic

Envoi

11 5

of representation (putting things much too quickly here) no doubt inhibited for essential reasons. It is not enough to say that Heidegger does not
recall us to the nostalgia of a presentation hidden under representation.
If there remains nostalgia, it does not lead us back to presentation. Not
even, I would add, to the presumed simplicity of Anwesenheit. Anwesenheit is not simple, it is already divided and differing, it marks the place of
a splitting, a division, a dissension [Zwiespalt]. Engaged in the opening
up of this dissension, and above all b y it, under its assignation, man is
watched by what-is, Heidegger says, and such would be the essence (Wesen) of man "during the great Greek epoch." Man thus seeks to gather in
saying (legein) and to save, to keep (sozein, bewahren), while at the same
time remaining exposed to the chaos of dissension. The theater or the
tragedy of this dissension is not yet seen as belonging either to the scenic
space of presentation (Darstellung) or to that of representation, but the
fold of dissension would open up, announce, send on everything that will
afterward come to be determined as mimesis, and then imitation, representation, with the whole parade of oppositional couples that will form
philosophical theory: production/reproduction, presentation/representation, original/derived, and so on. "Before" all these pairs, if one may say
that, there will never have been presentative simplicity but another fold,
another difference, unpresentable, unrepresentable, jective perhaps, but
neither objective, nor subjective, nor projective. What of the unpresentable or the unrepresentable? How to think it? That is now the question,
and I will come back to it in a moment.
Third justification. This one really floats on the Rhine. I had thought
at first, for this congress of societies of French-language philosophy in
Strasbourg on the theme of representation, to take the European measure
of the event by referring to what happened eighty years ago, at the turn of
the century, at the time when Alsace was on the other side of the frontier,
if one can say that. I had first thought of referring to what happened and
what was said about representation at the French Society of Philosophy.
The linguistic altercation with the other as close relative [germain] organized a whole debate to stabilize French philosophical vocabulary, and
there was even a proposal made to exclude, to scrap the French philosophical term representation, to strike it from our vocabulary, no less, to
take it out of service because it was merely the translation of a word that
came from beyond the blue line of the Vosges; or at the very least, and
confronting historic misfortune with a brave face, to "tolerate" the use of

u6

Envoi

this word that is, it was said at the time with some xenophobic resentment, "barely French."
One may find the archive of this gallocentric corpus in the Bulletin de
la Societe francaise de philosophie for 1901, to which what is rightly called
the Vocabulaire technique et critique de la philosophie by Andre Lalande
refers. In the very rich article on the word "presentation," one may see in
the process of formation the proposal to banish both the word "presentation" and the word "representation." During the discussion that took
place at the Society of Philosophy on May 29, 1901, on the subject of the
word "presentation," Bergson had this to say: "Our word representation is
an equivocal word that, based on the etymology, ought never to designate
an intellectual object presented to the mind for the first time. It ought to
he reserved for ideas or images that bear the mark of prior work carried
out by the mind. There would then be grounds for introducing the word
`presentation' (also used by English psychology to designate in a general
way all that is purely and simply presented to the intelligence)." This
proposal of Bergson's recommending the authorization and official legitimation of the word "presentation" evoked two kinds of highly interesting
objection. I continue reading: "I have no objection to the use of this word
[presentation]; but it seems to me very doubtful that the prefix re, in the
French word representation, originally had a duplicative value. This prefix
has many other uses, for example, in recueillir, retirer, reveler, requerir,
recourir, etc. Is not its true role, in representation, rather to mark the opposition of subject and object, as in the words revoke, resistance, repugnance,
repulsion, etc.?" (This last question seems to me at once aberrant and
hyper-lucid, ingenuously inspired.) And here M. Abauzit rejects, as Jules
I ,achelier will later, Bergson's proposal to introduce the word presentation
in place of representation. He disputes the view that the re of representation implies a duplication. If there is duplication, it is not, he says, in
the sense that Bergson indicates (repetition of a prior mental state) but
"the reflection, in the mind, of an object conceived as existing in itself."
Conclusion: "Presentation is therefore not justified." As for Lachelier, he
recommends a return to French and thus purely and simply the abandonment of the philosophical use of the word representation:
It seems to me that representation was not originally a philosophical term
x"French, and that it became one only when a translation was wanted for
V on/din/ix there Lachelier seems at least to overlook, even if he is not alto-

