Radical Feminism Today Denise Thompson PDF
Radical Feminism Today Denise Thompson PDF
Radical Feminism Today Denise Thompson PDF
Today
Denise Thompson
Denise Thompson
SAGE Publications
London Thousand Oaks New Delhi
Denise Thompson 2001
Introduction 1
1 Defining Feminism 5
On definition 5
Defining feminism 6
A feminist standpoint 17
4 Feminism Undefined 53
5 Other Definitions 59
Patriarchy 59
Sexism 63
Women 64
Gender 72
Dichotomies 79
6 Difference 81
Differences between the sexes 81
Feminist object relations theory 82
Conclusion 146
References 149
Index 159
Introduction
The white, male, middle-class intellectual response to this revolt [of the other]
has been to appropriate this claim to otherness as its own revelatory experi-
ence. . . . As a male theorist declared unilaterally: we have found that we are all
others (Paul Ricoeur, quoted in H. Foster, ed., The Anti-Aesthetic, 1983: 57).
He forgot that he was once more speaking for all of us. The noisy protests of
others hitherto mute (or ignored / unheard) must have come as a huge shock to
him. . . . He could not understand these protests in any other way than by assum-
ing this other to be him again, or to be again there for him to appropriate as
his own. (Campioni, 1991: 4950 her emphasis)
On the other hand, I do address many of the issues which have been raised
under the postmodernist banner, and many of the texts I discuss are expli-
citly identified as postmodernist.
The referent of the feminism I will be alluding to throughout this pre-
sent work is that second wave of feminism, initially known as the Womens
Liberation Movement, dating from the late 1960s and early 1970s. Femi-
nism, in the sense of women defending their own interests in the face of
male supremacy, is of much longer duration than the last three decades, and
hence to call this latest manifestation a second wave does an injustice to
the long history of womens struggles on their own behalf (Lerner, 1993;
Spender, 1982). (There is no third wave feminism at present is a clarifi-
cation and holding on to the insights and gains of the Womens Liberation
Movement in the face of the male supremacist backlash, and of those
co-optations and recuperations which penetrate (pun intended) the very
body of feminism itself. Still less have we arrived at any era of postfemi-
nism, for the simple and obvious reason that male supremacy still exists.)
But although feminism has wider historical connotations than I give it here,
my task is not to write a history of feminism throughout the ages; it is,
rather, to engage in the self-clarification of the struggles and wishes of the
age I myself have lived through (to paraphrase an insight of Marxs).2
As I mentioned above, it is radical feminism which provides my own
standpoint and which I regard as feminism per se. But although I will be
INTRODUCTION 3
arguing at length that much that is called feminism is not, I have often
allowed the designation feminism to stand even while I argue against it. In
other words, I use the term feminism in a systematically ambiguous way.
Sometimes I mean feminism per se, that is, radical feminism which identifies
and opposes male domination; and sometimes I accept the self-identification
as feminism even while disagreeing with it. Which is which should be clear
from the context. I have kept the ambiguity in the interests of open-endedness
because it resides in the texts under discussion. It is sometimes the case that
I criticize one aspect of a text which in other respects displays impeccable
feminist credentials.
The texts which I use to exemplify this kind of academic feminism have
been selected randomly. They are exemplary only, and not in any sense chief
offenders in the issues I identify. They are intended to illustrate certain
themes, and not to castigate individual authors or particular pieces of work.
I could have chosen any number of other texts to illustrate those themes,
which are endemic in academic feminist theorizing and not peculiar to par-
ticular authors.
My task is not to sort out who is a feminist and who is not. The issue of
defining feminism is not a question of who is (or is not) a feminist. While it
may indeed be the case that no one has the right to tell anyone else whether
or not she is a feminist, that is not what is involved. To see it in that way can
only impede the progress of feminism because it stymies the important pro-
ject of self-clarification by placing a ban on saying what feminism is. It
reduces politics to a matter of personal preference and opinion. The crucial
question is not Who is a feminist? but What is feminism? This latter ques-
tion can only be addressed with reference to the logic of feminist theory and
practice. The meaning of feminism needs to be radically contested and
debated. But that cannot happen as long as feminism continues to be impli-
citly defined only in terms of anything said or done by anyone who identifies
as a feminist.
As an exercise in radical feminist theory, this present work is somewhat
unusual. Radical feminist writing has not on the whole tended to engage in
explicit theory-making in the sense of building on, extending and engaging
with attempts to say what feminism is. For if radical feminism has not been
welcomed into academe, the feeling has been mutual neither has radical
feminism been eager to intrude upon the more arcane levels of theorizing.
Arising as it does out of the practical politics of womens lives and experi-
ences, and springing directly from the changed consciousness which is femi-
nism, the theory has tended to show itself in the issues addressed and in the
ways in which those issues are interpreted, rather than by being said out-
right.3 In most cases feminist theory is implicit in feminist texts, rather than
explicitly spelled out. By and large this has been a deliberate strategy on the
part of radical feminist theorists. It has meant that radical feminism has
remained tied to issues of real concern to women, rather than being enticed
by the seductions of theory for theorys sake (Stanley and Wise, 1993). For
the most part, radical feminism has focused on exposing the worst excesses
4 INTRODUCTION
of the social system which is male supremacy. The need to say what feminism
is, however, has become urgent and pressing in light of the strength and
influence of the anti-feminist backlash, a backlash which is increasingly
masquerading as feminism itself. This present project is a contribution to
the debate.
The work is divided into two Parts. Part One is called Understanding Femi-
nism. In it I discuss what is at stake in feminist politics. In Chapter 1 I
define feminism as a moral and political struggle of opposition to the social
relations of male domination structured around the principle that only men
count as human, and as a struggle for a genuine human status for women
outside male definition and control. I also discuss what is involved in a
feminist standpoint. Chapters 2 and 3 deal with the concept of ideology.
Chapter 2 discusses some objections which have been raised to the use of
the term, and argues that it is useful as a designation of the ways in which
domination is disguised in order to justify it and make it palatable. In this
chapter I also criticize arguments to the effect that truth is complicit with
domination, and discuss the issue of comprehensibility in feminist theory. In
Chapter 3 I investigate some of the ways in which ideology works, through
the inculcation of pleasure and desire, and through interpreting relations of
ruling as the personal preferences or attributes of individuals. Part Two is
called Misunderstanding Feminism. It is devoted to criticisms of a number
of ways of characterizing feminism other than in terms of the opposition to
male domination. Chapter 4 discusses the feminist reluctance to define femi-
nism. Chapter 5 discusses a number of implicit definitions of feminism in
terms of women, patriarchy, sexism, gender and dichotomies, arguing
that all these meanings have limitations as the chief designator of a feminist
politics. Chapter 6 looks at the question of differences between the sexes.
In Chapters 7 and 8 I discuss in some detail the question of differences
among women, and in particular the contentious issue of race and the part
it has played in feminist politics. In the last chapter, I use the early radical
feminist insight that male domination is the primary form of social domina-
tion in order to suggest alternative ways of bringing a feminist perspective
to bear on racism and imperialism.
Notes
1 For a critique of the concept of essentialism and its unjustified use against
radical feminism, see Thompson, 1991, Chapters 7 and 10.
2 Letter to Ruge, Kreuznach, September 1843, in Early Writings, Penguin Books,
1975: 209.
3 The reference is to Ludwig Wittgensteins distinction between showing and
saying: What can be shown cannot be said (Wittgenstein, 1951: 4.1212). The dis-
tinction may be absolute in the case of logic. But a political commitment such as femi-
nism must be able to identify explicitly the interests, meanings and values which
determine both what feminism is struggling against and what it is struggling for. In
that sense, any distinction between what can be said and what must simply be shown
is provisional. It is tied to certain purposes and shifts according to the task at hand.
Part One Understanding
Fe m i n i s m
1 Defining feminism
On Definition
Defining Feminism
The theme of social construction runs throughout the literature of second-
wave feminism. (Gender is commonly used to denote this theme but, as I
argue at some length later, there are grave problems with this usage.) This is
intended to emphasize the fact that sex, sex differences, relations between
the sexes, the very category of women itself, are due to social arrangements
and not to biological necessity, that these are questions of culture not nature.
To insist that the situation of women is socially constructed, and not natu-
rally given, is a necessary emphasis given the justificatory role still played by
biological explanations for womens social subordination. But the idea of
social construction is not a new one, nor is it a peculiarly feminist one even
in the weakest sense, that is, concerned specifically with women. It origi-
nated with sociology.1 It is not even a particularly radical idea, since it can
be found in the most conservative of sociological writings. Although it is an
DEFINING FEMINISM 7
brings into question the split between public and private on which
conventional politics depends. Feminist politics requires that the nature of
politics in the conventional sense be radically changed if it is to include the
interests of women. This requirement cannot be met by a tokenistic fitting
of some women into positions which remain unchanged. Women cannot be
equal with men as long as there is no equality among men. In feminist
terms, what women want is a human status where rights, benefits and dig-
nities are gained at no ones expense, and where duties and obligations do
not fall disproportionately on the shoulders of women. Such a project
promises to transform politics altogether.
Politics is also concerned with social relations of power, and the relations
of power which feminism identifies are those of male domination. Feminism
aims to expose the reality of male domination, while struggling for a world
where women are recognized as human beings in their own right. Using
the unequivocal and adamantine terminology of male domination and its
synonyms does not mean mens absolute power and womens absolute
powerlessness. It is used for the sake of clarity, in order to designate as
clearly as possible what it is that feminism is opposing.
If it is feminisms peculiar genius to have uncovered the social reality of
male domination, simply to appeal to social construction becomes radically
inadequate as a feminist strategy. If social reality is male supremacist, then
what the social construction thesis implies is that we are constructed as
the bearers of the social relations of male supremacy. But while this is a
major implication of feminist theory, it is immediately countered by the exis-
tence of feminism itself. Feminism says that male domination constitutes the
conditions under which we live, but that it ought not to be so. At one and
the same time, feminism both exposes the existence of male domination and
challenges it. Indeed, it is through exposing male domination as domination
that feminism poses its major challenge, since social domination operates
most efficiently to the extent that it ensures compliance by being disguised
as something else, and not domination at all. It has been the task of femi-
nism to tear away the masks behind which male domination hides its true
nature, and expose it for the dehumanizing system it really is.
Male domination does not mean what one writer referred to as unrelent-
ing male drives for dominance and mastery (Hawkesworth, 1989: 543). It
does not mean that all men are invariably oppressive to all women all the
time, nor that women are invariably the passive, peaceable victims of a male
will to power. It is a social system, a matter of meanings and values, practices
and institutions. While social structures are maintained through the com-
mitment and acquiescence of individuals, and can be eroded by the refusal
of individuals to participate, they have a life of their own, and can continue
to exert their influence despite the best efforts of the well-intentioned. The
manifestations of male domination, although they are sometimes horrifically
violent and degrading, are also subtle, mundane, ordinary, unremarkable,
and, moreover, very deeply embedded in the psyches of individuals, and not
just male individuals either. It constitutes the social environment of women
DEFINING FEMINISM 9
not brought into being by social actors but continually recreated by them via the
very means whereby they express themselves as actors. In and through their
activities agents reproduce the conditions that make these activities possible. . . .
The fixity of institutional forms does not exist in spite of, or outside, the
encounters of day-to-day life but is implicated in those very encounters. . . .
Human societies, or social systems, would plainly not exist without human
agency. But it is not the case that actors create social systems; they reproduce or
transform them, remaking what is already made in the continuity of praxis.
(Giddens, 1984: 2, 69, 171 emphases in the original)
But while this account fills out the concept of social construction, it is
still inadequate for feminist purposes because it says nothing about domina-
tion. In Giddens account, the very possibility of the existence of social con-
ditions of domination is argued away. He defines power in terms of human
agency, as the capacity of individuals, singly or collectively, to get things done,
to achieve outcomes, to make a significant difference in the world. He is fully
aware that people do not have unlimited freedom of action. But he casts
the issue only in terms of constraint and enablement, while providing no
10 U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
criteria for deciding which is which. He says that the structural properties
of social systems are both enabling and constraining (Giddens, 1984: 162).
But if constraint is enablement (and vice versa), how do we distinguish
between the constraints which enable, that is, which provide the basic pre-
requisites for action, and those which enable no more than peoples con-
sent to their own oppression? He also says that constraint operates through
the active involvement of the agents concerned, not as some force of which
they are passive recipients (p. 289), and that all forms of dependence offer
some resources whereby those who are subordinate can influence the activi-
ties of their superiors (p. 16). But while this might be true, it takes for
granted the very issues of dependence, subordination and superiority which
feminism seeks to bring into question.
He also says that Domination and power cannot be thought of only
in terms of asymmetries of distribution but have to be recognized as inherent
in social association (or, I would say, in human action as such) (pp. 312).
But if domination is power, and power is social association or human
action as such, there is no way of distinguishing between those dominating
forms of power which serve the interests of some at others expense, and
those forms which everyone needs if we are to operate in the world. If domi-
nation cannot be separated out from power and confined to asymmetries
of distribution, how do we distinguish power-as-capacity (including access
to those resources which enable human action) from power-as-domination
(including the monopolization of resources and their accumulation in the
hands of the few) (Allen, 1998; Hartsock, 1974)?2 On Giddens account,
there is no possibility of political struggle against relations of ruling and for
the capacities of everyone to control the conditions of their own existence.
But for feminist purposes constraint is not really the issue. Although
women may indeed be constrained under conditions of male supremacy,
from the perspective of women constraints on the worst excesses of male
behaviour are positively beneficial. The restraining powers of the state, for
example, have sometimes been of benefit to women. The police and the
judiciary have the power to protect women and children from violent men,
and that power is sometimes used effectively, if too often reluctantly. The
state also has the power to redistribute income, and that power operates in
favour of the women and children who comprise a disproportionately large
segment of the poor. That the state thereby constrains men, by imposing
penalties for violence and by taxing the wealthy, is a positive virtue from the
point of view of women. To couch questions of freedom and power in terms
of enablement and constraint betokens a masculine ethos. This is the
world view of those who already have the capacity to act freely because the
world is made in their image and likeness, or who react violently if they are
deprived of what they have been promised is theirs by right.
The political concern with power is a concern with the sort of power
which causes problems, that is, the domination which results in harm and
misery. The problem with power is not that it achieves outcomes, but that it
is exercised to prevent categories of people from achieving even the most
D E F I N I N G F E M I N I S M 11
basic outcomes necessary for their human dignity and respect. A liberatory
politics like feminism is a stance taken against power in the form of domi-
nation and in favour of power in the form of the exercising of capacities at
no ones expense. It requires knowledge of the ways in which power-as-
domination is exercised, because those ways are not always overt and delibe-
rate. It is a sociological truism that the social control of populations is most
efficient when people control themselves, when they perceive the status quo
as in their own interests and acquiesce more or less willingly in its main-
tenance and reproduction. Indeed, this commitment on the part of individu-
als is essential if the social order is to be reproduced at all. It is often the case
that the interests of some people can prevail over and against the interests
of others, without those others putting up any opposition at all. As Steven
Lukes points out, power-as-domination is frequently exercised by control
over sources of information so that people do not even get to find out that
they have grievances, much less protest against or act to change oppressive
conditions.
the most effective and insidious use of power is to prevent . . . conflict from aris-
ing in the first place. . . . is it not the supreme and most insidious exercise of
power to prevent people, to whatever degree, from having grievances by shap-
ing their perceptions, cognitions and preferences in such a way that they accept
their role in the existing order of things, either because they can see or imagine
no alternative to it, or because they see it as natural and unchangeable, or
because they value it as divinely ordained and beneficial? (Lukes, 1974: 23, 24)
happens are many and various and rarely commented upon). Moreover,
women have many and varied strategies for resisting male domination.
Some of these merely reverse the power hierarchy. Some are complicit with
the meanings and values of domination while defeating a particular indivi-
dual or individuals (male or female). Other strategies of resistance on the
part of women radically undermine the belief in womens inferiority and
availability to men, and manifest a power and capability far beyond anything
permitted to women within the confines of the conventional female role.
Male monopolization of human status dehumanizes everyone, for if
women are not human, men cannot be genuinely human either. Tyranny
corrupts. It corrupts the tyrannized by requiring of them the values of
subservience, but (as Hegel pointed out) it is even more corrupting for the
tyrant. By failing to recognize the humanity of his female other, the tyrant
destroys his own human status. Because he will not allow her her own
unique self, he deprives himself of anyone to recognize him. Because every-
ones first other is female, the mother, the process of dehumanization starts
at once, from the beginning of each human existence, and hence humanity
under male supremacist conditions is flawed from the outset.
What feminism is fighting for is a world in which women have, and are
seen to have, a fully human status. It is this aspect of the feminist struggle
which has received the most attention, to the point where feminism has
tended to be implicitly defined solely in terms of women. This focus of
attention is vitally important. It is necessary to rescue women from histori-
cal oblivion, to insist on womens human rights and dignities, to expose the
injustices and harm done to women, to assert in a multitude of ways that
women are human beings deserving of respect. But although many of the
feminist enterprises devoted to women display insight into the social system
of male domination even when it is not stated explicitly, focusing on women
in and of itself says nothing about the male supremacist relations of ruling
which makes this focus necessary. As a result, defining feminism only in
terms of women has given rise to a number of futile debates, about what is
involved in the category of women, for example, or about whether women
are the same as or different from men. It has also had the unfortunate politi-
cal consequence of dividing women into a multiplicity of incompatible
social categories. Hence, although defining feminism in terms of women is
necessary, it is not sufficient as the unifying factor of feminist politics. It is
the opposition to male domination which makes feminism relevant to
women wherever they are situated, however differently they are excluded
from recognition as human.
Because the male monopoly of the human is still too little recognized,
because it is still veiled by hegemonic meanings and values which authenti-
cate maleness and depreciate femaleness, the creation of a human status for
women requires that women seek recognition from each other, that women
live in connection with women and recognize each other in ways which are
outside male control and definition. It used to be argued that lesbianism was
central to this project, as long as lesbianism was itself defined as women
14 U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
identifying with women, women loving women, women seeing each other
as human individuals lacking nothing (Abbott and Love, 1972; Myron and
Bunch, 1975). Lesbianism was seen as central to feminism, both as a chal-
lenge to male supremacy because of its challenge to the dominance of hetero-
sexual desire, and as a redefining of the category of women, for women and
by women and outside the male hegemony. This did not mean that all femi-
nists, or all women, should be lesbians (any more than all women should
be any other one thing in particular). It meant that lesbianism, as mutual
recognition between women, should be accorded an honoured place within
second-wave feminism, so that it was available to women as a real alterna-
tive to defining themselves only in relation to men.
Initially, during the 1970s, it was argued that lesbianism was also central
to feminism because it was a sexual practice and because of the kind of
sexual practice it was, that is, sexual desire and activity without the penis,
and hence a sexuality with a potential for equality rather than domination.
But subsequent developments in the meaning of lesbianism have almost
buried that feminist stance. One of those developments was the rise to
prominence of lesbian sadomasochism, supported by a sexual libertarianism
which defined sex only in terms of bodies and pleasures and which
demanded that sex be placed beyond political critique. It seemed that les-
bian sex, too, could be hi-jacked for male supremacist purposes. This should
have come as no surprise, since feminism had early identified the connec-
tion between sex and domination at the heart of male supremacist meanings
and values. We had not, however, gone far enough in our analysis, and
investigated the ways in which women, too, could be complicit with eroti-
cized domination. Another development which rejected the feminist stance
was the influence of a discourse of liberal tolerance whereby lesbianism was
defined merely as a sexual preference, as the personal attribute of some
(few) individual women. Although preferable to contempt or persecution,
this attitude of tolerance ignored the social context of phallocratic reality
within which sex is still embedded, and hence took the feminist politics out
of lesbianism.
None the less the feminist point remains (marginalized and derided though
it might be). The feminist point is that sex is central to womens oppression.
It is through heterosexual desire that women are fitted, and fit themselves,
into their subordinate roles in relation to men. Relations of domination
function most efficiently to the extent that individuals consent to the status
quo, rather than being overtly and forcibly coerced. People must accept the
sphere allotted to them within the hierarchy and see it as the only reality. It
is womens lot to serve men, to see no alternative to their subordinate roles
in relation to men, to gain access to human status only through men, and
to embrace that as their own identity. Heterosexual desire puts the excite-
ment and the reality into womens subordination to men (Jeffreys, 1992).