Envoi

117

gether wrong at a certain level, the fact that Vorstellung too was a translation
of the Latin repraesentatio]. But people certainly said represent something to
oneself and I think that the particle re, in this expression, indicated, according
to its ordinary sense, a reproduction of what had been antecedently given,
but perhaps without one's having paid attention to it. . .. M. Bergson's criticism is therefore, strictly speaking, justified; but one ought not to be so strict
about etymology. The best thing would be not to talk at all in philosophy of
representations and to be content with the verb se representer [to represent to
oneself Trans.]; but if there is really a need for a substantive, representation
in a sense already consecrated by usage is better than presentation, which in
French evokes ideas of a wholly different order.

There would be much to say about the reasons adduced for this conclusion, about the necessary distinction, according to Lachelier, between current usage and philosophical usage, about the mistrust of etymologizing,
about the transformation of sense and the philosophical development of
a sense when one goes from an idiomatic verbal form to a nominal form,
about the necessity of speaking "philosophy" in one's own language and of
remaining wary of violations imported by translation, about the respect,
nevertheless, due to established usages that are better than neologisms
or the artifice of a new usage dictated by philosophy, and so on. I would
like merely to indicate that this truly xenophobic mistrust with respect
to philosophical importations into the idiom is not only concerned, in
Lachelier's symptomatic text, with the invasion of French by German,
but, in a more general and more internal fashion, with the violent contamination, the grafting of philosophical language onto the body of natural and ordinary language, which is hard to tolerate and, in truth, ought
to be rejected. For it is not only in French, and deriving from German
philosophy, that this malady would have progressed and left these unfortunate traces. The trouble has already begun within the body of the German language, in the relation of German to itself, in Germano-German.
And Lachelier is visibly dreaming of a linguistic therapy that would not
only avert this French malady coming from Germany but that could be
exported in the form of a European council of languages. For, he murmurs, our German friends themselves have perhaps suffered the effects of
philosophical style, they have perhaps been "shocked" by the philosophical use of the word Vorstellung:

II] n the ordinary sense, "take the place of . . . ," this prefix [re] seems rather

118

Envoi

to express the idea of a second presence, of an imperfect repetition of the


primitive and real presence. It can be said of a person who acts in the name of
another, and of a simple image that makes present to us in its way an absent
person or thing. From this comes the sense of "representing to oneself" [se
representerl internally a person or a thing by imagining them, from which
point we have finally arrived at the philosophical sense of representation. But
this transfer seems to me to involve something violent and illegitimate. It
ought to have been possible to say "representation-to-oneself" [se-representation], and not being able to do this, the word should have been renounced.
Also it seems to me likely that we did not ourselves derive representation from
"represent to oneself," but simply copied Vorstellung in order to translate it.
We are certainly obliged, today, to tolerate this use of the word; but it seems
to me barely French.

And after some interesting allusions to Hamelin, Leibniz, and Descartes with respect to the use they nevertheless made of the same word,
Lachelier concludes in this way: "There are grounds for inquiring whether
Vorstellung was not derived from sich etwas vorstellen (to represent something to oneself), and whether the Germans themselves were not shocked
when people began to use it in the philosophical sense."
I note in passing the interest of this insistence on the "self" of "represent to oneself" as well as on the sich of sich vorstellen. It indicates to
what degree Lachelier is rightly sensitive to this auto-affective dimension
that is undoubtedly the essential factor in representation and that is more
clearly marked in the reflexive verb than in the noun. In representation, it
matters above all that a subject gives itself, procures for itself makes room
for itself and in front of itself for objects: it represents them to itself and
sends them to itself, and it is thereby that it has them at its disposal.
If I consider the reflections I have been presenting to you as adduced
reasons (des attendud (which are more or less expected), they are adduced
in view of questions and not of conclusions. Here then, to conclude, are
some questions that I would like to submit to you in their most economical formulation, indeed, in the telegraphic form suitable for such a
dispatch.
first question. This question touches on the history of philosophy, of
language, and of French philosophical language. Is there such a language,
and is it one language? And what has happened in it or at its borders since
the debate in i9oi around the words presentation and representation at the
Society of French Philosophy? What does the elaboration of this question
qsftv ppose?

IEnvoi

"9

Second question. This question relates to the very legitimacy of a general


interrogation about the essence of representation, in other words, the use
of the name and title "representation" in a colloquium in general. This
is my principal question, and although I must leave it in a minimally
schematic state, I should explain it a little more than the preceding one,
the more so because it may perhaps lead me to outline another relation
to Heidegger. It is still a matter of language and translation. One might
object, and I take this objection seriously, that in ordinary situations of
ordinary language (if there are such things, as we ordinarily believe) the
question of knowing what we intend by the name of representation is
very unlikely to arise, and if it arises, it does not last a second. It is enough
that there be a context that, while not saturated, is reasonably well determined, just as it is in what we call ordinary experience. If I read or
hear on the radio that the diplomatic or parliamentary representatives [la
representation diplomatique ou parlementaire] of some country have been
received by the head of state, that representatives [representants] of striking workers or the parents of schoolchildren have gone to the ministry
in a delegation, if I read in the paper that this evening there will be a
performance [representation] of Moliere's Psyche, or that such and such
a painting represents Eros, and so forth, I understand without the least
equivocation and I do not take my head in my hands to figure out what
it means. Obviously, it suffices for me to have the average competence
required in a certain state of society and of its educational system, and so
on. And that the destination of the sent message have a high probability
and be sufficiently determined. Given that words always function in a
(presumed) context destined to assure normally the normality of their
functioning, to ask what they can mean before and outside every such
determined context is to interest oneself (it might perhaps be said) in a
pathology or a linguistic dysfunction. The schema is well known. Philosophical questioning about the name and the essence of "representation"
before and outside of every particular context would be the very paradigm
of this dysfunction. It would necessarily lead to aporias or to pointless
language games, or rather to language games that the philosopher would
take seriously without perceiving what, in the functioning of language,
makes the game possible. In this perspective, it would not be a matter
of excluding philosophical styles or models from ordinary language but
of acknowledging their place among others. What we as philosophers in
the past few centuries or decades have made of the word "representation"

120

Envoi

Envoi

would come to be more or less well integrated into the ensemble of codes
and usages. This would also be a contextual possibility among others.
This type of problematicand I am indicating only its opening in
principlecan give rise, as we know, to the most diverse developments,

121

of all uncovers itself as presence, more rigorously as

A nwesenheit. In order
for the epoch of representation to have its sense and its unity as an epoch,
it must belong to the assembled gathering

[rassemblemend of a more orig-

inary and more powerful envoi. And if there had not been the gathering
of this envoi, the Geschick of Being, if this Geschick had not announced

for example, on the pragmatic side of language; and it is significant that


these developments should have found a favorable cultural terrain outside
the duel or dialogue of the Gallo-Germanic A useinandersetzung, within

epoch of representation could come to order it in the unity of a history

the Franco-German annals to which I have somewhat confined myself up

of metaphysics. No doubtand here one must be twice as careful and go

itself from the start as the

A nwesenheit of Being, no interpretation of the

to now. Whoever one takes to be its more or less Anglo-Saxon represen-

twice as slowly, which is much more than I can do herethe gathering

tatives, from Peirce (with his problematic of the represented as, already,

of the envoi and of destinality, the

representamen), or from Wittgenstein, if he was English, to the most diverse champions of analytic philosophy or speech-act theory, is there not
here a decentering in relation to the A useinandersetzung that we too readily consider a point of absolute convergence? And in this decentering,
even if we do not necessarily follow it along the Anglo-Saxon tracks I
have just merely alluded to, even if we suspect them of being still too
philosophizing in the centralizing sense of the term, and if in truth the
eccentricity begins at the center of the continent, will one perhaps find
there the incitement to a problematic of a different style? It would not be