Lesbianism within the feminist context was meant as a challenge to the
exclusiveness and naturalness of heterosexual desire as the only form of
intimacy women are allowed. It was a refusal to serve or service men, a
D E F I N I N G F E M I N I S M 15
I am making the much stronger claim that this is what feminism is. The
definition is presented as the definition of feminism, the one which makes
sense of the feminist project. It addresses the logic of feminist politics,
theory and practice; and it is broad enough to include most of what is
recognized as feminism, while being specific enough to allow anti-feminist
arguments and assertions to be identified and excluded. It is true that I am
a single individual making the claim, and that I speak on no ones behalf but
my own. But that does not debar me (or anyone else) from saying what femi-
nism is. This does not mean that the definition proposed here is unchal-
lengeable and beyond argument. On the contrary, because it is argued for in
the clearest possible terms, it is very much open for debate. Disagreements,
however, cannot be resolved by means of well-intentioned decisions to
respect our individual differences of opinion. Although polite agreement to
disagree may sometimes be the only civilized option, it does not resolve the
contradictions, but simply postpones them. While individual feminists are
the participants in the debate, feelings and opinions are not sufficient refer-
ents for feminist theory, which must be argued through with reference to the
logic and evidence of feminist theory and practice.
Neither is the definition I propose confined to one type of feminism. The
tendency to refer to feminisms in the plural is an evasion of the real and
important contradictions between competing assertions made in the name
of feminism. To the extent that arguments are mutually contradictory, the
conflicts will never be resolved by separating the antagonistic positions and
allocating them to different feminisms. Respect for differences can be car-
ried too far, especially when those differences are not just differences but
glaring incompatibilities. I intend that the definition I have proposed here
will allow the conflicts to be addressed directly.
A Feminist Standpoint
What I have been arguing for is a feminist standpoint, although the sense in
which I use the term differs crucially from the way it is already being used
within feminist writings. I do not ground a feminist standpoint in women,
womens experience, womens pain and oppression (Jaggar, 1983), womens
life activity (Harding, 1986; Hartsock, 1985; Smith, 1972), womens empa-
thy (Keller, 1983), womens more integrated (than mens) ways of knowing
(Rose, 1987), nor in any postulated unique access women might have to car-
ing (Noddings, 1984), or to peculiarly female forms of knowledge (Andolsen
et al., 1987). The concept of a feminist standpoint could only have come
from women, and it must not lose sight of women and womens interests. But
womens social location alone is not sufficient guarantee of feminist com-
mitment, vide womens embracing of right-wing, fascist, misogynist values,
for example, and the myriad of ways in which women can embrace our own
oppression because it is the only reality we know. And men are capable of
understanding a feminist standpoint, although not capable of contributing
18 U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
to one, I would suggest for strategic reasons men still tend to dominate
wherever they are included, because male supremacy is still the way the
world is and its patterns and habits are still too deeply ingrained.
A feminist standpoint, as I interpret it, starts from the question which is
prior to any discussions about womens nature, womens abilities, womens
life situations, etc. That question is: why are women and their concerns
problematic? It is the answer to that question because of male supremacy
which constitutes the revolutionary potential and actuality of feminism. A
feminist standpoint is grounded first and foremost in acknowledging the
existence of male domination in order to challenge and oppose it. This con-
sciousness arises out of the social positioning of women because the problems
of womens exclusion from human status are more pressing for women
(although in the long term everyone stands to gain a human status which is at
no ones expense). But womens consciousness of their life situations does not
become feminist until it develops into an awareness that womens social posi-
tioning is structured by male domination, and unless the male monopolization
of human status is resisted consciously, deliberately and continuously.
Most of the proponents of a feminist standpoint are aware that womens
experience alone is insufficient for feminist politics, but they are vague on
the question of how we get from experience to theory and politics. How
does a feminist consciousness arise out of womens life activity when all
women are not feminists, and some women are actively anti-feminist? What
is it that has been achieved with the commitment to a feminist standpoint?
What is it that is being struggled against and what is being struggled for?
What is it that a feminist standpoint aims to liberate us from?
None of the feminist standpoint theorists unequivocally identifies engag-
ing with male supremacy as the link which transforms womens experience
into feminist politics. They certainly recognize the existence of, and oppose,
male domination. They also apply this recognition to their analyses. But
they do so only implicitly or tangentially, while at the same time failing to
acknowledge that it is this very challenge to male domination which pro-
vides the structuring principle translating a consciousness of womens lives
into feminist politics. In the absence of any explicit naming of what the
feminist political struggle is about, their task is confined to finding some-
thing intrinsic to womens lives which in and of itself leads to a feminist con-
sciousness. But to the extent that they do find this something, they do so
because their prior commitment to acknowledging the existence of male
supremacy allows them to see it.
Nancy Hartsock, for example, states that womens lives make available a
particular and privileged vantage point on male supremacy (Hartsock,
1987: 159). She then proceeds to examine what she refers to as womens
life activity and the sexual division of labour in order to find that privi-
leged vantage point. But her account of womens life activity is already
informed by her commitment to opposing male supremacy. It is her feminist
standpoint which enables her, for example, to perceive the sexual division
of labour as a political problem rather than a fact of nature, womens
D E F I N I N G F E M I N I S M 19
sufficient for feminist politics. She says that the standpoint of women . . . is
not something that can be discovered through a survey of womens existing
beliefs and attitudes (Jaggar, 1983: 371), and that all aspects of our experi-
ence, including our feelings and emotions, must be subjected to critical
scrutiny and feminist political analysis (p. 380). She discusses the case of
right-wing women whose thinking about their lives and experiences, far
from leading to a feminist consciousness, has resulted in a militant anti-
feminism. She concludes the discussion by saying: Simply to be a woman,
then, is not sufficient to guarantee a clear understanding of the world as it
appears from the standpoint of women (pp. 3823).
But although she is aware that it is political struggle which transforms
womens experience into a womens standpoint, and although she is also
aware of male dominance as one of the problems addressed by feminist
politics, she does not identify the struggle against male dominance as the
crucial defining factor of that politics. She acknowledges the insight that
the prevailing culture is suffused with the perceptions and values of male
dominance as one of the main contributions of radical feminism. But she
seems to believe that this insight entails attempting to create an alternative
womens culture which is unrealistic, elitist and incomprehensible to most
women. She says that it is only socialist feminism which is able to explain
why this culture is dominant and to link the anti-feminist consciousness of
many women with the structure of their daily lives, because socialist femi-
nism is explicitly historical materialist. But at this point male dominance
drops out of her account this culture is simply dominant and we are
left with nothing but womens daily lives and a political and scientific
struggle which has lost its central focus (p. 382). Without male domination
as the inimical adversary of feminist politics, there is no possibility of iden-
tifying the ways in which womens lives are imbued with the meanings and
values of male supremacy, and hence no possibility of engaging in any politi-
cal struggle at all. Jaggar eventually acknowledges this. She emphasizes the
long and protracted nature of the feminist struggle to reveal the intricate
and systematic reality of male dominance, and says that In the end an ade-
quate representation of the world from the standpoint of women requires
the material overthrow of male domination (p. 384).
Nothing more than this acknowledgement is needed for a feminist stand-
point, since to expose, name and describe male domination is already to
acknowledge womens interests in opposing it. It is at this point, once the
existence of male domination has been recognized, that all the really hard
questions start: What counts as male domination? How do we recognize it?
Is this particular phenomenon an instance of male domination or is it not?
What does sexuality have to do with it? What is my responsibility? Can any-
thing be done about it? Should anything be done about it? It is certainly part
of the feminist enterprise to insist on the recognition of womens contribu-
tion to subsistence, and their contribution to childrearing (Hartsock, 1987:
164). But to focus only on revaluing womens traditional activities, impor-
tant though that is, is not what centrally defines a feminist standpoint.
D E F I N I N G F E M I N I S M 21
Notes
1 Martha Nussbaum locates the origin of the idea of social construction even
earlier in history, in ancient Greek philosophy (Nussbaum, 1999: p. 5 of 12).
2 Allen suggests a third meaning of power, a concept of power-with as a way
of theorizing coalitions with other social movements (p. 8). But this is already con-
tained in the idea of power-as-capacity, Allens power-to, since there is no implica-
tion that the power to achieve outcomes only happens in isolation.
3 I am indebted to Renate Klein for drawing my attention to this point.
2 Ideology justifying
do m i n a t i o n
this factual acceptance need not involve any signs of normative acceptance or
indoctrination. . . . Compulsion is most obviously founded in the structure of
economic relations, which oblige people to behave in ways which support the
status quo and to defer to the decisions of the powerful if they are to continue
to work and to live. (ibid.: 122, 1545)
24 U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
The notion of ideology appears to me difficult to make use of, for three reasons.
The first is that, like it or not, it always stands in virtual opposition to some-
thing else which is supposed to count as truth. . . . The second drawback is that
the concept of ideology refers, I think, necessarily, to something of the order of
a subject. Thirdly, ideology stands in a secondary position relative to something
which functions as its infrastructure, as its material, economic determinant, etc.
For these three reasons, I think that this is a notion that cannot be used without
circumspection. (Foucault, 1980: 118)
But Foucaults objections are otiose, not surprisingly, given that he makes
no distinction between power and domination, a tendency which he shares
with most social theorists. While much of what Foucault said about power
is accurate, his account is limited by his inability to recognize domination
and hence to conceive of alternatives. None the less, he does clearly state the
main objections to the concept of ideology. To take his third point first: as I
pointed out above, using the concept of ideology does not necessarily entail
any commitment to a base/superstructure model of society. It is not intrin-
sically tied to the idea of an economic base outside ideology and which
determines it.
Foucaults second point that the concept of ideology necessarily implies
something of the order of a subject is correct. But rather than being an
objection to using the term, that implication is one which should be retained.
While it is politically important to challenge the ideology of individualism,
not all references to individuals are ideological, and unless there is some idea
of what it is to be human there can be no politics and no morality. Accepting
the need for something of the order of a subject does not entail accepting
the other connotations which Foucault appears to believe are inextricably
tied in to the idea of the individual (Foucault, 1980: 98, 117). It is possible
at one and the same time to acknowledge that the subject is historically con-
stituted, and that each of us is a locus of moral choice and responsibility. To
leave the account of the subject where Foucault does, as both constituted by
power and its vehicle (ibid.: 98), is to leave us trapped in domination, with
no choice except inert subjection, active compliance, or magnanimity on the
part of the powerful. While there may not be any source of all rebellions, or
pure law of the revolutionary (Foucault, 1985: 96), it is possible to refuse
complicity, not always or once and for all, but over and over again, and wher-
ever it is possible. And those refusals, sometimes tentative, sometimes
adamant, sometimes partial, sometimes absolute, sometimes negotiable,
sometimes permanent, are made by individual human beings who live with
the consequences. Hence, the notion of ideology does require something of
the order of a subject, although not one existing outside any system of mean-
ing at all, but one capable of actively choosing among alternatives to the
extent that alternatives are available and recognizable.
To come finally to Foucaults first point: that the use of the term ideology
necessarily stands in opposition to something identified as truth.3 In the
sense in which I use the term, ideology is not one special kind of discourse
among others (using discourse in the broadest sense to mean a system of
I D E O L O G Y J U S T I F Y I N G D O M I N AT I O N 27
meaning). Rather, it is, as Jorge Larrain says, a level of meaning which can
be present in all kinds of discourses . . . [and which] may well be absent
(Larrain, 1979: 130, 235 n. 2). It is not the case that we are always in
ideology. What we are always in are systems of meaning. Whether mean-
ings are ideological or not depends on whether or not they are used in the
service of domination. That cannot be decided from a position of neutrality.
Domination can only be seen from a position which involves a willingness
to see it. Without such a position, manifestations of domination can always
be interpreted as something else, as isolated instances, exceptions, idiosyn-
crasies, personal pathologies or trivia, or even as something they are not
pain as pleasure, for example, or degradation as fun, humiliation as pride,
oppression as freedom.
Because ideological meanings can appear anywhere, there is no need to
posit an alternative to ideology, a discourse of truth with which to counter
lies, falsehoods and distortions, the usual contender for this status being
science. The distinction between what is ideological and what is not, is not
always a distinction between falsehood and truth. Although questions of
truth and falsity are not irrelevant in deciding what is ideological and what is
not, they are not the same question. Given that relations of domination con-
stitute the status quo, ideological beliefs are often true (at least in the refer-
ential sense) rather than false. Whether or not any particular ideological
practice is true or false depends on the standpoint from which it is viewed.
From the standpoint of immersion in the male supremacist status quo, it is
true, for example, that the only form of adult intimacy available to women is
a sexual relation with a man, that womens lives revolve around getting and
keeping a man. Women (and men) believe it, act upon it, make choices based
upon it, run their lives according to it. From a feminist standpoint, it is a lie.
It involves a calculated falsehood which suppresses consciousness of alter-
natives, which obliterates the knowledge that women can also be intimate
with women, as friends, lovers and kin, with children as human beings rather
than as burdens or jailers, with men simply as friends, and that women can
live happy and fulfilled lives without sexual relationships with men.
By and large, ideology is not stated in testable form. The generalized
belief that only men are human, for example, is never stated in these terms.
Indeed, to say it aloud is already to undermine its efficacy because it can
only operate as long as it remains hidden. Saying outright that male
supremacist conditions allot a human status only to men, exposes the con-
tradiction between the ideology and the fact that women are human too.
Instead of being openly acknowledged, belief in the male as the human
norm shows itself in a myriad of disparate contexts, the connections between
which only appear from a feminist standpoint. It frequently operates through
what might be called the phenomenon of female non-existence. There are
those occasions of everyday social life where women are habitually talked
over and ignored, where matters of interest to women are either never
raised or are dropped as quickly as possible, where men talk to each other
as though there were no women present, where at best women are listened
28 U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
supremacy. Violent and arrogant males are those who have learned that
lesson only too well, who have managed to continue denying the evident
humanity of women, and whose own sense of humanity extends no further
than their genitals. The violence and arrogance express a subliminal aware-
ness of the paltriness of the only justification they know for their own exis-
tence. The consequence for women is a permanent reign of terror, subdued
most of the time, but always there curtailing our freedom of movement and
action.
When the existence of women is acknowledged, it is interpreted in terms
favourable to men. To be a woman under male supremacist conditions
means to be the helpmeet and nurturer of males. To be a woman is not to
exist in her own right. If she settles for her conventional role, she is confined
to the constricted sphere of domesticity, financially deprived, emotionally
and economically exploited, isolated from other women, restricted by the
ever-present needs of the children, subjected to the whims of an individual
man, her quality of life dependent on whether or not he is good to her, on
his decisions, not hers. Women have developed countless stratagems for
retrieving some sense of dignity and self-respect, or alternatively some modi-
cum of power and domination, despite the limited domain within which
they are allowed to operate. And caring for and relating intimately to
children is a worthwhile and dignified project in itself, despite the low valua-
tion it is given in phallocratic reality. But what it means to be a woman
under conditions of male supremacy is to be expected to service men and
children, preferably male.4
For the purposes of feminist politics, whether any particular ideological
pronouncement is true or false is not the main issue. What a feminist poli-
tics has to decide is whether the meanings which structure peoples lives
reinforce relations of ruling by reinforcing the interests of the dominators
and suppressing the interests of the subordinated, whether meanings can be
used to challenge or undermine domination, or whether they have to be
changed or discarded altogether. These are decisions which cannot be made
once and for all, but which will continue to need to be made as long as male
supremacy lasts. But such decisions cannot even be made unless the exis-
tence of male domination is seen in the first place.
Tr u t h a n d D o m i n a t i o n
The question of truth is not, however, irrelevant to feminist politics. Although
it is not often addressed in feminist writings, there are some writers who are
explicitly opposed to the idea that feminism can make claims to truth, on the
grounds that such claims are inherently complicit with domination.
This is the position Jane Flax takes, for example (1990: 2223). She asserts
a direct connection between truth and domination, and asks: What are the
relations of knowledge and power? Does all knowledge necessarily inflict
violence on things, ourselves, and other persons? (p. 236, her emphasis) a
question she has already answered by equating a claim to truth with a will
30 U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
to power (p. 12). For Chris Weedon, too, claims to truth are inexorably
implicated in domination:
Truth is by definition fixed, absolute and unchanging. It is the final guarantee
of the way things are. . . . It is in making claims to truth that discourses demon-
strate their inevitable conservatism, their investment in particular versions of
meaning and their hostility to change. (Weedon, 1987: 131)
To me, feminism means the personal is political, however, this is totally oppo-
site to the ethos of Academia. Academia means being detached, objective,
32 U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
Such complaints are not new. In 1976, some women criticized aspects of
the Patriarchy Conference, held in London in that year, as intimidating and
mystifying (Dalston Study Group, 1978). They said that certain papers pre-
sented at the conference were no different in kind from those presented in
a male academic environment. The organization of the sessions did not
allow the listeners to intervene or contribute; the language within which the
ideas were expressed was the impoverished depersonalized analytical lan-
guage of intellectuals, which bore no relation to day to day language, and
which had the effect of making large numbers of women feel inadequate,
stupid or angry; and the papers made no reference to debates within the
womens movement on the very issues those papers were supposedly
addressing.
They suggested that the problem was partly a result of the paper-givers
failure to make their theoretical framework clear and accessible to those
who were not acquainted with the particular theoretical constructs being
used; partly a result of the isolated social position of radical intellectuals
vis vis the groups . . . whose interests their theory seeks to represent and
sharpen. They themselves were not opposed to theoretical work per se. But
they felt that theory needed to be linked to struggles and strategy and to
controversies within the movement, that arguments needed to be stated as
clearly as possible and terms not in everyday use explained, and that the
theorizer should incorporate her own process into her theorizing, clarifying
her agreements and disagreements and acknowledging her own confusions.
The problems identified by the Dalston Womens Study Group remain
unresolved over 20 years later. If anything, they have worsened under the
influence of postmodernism. The inaccessibility of academic feminist theory
was a problem then, and it is still a problem now, because the original
problem has not been overcome. The original problem is the requirement
that feminism subordinate itself to malestream thought, within either the
traditional academic disciplines or whatever intellectual fashion is current.
There is a sense in which combining feminism with already recognized
academic disciplines is a reasonable endeavour. Feminism did not start as
an academic discipline, but as a groundswell of discontent arising out of
womens changed perceptions of their own experience. This discontent was
inchoate and untheorized, sometimes confused and confusing, sometimes
prematurely closed off to debate. Already established academic disciplines
seemed to promise intellectually rigorous ways of organizing and managing
the changing consciousness of the world and womens place in it. But as the
members of the Dalston Study Group pointed out, those best placed for
doing the theorizing failed to stay in touch with the womens movement and
their own experience of feminist politics. They allowed themselves to be
seduced by the intricacies and sophistication of what they encountered in
I D E O L O G Y J U S T I F Y I N G D O M I N AT I O N 33
theorists have (Trebilcot, 1991: 49), that we substitute stories for theory
allows no way of deciding between stories which reinforce the meanings and
values of domination, and those which illustrate the meaning of feminism
for womens lives. It is to ignore the fact that the experience which gener-
ates the stories is already theory-laden. Simply telling stories without any
analysis or critique threatens to allow free rein to those meanings and values
which already constitute experience as real. To fail to acknowledge the
social conditions within which experience is already embedded is to reduce
the political to the personal, to a matter of opinion with no way of adjudi-
cating between conflicting accounts of the way the world is. This outcome
is entirely functional in maintaining the dominant status quo. If conflicts
cannot even be addressed, because everyone is simply entitled to her own
opinion, they cannot be resolved. Theory is what provides the moral and
political meaning, purpose and value of experience. If the theorizing is not
done deliberately, it happens anyway; and since structures of domination
operate most efficiently through the acquiescence of subordinated popula-
tions, opposition to relations of power requires constant vigilance if they are
to be challenged and complicity avoided. Theory in this sense is vital to the
continued existence of feminist politics.