a matter, then, simply of handing so-called philosophical language back


over or submitting it to ordinary law and making it answer before this
last contextual court of appeal, but of asking whether, in the very interior
of what offers itself as the philosophical or merely theoretical usage of
the word "representation," one can presume the unity of some semantic
center that would give order to a whole multiplicity of modifications and
derivations. Is not this eminently philosophical presumption precisely of
a representative type, in the central sense claimed for the term, in that a
single self-same presence delegates itself in it, sends, assembles, and finally
finds itself in it again? This interpretation of representation would presuppose a representational pre-interpretation of representation, it would still
he a representation of representation. Is not this unifying, gathering, derivationist presumption at work in Heidegger up to and including in his
strongest and most necessary displacements? Do we not find an indication
of this in the fact that the epoch of representation or Vorstellung appears
there as an epoch in the destiny or the gathered sending (Geschick) of Being? And that the Gestell continues to relate to it? Although this epoch is
neither a mode nor, in the strict sense, a modification of an entity or of a
substantial sense, any more than it is a moment or a determination in the

I lege' iait sense, it is certainly announced by a sending of Being that first

Geschick does not have the form of a


telos, still less of a certainty (whether Cartesian or Lacanian) of the arrival
at destination of the envoi. But at least there is (es gibt) an envoi, a sending. At least a sending gives itself, and it gathers itself together with itself;
and this gathering is the condition, the being-together of what offers itself
to thought so that an epochal figurehere that of representationcan

detach itself in its contour and order itself in its rhythm within the unity
of a destination or rather of a "destinality" of Being. No doubt the beingtogether of the

Geschick, and one can say the same of the Gestell, is neither
that of a totality nor that of a system, nor that of an identity comparable
to any other. No doubt we must take the same precautions with respect to
the gathering of every epochal figure. Nevertheless, the question remains:
if in a sense that is neither chronological nor logical, nor intrahistorical,
the whole historial and destinal interpretation orders the epoch of representation (in other words modernity, and in the same text Heidegger
translates: the era of the

subjectum, of objectivism and subjectivism, of

anthropology, of aesthetico-moral humanism, and so on) around an originary envoi of Being as

A nwesenheit, which translates itself as presence and

then as representation according to translations that are so many mutations within the same, within the being-together of the same envoi, then
the being-together of the originary envoi arrives reflexively
itself in a way, in closest proximity to itself, in

[s'arrive[ at
A nwesenheit. Even if there

is dissension

[Zwiespald in what Heidegger calls the great Greek epoch


and the experience of A nwesenheit, this dissension gathers itself in the
legein. It rescues and preserves itself and thus assures a sort of indivisibility of the destinal. It is in basing itself on this gathered indivisibility
of the envoi that Heidegger's reading can single out

[detached epochs,
including the most powerful, the longest, and also the most dangerous

of all, the epoch of representation in modern times. Since this is not an


epoch among others, and since it

detaches itself

in its privilege, in a very

9::

Envoi

particular way, might one not be tempted to say that it is itself detached,
sent, delegated, taking the place of what in it dissembles itself, suspends
itself, reserves itself, retreats and retires there, namely, Anwesenheit or even
presence? One could type this detachment in several ways (as metaphor,
metonymy, mode, determination, moment, etc.), but all of these will be
unsatisfactory for essential reasons. It will all the same be difficult to avoid
wondering if the relation of the epoch of representation to the great Greek
epoch is not still interpreted by Heidegger in a representative mode, as if
the couple A nwesenheit/repraesentatio still dictated the law of its own interpretation, an interpretation that does no more therefore than redouble
and recognize itself in the historial text it claims to decipher. Behind or
beneath the epoch of representation, in retreat [en retraid, there would be
what it dissembles, covers over, forgets as the very envoi that it still represents, presence or A nwesenheit in its gathering in the Greek legein that will
have saved it, above all, from dislocation. My question then is the following, and I formulate it too quickly: Wherever this being-together or with
itself of the envoi of Being divides itself, defies the legein, frustrates the
destination of the envoi, cannot the whole schema of Heidegger's reading be contested in principle, historially deconstructed? If there has been
representation, it is perhaps, precisely (and Heidegger would acknowledge
this), because the envoi of Being was originarily menaced in its beingtogether, in its Geschick, by divisibility or dissension (what I would call
dissemination)? Can we not then conclude that if there has been representation, the epochal reading of it that Heidegger proposes becomes, by
virtue of this fact, problematical from the beginning, at least as a normat ive reading (and it wishes to be this also), if not as an open questioning
of what offers itself to thought beyond the problematic, and even beyond
the question of Being, of the gathered destiny or of the envoi of Being?
What I have just suggested concerns not only the reading of Heidegger,
either his reading of the destination of representation or the one we would
propose of his own reading. It concerns not only the whole ordering of
epochs or periods in the presumed unity of a history of metaphysics or
of the West. It is a matter of the very credit we, as philosophers, would
want to grant to an organization of all the fields or of all the sections of
representation centered and centralized around a supporting sense and a

fundamental interpretation. If there has been representation, it is because


the division will have been stronger, strong enough that this supporting
sense no longer keeps, saves, or guarantees anything in a sufficiently rigorous fashion.

Envoi

9:;

So the so-called modern problematics or metamorphoses of representation would no longer be at all representations of the same, diffractions of
a unique sense starting from a single crossroads, a single place of meeting or passing for convergent approaches, a single congression or a single
congress.
If I had not been afraid of abusing your time and your patience, I
would perhaps have tried to put to the test such a difference of representation, a difference no longer ordered according to the difference of A nwesenheit or presence, or according to difference as presence, a difference
that would no longer represent the same or the self-relation of the destiny
of being, a difference that could not be repatriated in the sending of self,
a difference as a sending that would not be one, and not a sending of self.
But sendings of/from the other, of/from others. Inventions of the other. I
would not have attempted this test by proposing some scholarly, scientific
demonstration cutting across the different sections proposed by our organizing committee, across different types of problematic of representation
in the abstract singular [la representation]. Rather, my preference would
have carried me to the side of what is not represented on our program. Two
examples of what is not represented and I will have finished.
First example. In the various sections proposed, is there at least a virtual
topos for what, under the name of psychoanalysis and under the signature
of Freud, has bequeathed to us such a strange corpus so strangely charged
with "representation" in all languages? Does the vocabulary of Vorstellung, of the Vorstellungsreprasentant, in its abundance, its complexity, the
prolix difficulties of the discourse that carries it, manifest an episode of
the epoch of representation, as if Freud were thrashing about confusedly
under the implacable constraints of a program and a conceptual heritage? The very concept of drive and the "fate of the drive" (Triebschicksal),
which Freud situates at the frontier between the somatic and the psychic,
seems to require for its construction recourse to a representative scheme,
in the sense first of all of delegation. Similarly, the concept of repression
(primary or secondary, strictly speaking) is constructed on a concept of
representation: repression bears essentially on representations or representatives, delegates. This meaning of delegation, if we follow Laplanche
and Pontalis here in their concern for systematization, would give rise to
two interpretations or two formulations on Freud's part. Sometimes the
drive itself is considered a "psychic representative" (psychische Reprasentanz or psychischer Reprasentant) of somatic stimuli; sometimes the drive
is considered the somatic process of stimulus itself, and it is the drive that

Envoi

12 ?

is said to be represented by what Freud calls "representatives of the drive"