Feminism gives rise to certain kinds of questions, names the kinds of
things it names, uncovers certain kinds of facts, and interprets the world in
the way it does, because of its prior moral and political commitment to
opposing male domination in the interests of women first, a priority made
necessary in a world in which women are placed last or nowhere at all. The
feminist project involves both meaning and truth. It is feminisms politics
and morality which give it its meaning, that is, the ways in which feminist
understanding happens and the world makes sense from a feminist stand-
point. The truth of feminism arises out of its system of meanings, in the
sense that, with the advent of feminism, certain questions could be asked,
certain facts appeared, and certain answers became possible, which were
previously inconceivable. Feminist knowledge acquires its meaning through
its political understanding of relations of power, and through its project of
re-interpreting and changing reality in order to create possibilities for
women to control the terms of our own existence, a project which proceeds
at the expense of men only to the extent that men remain committed to a
human status acquired at womens expense. Feminism uncovers certain
facts about the world, and in that sense can lay claims to truth. But although
feminist theory is an empirical endeavour, concerned with discovering facts
about the world and organizing and explaining those facts, the empirical
content of feminist theory is not its most important aspect. Given the social
power of the forces of male supremacy, the facts will frequently be against
us anyway.
Since feminist knowledge is explicitly neither value-free nor disinterested,
the knowledge which it generates is based on, and productive of, identifiable
interests and values. It is formulated in the interests of women, in particular
womens interest in seeing an end to male domination, and in opposition to
I D E O L O G Y J U S T I F Y I N G D O M I N AT I O N 35
those vested and powerful interests which maintain the male as the human
norm, and which enforce the interests and human rights of some individuals
at the expense of others. The moral values which feminism espouses are those
of a genuinely human status available to all. The primary feminist value is a
commitment to the ideal of human dignity, of the right of every human being
to a dignified standard of human existence. The question of human dignity is
an ethical one, not an empirical matter. That the ethic of human dignity is
constantly violated in fact does not invalidate the moral judgement that
people ought to be treated with respect. This commitment starts from the
standpoint of women, because the exclusion of women from human rights
and dignities is the most systematic and widely distributed of all human
exclusions, because men have too much to lose, namely their masculinity
defined at womens expense (although everything to gain), and because
women already provide a model of the human unencumbered by the rapa-
cious demands of the phallus. Women can be complicit with the meanings
and values of male supremacy, and men can resist. But womens lack of the
supreme value of phallocratic reality, suggests that women also lack the chief
barrier to connecting with other human beings as unique and valuable ends
in themselves, and provides a starting point for a revolution in the terms and
conditions of human existence.
Notes
1 To use the term in this way is to confine it to one of its many meanings
(Eagleton, 1991). Any meaning which deletes the connotations of domination, how-
ever, bowdlerizes the word and deprives it of its political import.
2 The question of why women stay with violent men is an ideological one, as is
the explanation that they stay because they like being beaten. Both question and
answer ignore the structural constraints of economic dependence and male posses-
siveness which marriage still imposes on women. It also ignores the fact that many
of the women killed by the men they have been intimate with, are killed after they
leave, that is, they are killed because they have left.
3 Or science. For a discussion of the science versus ideology debates, see
Larrain, 1979.
4 It is a fascinating exercise to ask oneself what is the sex of the children por-
trayed in the public media films, television, newspapers, advertisements, novels.
They are almost invariably male, especially if the child is active and adventurous.
5 Interestingly, Jane Flax concludes her book with a distinction between meaning
and truth. She suggests the possibility of displac[ing] truth / falsity with problems of
meaning(s) (Flax, 1990: 222). She does not discuss in detail what that might involve,
and she is doubtful about its feasibility. Perhaps it is better only to analyze desires for
meaning and to learn to live without grounds, she says (p. 223). However, having
located domination wholly on the side of truth, she does not perceive that questions
of meaning, of how the world is known and understood, of communication, clarity,
intelligibility and accountability, also involve questions about domination.
6 This is a variation on a statement by Catharine MacKinnon: Sexuality is to
feminism what work is to marxism: that which is most ones own, yet most taken
away (MacKinnon, 1982: 1).
3 Ideology enabling and
disguising domination
A bove all, ideology is intended to be made true. One of the chief ways in
which consent to oppression is managed is through the cultivation of
desire, the constitution of subjects who embrace relations of domination
because they want to, because it is pleasurable to do so. Pleasure and desire
enable the continuation of the social conditions of male supremacy. This
cannot be left to chance or nature, but must be constantly reinforced and
endlessly reiterated.
The medium which expresses male supremacist desire most clearly, with-
out apology, equivocation or adornment, is pornography. In what follows, I
locate the pornographic imagination with men because what I am criticizing
is the ideological construction of sex around the penis. As such, porno-
graphy and its practices operate in the interests of men in complicity with
the belief that humanity depends on penis-possession. But although the
primary motivating force and raison dtre of pornography is the eroticizing
of mens domination of women, the pleasures and desires of domination are
restricted neither to the male psyche nor to heterosexuality. The purpose of
ideology is to purvey the interests of the dominators as the interests of all,
and it serves its purpose to the extent that anyone can be complicit with the
pornographic imagination. The meanings and values of domination, while
they originate in the phallic mandate that women service the penis, can be,
and are, generalized to any human interaction whatsoever. Women can be
complicit with the ideology of pornography to the extent that they accept a
second-rate human status for themselves and eroticize their own subordi-
nation. This is exemplified in conventional heterosexual relations where
women believe that they cannot live without a man, that they are empty and
unfulfilled unless they are in a relationship with a man, and who structure
their lives around that desire. Alternatively, women can also be complicit to
the extent that they strive to be like men, finding value only in men, hold-
ing women in contempt, and accepting an erotics of domination as their
own desire. The latter is exemplified in lesbian sadomasochism. Although in
lesbian relationships there is no actual penis present, sadomasochism is phal-
lic desire. Not only are sadomasochistic practices the acting out of desire for
domination and subordination, the penis is frequently present in effigy, as a
I D E O L O G Y E N A B L I N G A N D D I S G U I S I N G D O M I N AT I O N 37
dildo (Jeffreys, 1993: 2830). Gay male sexual practices, too, can be complicit
with phallic desire, even though there are no women present, to the extent
that those practices are sadomasochistic; and again, women are frequently
present in effigy, as drag. Both lesbian and gay male relationships can
mimic heterosexuality. None the less, although the ideology of pornography
reaches beyond the male psyche and the heterosexual context, I have con-
fined it to that context in order to show the central significance of porno-
graphy most clearly and succinctly.
The central symbol structuring male supremacist desire is the penis-as-
phallus. Because the following discussion focuses on those social conditions
under which the penis is the phallus, that is, the chief value structuring the
social conditions of phallocratic reality, I use the two terms, penis and phal-
lus, interchangeably. Used in this sense, the penis is not simply anatomy.
I am not referring to it as some kind of in itself biological organ, since such
a usage (to the extent that it makes any sense at all) would mean that phallic
domination is inevitable and unchangeable. Rather, what I am referring to is
the meaning the penis carries under male supremacist conditions, a meaning
which can be changed without doing any damage to the organ in itself. As
should already be obvious, I believe not only that the penis can be severed
from its role as primary symbol of domination, but also that that separation
must be a present possibility (rather than a future hope), otherwise it would
be inconceivable. But although it is already possible to conceive of the penis
as just another bodily organ, possible on the part of both sexes although more
possible for women because they have less at stake in the hyper-valuation of
the penis and more to gain by reducing its significance, there is a great deal
of feminist work still to be done before the penis-as-phallus is abolished and
a genuinely human status becomes available to all.
The chief meaning and value of male supremacist conditions is that penis-
possession stands for human status (Dworkin, 1981; Thompson, 1991).
Those who have penises are automatically human; those who do not, are
not, although that lack can always be contested and frequently is. Because
the penis is the central symbol of human status under conditions of male
supremacy, the chief pleasures and desires of those conditions centre around
the penis. Because the penis means sex, the chief pleasures and desires of
male supremacist conditions are those of sex.1 The ideology of the natural
operates to keep sex out of the domain of the moral and the political, to ren-
der it beyond questioning and debate (unless it goes too far, in which case
its excesses are located with isolated pathological individual men, or blamed
on women). Under the ideological imperative of penis-possession, sex is the
last bastion of the natural and men are its bearers. Although for most pur-
poses male supremacist ideology equates women with nature, because both
must be dominated by men as resources to be mined to fuel male power,
within the ideology of phallic sexuality it is men who are entirely natural.
That ungovernable male sex drive must be allowed to operate at any cost
because it is nature, only nature and nothing but nature. It is mens nature,
therefore it is human nature. It is beyond investigation, beyond political
38 U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
and moral critique. It exists and the lives of everyone must be structured
around it. The problems resulting from its unchecked impetus rape, pros-
titution, world over-population, AIDS, enforced pregnancy, for example
can only be managed, not abolished, because the penis must never be
hampered in its progress. Men cannot help themselves because the penis has
a life of its own and is not subject to the conscious will. What the penis
obeys is nature, its desire and activity a direct and automatic result of the
effect of hormonal secretions on the male body. Hormones are natural,
penile activity is caused by hormones, male sexual activity is governed by the
rule of nature.
From a feminist standpoint, however, this is nothing but male suprema-
cist ideology. Far from being natural, phallic sexuality is a moral and politi-
cal activity. Men do have a choice and they can be held to account when
they exercise their freedom to choose at womens expense. Mens sexual
behaviour is not caused by hormonal dictates. It is because the penis serves
the ideological function of symbolizing human status that it is so heavily
charged with erotic energy, and not because it is driven by testosterone. Men
must keep using it because they need to keep proving that they exist, that
their humanity is inextricably entwined with penis-possession; women
must be constantly used by it to prove that men exist, that the sum total of
a man is his penis. Because there is no humanity beyond the penis, what the
penis can do it ought to do. Anything and everything must be subordinated
to penile activity if men are to be what phallic ideology requires them to be.
Although there are penalties and sanctions against the worst excesses of the
penis, ranging from disapproval to imprisonment, the culture of male
supremacy still gives permission for those excesses. There are prison sen-
tences for rape, the murder of women, incest, for example, but there is also
a plethora of excuses provided to demonstrate that nothing happened, or
nothing of any importance.
Pornography is the ideology of male supremacist masculine desire writ
large and shameless. It is the clearest, most unequivocal expression of male
supremacist ideology in existence. As Sheila Jeffreys has said:
Pornography made it clear that what constituted sex under male supremacy was
precisely the eroticised subordination of women. Inequality was sexy and the
sexiness of this inequality was the grease that oiled the machinery of male
supremacy. The sexiness of male supremacy . . . was the unacknowledged motor
force of male supremacy. Through sexual fantasy men were able to reinforce the
sense of their power and of womens inferiority daily and be rewarded for every
thought and image of women subordinated with sexual pleasure; a pleasure
acknowledged to be the most valuable form of pleasure in male-supremacist
culture. (Jeffreys, 1990: 2523)
Pornography is the ideology which reinforces the phallic desire of men who
already want it because they seek it out and pay for it. It depicts the worst that
men can do to women and encourages them to do it. It tells men they have a
right to do whatever they want to do with their penises. It tells them that
I D E O L O G Y E N A B L I N G A N D D I S G U I S I N G D O M I N AT I O N 39
women are infinitely available to men, that they are endlessly compliant, that
they are enamoured of the penis and enchanted with what it can do, that they
will take anything, anything at all, and beg for more. It says that women are
there for men to fuck, that that is the sole reason for female existence. It says
that women are nothing but things, a collection of fetishized body parts,
breasts, buttocks, hair, faces and legs arrayed for male delectation, orifices
serving as receptacles for the penis. Because it portrays women as objects, it
gives men permission to harm women. It tells them that women are not
human, that they do not suffer, whatever is done to them. It tells men that
they can hurt women because it is already being done and no one is com-
plaining, including the women portrayed. Pornography is the theory; sexual
violence, rape, prostitution and compulsory heterosexuality are the practices.
This does not mean that pornography causes male sexual violence, that it is
separate from sexual violence and prior to it. Male sexual violence is not
caused by anything. To frame it in such a way is to be complicit with the ideo-
logical belief that male sexuality is natural. Rather, male sexual violence is
a moral evil for which the men who do it are responsible and about which
they have choices. Pornography is an apologia for male sexual violence. It
provides it with meaning, gives men permission for it, and deadens male
ethical sensibilities.
The misogynist social implications of pornography, however, are largely
hidden from women. Although some of its less blatant icons appear in
public media, especially advertising which cynically evokes desires already
in place, the worst productions of the pornographic imagination are still
closeted in adult bookstores, video shops and movie houses. Although men
bring it home, they do so as individuals, and hence its systematic nature is
disguised. It is for this reason that the struggle against pornography has
come to occupy such a central position in the radical feminist critique of
male supremacist relations of power. Radical feminist campaigns against
pornography are intended to tell women how men are willingly being
trained to view them. As Andrea Dworkin said:
Women did not know. . . . I decided that I wanted women to see what I saw. This
may be the most ruthless choice I have ever made. But . . . it was the only choice
that enables me to triumph over my subject by showing it, remaking it, turning
it into something that we define and use rather than letting it remain something
that defines and uses us. (Dworkin, 1981: 304)
Individualism
An ideology of desire is also an ideology of individualism. If the interests of
the ruling class are to be presented as the interests of all, their systematic
nature as domination must be disguised. Where better to hide the dominat-
ing nature of relations of ruling than in the depths of the individual psyche?
If domination is desired, it cannot be challenged and opposed. If it consti-
tutes the very roots of personal identity, it cannot be seen as systematic. If it
operates by means of feelings and emotions, it belongs in the realm of pri-
vate satisfaction, not public politics. If domination is fragmented and dis-
persed among individuals, it cannot provide the basis for common interests
among the oppressed.
The ideology of individualism depicts humanity as a set of isolated
selves, floating freely in a space which is social only to the extent that there
are many selves. Each self is detached from every other, and contains within
itself all that is necessary for identification as human. Desires, needs, inter-
ests, beliefs, actions, feelings, attitudes and behaviours, are perceived as per-
sonal properties intrinsic to each individual, and as arising fully formed
within each individual psyche. The desires, etc., of any one individual can
come into conflict or competition with those of any other, or can provide a
reason for co-operation. But social interaction happens only after those
desires, etc., have been identified, after they have been located as the inher-
ent property of an individual person.
In contrast, a feminist politics needs to be able to see that male domina-
tion is a social system of ideological meanings and values which certainly
44 U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
influence the hearts and minds of individuals, but which are not co-extensive
with them. Although that influence is not monolithic and inevitable, it is
intransigent to the extent that those meanings are perceived as essential
attributes of individuals, rather than as ideological requirements of relations
of ruling. If relations of domination and subordination are interpreted as
nothing but properties of individuals, they cannot be seen as relations of rul-
ing at all. They become simply a matter of preferences and choices engaged
in by discrete individuals who have no responsibilities beyond their own
immediate pleasures and satisfactions. In this libertarian discourse, politics
vanishes. If only individuals exist, political critique can only be seen as per-
sonal insult or annihilation of the self, and disagreement becomes assertion
of the self against threatening and hostile others. Freedom is reduced to the
absence of constraint, either on the part of the self or of others. The dam-
age done to self and others by relations of ruling is either not addressed, or
is purveyed as a positive good emanating from within desiring individuals.
The clearest examples of this kind of unthinking commitment to the ideo-
logy of the atomized individual can be found in the libertarian defence of sex
radicals, sexual outlaws or erotic dissidents. In Gayle Rubins paper,
Thinking Sex (Rubin, 1984), this defence is couched in terms of an account
constructed around a set of unjustly treated individuals paedophiles,
fetishists, sadomasochists, etc. who just happen to have a certain kind of
intrinsic sexual desire which structures and informs their personal identity and
makes them the kinds of individuals they are. As individuals with particular
sexual needs, they have a right to the expression of their sexual desire, a
right which they are unfairly prevented from exercising by moralistic prohi-
bitions and sanctions which Rubin perceives as emanating both from the domi-
nant heterosexual society and from feminism. Within the terms of Rubins
account, these sexual desires are self-evidently not socially constructed,
because they are treated with social disapproval and moral outrage. Rubin
assumes without question that these desiring individuals cannot possibly be
socially constituted because they are despised and rejected. They are subjected
to forms of social control only after they are recognized as the kinds of indi-
viduals they are. Society only arrives on the scene once these individuals have
been recognized for what they are, and the best thing society can do is to
leave them alone to exercise their individual rights and freedoms in peace and
in private. It is no accident that Rubins defence is couched in wholly indivi-
dualistic terms, in terms of fetishists rather than fetishism, sadomasochists
rather than sadomasochism, etc., in terms of people rather than in terms of
social practices with shared meanings and values. By keeping her focus firmly
fixed on people, she can surreptitiously appeal to the whole range of assump-
tions embedded in the ideology of individualism the public / private dis-
tinction, the dichotomy between individual and society, and the idea of
freedom as lack of constraint, of rights as the untrammelled exercise of the
will, and of desire as the personal property of single individuals. By avoiding
addressing desire as social practice, Rubin can avoid addressing the origins of
desire in the social conditions of male domination.
I D E O L O G Y E N A B L I N G A N D D I S G U I S I N G D O M I N AT I O N 45
moral agency simply is the ability to choose in limited situations, to pursue one
possibility rather than another, to thereby create value through what we choose,
and to conceive of ourselves as ones who are able to and do make choices and
thus as ones who are able to make a difference for ourselves and each other in
this living. . . . It is not because we are free and moral agents that we are able to
make moral choices. Rather, it is because we make choices, choose from among
alternatives, act in the face of limits, that we declare ourselves to be moral
beings. (Hoagland, 1988: 231 her emphasis)
For Hoagland the individual is the locus of moral choice, not absolutely,
but within constraints. This means that, even under conditions of male
domination, we do have alternatives and can make choices between them,
and to the extent that this is possible we are responsible for our actions and
hence free agents. At the same time, however, to the extent that we are sub-
jected under conditions of domination, not only through outright coercion
(violence, economic deprivation, etc.), but also through ideological manipu-
lation of our hearts and minds, there will frequently be occasions when we
are not responsible, either wholly or in part. In this account, the individual
is she who makes decisions between accepting responsibility and refusing it,
who acts when she can make a difference and refrains from acting, or with-
draws, when she cant, and avoids de-moralization by struggling constantly
against succumbing to the meanings and values of domination and holding
fast to the values of a genuinely human status for all.
This work of Hoagland is in contrast to other attempts to open up a space
of effective action within the domain of everyday life, which fail because
they do not acknowledge the ideological structuring of everyday experience.
Dorothy Smith, for example, interprets the lived actualities of peoples
lives as a form of authenticity which she contrasts to the ideological appa-
ratuses of the relations of ruling. Her purpose is to give sociology a human
face by extricating it from the objectivized forms of knowledge of its pre-
sent location in the textual realities of administration, management, pro-
fessional discourse, and the like, and locating it in the lived actualities as
people know them in their everyday / everynight lives (Smith, 1990: 97
and passim). But despite her clear perceptions of particular manifestations
of male domination, especially in her earlier book (Smith, 1987), Smith sees
domination only in its bureaucratic forms, and not in its mundane aspects
as manifested in everyday life. Instead, she appeals to everyday life, in the
form of womens experience, as a corrective to the traditional masculine
bias of sociology. She interprets domination as confined to objectified,
bureaucratic forms of relations of ruling, and fails to see that the womens
experience to which she appeals is already structured within relations of
male domination.
I D E O L O G Y E N A B L I N G A N D D I S G U I S I N G D O M I N AT I O N 49
For not all meaning and value serve domination. For those not in the
direst straits, for those who have access to the basic necessities of human
existence food, shelter, physical safety, freedom of movement and associa-
tion, etc. there is always the possibility of manoeuvre, negotiation and
innovation, and meanings and values can be changed, although not easily. In
that sense, anyone can be complicit and anyone can resist. But the two are
not, of course, symmetrical. For the most part compliance requires no more
than unthinking acceptance of what everyone knows to be the case, pro-
ceeding as usual without deliberation or reflection, knowing how to go on
without thinking about it, although even here there is room to move.
Resistance, however, requires a greater degree of self-reflection and deliber-
ate choice, questioning the world-taken-for-granted, espousing some
values and rejecting others, seeing the world in one way and not in another.
It involves recognizing both freedom and constraint, both the extent to
which one is responsible and the extent to which one is not. And because
these decisions cannot be made once and for all, it involves a constant readi-
ness to reconsider.
What any particular individual might or might not do, ought or ought not
to do, cannot be stated in general terms. Feminism does not lay down rules
and regulations, prohibitions and prescriptions, for individuals to follow or
avoid. What actions follow from any particular critique is for each of us to
decide for herself (or himself ). I would assert, as an ethical first principle, that
human beings ought to be free to choose between alternatives, and that, as a
matter of fact, we frequently are, at least those of us who are already provided
with basic necessities. The individual is a free agent to the extent that she has
access to alternatives, allows herself to recognize that alternatives exist, and
acts with knowledge of the extent and limits of her responsibility. No one can
do it completely alone. Non-compliance with dominant meanings and values
involves risking social rejection, non-acceptance or irrelevance, and some-
times violence, or (because society is not only out there but also in here)
madness. Effective refusal to comply requires an alternative body of mutual
knowledge, of shared meanings and values, which provides a social context
for resistance. This is what feminism supplies.
But just as male domination is not monolithic, rigid and static, neither is
feminism an absolute alternative. Feminisms primary commitment is to the
interests of women (and, not incidentally, also to the interests of men, to the
extent that men can see that a human status achieved at no ones expense is
in their interests too). Feminism is not concerned to criticize, or even theo-
rize, current social arrangements as long as they do not operate against
womens interests either by including women as mens subordinates, or by
excluding women from humanly valuable forms of life. Neither is feminism
critical of current arrangements which do not validate domination, which
allow for mutual recognition, respect and caring between people. Male
domination is a theoretical construct devised for a certain purpose, to focus
attention on those aspects of reality which must be denied if the social
system that is male domination is to be maintained. The feminist focus on
I D E O L O G Y E N A B L I N G A N D D I S G U I S I N G D O M I N AT I O N 51
Notes
1 This has been noted by a number of radical feminist theorists, among whom
are Catharine MacKinnon, Andrea Dworkin and Sheila Jeffreys.
2 The term is Sheila Jeffreys. She says: I use the term lesbianandgay to
describe those theorists who apparently make no distinction between lesbians and
gay men in their theory. They avoid feminist insights about the different sex class
positions of women and men and homogenize experience to create a universal gay
theory in which lesbian specificity disappears (Jeffreys, 1993: 18 n. 2).
3 I am greatly indebted to Mia Campioni for countless conversations over many
years on the male supremacist constitution of the maternal relation and the crucial
part it plays in the management of male power (Campioni, 1987, 1991, 1997).
4 Hence the preoccupation throughout the history of malestream social thought,
from Hobbes to Foucault, with the problem of social order, a preoccupation which
establishes conflict and antagonism as the primal reality, as that which must be over-
come in order for society to exist. Malestream social thought has focused on the
question: How is society possible given the original antagonism of the war of each
against all? Feminism, however, starts from the diametrically opposite question:
How do antagonism and conflict come about, given that we all originate from
within a social relationship?
P a r t Tw o Misunderstanding
Fe m i n i s m
4 Fe m i n i s m u n d e f i n e d
This single paragraph comprises the whole of Butlers critique within this text.
The scantness of the argument indicates both Butlers belief in the self-evident
nature of the critique, and her scorn for the form of feminist theorizing she
56 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
Note
1 These authors apply the phrase to womens oppression, not to patriarchy or
male domination.
5 Other definitions
Patriarchy
Patriarchy is the term most commonly used to designate the social problem
identified by feminism (or it used to be it would appear that it has
60 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
been supplanted by gender). But in its usual meaning of rule of the father,
the term patriarchy is a misnomer applied to the form of domination
challenged by feminism. The paternal domination portrayed in western
history, myth and literature is the rule of the father over the son. It involves
the imposition of, or struggles against, the ascendancy of some men over
other men. Patriarchy in this sense is an affair between men, and is rele-
vant to women only derivatively through our implication in power hierar-
chies among men.
But whatever the status of some males in relation to other males, the
problem identified by feminism is the subjection of women to men. Or
rather, because women have always resisted subjugation and asserted our
own worth despite the male monopolization of the human norm, as well
as acquiesced, accommodated ourselves, manoeuvred for some space and
freedom of movement, beat the oppressor at his own game, used his obses-
sions and weaknesses against him, etc., it is the male supremacist dream and
reality of female subjection which is of concern to feminism, not struggles
for ascendancy among men. To the extent that women aid the sons in their
battles with the fathers, no matter how worthy the cause, no matter how
justified the sons complaints, women are once again working in mens
interests. These may indeed be womens interests as well, but that cannot be
decided unless it is possible to see womens interests in the first place.
By identifying the enemy as patriarchy, feminism has somewhat mis-
named it, although it has not always misrecognized it. To the extent that the
problem of power-as-domination addressed by feminism is recognized as
male domination, it is identified accurately, whatever it is called. Kate
Millett, for example, named the problem patriarchy, but defined it pri-
marily in terms of male supremacy: If one takes patriarchal government to
be the institution whereby that half of the populace which is female is con-
trolled by that half which is male, the principles of patriarchy appear to be
twofold: male shall dominate female, elder male shall dominate younger
(Millett, 1970: 25). Ti-Grace Atkinson did not use the term patriarchy, but
she did identify the problem addressed by feminism as the domination of
women by men. Her preferred designation was the sex-class system:
problem? If this is what she meant, then she is wrong. Given that feminist
theory and practice is grounded in experience, it would seem obvious that
it always takes culturally specific forms, namely the forms and variations
which the feminist knows from her own experience. There may be problems
with generalizing from one specific historical and cultural context to other
historical periods and cultures. But those problems occur, not because the
original account was not specific enough, but because it was inaccurately
generalized to contexts where it did not apply (in which case its non-
application needs to be argued for, not simply asserted as self-evident). On
the other hand, if she meant that radical feminism is at fault because it
leaves unexplained every specific form of male domination and female sub-
ordination, then she was demanding the impossible.
This appeal to historical (and cultural) specificity played an important
role in socialist feminist attempts to amend what was regarded as the faults
and naveties of radical feminism. Michle Barrett also objected to early
radical feminist uses of the term patriarchy, on the grounds that such uses
invoke an apparently universal and trans-historical category of male domi-
nance, leaving us with little hope of change (Barrett, 1984: 12). But it is not
clear what the charge amounts to. Why would invoking male dominance
leave us with little hope of change? On the contrary, it is only by identify-
ing the problem as male dominance that there is any hope of change at all.
Unlike Beechey, Barrett did not feel that the term patriarchy was retriev-
able for present feminist purposes. She proposed to use it to refer only to soci-
eties where male domination is expressed through the power of the father.
Such societies, she said, are not capitalist ones (pp. 2501). However, this left
her without a term to refer to those current relations of ruling challenged by
feminism. Her preferred term for the problem addressed by feminism was
womens oppression, and she did sometimes use the term male domination.
But she did not connect the two by attributing womens oppression to male
domination, as of course she could not, because such an endeavour would be,
in her own terms, universal and trans-historical. As a consequence she could
only account for womens oppression in terms of contemporary capitalism.
But while it is certainly the case that women are oppressed by capitalism, there
are dimensions to that oppression male sexual violence, to name just one
which even the most thorough investigation of capitalism would never
uncover, and hence open the way to change. Barrett tried to resist arguing that
womens oppression was a consequence of capitalism. She criticized attempts
to account for womens oppression in terms of the supposed needs of capi-
talism itself (p. 248), or as a functional pre-requisite of capitalism (p. 249).
But her own insistence on confining the account of womens oppression to
a material basis in the relations of production and reproduction of capitalism
today (p. 249) left her with no alternative.
I would suggest that the term patriarchy has a limited usefulness for femi-
nism, given its tendency to slide back into its original meaning of the rule of
the father, and its socialist feminist history as a term emptied of meaning.
At the very least, feminists need to be alert to traps laid for the unwary by
OT H E R D E F I N I T I O N S 63
ill-considered uses of the term. At the same time, it does have an honourable
feminist history, and with a little feminist caution it can still provide good
service.
Sexism
The problem with the term sexism is that it does not contain domination
as its immediate referent, and hence does not immediately identify the
sex which dominates. It fits too easily into the individualist terminology of
liberalism, of rights, discrimination, attitudes, and prejudices. To the
extent that sexism means no more than distinctions based on sex, it
assumes an original equality between sexed individuals, an equality which is
transgressed by any action favouring one sex over another, including actions
taken by women in defence of their own interests. As a consequence it can
be used against actions taken to redress the wrongs done to women, as well
as against attempts by women to establish (literal or metaphorical) space
outside male intervention and control.
Although the term was widely used in the 1970s, it did not receive much
theoretical discussion. There was some discussion in Australia which
revealed the basic flaw in the idea, but instead of resolving it, the debate
reproduced the confusion. Sexism continued to be defined in the bland,
neutral terminology of liberal pluralism, despite the discussants awareness
that such a definition depoliticized the term and rendered it useless for femi-
nist politics (Refractory Girl, 1974a, 1974b; Summers, 1975: 22).
The Hobart Womens Action Group (HWAG) defined it in terms of
organizing people according to sex and sexual behaviour, and attributing
various behaviour, personality and status traits to people on the basis of sex
(Refractory Girl, 1974a: 30). The authors took some pains to argue that
sexism was not identical with a patriarchal society. A society in which
women ruled (matriarchy), or one in which the sexes had equal power and
influence although in different spheres, would also be sexist, they argued,
because it would still be structured along sex lines.
On another occasion, however, the HWAG did acknowledge a connection
between sexism and patriarchy. They pointed out that, although it might
be theoretically possible to have forms of sexism which were power-neutral
in that they were divisions of roles and personality without subordination, or
even to have a matriarchal form of sexism where women ruled men, in
actual fact, they emphasized, the only sexism that we know is sexism in its
patriarchal manifestation. They criticized uses of the term which were purely
theoretical in the sense that those uses did not locate sexism within current
patriarchal society. At the same time, however, they themselves defined it
solely in theoretical terms, by denying that it meant the institutionalized
subordination of women to men (Refractory Girl, 1974b: 23).
Despite the writers own strictures against using sexism in senses other
than the patriarchal one, that was exactly what they themselves were doing.
They did not give any reasons why the purely theoretical sense should be
64 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
Wo m e n
Feminism is necessarily concerned with women. It is the womens move-
ment, and it is womens liberation which is at stake. It is women who are
harmed, women who are oppressed and subordinated, women whose con-
sciousness changed to see oppression for what it was, and to see, too, that
OT H E R D E F I N I T I O N S 65
(Delmar, 1986). She said that such a concern was not specific to feminists,
that it threatened to marginalize women and maintain their exclusion from
the general field of human endeavour, and that it implied a unity and
homogeneity among women which did not exist. Although she kept return-
ing to a definition of feminism as a concern with womens issues, she did
not commit herself (or feminism) to any one definition, since she disagreed
with the idea that there can be any true and authentic feminism (p. 9).
She provided what she regarded as a minimalist definition of a feminist as
at the very least . . . someone who holds that women suffer discrimination
because of their sex, that they have specific needs which remain negated and
unsatisfied, and that the satisfaction of these needs would require a radical
change (some would say a revolution even) in the social, economic and
political order (p. 8). She found this definition unsatisfactory, not, however,
because it failed to mention male domination, but because things were
more complicated than this.
She mentioned male domination, briefly and dismissively, only twice. She
rejected any strong desire to pin feminism down by means of a preoccu-
pation with central concerns like sexual division and male domination,
because of disagreements about the reasons for womens situation and about
what should be done about it, and bitter, at times virulent disputes (p. 9).
The second mention occurred in the context of a discussion of sexual poli-
tics. She regarded this as a new concept involving the idea of women as a
social group dominated by men as a social group (male domination / female
oppression). But she did not follow up this insight, concluding instead
with the assertion that the feminist idea of sexual politics was primarily
focused on the pursuit of questions about the female body and its sexual
needs (pp. 267). She did not discuss the possibility that feminisms con-
cern with the female body might be inspired by a need to challenge male
proprietorship of female bodies. It is not therefore surprising that Delmar
found feminisms concern with women unsatisfactory, since she failed to
acknowledge the reason why feminism might be so concerned, that is,
womens exclusion from human status.
Naomi Schors definition of feminism, despite its inclusion within femi-
nism of mutually exclusive positions, does implicitly characterize feminism
as a concern with women:
As well as its concern with women the place [society] assigns women,
female nature, maternalism, familialism, etc. this definition also dis-
plays a concern to challenge womens subordination denunciations of a
subaltern condition. Hence it would presumably exclude from the ambit of
feminism discourses which did not identify and oppose womens subordi-
nation. But it does not locate the reasons for womens subordination with
male supremacy, and it is so inclusive as to be useless for feminist politics.
The tolerant acceptance of contradictory positions closes down debate and
precludes any possibility of clarifying, much less resolving, the contradic-
tions. For example, the characterization of the essentialism debate as a
matter of warring forces misrepresents it. There are not two symmetrical
camps, one claiming an essentialist position and the other a constructionist
one. No one deliberately embraces essentialism as their own position.
There is only one position here, and that involves the accusation that cer-
tain feminist writings, usually designated radical or cultural feminism, are
essentialist (Eisenstein, 1984; Segal, 1984). Those so accused neither
espouse essentialism nor speak in their own defence, and hence cannot be
seen to hold a position in the debate at all (Thompson, 1991). Schors all-
embracing characterization of feminism reduces it to nothing more than
what is said by anyone who identifies as a feminist.
But women have varying degrees of awareness of and opposition to the
realities of male domination. To define feminism only in terms of what
women say, does not provide any criteria for distinguishing feminist state-
ments from anti-feminist or misogynist pronouncements by women. To cite
another example: to define feminism, as Carol Bacchi does (citing Linda
Gordon), as a sharing in an impulse to increase the power and autonomy
of women in their families, communities and / or society (Bacchi, 1990:
xix), allows no way of identifying as anti-feminist right-wing discourses on
women. Right-wing women sometimes co-opt the feminist terminology for
use in their anti-feminist crusade. For example, Babette Francis is a founder
of the anti-feminist group Women Who Want To Be Women, a member of
a number of pro-life (that is, anti-abortion) groups, and a committee mem-
ber of the right-wing Council for a Free Australia. She considers herself,
however, a feminist in the true sense of the word, that is, a believer in
equal rights for women (Rowland, 1984: 1301). Francis speaks in terms
of rights rather than in terms of increasing womens power and autonomy.
But she is certainly concerned with womens place in their families, com-
munities and / or society. Unless the limitations on womens power, auto-
nomy and rights are located with male domination, there is too little to
distinguish Francis view of feminism from a genuinely feminist one.
In fact, however, Bacchi does not confine herself to this definition of
feminism, which she acknowledges is used loosely in her text. Central to
her own feminism is a social model which includes women in the human
standard (Bacchi, 1990: 266 her emphasis). It is this model which pro-
vides the crux of her argument against the sameness / difference model of
relations between the sexes. In that sense, her account is not about women
OT H E R D E F I N I T I O N S 69
at all, but about those conditions which cause us to lose sight of the fact that
what is at issue are necessary social arrangements for humane living (p. xv).
In another sense, however, she is centrally concerned with women, but in a
way which clearly distinguishes her account from right-wing discourses on
women. By acknowledging the feminist project as working for the inclusion
of women in the human standard, she is also acknowledging womens exclu-
sion from that standard as the problem. In doing so, she is also acknowl-
edging male domination as the problem, even though she does not use the
terminology.
The chief problem with the category of women, or so it is said, is that it
is essentialist. While I argue that feminism is not in fact defined solely in
terms of women, the anti-essentialist argument is that feminism is defined
in terms of women but that it ought not to be. Judith Butlers is one such
argument (Butler, 1990). She disagrees with what she sees as the feminist
assumption that there is some existing identity, understood through the
category women, who not only initiates feminist interests and goals within
discourse, but constitutes the subject for whom political representation is
pursued (p. 1). She says that, because identities are inescapably formed
within a field of power, no appeals can be made on their behalf as a way
out of relations of power. There is no subject outside or before the law
which can provide a basis for challenging the law. The identity of the femi-
nist subject, she says, ought not to be the foundation of feminist politics, if
the formation of the subject takes place within a field of power regularly
buried through the assertion of that foundation (p. 6). In other words, femi-
nism cannot appeal to women as the basis for its refusal of relations of
power because women are already constituted by those very relations.
But arguments like this depend on assuming that the foundation of femi-
nist politics is the category women, instead of male domination. Feminism
needs to be able to refer to women if the harm done to women by the
dehumanizing procedures of male supremacy is to be addressed. But the
word does not refer to any asocial and monolithic essence. It has perfectly
serviceable uses. Sometimes the purposes for which it is used are male
supremacist in meaning and value (although the prevalence of ladies and
girls suggests some discomfort with the word women). Sometimes the
purposes are feminist. But it serves no feminist purpose to abandon the
word simply because some of its uses are male supremacist.
Arguments like Butlers are politically stultifying. Such a move abolishes
feminist politics, not only because it abandons the category women, but
because it abolishes any possibility of ethical refusal of relations of domina-
tion. If the terms of the debate are so arranged that relations of domination
constitute the whole of the social, because there is no way out of the
social (as everyone knows), there is also no way out of relations of domi-
nation, and hence no possibility of resistance and refusal. Putting it in these
terms is to commit the same solecism the accusers of essentialism suppos-
edly find elsewhere. It is to reify the social into a monolithic totality out-
side the individuals who live and act within it. The fact remains that it is
70 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
possible to refuse certain meanings, values and actions for certain purposes.
People do it all the time. Whether something is an embracing of relations of
domination, or whether it is a refusal, can only be decided by allowing that
both possibilities exist. And such possibilities can only be seen to exist if
male domination is not the whole of the social.
The word women is undoubtedly a social category. (What else could it
be?) But that does not mean that it cannot be used for the feminist purpose
of refusing complicity with male domination. Such refusals are not outside
the social in any absolute sense (if that makes any sense at all). They are a
constant process of engagement with the social order which is male
supremacy. If ever male supremacy ceases to exist, what will have gone is not
the social per se, but its nature as male supremacist. But short of such a
utopian outcome, those occasions which are already refusals of complicity
with male domination and they must exist otherwise opposing male
supremacy would not be thinkable are not thereby outside the social. To
assume without question that they must be, is to fall into the very trap of
essentialism which is supposedly being avoided. It is also to argue for politi-
cal passivity. If we cannot refuse domination because that would require
being outside the social, there is nothing to be done and political activism is
futile. Butler appears to be perfectly satisfied with this conclusion. I am not.
Neither is it necessary. The subject of feminism is not women, either in
the sense of theoretical subject matter, or in the sense of that identity in
whose name feminist politics proceeds. The subject matter of feminism is
male supremacy. The theory and practice of feminism proceed in the inter-
ests of women because women are the chief victims of male supremacist
relations of power, because women are more likely to be in a position to
perceive the problems (although those perceptions are not automatic or
inevitable), and because current relations of power benefit men at womens
expense. The task of feminism is neither to improve the situation of women
within conventional and subordinated statuses, nor to abolish them
absolutely, but to recognize the importance, worth and human dignity of
women, and to create (or maintain) possibilities for genuinely human
choices for women however and wherever we are placed. More importantly,
feminism is concerned with the whole of the human condition, and not just
with that restricted sphere conventionally allocated to women (although still
controlled by and for the benefit of men). Feminism is as much concerned
with war as it is with nurturing, as much with planetary pollution as with
housework, with capitalist accumulation as well as equal pay, with a revolu-
tion in meanings and values as well as childbirth, with reason as well as emo-
tion, with the mind as well as the body. Nothing is outside feminist concern
as long as male supremacy continues to exist.
Neither is feminism only, or primarily, about womens experience.
Feminism must remain grounded in experience, in some sense at least, if it
is not to deteriorate into a set of academic exercises. But feminist theory
cannot remain simply at the level of experience in the sense of incommen-
surable individual life histories, because experience is already theory-laden,
OT H E R D E F I N I T I O N S 71
history and start seeing ourselves with our own eyes and living our lives in
our own interests.