(Triebreprasentanz or Triebreprasentant), which in their turn are envisaged
eitherprincipallyas representatives in the form of representation in
the sense of Vorstellung(Vorstellungsreprilsentanz or -reprdsentant), with a
greater insistence on the ideational aspect, or else in the aspect of the
quantum of affect concerning which Freud said on occasion that it was
more important in the representative of the drive than the representational aspect (intellectual or ideational). Laplanche and Pontalis propose
to surmount Freud's apparent contradictions or oscillations in what they
call his "formulations" by recalling that nevertheless, "they both contain
the same idea: the relation between soma and psyche is conceived of as
neither parallelistic nor causal; rather, it is to be understood by comparison with the relationship between a delegate and his mandatory"; they
add in a note: "It is a commonplace that, though in principle he is nothing more than the proxy of his mandatory, the delegate in such cases
enters in practice into a new system of relationships which is liable to
change his perspective and cause him to depart from the directives he has
been given." 12 What Laplanche and Pontalis call a "comparison" bears the
whole weight of the problem. If this comparison with the structure of
delegation is that on the basis of which one interprets matters as weighty
as the relations between soul and body, the fate of drives, repression, and
so on, the vehicle of the comparison must no longer be considered selfevident. What does it mean to charge or delegate someone, if this movement does not allow itself to be derived from, interpreted as, or compared
with anything else? What is a mission or a sending? This type of question
can be justified by other places in the Freudian discourse, and more narrowly by other appeals to the word or the concept of representation (for
example, the representation of a goal [Zielvorstellung] or above all the dist itict ion between representations of words and representations of things
I Wart and Sach or Dingvorstellungb to which as we know Freud assigned
a role between the primary and secondary processes or in the structure
of schizophrenia). One might wonder if, as Laplanche and Pontalis suggest in a slightly embarrassed way on several occasions, the translation
of representation or representative by "signifier" allows a clarification of
the Freudian difficulties. This obviously is what is fundamentally at stake
today in the Lacanian heritage of Freud. Here I can only point to this
stake, but I have tried to situate it in other writings. And the question I
pose about Freud (in his relation to the epoch of representation) can in
prink iple apply also to I ,acan. At all events, when Laplanche and Pontalis
-

Envoi

125

say about the word Vorstellung that "Freud does not set out immediately
to change its meaning [acception], but he does use it in an original way"
(zoo), this distinction between meaning and use is precisely where the
problem lies. Can we distinguish between, on the one hand, the semantic
content (ultimately stable, continuous, self-identical) and, on the other,
the diversity of uses, functions, and contextual investitures by assuming
that these latter cannot displace, or even totally deconstruct the identity
of the former? In other words, are so-called "modern" developments
like Freudian psychoanalysis, but we could cite othersthinkable only
with reference to a fundamental semantic tradition, or again to a unifying epochal determination of representation, which they would continue
to represent? Or else should we find in them an incitement giving us
to think altogether differently the diffraction of fields, and first of all of
sendings or referrals [des envois, ou des renvois]? Is one authorized to say,
for example, that the Lacanian theorization of Vorstellungreprasentanz in
terms of a binary signifier producing the disappearance, the aphanisis of
the subject, is wholly contained within what Heidegger calls the epoch
of representation? I can do no more here than point out the place of this
problem. It cannot admit of a simple answer. I refer chiefly to two chapters of the Seminar on The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis
("Tuche and Automaton" on the one hand, "Aphanisis" on the other). It is
highly significant that, in these chapters in particular, Lacan should define
his relation to the Cartesian "I think" and to the Hegelian dialectic, that
is to say, to the two most powerfully ordered and ordering moments that
Heidegger assigns to the reign of representation. The central nerves of the
problematic to which I refer here were recognized and fundamentally interpreted for the first time in the works of Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe and
Jean-Luc Nancy, from Le titre de la lettre, their joint work, to their latest
publications, respectively, Le sujet de la philosophie and Ego sum."
The second and last example promised concerns the limit-question of
the unrepresentable. To think the limit of representation is to think the
unrepresented or the unrepresentable. There are very many ways of placing the emphasis here. The displacement of emphasis can effect powerful
swerves. If to think the unrepresentable is to think beyond representation
in order to think representation from its limit, then one can understand
this as a tautology. And that is a first answer, which could be Hegel's no
less than Heidegger's answer. Both of them think of thinking, the thinking
of which representation is afraid (according to the remark of Heidegger
who wonders if we arc not simply afraid of thinking), as something that