Gender
One way of describing the problem with much academic feminist writing is
to characterize it as idealism in the sense in which the term ideology was
used by Marx and Engels (1974). Transferring concepts from their original
context to another context altogether, in this case from Marxist historical
materialism to feminism, needs to be done with caution. None the less there
does seem to be a similarity between the problem addressed by Marx and
Engels in the middle of the nineteenth century, and a tendency in much aca-
demic feminist writing to avoid challenging male domination. Marx and
Engels characterized a purportedly revolutionary critique which failed to
consider the real-life activity of human beings and their actual situation
within capitalist relations of power, as a battle in the realm of pure thought.
In doing so, they were not suggesting that philosophers stop thinking and
start acting. Rather, they were arguing that a philosophy which purported
to give an account of the human condition without acknowledging the power
relations in society was not just out of touch with reality, its obliviousness
served a purpose. That purpose was to deny the existence of relations of
power and disguise them as something neutral and universal. Hence, ideal-
ism does not mean working with ideas rather than fomenting revolution on
the factory floor or at the barricades. It means working with ideas which are
detached from, and fail to acknowledge, social relations of domination.
Since the relations of domination opposed by feminism are those of male
supremacy, feminist accounts which fail to acknowledge this are idealist in
this sense.
So the problem of idealism, in the sense in which I am using the term, is
not just a problem of a split between ideas and reality, but of the kind of
reality those ideas studiously ignore, that is, the reality of domination. My
use of the term takes on its meaning in the context of a critique of ideo-
logy. Idealism is one form ideology takes. Although Marx and Engels did
not make the distinction, it is a useful one because it makes the point that
ideology is not just a matter of ideas, that it reaches into every sphere of
human existence, including what is most intimate and commonplace.
Idealism is that form of ideology to which academe is especially prone. It
refers to the tendency for academic work to divorce ideas from the world
of the mundane. That tendency is not inevitable. To the extent that ideas
do not reinforce relations of ruling, they cannot be called idealist in this
sense, no matter how esoteric, abstract or removed from experience they
may be. But because playing with ideas is endlessly fascinating in itself the
disconnection can only be resisted through a conscious and deliberate com-
mitment to a moral and political framework which maintains the link
between ideas and what those ideas are for. Concepts like gender fail to
maintain that link.
OT H E R D E F I N I T I O N S 73
gender is not to culture as sex is to nature; gender is also [sic] the discursive /
cultural means by which sexed nature or a natural sex is produced and estab-
lished as prediscursive, prior to culture, a politically neutral surface on which
culture acts. . . . This production of sex as the prediscursive ought to be under-
stood as the effect of the apparatus of cultural construction designated by
gender. (Butler, 1990: 7 her emphases)
In arguing that sex is itself a social construct, and hence not natural or bio-
logical at all in so far as it is of concern to feminism, Butler is perfectly cor-
rect. But if that is the case, if sex is already social, what part is played by the
term gender? What does using gender add, that is not already contained
in sex viewed from a feminist standpoint? According to Butler, gender is
an apparatus of cultural construction which purveys sex as natural. But
that can be said without recourse to gender, namely, sex is a social con-
struction which presents itself as natural. To say it like that is far more direct
and challenging to conventional wisdom than interpolating gender between
sex and its social construction. It is after all sex which is the social construct,
and not something other than sex. Using a different word, gender, for the
social construct, implies that sex is something other than the social construct.
Butler herself is at least partly aware of this problem. She says: If the
immutable character of sex is contested, perhaps this construct called sex
is as culturally constructed as gender; indeed, perhaps it was always already
gender, with the consequence that the distinction between sex and gender
turns out to be no distinction at all (p. 7). But she does not take the next
step in the argument and dispense with the word gender, to focus instead
on sex and its discontents. Retaining sex and rejecting gender would not
fit in with her purpose, which is to open up a theoretical space within what
she sees as feminism, for those incoherent or discontinuous gendered
beings who appear to be persons but who fail to conform to the gendered
norms of cultural intelligibility by which persons are defined . . . [and whose]
persistence and proliferation . . . open up within the very terms of that
matrix of intelligibility rival and subversive matrices of gender disorder
(p. 17). The examples she mentions in her text of such gender disorder are
lesbians, especially those who destabilize and displace the heterosexual
norms of masculinity and femininity through butch / femme role play
(p. 123), Foucaults hermaphrodite Herculine Barbin, male homosexuality
(pp. 1312), and drag and cross-dressing (both male, although she does not
say so) (p. 137). The term gender is perfect for this purpose just because
of its incoherence and idealism. Because it has no definite meaning, and
because it is detached from the only referent that makes any sense, namely
sex, it can take on any meaning at all. It is much more difficult to interpret
sex as a multiple interpretation, as a free-floating artifice, as a shifting
phenomenon, as a complexity whose totality is permanently deferred,
never fully what it is at any given juncture in time, as fictive, phantas-
matic and illusory. Sex remains too tied in with its ordinary meanings of
male and female, and heterosexual desire and activity, and hence too close
to those traditional sites of male supremacy.
OT H E R D E F I N I T I O N S 77
people have sex in both senses of the word, in the sense that there are two
sexes, and in the sense of sexual desire and activity. That they are usually
confused, as Johnson pointed out, is a consequence of the heterosexual
hegemony sexuality happens because there are two sexes, that is, sex is
always heterosexual. Substituting gender for sex compounds the confusion
because it evades the necessity for disentangling it. More importantly,
because in most of its usages gender is meaningless, it can take on any
meaning at all, including anti-feminist ones. By being detached from its ordi-
nary language referent sex, it floats freely in a discursive space far removed
from the actual social relations of male supremacy. It is politically unlocat-
able. The frequency with which this happens gives rise to the suspicion that
that is what has been intended all along.
Dichotomies
Another way of designating the problem addressed by feminism is through
a critique of dichotomies (or binary oppositions or dualisms). Such criti-
cisms do recognize a hierarchical relation between the two terms whereby
one term is always valued over the other, as well as locating the valued term
with the male and the devalued one with the female. But they tend towards
idealism to the extent that they see the oppositional logic as the basic
problem generating the differential valuations of men and women, rather
than seeing that logic as itself a consequence of the social relations of male
supremacy.
Moira Gatens, for example, summarizes her overview of some of the ways
philosophy has conceived of women as follows:
In the introduction, it was suggested that the mind / body, reason / passion and
nature / culture dichotomies interact with the male / female dichotomy in
extremely complex ways, often prejudicial to women. What has been shown in
the ensuing chapters is the way that these dichotomies function in the work of
particular philosophers and the consequences of this functioning for their views
on sexual difference. It has become apparent in the course of this analysis that
in contemporary thought it is the private / public distinction which organizes
these dualisms and gives them their distinctively sexually specific character.
(Gatens, 1991: 122)
Despite her frequent insights into the ways in which the human norm is
purveyed as only male, by substituting dichotomies organized around the
private / public distinction for the explicit acknowledgement of male
supremacist relations of ruling, she reduces mens rule to an effect of some-
thing more basic. In this account, the feminist political task is not to mount
a direct challenge to male domination. Rather, it becomes a matter of work-
ing towards the break[ing] down of the coherence of Western culture in
order that it may be reassembl[ed] in a more viable and polyvalent form
(p. 121 first interpolation in the original). The problem to be addressed is
the coherence of Western culture, and the solution is to break this down in
80 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
The problem here is the opposition itself and its rigidity, not the fact that
that opposition (between the sexes) constructs the male as the norm, as the
only human subject, at the expense of any interests females might have in
our own human status. But it is not the fact that the differences between the
sexes are rigid or even opposed that is the main problem for feminism,
but the fact that the differences encode and enforce male supremacy
(MacKinnon, 1990). The feminist task, then, is not to shatter and fragment
the grand dichotomy of male and female into a multiplicity of fluid and
shifting genders, sexualities, identities or forms of otherness (other
than whom?), but to continue to oppose male domination, however and
wherever it manifests itself, in the interests of a female human status which
is not defined at the expense of anyone at all.
Notes
1 Before she discussed socialist feminist writings, Beechey expressed some dis-
quiet at the possibility that she might be being unfair to particular writers by con-
fining her discussion to an incomplete survey, instead of providing a comprehensive
review of the Marxist feminist literature (1979: 72). She did not express any such
disquiet at the incompleteness of her review of radical feminist literature.
2 Bourdieu later expanded this paper into a book (Bourdieu, 1998).
3 The parenthetical a is not meant to imply the first of a series, to be followed
by b, c, d, etc. It signals that the sentence is actually two sentences compressed
into one Gender is representation and Gender is a representation.
4 Nussbaums review evoked a number of protests (The New Republic, 1999).
But even those sympathetic to Butlers work have been known to express many of the
same concerns as Nussbaum. Seyla Benhabib, who was one of those who protested at
Nussbaums review, has said: in Gender Trouble at least, Butler subscribes to an overly
constructivist view of selfhood and agency that leaves little room for explaining the
possibilities of creativity and resistance (Benhabib, 1999: p. 2 of 17).
5 Catharine MacKinnon makes the same kind of distinction (MacKinnon, 1987,
1991: xiii). She says that she tends to use the words sex and gender interchange-
ably, since she does not agree with the distinction between biology and society
entailed in the sex / gender distinction. I prefer not to use the word gender at all
because of its apolitical connotations.
6 Difference
the male remains the norm against which women are measured. Keeping the
debate at the level of sex differences serves the purpose of avoiding the
question of the systematic subordination of women to men. Once this is
recognized, the question of whether women are the same as or different
from men becomes irrelevant. Women can be the same as men, and still be
subordinated. Exceptional women can be isolated from other women to
supply a token female representation in hierarchical positions normally
reserved for men, while those positions continue to function in the interests
of men and against the interests of women. And although womens difference
from men is usually justification for womens subordination, it can also be
a source of women-only power and identification.
I have identified three contexts within which the question of differences
between the sexes has been discussed within second-wave feminism, the
first two of which I mention only briefly here. The first of these debates
originated in psychology, with token excursions into sociology, anthro-
pology, primatology, ethology, endocrinology and the medical model in gen-
eral. There is a fairly extensive literature on the subject, but it has limited
use for feminist theorizing because it tends to be empiricist and positivist. It
assumes unquestioningly that sex differences are objective matters of fact
discoverable through the purportedly value-free methods of psychological
testing, some of which involve only animals and not human beings at all
(e.g. Maccoby and Jacklin, 1974). In its commitment to objectivity, it fails
to address the values which are an inherent part of relations between the
sexes, a failure which drains its investigations of meaning. Refusing to
address value questions directly within the inherently moral arena of human
interactions does not abolish moral judgements. It merely ensures that those
moral judgements which do structure and inform the research will be those
of the status quo, of the world-taken-for-granted which feminism is chal-
lenging. Painstaking and detailed though much of this work was, it was
ultimately pointless because it failed to ask recognizably human questions
about sex differences.
The second context in which discussion of sex differences is supposedly
to be found is what has been called French feminism. But this designation
covers such a large and disparate group of theorists that it is impossible to
discuss them under a single heading. Since any attempt to do so must fail,
given the intricacies and sheer volume of these works, I mention them only
in passing.2
The problem with this formulation [of an initial unity] is the idea of a separa-
tion from oneness; it contains the implicit assumption that we grow out of rela-
tionships rather than becoming more active and sovereign within them, that we
start in a state of dual oneness and wind up in a state of singular oneness . . . the
issue is not only how we separate from oneness, but also how we connect to and
recognise others; the issue is not how we become free of the other, but how we
actively engage and make ourselves known in relationship to the other. (Benjamin,
1989: 18 her emphasis)
Benjamin argues that the infant is active in relation to the mother from
birth. The baby can respond to soothing and holding or resist, co-operate or
turn away, focus on the mothers face, react to the mothers voice, and
(although Benjamin does not mention this) smile, during the first few weeks
of life. The possibility of mutual recognition, of emotional attunement,
mutual influence, affective mutuality, sharing states of mind (p. 16) between
mother and infant is there from the beginning. The motherinfant relation-
ship is one already capable of mutual recognition. Infants are active partici-
pants who help shape the responses of their environment, and create their
own objects . . . the infants capacity to relate to the world is incipiently pre-
sent at birth and develops all along (pp. 16, 17); and real mothers in
our culture, for better or worse, devote most of their energy to fostering
independence (p. 152).
The implication of Benjamins argument concerning the first bond
(between mother and child) is that it is only the relationship between
mother and child which holds the potential for generating mutual recogni-
tion, and that the fathers intervention irrevocably destroys the possibility of
mutuality between the sexes, at least under present conditions and to the
extent that adult individuals do not resist the dominant trend. The fathers
intrusion ruptures, not a solipsistic oneness, not an undifferentiated unity,
but a mutuality, a flexible balance of separation and connection responsive
to the needs and desires of both mother and infant, a reciprocity of give and
take which is already present. Mothers and infants, it would seem, do very
well all by themselves. As Benjamin herself says: if . . . we believe that
infants take pleasure in interpersonal connection and are motivated by
curiosity and responsiveness to the outside world, we need not agree to the
idea that human beings must be pulled by their fathers away from maternal
bliss into a reality they resent (p. 174).
What Benjamins account suggests (although she herself does not draw
out the implication) is that women cannot be left alone to get on with it if
male supremacy is to be maintained. Women are not to be trusted to be
whole-hearted in the male cause. They must not be left to raise children,
88 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
especially male children, without intervention. Once the child starts reaching
out to the world, the disruptive intrusion of the father becomes necessary.
Not, however, as a father, either literally or symbolically, nor merely as the
first outsider . . . represent[ing] the principle of freedom as denial of depen-
dency (p. 221), as Benjamin puts it, but as the nearest significant adult male.
Single mothers of sons are gravely cautioned about the dire consequences
for their sons masculinity of the absence of male role models. The small
male must be provided with a model of what he can aspire to, one who is
personally present and who actively intervenes to show the boy the kind of
place waiting for him once he has repudiated the world of the feminine. He
has his own little symbol of all that he is heir to, but it is little and mother
is still powerful, loving, nurturant and needed. The small female must start
her lessons in heterosexuality. She must learn that full human status is not
her birthright, and that her only access to it is second-rate and via subordi-
nation to those who bear its anatomical symbol. Ideally, she should learn to
love it. But given the prevalence of fatherdaughter incest, and its social
condonation by way of silence and denial, love is obviously not a prerequi-
site for the females training in heterosexual desire. Indeed, if the female is
to be trained in sexual subservience, then sexual violence from an early age
would seem to be entirely functional for that training process.
In light of this analysis, the solution to whatever problems might be con-
nected with womens mothering is not shared parenting, as feminist object
relations theory recommends, at least not in the foreseeable future. Given
that the theory itself points out the unlikelihood of fathers mothering to the
same extent that women do, it is not clear how it might be brought about. If
current arrangements of mothering render males more or less incapable of
human relationships, and if that incapability is not just an unwillingness, but
is an intrinsic aspect of the masculine sense of self, deeply embedded in
unconscious processes of fear and desire, hatred and contempt, then male
mothering will not become a social norm simply through conscious decision
and rational choice on the part of men. The very meaning of masculinity
itself must change. It must be divested of its contempt for and dread of the
female (and of the reverence and adoration which serve as a superficial gloss
masking the actual relations of power), of its competitiveness, aggression,
violence and addiction to hierarchy, and of its eroticized obsession with
penis-possession, in favour of a genuine humanity which excludes no one
from human rights and dignities.
Until and unless that happens, it is dangerous to suggest that men take on
the care of infants and small children. Even if they were to do so in any num-
bers, a large if given the great hurdle of male reluctance, at the very least
they would simply dominate mothering at the expense of women, just as
they dominate everything else. But there is an even greater danger involved
as long as the penis continues to function as the symbol of the only human
status allowed, and that is male sexual abuse of children. It is foolhardy to
recommend that men have greater access to children, unless the glorification
of penis-possession has first been acknowledged and overcome.6 What must
D I F F E R E N C E 89
Notes
1 Alison Jaggar recognizes the confounding as a problem but does not resolve it
(Jaggar, 1990).
2 French feminism in the Anglophone academic context has been criticized as
an Anglo-American construct which misrepresents the actual history of feminism in
France (Delphy, 1996; Moses, 1998; Winter, 1997).
D I F F E R E N C E 91
are specifically mentioned. Because women are still struggling for a human
status, we frequently cannot even express what we want, much less get access
to the necessary resources, especially if womens needs come into conflict
with what men perceive as their justified claims against other men. Too often,
women become the terrain over which battles for supremacy among men are
waged, unless the feminist insight into the male supremacist defining of the
human as only male is kept constantly in mind.
That is not to say that feminists cannot give political priority to race
and / or class. There are times when politically committed women must
challenge the oppressions of class and / or race directly because the urgency
of the situation demands it. Andrea Dworkin argued this in terms of states
of primary emergency. What she meant by this was that, in certain con-
texts, certain identities brought with them more pressing, immediate and
dangerous problems than others. She gave the examples of the Jew in Nazi
Germany, and the Native American during the colonization of the US. That
first identity, she said, the one which brings with it as part of its definition
death, is the identity of primary emergency (Dworkin, 1974: 23). Even
short of death, the economic deprivation which capitalism visits upon a
large proportion of the worlds population, and the dehumanizing effects of
racism, require their own specific politics. But unless feminism is a constant
presence in those politics, women will continue to be excluded from agen-
das devised by men in their own interests. As long as feminism is conceived
as a commitment to the human dignity of all, it is already a commitment to
opposing race and class oppression. But feminist involvement in these poli-
tics focuses on the effects on women of the hierarchies of class and race,
both the ways in which those hierarchies specifically disadvantage women,
and the ways in which women reproduce those hierarchies among ourselves.
Once male domination is identified as the main problem addressed by a
feminist politics, it can be acknowledged that women experience male domi-
nation differently, depending on where they are situated in relation to race,
class, or any other social location.
I am not going to discuss class in this present work, despite the lack of
resolution of many of the questions involved in discussions of women and
class the difficulty of allocating women to class positions (not to mention
the difficulty of allocating men); the derivative nature of class for women
and its dependence on their relationships to men;1 confusions about what
class means, whether it can be accounted for in terms of status, prestige,
privilege and access to resources, or whether it is confined to the Marxist
concept of ownership and non-ownership of the means of production (in
which case it is irrelevant to women); and, most importantly, the absence of
any acknowledgement of the existence of a ruling class. Although there are
some discussions in the feminist literature which deal explicitly with class (for
example, Lesbian Ethics, 1991; Phillips, 1987), within the category of dif-
ferences between and among women it is the question of race which has
received the most attention. Class has tended to play a subsidiary role, men-
tioned only briefly and tangentially in discussions primarily concerned with
94 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
race. Moreover, the main problem with the feminist race debate the
ignoring or denial of male domination and the concomitant focus on hierar-
chies among women is also to be found in discussions of class. Hence,
much of what is said about race is also relevant to class.
waged, categories which contain only men unless women are explicitly
mentioned. The exclusion of black women or women of colour is blamed
on a white womens movement, when the original exclusion is a male
supremacist one, that is, the exclusion of women from every human cate-
gory because they are not men. In contrast, starting from the standpoint of
opposition to male domination allows the problem of womens exclusion
from all human categories to be addressed directly, in a way that focusing
exclusively on race does not. Texts authored in the name of feminism can
be complicit with this exclusion of women from categories defined in terms
of race, but it does not originate there. Rather, it originates with the male
supremacist ideology that only men count as human. Starting with that
same ideological construct in mind also promises to throw light on the male
supremacist aspects of racism and imperialism, connections between racism
and masculinity which are hinted at in some of the malestream anti-racist
and post-colonialist literature, but which remain at the level of suggestive
insights for lack of a feminist analysis. Ignoring the ideological constitution
of the male as the human norm means failing to identify the ways in which
racism and imperialism have mirrored the domination of women by men,
and the male supremacist nature of the anti-racist and post-colonialist strug-
gle itself.
Although raising these issues goes against the grain of most of what has
been said in the name of an anti-racist feminism, there is no benefit to be
gained, either for feminism or for the anti-racist struggle, in refusing to
address the problems because they are too hard, too confusing, or too
threatening. Ignoring the problems will not make them go away. Silence,
whether well-intentioned or guilt-stricken, leads nowhere except to political
paralysis. As it stands at the moment, the debate provides no ground from
which to start righting the wrongs which are supposedly at issue. A feminist
anti-racist politics must involve more than the simple acceptance and meek
reiteration of anything and everything said by or on behalf of women of
colour without challenge, argument or debate. Otherwise it does a grave
injustice both to feminisms own insights and political priorities, and to
those of the anti-racist struggle.
Exclusion
One of the chief complaints levelled against feminism is that it has excluded
women of colour. Roxana Ng, for example, said, Working in the womens
movement . . . women of colour . . . feel silenced from time to time. Our
unique experiences as women of colour are frequently overlooked in dis-
cussions about womens oppression (Ng, 1993: 197). Ng does not identify
any agents of this silencing and overlooking. She does not say what it might
be that leads to women of colour to feel this way, but given the prevalence
of the problem I have called academic feminism, women of colour are not
alone in feelings of alienation and irrelevance in relation to much of what is
published as feminism.
96 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
Alice Walker (1982) also gives some examples of this kind of exclusion.
The first involved Patricia Meyer Spacks book, The Female Imagination
(1976). Spacks herself acknowledged that her research was confined to writ-
ings by white, middle-class women, because, she said, she was reluctant to
theorize about experiences she hadnt had (1976: 5). But, as Walker pointed
out, this was an inadequate excuse for excluding writings by US black
women, since Spacks included the Bronts although she had no experience
of nineteenth-century Yorkshire either. But the problem with Spacks book
went further than this. Not only did she fail to include writings by black
women, she did so in the face of a golden opportunity to expand her own
female imagination. At the time she was writing the book, she was sharing
an office with Alice Walker who was teaching a course on Black women
writers, and who was prepared to share the fruits of her own research with
Spacks. Walkers second example involved Judy Chicagos exhibition, The
Dinner Party, which included only one plate referring to black women,
the one devoted to Sojourner Truth. Walkers objection was not just to the
tokenism of including only a single example. It was also directed to the kind
of example it was. Although all the other plates depicted stylized vaginas,
the Sojourner Truth plate did not. Instead, it depicted three faces, one weep-
ing, one screaming and one smiling. Walker commented that, although there
is something to be said for depicting women in terms of faces rather than
vaginas, that was not what the exhibition was about, and the faces were
nothing but tired old clichs about black women. Walkers third example
involved a brief exchange at an exhibition of women painters at the
Brooklyn museum. In response to one womans question about whether
there were any black women painters represented, another woman replied:
Its a womens exhibit!
These are the kinds of things for which a feminist politics needs to be alert,
and to resist. But it is not clear that couching the problem in terms of exclu-
sion is an adequate way of addressing it. It implies that the solution is inclu-
sion, and any attempt to include solely on the grounds of race threatens to
become tokenistic. This may be motivated by the best of intentions, to rec-
tify the structural inequality of exclusion and as a form of positive discrimi-
nation in favour of those who are automatically discriminated against unless
deliberate action is taken to include them. But because it involves sorting
women into racial categories, it threatens to relapse into the very racism it is
designed to combat. To the extent that it is only race which matters, at the
expense of any other criteria of judgement, it reinforces racial divisions
among women, and reaffirms white in the dominant position of being able
to afford magnanimity. I do not think there is any general solution to this
dilemma. The problem could be partly redressed, however, if those who have
the power to make decisions about inclusion and exclusion for example,
organizers of conferences, editors of anthologies, publishers kept feminism
in the forefront of the decision-making process, and refrained from making
race the sole criterion of judgement. But that involves being clear about what
feminism is in the first place.
D I F F E R E N C E S A M O N G W O M E N 97
The question of . . . why [US] black women have not joined the womens move-
ment in large numbers and have been generally hostile to feminism . . . has been
raised . . . by white feminists in order to develop better ways to recruit black
women into their movement. . . . In discussing this issue, there is a need to put
aside the narrow and limited confines of feminism as defined and dominated by
mainly middle- and upper-class white women to reach a broader analysis that
could include the experiences of all women under white male domination. . . .
white feminists . . . have objectively excluded [women of color] from equal par-
ticipation in the womens movement. . . . the racism of white women will not
allow them to give us the right to speak on our own behalf. (Omolade, 1985:
247, 256)
supplicants who can only demand concessions, and who have no power to
create feminism themselves because feminism belongs to someone else and
hence is something other than their own conviction. But that cannot be so.
Perhaps what she was talking about was access to resources like academic
credibility, respectability and employment, publishing, invitations to speak,
etc. And it is true that not all feminists, not even all feminists who want to
write, speak and publish, have access to these resources. But if this was her
point, it was not entirely accurate. Even at the time she was writing (1980),
US black women (the we of her text) had been writing and publishing
within feminism for at least ten years (for example, Beal, 1970; Black
Womens Liberation Group, 1970; Kennedy, 1970; Norton, 1970; Ware,
1970) and presumably they were doing so out of their own feminist insights.
Without the unifying practice of struggling against male domination,
feminism becomes simply a question of women who have nothing in
common to the extent that not all women share all forms of oppression. bell
hooks, for example, defines feminism as the struggle to end sexist oppres-
sion (hooks, 1984). The term sexist oppression does not refer to the social
system of male domination and hence focus attention on the sex whose
interests are maintained by sexist oppression, the sex which benefits from
permission to oppress women. Rather, the sex referred to by hooks con-
cept of sexist oppression is the female sex. The concept refers to any
oppression suffered by women:
By repudiating the popular notion that the focus of feminist movement should
be social equality of the sexes and emphasizing eradicating the cultural basis of
group oppression, our own analysis would require an exploration of all aspects
of womens political reality. This would mean that race and class oppression
would be recognized as feminist issues with as much relevance as sexism.
When feminism is defined in such a way that it calls attention to the diversity
of womens social and political reality, it centralizes the experiences of all
women, especially the women whose social conditions have been least written
about, studied, or changed by political movements. (hooks, 1984: 25)
say, has had its own explicit form of racism in the way it has given high
priority to certain aspects of struggles and neglected others, and it has often
been blind and ignorant about the conditions of [US] Black womens lives
(Joseph and Lewis, 1981: 4). They do not identify this White womens
movement any further. They do not tell us which struggles have been given
priority in which feminist writings or practices, nor which aspects have been
neglected. Instead, they go on to tell us that the movement was bound to
emphasize some things and ignore others, because it was started by women
who experienced specific White realities. But this is by no means self-
evident. If we look at the issues raised by feminism rape and other forms
of male violence, for example, or womens access to a living wage, or con-
trol over our own reproductive capacities, or freedom from male imposition
and constraint it is not at all obvious that these are only White realities.
Neither do we know whether feminism was started by white women, or
even if the idea of feminism being started by anyone makes any sense,
given the long and varied history of womens resistance to male power, a
history which has not always been written down, but which must have
existed because male domination is nowhere absolute.
But the authors do not address any of these questions. Once they have
labelled feminism, even in part, as the white womens movement, its
racism appears as a kind of logical necessity. On this account, the white
womens movement was inevitably and inescapably racist because it was
white. The authors do acknowledge that womens liberation did and does
touch on questions which in different ways affect all womens lives and
mens lives too (emphasis in the original), that is, that womens liberation
is not only white. But if it is not only white, then its supposed racism can-
not be the result of being concerned only with white women. There must
be other reasons why feminism, or the white aspects of it, is racist. But
the authors do not give us any other reasons, or at least, no other reason
which makes any sense. They do give us one other reason, and that is that
the movement did not begin with women who had some all-encompassing
political and historical knowledge (p. 4). But in that case, they are blaming
feminism, or that aspect of it they designate the White womens move-
ment, for not doing the impossible, for not having some all-encompassing
political and historical knowledge.
It cannot be the case that racism is nothing but an aspect of being white.3
In the first place, racism is a moral issue. It involves attitudes and behaviours
about which people have choices. It is possible to refuse to be implicated in
racism, and those who are complicit with racism can be held responsible.
And in the second place, racism is a manifestation of the social system of
racial supremacy which purveys white as the criterion of human status. As
such, its meanings and values insidiously influence the choices, decisions
and world views, not only of those who qualify for the benefits and privi-
leges of being white, but also of those it most oppresses. As a consequence,
it cannot be assumed that the social system of white supremacy has no influ-
ence on those who are not white. That is not to say that negative attitudes
D I F F E R E N C E S A M O N G W O M E N 101
towards whites on the part of, say, Aboriginal people are racist, even when
those attitudes explicitly refer to race. Because the system of domination is
white supremacy, blacks cannot be racist towards whites. In white suprema-
cist terms, white is always the reference point of highest value against
which other racial groups are measured and found wanting, and it occupies
that supreme position by virtue of being not a race at all, but a signifier of
the universal human. But because white supremacy is a social system of
meanings and values, complicity can be found even among those most
oppressed by the system. Like any system of domination, it operates through
the inculcation of self-hatred and self-depreciation among the oppressed, as
well as through blatant imposition.
For example, in her study of the writings of a number of US Afro-
American women, Mary Helen Washington discussed what she had found
was a persistent and revealing theme in the lives and literature of Black
women. She called this theme the intimidation of color. By this she meant
the harsh judgements made, sometimes by black women about themselves,
sometimes by both women and men about other black women, judgements
which made invidious comparisons between black skin and Afro hair on the
one hand, and white standards of beauty on the other. She quoted from the
Introduction to a volume of short stories by Afro-American women in which
the author wrote: In almost every novel or autobiography written by a
black woman, there is at least one incident in which the dark-skinned girl
wishes to be either white or light-skinned with good hair (Washington,
1982: 210). Michele Wallace provides another example. She tells us what
happened when, at the age of 13, she went to school one day with her hair
openly displayed in an Afro, instead of being hidden in braids disguised in a
long flowing scarf. She said that black men on street corners began to
whoop and holler at her. When she asked someone why, she was told:
They think youre a whore, sugar (Wallace, 1982: 56). This experience
of Wallace illustrates the intertwining of white supremacy with male
supremacy. The black men, debarred from fully human status themselves by
the system of white supremacy, could still embrace the values of that system
by judging black women according to male supremacist criteria. Such atti-
tudes are not strictly speaking racist, since racism involves attitudes and
behaviours on the part of members of the dominant group imposed on those
judged inferior. The point at issue here is that they are not separate from
racism, they too are part of the social system of white supremacy which
needs to be challenged by a feminism committed to womens interests, as
indeed they have been, particularly in the writings of US Afro-American
women.
The solution to the problem of a self-styled feminism which is either
incomprehensible or actively hostile to what many of us know as feminism,
lies in feminists taking responsibility for feminism, for its significance for
and relevance to our own lives, for what we will accept as feminism and
what we will not, for contesting and debating its meaning, for continuing to
struggle for access to resources. Feminism is never located somewhere else
102 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
apart from the speakers own position. It is not something other than the
speakers own political engagement. It is not the prerogative of any particu-
lar category of women with the power to invite or exclude other women. It
is a political and moral struggle available to anyone. If a woman of colour
engages in that struggle, then that is where feminism is, wherever else it may
be as well. As Alice Walker put it:
There was never a time when Our Mother [i.e., herself] thought, when someone
spoke of the womens movement, that this referred only to the womens move-
ment in America. When she thought of women moving, she automatically
thought of women all over the world. She recognized that to contemplate the
womens movement in isolation from the rest of the world would be given the
racism, sexism, elitism, and ignorance of so many American feminists extremely
defeating to solidarity among women as well as depressing to the most opti-
mistic spirit. Our Mother had travelled and had every reason to understand that
womens freedom was an idea whose time had come, and that it was an idea
sweeping the world. (Walker, 1982: 41)
Irrelevance
Another objection which has been raised against feminism in the context of
the race debate is that it is irrelevant to the lives of women subjected to
racial oppression. At the beginning of this second wave of feminism in
Australia, there were many Aboriginal women who expressed this view.4
The Aboriginal women at the Women and Politics conference in Canberra
in 1975 did not see themselves as feminists, but located their political prio-
rities with the struggles of Aboriginal people. They regarded the oppression
of Aboriginal people by white society as the most urgent problem, and the
Aboriginal struggle as far more important than what they perceived to be
the comparatively trivial concerns of women they saw as more privileged
than themselves. They also saw themselves as less in need of feminism than
white women, because Aboriginal culture allowed women more equality
than white culture did, because Aboriginal women were already in the fore-
front of the movement for Aboriginal self-determination, and because
Aboriginal women had always had supportive networks among themselves
(Aboriginal and Islander Women, 1975a, 1975b).
This stance on the part of Aboriginal women is not surprising, based as it
was on a well-founded suspicion on the part of Aboriginal women of any-
thing seen to emanate from white Australia. But the seeming antagonisms
between Aboriginal politics and feminist politics were due to a number of
misinterpretations. Feminism was often trivialized by Aboriginal women
activists, as mak[ing] men do the washing up (Grimshaw, 1981: 88), as
chatter . . . about sexual oppression and the competitive orgasm (Sykes,
1975: 318), as a struggle for a more equal distribution of power between
the white sexes (Sykes, 1984: 66), as the opposition to male chauvinism
and as an extremely anti-male ideology (Venceremos Brigade, 1975).
Another common misinterpretation concerned the perception of feminism
D I F F E R E N C E S A M O N G W O M E N 103
the Aboriginal Legal Service (ALS) in cases of domestic violence where their
partners are also Aboriginal. Because of its policy of not acting in any case
against an Aboriginal person, the ALS will not represent Aboriginal women
who charge Aboriginal men with violence (Hole, 1994).
Struggling against male domination is antagonistic to men only to the
extent that men are committed to male domination. The feminist practice
of excluding men from women-only groups, events and activities was
sometimes perceived by Aboriginal women as man-hating (for example,
Fesl, 1984: 110). But it is no more than a strategic decision to provide for
women some space, always temporary and sometimes contested, which
men cannot dominate because they are not present. Provision of women-
only occasions, spaces and support networks was part of many traditional
Aboriginal societies, and continues among Aboriginal people today (Bell,
1983, 1987; Hamilton, 1981).
The political struggles of Aboriginal women for their own identity and
dignity as women in solidarity with each other, bring Aboriginal women into
conflict with Aboriginal men only if Aboriginal men are committed to the
meanings and values of male domination, only if Aboriginal men, too, are
violent towards women, and collude with male contempt for the female. In
opposing the racism of white Australia, Aboriginal women are also oppos-
ing male supremacy, because the colonization of Australia, and what was
done to Aboriginal people by the European settlers, was male supremacist
as well as white supremacist. Aboriginal women were not raped by white
women. Neither were the massacres of Aboriginal people perpetrated by
women. That does not mean that European women were innocent of
racism. They may have been complicit with the actions of the male coloni-
zers. Many white women exploited the labour of Aboriginal women and
girls as unpaid domestic servants (Tucker, 1977; Ward, 1987), although it is
as well to remember that the chief beneficiaries of the domestic labour of
Aboriginal women were white men, and that the households were managed
for the ease and comfort of the husbands, sons, fathers and brothers of the
white mistresses. European women may have blamed Aboriginal women for
the sexual misbehaviour of white men; they may have condoned, excused or
justified the massacres. But whether they protested or not, women have
never had the social power necessary to colonize and subdue people. The
European women involved in the colonization of Australia were mostly
wives, prostitutes and servants, that is, under male control.
The male supremacist nature of the colonization of Australia appears not
to have been recognized by some of the participants in the debate. For exam-
ple, Bobbi Sykes all too brief history of black women in Australia (1975),
is a history of the rape of Aboriginal women by white men. This issue of rape,
which is so clearly of concern to all women, was used by Sykes to argue for
the irrelevance of feminism to Aboriginal women. She was able to do this,
firstly by ignoring the inherently male supremacist nature of rape, and defin-
ing it instead as an aspect of racism, and secondly by characterizing feminism
as white womens groups which Aboriginal women refused to join. But the
D I F F E R E N C E S A M O N G W O M E N 105
But there are problems with this kind of account. There are indications
from the work of female anthropologists that this supposed cultural leader-
ship of men is a construct of the male supremacist nature of colonization.
Given the important part played by women in the cultural life of the people
in traditional Aboriginal societies, it is not at all clear that men were the
spiritual leaders in traditional societies (leaving aside the question of what
might count as a leader in those societies). Both sexes had spiritual respon-
sibilities. Sometimes these were joint responsibilities, but sometimes they
were so separate and distinct that men were not permitted knowledge of
womens rites, and vice versa. As men, whether as anthropologists, govern-
ment officials or curious individuals, the colonizers would not be informed
of womens business, and hence it would appear that the spiritual life of
the people was largely mens business. Although I would agree that there
is a sense in which men are more demoralized by the destructive effects of
colonization than women, I would suggest that that is yet another conse-
quence of the male supremacist values of the dominant culture, which
promises colonized men a human status and deprives them of it at one and
the same time. They are human because they are men, but they are also
less than human because they are not members of the dominant race. It is
in this sense that Aboriginal men have more to lose than Aboriginal women,
not in the sense that they are deprived of something they once had, but in
the sense of a savage double-bind which women escape because they are not
given the promise of human status in the first place. The colonizer is
unlikely to grant to the women of what he sees as an inferior race what he
does not allow to the women of his own race.
Sometimes the relevance of feminism has been acknowledged by Aboriginal
women. For example, Hilary Saunders said: Womens Liberation has played
a part in bringing about a certain form of awareness in Black women. She
went on to qualify that statement by saying that Aboriginal women could
not afford to let that awareness go too far because of the injustices suffered
by Aboriginal people as a whole. But she did point out that Aboriginal
women needed to struggle against attempts by Aboriginal men to protect
them, thereby placing Aboriginal women in a subservient role and denying
them the right to speak and to take up positions of leadership (Saunders,
1975). But often Aboriginal women activists spoke as though there were no
common meeting ground between Aboriginal women and white women, as
though the only men who ever caused women any trouble were white men,
as though Aboriginal men were only comrades, kin and fellow sufferers
in oppression, and never raped, bashed or molested women and children.
The motive behind the silence about Aboriginal male violence against
women and children (and each other and themselves) is understandable. No
one committed to the interests of Aboriginal people wants to provide
ammunition for racists. But the silence has been lethal for Aboriginal
women (Queensland Domestic Violence Task Force, 1988). As Diane Bell
put it:
D I F F E R E N C E S A M O N G W O M E N 107
third-world women are not victims of male control, but are merely portrayed
as such by Western feminism.
This strategy draws distinctions which are terminological rather than sub-
stantive, since they are distinctions between something described in neutral
language and something described pejoratively. For example, in her criticism
of Fran Hoskens work on genital mutilation, she acknowledges that it
is true that the potential of male violence against women circumscribes
and elucidates their social position to a certain extent. But, she goes on to
say, defining women as archetypal victims freezes them into objects-
who-defend-themselves, men into subjects-who-perpetrate-violence, and
(every) society into powerless (read: women) and powerful (read: men)
groups of people (p. 67). The difference in emotional tone between these
two statements points to another difference between them. In the second
statement, men are named as the perpetrators of violence against women,
whereas in the first they are not. Male violence against women is only
potential; it not only circumscribes, it also elucidates (whatever that
might mean in this context); and it does not even circumscribe women, but
only their social position, and only that to a certain extent. The implica-
tion is that, if the responsibility of men for their violence against women is
to be named, it must at the same time be rendered non-existent by being
exaggerated to the point of absurdity. Hence, Mohantys denial of male
domination also involves denying mens responsibility in the maintenance of
womens subordination.
Mohanty insists that writings on third-world women must confine them-
selves to empirical studies of gender differences (p. 77), which she con-
trasts with universalistic, ahistorical categories (p. 78). She says that she is
not arguing against generalization, but against those generalizations which
are not careful, historically specific and complex (p. 77). The difference
appears to be whether or not men are identified as the beneficiaries or per-
petrators of womens subordination. The single Western feminist text
which she views favourably does not mention men, or at least not in the
quoted excerpt. The women lace-makers discussed in this text are exploited
by a hegemonic . . . world market, a production system, a culturally speci-
fic mode of patriarchal organization, a housewife ideology, etc., but not
by men it would seem (p. 74).5 In contrast, in a criticism of a book on
women in Africa, Mohanty says that she does not object to the use of uni-
versal groupings for descriptive purposes, such as the phrase all the women
of Africa. The problem, she says, is that descriptive gender differences are
transformed into the division between men and women. She clarifies the
nature of this division in the next sentence: Women are constituted as a
group via dependency relationships vis-a-vis men, who are implicitly held
responsible for these relationships (p. 68). The generalization she objects
to here is holding men responsible. (And once again it appears that such
divisions are solely a construct of Western feminist discourses and that
none exist in reality.) The distinction Mohanty herself supposedly draws
between those generalizations of which she approves, and those of which
110 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
Notes
1 As Virginia Woolf so elegantly put it, struggling with the same issue in the
British context: Our ideology is still so inveterately anthropocentric that it has been
necessary to coin this clumsy term educated mans daughter to describe the class
D I F F E R E N C E S A M O N G W O M E N 111
whose fathers have been educated at public schools and universities. Obviously, if the
term bourgeois fits her brother, it is grossly incorrect to use it of one who differs
so profoundly in the two prime characteristics of the bourgeoisie capital and envi-
ronment (Woolf, 1952: 265 n. 2).