12,6

Envoi

crosses the boundary or takes a step beyond or to the hither side of representation. This is even the definition of both representation and thought
for Hegel: Vorstellung is a mediation, a mean [Mitte] between the unfree
intellect and the free intellect, in other words, thought. This is a double
and differentiated way of thinking thought as the beyond of representation. But it is the form of this passage, the A ufhebung of representation,
that Heidegger still interprets as belonging to the epoch of representation.
And yet, although Heidegger and Hegel are not thinking thought as the
beyond of representation in the same way here, a certain possibility of a
relation to the unrepresentable seems to me to bring Hegel and Heidegger
(at least what these proper names refer to, if not what they represent)
closer together. This possibility would concern the unrepresentable, not
only as that which is foreign to the very structure of representation, as
what one cannot represent, but rather and also what one must not represent, whether or not it has the structure of the representable. I mention
here the immense problem of the prohibition that bears on representation,
on what it has been possible to translate more or less legitimately (another
extraordinary problem) from a Jewish or Islamic world as "representation." Now I would not say that this immense problem, whether it concerns objectifying representation, mimetic representation, or even simple
presentation, indeed, simple naming, is just overlooked by thinking of a
Hegelian or Heideggerian type. But it seems to me in principle relegated
to a secondary or derivative place in Heidegger (in any case it does not, at
least to my knowledge, form the object of any specific attention). And as
for Hegel, who speaks of it more than once, in particular in his Lectures
op, A esthetics, it is perhaps not unwarranted to say that the interpretation
of this prohibition gets derived and reinscribed in a procedure of much
wider scope, dialectical in structure, and in the course of which the prohibition does not constitute an absolute event coming from a wholly other,
which would absolutely sunder or asymmetrically reverse the progress of a
dialectizable procedure. This does not necessarily mean that the essential
traits of the prohibition are thereby misunderstood or dissembled. For
example, the disproportion between the infinity of God and the limits of
human representation are taken into account and the wholly other can
thus be seen to declare itself in Hegel's treatment. Conversely, if one concluded that there was a dialectical effacement of the sharp edge of the prohibition, this would not imply that any taking into account of this edge
(for example, in a psychoanalytic discourse) would not eventually lead to

Envoi

127

an analogous result, that is, to a reinscribing of the origin and significance


of the prohibition on representation in an intelligible and wider process
in which the unrepresentable would disappear again like the wholly other.
But is not disappearance, non-phenomenality, the destiny of the wholly
other and of the unrepresentable, indeed, of the unpresentable? Here
again I can only indicate (by referring to work that has been ongoing all
this year with students and colleagues) the beginning and the necessity of
an interrogation for which nothing is in the slightest degree certain, above
all what is calmly translated as prohibition or as representation.
To what, to whom, to where have I been ceaselessly referring in the
course of this introduction, at once insistently and elliptically? I will venture to say: to envois and to renvois, to sendings and sendings back, already,
that would no longer be representative. Beyond a closure of representation
whose form could no longer be linear, indivisible, circular, encyclopedic,
or totalizing, I have tried to retrace a path opened onto a thinking of the
envoi that, while having a structure still foreign to representation, like the
Geschick des Seins of which Heidegger speaks, did not as yet gather itself
to itself as a sending of Being through A nwesenheit, presence, and then
representation. This, as it were, pre-ontological sending does not gather
itself together. It gathers itself only by dividing itself, by differing/deferring itself. It is not originary or originarily a sending-of/from [envoi-de]
(the sending of something-that-is or of a present that would precede it,
still less of a subject, or of an object by and for a subject). It does not form
a unity and does not begin with itself, although nothing present precedes
it; it emits only by already sending back; it emits only on the basis of the
other, the other in itself without itself. Everything begins by referring back
[par le renvoi], that is to say, does not begin. Given that this effraction or
this partition divides every renvoi from the start, there is not a single renvoi
but from then on, always, a multiplicity of renvois, so many different traces
referring back to other traces and to traces of others. This divisibility of the
envoi has nothing negative about it, it is not a lack, it is altogether different
from subject, signifier, or the letter that Lacan says does not tolerate partition and always arrives at destination. This divisibility or this differance is
the condition for there being any envoi, possibly an envoi of Being, a dispensation or a gift of being and time, of the present and of representation.
These renvois of traces or these traces of renvois do not have the structure
of representatives or of representation, or of signifiers, or of symbols, or
of metaphors, or of metonymies, and so on. But as these renvois from the