2 There are exceptions (Lorde, 1978, 1979a; Wallace, 1990).
3 Racism does not always take the form of white supremacy, although it always
involves domination and subordination. The racism of Japanese society, for exam-
ple, is not directed against Koreans or the indigenous people, the Ainu, because they
are not white, but because they are not Japanese. Even in the West there are forms
of racism, such as anti-semitism, which are not white supremacist.
4 There were also Aboriginal women who were feminists, who had had harsh
personal experience of male violence and who were committed to feminism as the
struggle against it (Janne Ellen (Reid), personal communication, March 1995). Their
presence has been expunged from the record.
5 In fact, Maria Mies makes it quite clear that it is men who exploit the women
and benefit from their labour: [The] men may belong to different classes, but they
have in common that their own productive activity is based on the exploitation of
female labour, both of their own women as well as that of other women (Mies,
1982: 109).
8
What does it mean
to call feminism white
and middle-class?
linguistic term (Spender, 1980: 1924). The category blacks, too, is male;
here also, male is the default option, the neutral referent which switches
in automatically, and which can be displaced only by adding extra qualifiers.
It may be that it is this kind of exclusion that black feminists are referring
to when they accuse feminism of being white, middle-class. But the error
in Stimpsons paper, as with all such arguments, is due to a failure of femi-
nist commitment, a failure to recognize the male supremacist implications
of using any term referring to a category of human individuals without
explicitly rectifying the exclusion of the female.
Elizabeth Spelman places a great deal of emphasis on this women and
other oppressed groups usage as evidence for the white, middle-class
nature of feminism (Spelman, 1988). She quite rightly points out that equat-
ing the social position of women with the social positions of other oppressed
groups, such as blacks, slaves, proletariat, ignores the existence of the
women of the other oppressed groups, women who are blacks or slaves or
exploited workers. If women are contrasted with other oppressed groups,
then the only women being referred to are privileged women who are not
members of other (than women) oppressed groups. But her argument
depends on how important the women and other oppressed groups analogy
is to feminism. She obviously regards this analogy as at least important, if not
central, to dominant Western feminist thought, since she gives it a great deal
of attention.
It is true that the early radical feminists sometimes referred to oppressed
groups other than women as though those groups contained no women.
For example, Ti-Grace Atkinson said: Women have been murdered by their
so-called function of childbearing exactly as the black people were mur-
dered by their function of color (and black women by both, although
Atkinson did not say so) (Atkinson, 1974: 5 her emphasis). But the ana-
logy has rarely been used by feminists, simply because it excludes categories
of women. As Robin Morgan put it at the beginning of this second wave
of feminism: It . . . seems obvious that half of all oppressed peoples,
black, brown, and otherwise, are women, and that I, as a not-starving white
American woman living in the very belly of the beast, must fight for those
sisters to survive before we can even talk together as oppressed women
(Morgan, 1970: xxxix her emphasis).
Far from being a vital component of feminist theory, as Spelman seems
to think, the parallel between women and other oppressed groups has
never been anything but an aside, an extra bit of special pleading. In the
early 1970s it was a reference to the political movements feminists had
been active in and were leaving behind because of those movements male
dominance the anti-Vietnam war protests, and anti-racist and civil rights
movements. It was an attempt to argue the case for womens oppression by
pointing out the similarities between the oppression of women and other
forms of oppression. It was also (and still is) a product of frustration. It is
usually used in the context of a stubborn refusal to see womens oppression.
Drawing a parallel between oppression on the grounds of sex and oppression
114 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
Indian subcontinent. None the less, what must not be forgotten in any
criticism of Mayos work is her exposure of what are atrocities by any
criterion. It must also not be forgotten that she was fighting in the interests
of women, for a world where such things as the mutilation and casual
murder of girl children and the enforced immolation of women would not
exist. The racism in Mayos text was directed towards the very men who
were responsible for the suffering. Challenging the racism would mean
defending the men who systematically raped and murdered women and
children. It is not uncommon in the feminist race debate, to find that chal-
lenging racism means defending the men of the subordinated race (for
example, Spelman, 1988), rather than black or third-world or indigenous
women whose interests are once again elided in favour of men. That Daly
refused or neglected to do this is not altogether to her discredit.
Bulkin does, however, make a more cogent point in relation to her dis-
cussion of another text cited by Daly.3 Daly used this text as a source of
information about the career of J. Marion Simms, known in the US at the
time of his death in 1883 as the father of gynecology. Daly quite rightly
points out that Simms was a brutal butcher who perpetrated the most
appalling tortures on women in the guise of science, and who was honoured
by the male medical establishment for doing so. But as Bulkin points out,
although Daly does acknowledge that Simms originally learned his vile trade
on the bodies of black female slaves, that acknowledgement is cursory. And
yet Barker-Benfields text describes Simms experiments on black women in
some detail, along with Simms own admission that he used black women,
some of whom he bought for the purpose, because as slaves they had no
power to refuse and no right of redress. If Dalys purpose was to expose the
worst excesses of male brutality towards women, her failure to present her
readers with an account of what Simms did to black women can be seen as
complicity with the racist belief that what happens to black women is unim-
portant. The same suspicion arises in relation to Dalys discussion of the
experimental use on women of contraceptive technology. She allows that
low-income and nonwhite women are victimized in a special way, but she
says no more about this, and immediately proceeds to discuss well-educated
(miseducated) upper-middle-class women. While her discussion is apt and
to the point, in failing to discuss what was done to black and third-world
women she once again passed up an opportunity to expose some of the most
chilling aspects of gynocide (Bulkin, 1991: 1267; Daly, 1978: 2257, 259).
Perhaps it is this kind of thing that Audre Lorde was alluding to in her criti-
cisms of Gyn / Ecology, but she did not say so.
False Universalism
One of the chief ways in which feminism is held to be white and middle-
class (and Western and imperialist) is through the charge of false univer-
salism. Linda Nicholson says, for example: From the late 1960s to the
mid-1980s, feminist theory exhibited a recurrent pattern: Its analyses
W H I T E A N D M I D D L E - C L A S S ? 117
Nicholson does not tell us which aspects or forms of womens labor and
womens sexuality are Western, etc., and which are not. In the case of
118 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
little. Women do not have the power to universalize because women are not
even human in our own right, a state of affairs which feminism is centrally
concerned to address. Women can, and frequently do, support men in their
projects, embrace mens interests as their own, set aside, ignore, deny or
actively seek to undermine their own needs, and by so doing, acquire some
modicum of recognition and some small participation in the universal
human that man has made to suit his own interests. But no women anywhere
have the power to universalize in their own name. The most women can do
is reproduce male supremacist universals. If that is what is being done in the
name of feminism, then it certainly needs to be addressed. It is not, however,
addressed by the construct of false universalism, the nonsense of which
arises from construing universal as meaning all-inclusive as a matter of fact.
Since no content can be given to any claims about all the facts of human
existence, this is meaningless. Feminism does not need to try and confine
itself to one particular cultural context in order to avoid (empirical) univer-
salism. If universalism is not possible, nothing need be done to avoid it.
There has recently been some tentative re-thinking of universalism on
the part of those who had previously been opposed to accepting any such
notion (Benhabib, 1999). Seyla Benhabib says that there is a renewed
respect for the universal, largely because of the atrocities committed in
the name of particular ethnic, cultural and religious identities. Quoting
Naomi Schor, she instances the fact that Nazism was opposed to the
Enlightenment ideal of universalism , implying that there must be some-
thing positive in an ideal which was so antithetical to Nazi and fascist ideo-
logy. Schor is also quoted as saying that the ongoing ethnic cleansing
in Bosnia-Herzegovina, has if not revived universalism then called into
question the celebration of particularisms, at least in their regressive
ethnic form (Benhabib, 1999: pp. 1011). So a link is starting to be made
between the absence of any ideal of a common human condition and the
worst forms of inhumanity.
Benhabib distorts feminist history, however, when she attributes suspi-
cion of generalizations to the feminist movement of the 1980s across the
board. In a masterpiece of agent deletion, she asserts:
Benhabib is quite right in her account of what happened, and in pointing out
that this has had deleterious consequences for feminist politics. But she is
wrong in her belief that these kinds of accusations emanated from the
womens movement as a whole. On the contrary, it is not the case that
122 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
feminists in general are only now starting to realize that an ethical insistence
on a common humanity is a basic feminist requirement. Some of us have
known it all along. The accusations were usually levelled by one or another
variety of academic feminism against radical feminisms insistence that
women had a common interest in combating male supremacy (Bell and
Klein, 1996). Benhabib may indeed have been led to rethink her rejection of
concepts of the universal human by her recognition that appeals to cultural
particularity can lead to gross abuses of human rights and dignity. But she
remains unaware of what was at stake for feminist politics in the ban on
universalism, that is, a denial of womens common interest in challenging
male supremacy and claiming a human status of our own.
The sense in which feminist theory is universal does not entail that femi-
nism is as a matter of fact all-inclusive, either of women or the human race,
but that it is open-ended and non-exclusionary. Feminism has a universal
relevance because it addresses itself to the human condition. It is an ethical
insistence on the human rights and dignity of women (and of men too to the
extent that they can divest themselves of their phallocratic interests). As
such, it is precisely non-empirical, since if women were already in fact recog-
nized as full members of the human race, there would be no need for femi-
nism. As Marx and Engels once pointed out, each new revolutionary class
speaks in the name of the universal human (Marx and Engels, 1974).
Unfortunately, with the exception of feminism, all revolutionary classes have
fought only for the humanity of men. None the less, if it is the case that
the oppressed, those deprived of human dignity and status under conditions
of domination, must appeal to a universal human in making claims for their
own humanity, then to demand that feminism dispense with universal claims
is to demand that feminism refrain from claiming a human status for
women.
The construct of false universalism purports to demonstrate the falsity
of feminisms claims to universal relevance. It says that feminism, too, is
limited in its ethical claims, that it confines itself to the interests of compara-
tively privileged women, and by so doing is complicit with domination. But,
as Marx and Engels pointed out, the claim by the revolutionary class to rep-
resent the interests of all the non-ruling classes is true in the beginning, that
is, it is true as long as the revolutionary class does not become the new rul-
ing class. The claim to universal relevance only becomes an illusion when
the revolutionary class acquires a vested interest in domination, and defends
that interest as the interests of all (Marx and Engels, 1974: 656). It is
unlikely that feminisms ethical claim to universal relevance has yet devel-
oped into this kind of illusion, given that nowhere are women the new rul-
ing class (although they can be complicit with the old male supremacist
one), and given that feminism has consistently demonstrated a readiness to
oppose any and every form of domination. That opposition is a conse-
quence of the fact that all forms of domination harm women, including
that form which no other revolutionary class has ever recognized: male
domination.
W H I T E A N D M I D D L E - C L A S S ? 123
Imperialism
Whatever is happening to elicit the charge of false universalism, and the
correlative demand that the theorist confine what she says to her own
culture, it is not universalizing but something else altogether. It is an
attempt to warn against feminist complicity with Western imperialism.
While this is an important issue, it needs to be carefully and cogently
argued, and it needs to keep the feminist exposure of male domination at
the centre of the critique. Too often, the charge of feminist complicity with
Western imperialism is neither apposite nor accurate, and functions to
deny the existence of male domination in other cultures (Mohanty, 1988).
Hazel Carby does make one point which appears to support her claim to
find a Western imperialist bias within feminism. She says that some feminist
writings portray the third world as backward and the West as more
enlightened or progressive . She provides two quotations from a paper
by Maxine Molyneux, the second one of which does indeed appear to sup-
port Carbys contention. That quotation reads:
There can be little doubt that on balance the position of women within imperi-
alist, i.e., advanced capitalist societies is, for all its limitations, more advanced
than in less developed capitalist and non-capitalist societies. In this sense the
changes brought by imperialism to Third World societies may, in some circum-
stances, have been historically progressive. (Molyneux, 1981: 4 cited in Carby,
1982: 217)
Carby interprets this to mean that since Third World women are outside
of capitalist relations of production, entering capitalist relations is, neces-
sarily, an emancipating move (Carby, 1982: 217).
But Carby misses the point of Molyneuxs argument, which was that if
colonialism led to the abolition of such traditional practices as polygyny,
the brideprice, child marriages, seclusion, and forms of mutilation such as
124 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
In its demand for equality for women, feminism sets itself in opposition to
virtually every culture on earth. You could say that multiculturalism demands
respect for all cultural traditions, while feminism interrogates and challenges
all cultural traditions. . . . fundamentally, the ethical claims of feminism run
counter to the cultural relativism of group rights multiculturalism. (Cohen
et al., 1999: 27)
But it is the very setting up of the categories which keeps them distinct. In
fact Spelman never manages to combine them. Class is only ever men-
tioned as an occasional aside; and gender becomes another aspect of race.
This usually involves defining gender as different ways of being a man,
and pointing out that black men are not superior to white women. In doing
so, she not only misses the male supremacist connotations of her own
examples, she also misses crucial aspects of the racism. To give just one
example: she mentions that Emmet Till was murdered by white men for
talking to a white woman. This example occurs in the context of a discus-
sion of the ideology of masculinity in the United States which, Spelman
says, hardly includes the idea that Black men are superior to white women
128 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
(p. 89). But this interpretation misses the point. Till was not murdered by
white women, and he was not murdered because he was inferior to white
women, but because, in the minds of his male racist murderers, he was infe-
rior to white men. In the evil logic of racism, he was murdered because he
dared to behave like a white man towards a white woman, and because, as
a black male, he did not have a white mans prerogatives. His status as male
was crucial in his murderers perception of him as above himself . The
question of his social ranking in relation to white women did not arise
because the woman was no more than a pawn in a lethal white mans game.
Spelman gives us no information about the white woman Till spoke to.
Did this woman complain about his speaking to her, or did Tills murderers
act without her knowledge or consent? Did she collude with the murderers,
demanding that Till be punished because he dared to speak to her? Or was
she horrified at the murder? Did she protest, or did she not know what was
happening until it was all over? The answers to such questions are vital if
what is at issue is the complicity of white women with racism. By deleting
all reference to the woman in the case, Spelman is complicit with the male
supremacist belief that women are unimportant. In Spelmans account, all
the actors in the evil scenario were male. The woman had no moral agency.
We are not told whether she consented or protested, nor whether her
protests would have made any difference to the outcome. She is nothing but
an icon of white supremacist masculinity, useful as a justification for murder
in the racist male mind, but allowed no will of her own. The issue is not
whether or not she was inferior to Emmet Till; the issue is that she did not
exist at all in her own right. That Spelman missed the point is a consequence
of keeping the race and gender categories separate and distinct, and sub-
stituting the infinitely malleable concept of gender for male supremacy.
Spelman does attempt to argue the case for the white, middle-class
nature of feminism in other ways than the women and other oppressed
groups argument (discussed above). She says that feminisms exclusive focus
on gender and its concomitant oppression, sexism, has meant that womens
race and class identity, and the racism and classism some women face and
other women help perpetuate (pp. 11213), have been peripheral to, or
ignored by, feminist politics. As a consequence, the only kind of gender,
that is, the only way of being a woman, which feminism has acknowledged,
is that of women who are not subjected to racism and classism namely,
white middle-class women of Western industrialized countries (p. 3). The
solution, then, is to combine all three forms. We need to ask, she says, about
the ways in which race and class identity may be intertwined with gender
identity (p. 112).
While Spelman is right about the need to combine the three great forms
of oppression, her own attempt fails because she fails to get the feminism
right. Feminisms main concern is not gender or sexism, or even women
in the sense of what women are, but male supremacy. The question of
womens identity is problematic, not in and of itself, but because of the
male supremacist requirement that the only human identity permissible is
W H I T E A N D M I D D L E - C L A S S ? 129
male. That some men are more (and less) human than other men is also an
aspect of male domination. There is sufficient evidence for the domination
of men by men in Spelmans own text, as well as for feminisms awareness
of this. And yet she uses this evidence as a weapon against feminism, and
argues against the common position of women by pointing to relations of
domination among men. As might be expected, the discussion then proceeds
to focus on the oppression of men, with women cast in the role of oppres-
sors of men. (One example of this is her reference to the murder of Emmet
Till, discussed above.)
Another example occurs in her discussion of Simone de Beauvoirs The
Second Sex (Spelman, 1988: pp. 634). She disagrees with Beauvoirs state-
ments to the effect that the world belongs to men, and that everything in
girls experience confirms them in their belief in masculine superiority, by
pointing out that some women hold positions of superiority over some men:
a white girl [and] Black men . . . girls of the upper classes [and] working-
class men. But Spelman herself has already located these oppressions of
race and class in hierarchies among men prince and pauper, master and
slave . . . are all male. She also allows the same point by quoting without
comment Beauvoirs statement: In the upper classes women are eager
accomplices of their masters (emphasis added). If women are accomplices
rather than instigators, and men are masters, then what is at stake is pri-
marily the interests of men. That class relations and racial domination are
maintained at the expense of some men, makes them no less male interests.
That these interests are also defended by women does not make them
womens interests in any feminist sense, since they are based on womens
subordination. Women benefit from class privilege only to the extent that
they embrace their own subjugation to men. This does not mean that
women are innocent of racism or class privilege. But it does mean that, to
the extent that women defend race or class privilege, they are acting in com-
plicity with male supremacist values.
There is a sense in which the demand that feminism address all forms of
oppression is redundant. That is exactly what feminism is already doing
because feminism is happening wherever women committed to feminism are
situated. All feminists are already included because they are women strug-
gling against male supremacy and for their own human dignity. The issues
which feminism has placed on the public agenda are already relevant to all
women. Exposing male violence, especially sexual violence, or asserting
womens human right to control over the conditions of their own existence,
including the secure integrity of their own bodies, for example, are not
issues of concern only to relatively privileged women. Indeed, the less privi-
leged women are, the fewer resources they have, economic or otherwise, the
more pressing and vital such issues become. Feminism raises no barriers
against the participation of any woman (or the understanding of any man)
because all that is required for a feminist commitment is a feminist commit-
ment. That is not to say that there are no barriers in the way of womens
embracing of feminism. There are. Chief among those barriers are those
130 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
necessities like adequate shelter (they are sitting on the ground in the open
air and they only have grass huts to live in), food (there are six people but
only two plates, and anyway this is Ethiopia, notorious for its famines),
water (the trees are spindly and there is no other vegetation), cooking facili-
ties (the camp fire), or any of the other benefits enjoyed by women in
Australia. In comparison the IWD concerns of Australian women are trivial,
it says, a mere matter of careers and getting husbands to help with the
housework. Australian women (it is implied) are selfish and uncaring
either they see their careers as more important than their children whom
they put into child-care, or they dont have children at all, thus ignoring what
ought to be their primary mission in life. Either way, they are so privileged
that they dont really have anything to complain about when other women
are so deprived.
But there are other ways of looking at these issues. Wanting a career has
nothing to do with womens selfishness. (The question of mens selfishness
never arises unless the men are very, very rich, in which case it is called
greed, and quite rightly so.) Women need to establish their own financial
independence because being dependent on a man deprives a woman of the
most basic form of control over her own life and, not incidentally, her con-
trol over the conditions her children live under. It is true that, once women
have access to adequate resources, they have fewer children or none at all.
But it is also true that over-population is a major world problem. In the light
of that well-documented fact, it could even be said that having fewer
children, far from being a selfish act, is an altruistic one, a contribution to
world peace and security and sustainable development. As for the plight of
Ethiopian women, that is the fault and responsibility of men: of the men
who demand wives who are children in order to guarantee virginity; of the
men of the Ethiopian ruling class (the detestable Mengistu is no longer dic-
tator but he was neither the first, the last nor the only ruler of Ethiopia to
keep the population in misery); of the men who control a world economic
order which keeps nation states like Ethiopia beggared and poverty-stricken.
Whose interests are served by these invidious comparisons between
women? It is certainly not the interests of Australian women whose concerns
are distorted into something trivial and unimportant, and derided by being
placed in the mouths of Ethiopian women. But it is also not in the inter-
ests of Ethiopian women to be depicted as primitives living in grass huts and
squatting on the ground. Comparing and contrasting categories of women
is not in womens interests at all, as long as it deflects attention away from
the real problem by disguising or ignoring the workings of male supremacy,
or by reducing feminism to nothing but the trivial preoccupations of the
privileged.
Notes
1 Daly made the same point in her autobiography where she said that she
had pointed out in a conversation with Audre Lorde that Gyn / Ecology was not a
132 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
Male supremacy is the oldest, most basic form of domination. All other forms
of exploitation and oppression (racism, capitalism, imperialism, etc.) are exten-
sions of male supremacy: men dominate women, a few men dominate the rest.
All power structures throughout history have been male-dominated and male-
oriented. (Redstockings, 1970: 599)
134 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
The oppression of women by men is the source of all the corrupt values
throughout the world. . . . Since the oppression of women is generally agreed to
be the beginning of the class system and women the first exploited class, every
culture or institution or value since that time contains that oppression as a major
foundational ingredient and renders all political constructs after that initial
model of human oppression at the very least suspect. (Atkinson, 1974: 5, 30
her emphases)
women . . . comprise the oldest oppressed group on the face of the planet. . . .
[There is a] profoundly radical analysis beginning to emerge from revolutionary
feminism: that capitalism, imperialism, and racism are symptoms of male
supremacy sexism. Racism as a major contradiction, for example, is surely
based on the first alienizing act: the basic primary contradiction that occurred
with the enslavement of half the human species by the other half. (Morgan,
1970: xxiii, xxxix her emphasis)
the natural reproductive difference between the sexes led directly to the first
division of labor at the origins of class, as well as furnishing the paradigm of
caste (discrimination based on biological characteristics). . . . [Radical feminism]
sees feminist issues not only as womens first priority, but as central to any larger
revolutionary analysis. . . . the current leftist analysis . . . does not relate the struc-
tures of the economic class system to its origins in the sexual class system, the
model for all other exploitative systems, and thus the tapeworm which must be
eliminated first by any true revolution. (Firestone, 1981: 9, 37 her emphasis)
Feminists became tired of being told by male politicos that the liberation of
women could wait until after the socialist revolution, that, because womens
subordination was connected to the private ownership of the means of pro-
duction, the abolition of that private ownership would automatically mean
the abolition of womens subordination. Experiences in organizations of the
male left, of being pushed into the background and used as domestic and
sexual servicers, had led to a healthy scepticism on the part of politically
committed women. Insisting on the primacy of womens oppression was a
way of theorizing the need for women to organize independently.
But the radical feminist emphasis on the primacy of womens oppression,
and hence the primacy of male domination, went further than this. It was
not simply an organizational strategy for establishing political priorities,
although it was certainly that. It was also a radically different way of look-
ing at the world, different, that is, from the male dominant status quo. It
placed the interests of women first, and from that standpoint spoke in the
name of the universal human by asserting that the overcoming of womens
subordination would mean the overcoming of all other forms of subordina-
tion as well. For Ti-Grace Atkinson, for example, the oppression of women
by men created a world where no one could be free:
A human being is not born from the womb; it must create itself. It must be free,
self-generative. A human being must feel that it can grow in a world where
injustice, inequity, hatred, sadism are not directed at it. No person can grow into
a life within these conditions; it is enough of a miracle to survive as a function-
ing organism. (Atkinson, 1974: 5 her emphases)
On the radical feminist account, the struggle against male domination had
political priority over other forms of politics, not only because of a pressing
need to redress the harms done to women, but also because the liberation of
women would mean the liberation of all. But although the early radical
feminists saw all forms of domination as the result of male domination, they
did not tell us how this was so, apart from the appeal to history. They
tended simply to assert a link without analysing it. The present task, then, is
to extend this early radical feminist insight by identifying the links between
male domination and social domination in general.
main theme, an interesting by-product but never the crux of the matter. It
would appear that the reason for this is, once again, the male supremacist
belief that only men are human. In other words, nothing very much has
been said by connecting racism and masculinity, because all that has been said
is that racism is part of being human, masculinity being humanity per se.
The implications for racism of the fact that women are not masculine
remain undiscussed. What is also not discussed are the ways in which ideo-
logical justifications for the domination of men by men mimic those already
operating in the domination of women by men.
Linking racism with masculinity does not mean that women have some
special immunity to racism (or misogyny or any other form of elitist exclu-
sion). Although women do not have the social power to wreak the havoc
that men do, there have always been women who have supported men in
their projects, no matter how evil, as well as identifying their own interests
with those of men. Supporting and identifying with men is the only way
women are permitted access to the human under male supremacist condi-
tions, although that does not mean that women are not responsible for what
they do. Both sexes can fall into the easy automatic patterns of institutional-
ized racism. But it can be argued (although the anti-racist literature does
not) that masculinity is the meaning of racism in the sense that it operates
to render someone else subhuman in order to bolster ones own masculin-
ity, or, in the case of women, the masculinity of the men they identify with
or want to be recognized by. The link between masculinity and domination
is dehumanization. Domination requires the dehumanization of those whose
human rights cannot be allowed to stand in the way of the vested interests
of the powerful, just as masculinity requires the dehumanization of women.
But the parallel is not drawn in the anti-racist literature.
Ali Rattansi, for example, briefly mentions masculinity in the context of
racism without drawing any inferences. He says:
Said himself, however, refrains from doing so. He ends the discussion by
saying: it is not the province of my analysis here, alas, despite its frequently
noted appearance (p. 188). He did not comment on the fact that Flauberts
depiction of the Oriental woman differed not at all from standard phallo-
cratic depictions of any women anywhere. Neither did he comment on the
fact that it was a text about a woman which so aptly illustrated Orientalisms
approach to the East in general. If a text about a woman is typical of this
approach, if it can stand for the pattern of relative strength between East
and West, if it is an instance of a singularly unvaried and remarkably per-
sistent motif in Western attitudes to the Orient, then the fact that it is a text
about a woman is not just an interesting side issue. It is a vital clue to the
operation of that form of domination which is Western imperialism, of
which Orientalism is one manifestation.
There emerges from Saids text a coherent constellation of themes which
provides an unexpected substantiation of the early radical feminist insight
that the domination of women by men is the model for all forms of domi-
nation. Within the discourse of Orientalism, the Orient is feminized. It is
made like a woman.1 It is given female characteristics and treated the way
women are treated. It is never allowed to speak for or represent itself. He,
the European male, speaks for her. The differences between the West and
the Orient line up in the same way as male supremacist discourses construe
the differences between the sexes. For example, Lord Cromer, Orientalist
scholar and British governor of Egypt which he ruled almost single-handedly
between 1883 and 1907, summed up the differences as follows: The
European is a close reasoner; his statements of fact are devoid of any ambi-
guity; he is a natural logician, albeit he may not have studied logic; he is by
nature sceptical and requires proof before he can accept the truth of any
proposition; his trained intelligence works like a piece of mechanism (Said,
1994: 23940). Having delineated the supreme quality of the European
intellect to his own satisfaction, Cromer proceeded to contrast this with
what he variously designated the mind of the Oriental, the Egyptian, and
the present-day Arab. The thinking of this personage is, according to
Cromer, eminently wanting in symmetry and is of the most slipshod
description. He is singularly deficient in the logical faculty and incapable
of drawing the most obvious conclusions. He is much given to lengthy
M A S C U L I N I T Y A N D D E H U M A N I Z AT I O N 139
ways in which black people can be unwittingly complicit with their own
oppression, nor as those whose admission to full membership of the human
race cannot be long delayed. But without women, how can men be human?
Fanon did not ask the question.
Neither did Said. Although Said was more careful than Fanon to avoid
the ritualistic repetition of the word man, and although he sporadically
included references to work by women and to the importance of feminism,
no more than Fanon did he show any awareness that the original model of
dehumanization is male supremacy, the exclusion of women from human
status because we are not men.3 Indeed, by equating dehumanization with
being emasculated (see above) he is fully complicit with the ideological
belief that only men are human. If dehumanization means being deprived
of masculinity (emasculated), only men can lose their human status since
women do not have any masculinity to lose. It is not in fact the whole
region and its peoples who are emasculated, conceptually or otherwise,
by US social science, only the men, although all are dehumanized. It may be
that this is merely a terminological quibble. It is not a term Said used fre-
quently. But it is symptomatic of the continuing effectiveness of male
supremacys chief blind spot, namely the humanity of women. The solution
is not to include women while everything else remains the same. There is
in fact no immediately obvious solution to the problem of womens exclu-
sion from humanity. But acknowledging that it is in fact the case in the
ideological structures and processes of male supremacy, while insisting that
it ought not to be and acting to change it, is a necessary first step towards
ending domination.
A suggestive, if brief, account of the connections between masculinity and
domination in all its forms is provided by Sandra Hardings description of
the establishment, maintenance and reproduction of the stereotypically
masculine personality . . . the natures of the humans who design and control
patriarchy and capital. Harding went on to say:
The frantic maintenance of dualisms between mind and body, between culture
and nature, between highly-valued self and devalued others, take their first forms
in the process of becoming a male person who must individuate himself from
a devalued woman. Thus infant boys psychological birth in families with our
division of labor by gender produces men . . . who will need to dominate. . . . It
produces misogyny and male-bonding as prototypes of appropriate social rela-
tions with others perceived to be respectively unlike and like themselves. . . .
From this perspective . . . the vast panorama of the history of race relations
becomes one more male drama in which the more powerful group of men works
out its infantile project of dominating the other. (Harding, 1981: 152, 153)4
And, it might be added, the vast panorama of the history of capitalism, whose
chief value is the accumulation of limitless hoards of wealth by greedy men
obsessively proving to each other who has the biggest. The obscenity of
capitalism is the concentration of the worlds wealth in the hands of a few
men, including those salaried employees of capitalist enterprises, managers,
144 M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G F E M I N I S M
Notes
1 There is one sentence in Saids text which, if read in a certain way, says exactly
that. The full sentence reads: as early as Aeschyluss play The Persians the Orient is
transformed from a very far distant and often threatening Otherness into figures that
are relatively familiar (in Aeschyluss case, grieving Asiatic women) (p. 21). If we
read only the underlined words, the sentence becomes: the Orient is transformed
into women. But even taking the whole sentence into account, the meaning remains.
The Orient is transformed from a threat into familiarity by being depicted as women.
It is presumably irrelevant that the women are not in fact familiar, since they are
Asiatics. Obviously all women are the same in not posing any threat.
2 And sometimes boys too a land of cut-rate boys and women, as Frantz
Fanon once said (Fanon, 1952: 161).
3 In this context, it must be noted that Said did not receive any help from most
of what has been published as feminism, as I have been at pains to point out
throughout this present work. It must also be noted that these texts by Said and
Fanon are no worse than any of a myriad of others I could have chosen to illustrate
the ongoing hegemony of the male monopolization of human status. The problem
is not a personal deficiency of these two authors, but a social system of meanings and
values with which individuals can be complicit but which they can also resist and
challenge as long as they know about alternatives.
4 Unfortunately, Harding was later to repudiate this kind of insight, without,
however, either acknowledging her own earlier embracing of it, or providing any
reason for the shift in her point of view (Harding, 1986: 185).
Conclusion
to lose it as the jungle closes in around her once again. Sometimes the
gatekeeping fails because the master is fooled into believing that she is work-
ing in his interests because she is working in a traditional malestream disci-
pline, whereas what she is actually doing is using her feminist insight to
challenge and transform that discipline. Sometimes, sadly, it is the feminist
who is deceived into believing that she is operating in womens interests by
the mere fact that she is working in the field of Womens Studies, a self-
deception which can only be exacerbated by the tendency to re-name
Womens Studies Gender Studies.1 Sometimes the gatekeeping simply fails
for no perceptible reason (apart, that is, from the general reason that no
form of domination is inevitable).
I have said nothing in these pages about what is to be done in activist
terms. My task has not been to address any of the various ways in which
feminists in academe have struggled to place feminism on the intellectual
agenda. Rather, my task has been to clarify what feminism is in the most
general terms, to provide a number of illustrative examples of academic
feminist writings which fall short of feminist aims, and to discuss some of
the ways in which that happens. Certainly the theoretical schema I have out-
lined here has a multitude of practical implications. But decisions about
what needs to be done, including what needs to be done within the acade-
mic domain, are the prerogative of those who are doing it. My own contri-
bution to the struggle has been the clarification of feminist politics on the
level of meaning. How that meaning translates into practical activism will
depend on the particular problems and difficulties individual activists are
faced with. How one engages with specific realities cannot be dictated
beforehand. Each of us has to decide for herself (and himself) what is to be
done, whether or not anything can be done, and how far one can go before
the monstrous regime makes it too hard to go on. As Phyllis Chesler put it
in the titles of the first and last chapters of her book: Heroism is our only
alternative and Sister, fear has no place here (Chesler, 1994). Women are
no strangers to heroism, despite its traditional monopolization by men; and
although fear is an appropriate response to the Leviathan of male supremacy,
we cannot allow fear alone to stop us.
Note
1 Jocelyn Pixley has suggested that Gender Studies might have been justified
originally as an improvement on Womens Studies, because the designation
Womens Studies implies that the problems are only womens, whereas Gender
Studies would facilitate dealing with men as well. But although the word gender is
sometimes used to mean male domination, its chief use and function is to deny it.
And academic departments of Gender Studies are in fact devoted to anti-feminist
substitutions for feminism, of which the most fashionable at the moment is queer
theory.
References
Abbott, Sidney and Love, Barbara (1972) Sappho Was a Right-On Woman: A
Liberated View of Lesbianism, New York: Stein & Day.
Abercrombie, Nicholas, Hill, Steven and Turner, Bryan S. (1980) The Dominant
Ideology Thesis, London: George Allen & Unwin.
Aboriginal and Islander Women (1975a) Black women in society: discussion, in
Department of the Prime Minister and Cabinet (ed.), Women and Politics
Conference 1975: Volume 2, Canberra: Australian Government Publishing
Service, 1977.
Aboriginal and Islander Women (1975b) Aboriginal womens speak-out, in
Department of the Prime Minister and Cabinet (ed.), Women and Politics
Conference 1975: Volume 2, Canberra: Australian Government Publishing
Service, 1977.
Allen, Amy (1998) Rethinking power, Hypatia, 13 (1) (electronic version 13
pages).
Andolsen, Barbara Hilkert, Gudorf, Christine E. and Pellauer, Mary D. (eds) (1987)
Womens Consciousness, Womens Conscience: A Reader in Feminist Ethics,
San Francisco: Harper & Row.
Atkinson, Judy (1990a) Violence against Aboriginal women: reconstitution of cus-
tomary law the way forward, Aboriginal Law Bulletin, 2 (46): 69.
Atkinson, Judy (1990b) Violence in Aboriginal Australia: colonisation and gender.
Part I, The Aboriginal and Islander Health Worker, 14 (2): 521.
Atkinson, Judy (1990c) Violence in Aboriginal Australia: colonisation and gender.
Part II, The Aboriginal and Islander Health Worker, 14 (3): 427.
Atkinson, Ti-Grace (1974) Amazon Odyssey, New York: Links Books.
Bacchi, Carol Lee (1990) Same Difference: Feminism and Sexual Difference, Sydney:
Allen & Unwin.
Barrett, Michle (1984) Womens Oppression Today: Problems in Marxist Feminist
Analysis, London: Verso.
Barrett, Michle (1991) The Politics of Truth: From Marx to Foucault, London:
Polity Press.
Beal, Frances M. (1970) Double jeopardy: to be Black and female, in Robin
Morgan (ed.), Sisterhood is Powerful: An Anthology of Writings from the
Womens Liberation Movement, New York: Vintage Books.
Beechey, Veronica (1979) On patriarchy, Feminist Review, 3: 6682.
Bell, Diane (1983) Daughters of the Dreaming, Melbourne: McPhee Gribble / George
Allen & Unwin.
Bell, Diane (1987) The politics of separation, in Marilyn Strathern (ed.), Dealing
with Inequality: Analysing Gender Relations in Melanesia and Beyond, Sydney:
Cambridge University Press.
Bell, Diane (1991a) Intraracial rape revisited: on forging a feminist future beyond
factions and frightening politics, Womens Studies International Forum, 14 (5):
385412.
150 R E F E R E N C E S
Bell, Diane (1991b) Letter to the Editors, Womens Studies International Forum,
14 (5): 50713.
Bell, Diane and Klein, Renate (eds) (1996) Radically Speaking: Feminism Reclaimed,
Melbourne: Spinifex Press.
Bell, Diane and Nelson, Topsy Napurrula (1989) Speaking about rape is everyones
business, Womens Studies International Forum, 12 (4): 40316.
Benhabib, Seyla (1999) Sexual difference and collective identities: the new global
constellation, Signs, 24 (2), Winter (electronic version 17 pages).
Benhabib, Seyla and Cornell, Drucilla (eds) (1987) Feminism as Critique: Essays on
the Politics of Gender in Late-Capitalist Societies, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Benjamin, Jessica (1989) The Bonds of Love: Psychoanalysis, Feminism, and the
Problem of Domination, New York: Pantheon Books.
Black Womens Liberation Group (1970) Statement on birth control, in Robin
Morgan (ed.), Sisterhood is Powerful: An Anthology of Writings from the
Womens Liberation Movement, New York: Vintage Books.
Bligh, Vivian (1983) Study into the needs of Aboriginal women who have been
raped or sexually assaulted, in Fay Gale (ed.), We Are Bosses Ourselves,
Canberra: Australian Institute of Aboriginal Studies.
Bourdieu, Pierre (1990) La Domination masculine, Actes de la recherche in sciences
sociales, no. 84, September.
Bourdieu, Pierre (1998) La Domination masculine, Paris: Seuil.
Bulkin, Elly (1991) [1980] Racism and writing: some implications for white lesbian
critics, Sinister Wisdom, 43 / 44: 11434.
Butler, Judith (1987) Variations on sex and gender: Beauvoir, Wittig and Foucault,
in Seyla Benhabib and Drucilla Cornell (eds), Feminism as Critique: Essays on
the Politics of Gender in Late-Capitalist Societies, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Butler, Judith (1990) Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity,
London: Routledge.
Caine, Barbara, Gatens, Moira, Grahame, Emma, Larbalestier, Jan, Watson, Sophie
and Webby, Elizabeth (eds) (1998) Australian Feminism: A Companion,
Melbourne: Oxford University Press.
Campioni, Mia (1987) Bringing it all back home: love and hate in lesbian relation-
ships, Gay Information, 1718 Lesbian Issue.
Campioni, Mia (1991) Women and otherness, Journal of Australian Lesbian
Feminist Studies, 1 (1): 4957.
Campioni, Mia (1997) Revolting women, women in revolt, in Paul Komesaroff,
Philipa Rothfield and Jeanne Daly (eds), Reinterpreting Menopause: Cultural
and Philosophical Issues, New York: Routledge.
Carby, Hazel (1982) White women listen! Black feminism and the boundaries of
sisterhood, in Centre for Cultural Studies (eds), The Empire Strikes Back: Race
and Racism in 70s Britain, London: Hutchinson.
Chesler, Phyllis (1994) Patriarchy: Notes of an Expert Witness, Monroe, ME:
Common Courage Press.
Chodorow, Nancy (1978) The Reproduction of Mothering: Psychoanalysis and the
Sociology of Gender, Berkeley, Los Angeles and London: University of
California Press.
Chodorow, Nancy (1989) Feminism and Psychoanalytic Theory, New Haven and
London: Yale University Press.
Cohen, Joshua, Howard, Matthew and Nussbaum, Martha (eds) (1999) Is
Multiculturalism Bad for Women? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
R E F E R E N C E S 151