128

Envoi

other and to the other, these traces of differance, are not original and transcendental conditions on the basis of which philosophy traditionally tries
to derive effects, subdeterminations, or even epochs, it cannot be said, for
example, that representative (or signifying or symbolic, and so on) structure befalls them; we will not be able to assign periods or make some epoch
of representation follow upon these renvois. As soon as there are renvois,
and they are always already there, something like representation no longer
waits and one must perhaps make do with that so as to tell oneself this
story otherwise, from renvois to renvois of renvois, in a destiny that is never
guaranteed to gather itself up, identify itself, or determine itself. I do not
know if this can be said with or without Heidegger, and it does not matter.
This is the only chancebut it is only a chancefor there to be history,
meaning, presence, truth, language, theme, thesis, and colloquium. And
one still has to think here the chance granted, and the law of this chance.
The question remains open as to whether, to put it in classical language,
the irrepresentable of the envois is what produces the law (for example, the
prohibition of representation) or whether it is the law that produces the irrepresentable by prohibiting representation. Whatever the necessity of this
question of the relation between law and traces (the renvois of traces, the
renvois as traces), it exhausts itself perhaps when we cease representing the
law to ourselves, when we cease apprehending law itself under the species
of the representable. Perhaps law itself exceeds every representation, perhaps it is never before us, as that which poses itself in a figure or composes
a figure of itself. (The guardian of the law and the man from the country
are "before the law," Vor dem Gesetz, says Kafka's title, only at the cost of
never managing to see it, never being able to arrive at it. It is neither presentable nor representable, and the "entry" into it, according to an order
that the man from the country interiorizes and gives himself, is put off until death.)" The law has often been considered as that which poses, posits
itself, and gathers itself up in composition (thesis, Gesetz, in other words
what governs the order of representation), and autonomy in this respect
always presupposes representation, as well as thematization, the becoming-theme. Rut perhaps the law itself arrives, perhaps, arrives to us only by
transgressing the figure of all possible representation. Which is difficult to
conceive, just as it is difficult to conceive of anything at all that would be
beyond representation, but that perhaps commits us to think everything
altogether differently.
Translated by Peter and Mary A nn Caws

6 MePsychoanalysis

I am introducing hereme(into) a translation.


That says clearly enough where I will be led by these double voicetracks
[voied: to efface myself on the threshold in order to facilitate your reading. I'm writing in "my" language but in your idiom I have to introduce.
Or otherwise, and again in "my" language, to present someone. Someone
who in numerous and altogether singular ways is not there and yet is close
and present enough to require no introduction.
One presents someone to someone or to several, and as regards the
hOtes in French both the hosts who receive in their language and the
guests introducedelementary politeness demands that one not thrust
oneself forward. And it is being forward to the point of making oneself
indispensable as soon as you begin to compound the difficulties of translation (from my first word there has been at least one such difficulty here
at every step) and start hampering the interpreter of the interpreter, the
one who in his or her own language is supposed in turn to introduce the
introducer. One has the air of someone indefinitely prolonging dilatory
maneuvers, distracting attention, focusing it on oneself, commanding it by
insisting: this is what is mine here, belongs to me, the introducer, to my
style, to my way of doing, saying, writing, interpreting things, and believe
me, it's worth the detour, if I may say so, that's a promise, and so on.
This essay was published for the first time in English as the introduction to "The
Shell and the Kernel," an article by Nicolas Abraham, trans. Nicholas Rand, in
Diacritics E4"I (Spring 1979). The French text was subsequently published in
Confrontation, Cahiers 8 (1982).
129

You might also like