Gersh, Stephen Middle Platonism and Neoplatonism. The Latin Tradition, 2 Vols
Gersh, Stephen Middle Platonism and Neoplatonism. The Latin Tradition, 2 Vols
Gersh, Stephen Middle Platonism and Neoplatonism. The Latin Tradition, 2 Vols
----------XXIII/I----------
STEPHEN GERSH
VOLUME I
Preface xix
Chapter 1 CICERO 53
1.1 Introduction 53
1. 12 Cicero's Skepticism 58
I. IS Stoic Tendencies 71
ix
CONTENTS
1.2 Ethics 79
xi
CO:'IITENTS
3. I Introduction 199
xii
C< >NTE:'IITS
'
-l.-
., The Triadic System 227
) .
4.-4 Explicit and Implicit Triads 236
xiii
CONTENTS
X\"
CONTE:'IITS
X\"i
CO:'I/TF.NTS
.j
.....-.,.33 Man's Function 382
X\'ii
Preface
It b generally agreed that those types of philosophy which are loosely call-
ed plawnic" or 'Neoplatonic' have played a crucial role in the history of
European culture during the centuries between late antiquity and the
Rlnaissance. However. no scholar has attempted to describe the evolution of
these forms of thought in a single comprehensive academic study. In order 10
redress this surprising deficiencr, it therefore seems appropriate to present a
hiswry of the Platonic tradition during the Middle Ages. Such a history must
have at least three centers of focus - one in the transmission of ancient
philosophy to the mediaeval period, another in the eighth to ninth centuries,
and another in the twelfth century - although the intervening phases
dl'slnc at least a briefer treatment.
\X" hat follow~ here represents the first stage in this project of mapping the
course of Platonic philosophy during the Middle Ages. To the intelligent
ohsener it qukkly becomes evident that those mediaeval philosophers who
arc usu;tlly styled 'Piatonists' do nut develop their theories in direct response
10 (;reek philosophy. Owing to the peculiar historical circumstances in
which the mediaeval world arose from the ashes of ancient culture, these
writers were mostly deprived of immediate access to the greatest intellectual
achievements of the Greeks. Instead they elaborate their doctrines in relation
w the Latin philosophical literature produced between the classical period
and the end of antiquity. Thus. an adequate discussion of Platonism during
the Middle Ages must begin by examining these important channels of
transmission.
In earlier versions, parts of this study were presented as lectures before
various scholarly groups during the years 1977-83: the Divinity School,
llnivcrsity of Chicago; the Renaissance Seminar. University of Chicago; the
Midwest Patristics Seminar, Chicago; the Society for Ancient Greek
Philosophy. Boston; the Committee for Medieval Studies, University of
California, Berkeley; the Dominican School of Philosophy and Theology.
Berkeley; the Department of Philosophy, St. Mary's College of California,
.\lorag;t; the International Society for Neoplatonic Studies, Oklahoma City;
the lmernational Patristic Conference, Oxford. I am grateful to the par-
til"ipants in those seminars for learned observations which have sometimes
crept into my footnotes.
The author is pleased to acknowledge his debt to Ralph Mcinerny. Direc-
tor of the Medieval Institute at the University of Notre Dame, for his recom-
rnenuation that this manuscript should appear among the Notre Dame
PuiJiications in /l,fediettll Studies. Much is also owed to my research
xix
PRF.FACJ:
assistants Michael Tkacz, Hugh Griffith, Mary Frances Sparrow, Robert Ken-
nedy. and John Michalski for their labors during 1980-SS. Jean Oesterle took
time away from other projects in order to edit the length}' typescript and br-
ing a European writer's punctuation and spelling into line with American
conventions. The index of Latin texts was compiled with the assistance of
three graduate students in the Medieval Institute: Gregor)' Froelich, Michael
Paletta, and Steven Werner. Finally, Alice Osberger presided over the com-
plex operation in which the material was transmitted from typewriter to
word-processor to printer.
XX
Introduction
24.Jerome: Epist. 57.5 (Pl. 22, 571); 106,3 (Pl. 22, 8.:\9); Adt. Rufin. II,
25 (Pl. 2.3. 449C); and Praef in Pent. (Pl. 28, 182A). See G.). M. Bartelink:
'Piatons Protagoras bei Hieronymus'. Rheinisches Museum 122 ( 1977), p.
192 ff.
2S. Jerome: In Epist. ud Ga/at. Ill, S (Pl. 26, 401 B).
26. Jerome: Epist. -i8, 1.'\ (Pl. 22. S02).
27. P. Courcelle: Late /.a tin Writers and Their Greek Sources. translated
hr H. E. Wcdeck (Cambridge. MA. 1969), pp. 67-70.
28. Priscian: /nst. :;, 64 (Keil: Gmmm. Lat. 2. 182, 3-i); 6 . .35 (Keil:
Gramm. Lui. 2, 226, 9-11); 6. 6.3 (Keil: Gramm. Lat. 2,247,21-248,1); and
8, .35 (Keil: Gramm. Lat. 2. 402, 22-25).
MEDIAEVAL PLA TONlSM 9
29 ..krome: In Amos 11, 5 (PL 25, 1038A). The same translation is also men-
tioned at In lsaiam Xll, 40 (PL 24, 4090).
~0. Cicero: Tim. l.
~I. On Cicero as a translator (with or without reference to the Timaeus)
see A. Engelbrecht: 'Zu Ciceros Ubersetzung aus dem Platonis Timaeus .
\l''iener Studien .H ( 1912), pp. 216-226; G. Cuendet: 'Ciceron et saint Jerome
traducteurs. Re1ue des etudes Ia tines 11 ( 19.B). pp. 380-400; J. Humbert: A
propos de Ciccron traducteur du grec'. Melanges A. Ermmt (Paris, 1940). pp.
I (r -200: E. des Places: 'L 'equivalence keramlJmai-temperari. A propos de
lkux phrases de Pia ton tradu itc:s par Ckcron . Revue de pbilologie 16 ( 194 2 ).
pp. ll.~ .. 'i; A. Traglia: Note su Cicerone crltlco e trt~duttore (Roma. 1947);
R. Poncdet: l.iceron traducteur de Pia ton. L 'expression de Ia pensee com-
fJh.,e 1!11 latin classique (Paris, 1957); D. M. Jones: 'Cicero as Translator.
l'llil'ersity of London, Institute of Classical Studies. Bulletin 6 ( 1959), pp.
2221: H . .f. Hartun~: Ciceros Methode bei der iiiJersetzung griechiscber
Pbilosopbiscber Termini. Diss. (Hamburg, 1970). On specific points see also
T. B. de Graff: Timaeus 4 I a', ClciSsical Weekly 35 ( 1941-1942). pp. 244-45:
R. (jiomini: 'Ricercbe sui testo del Timeo ciceronlmw (Roma 1967);
'Cicerone. Tim. 6. !7', Ritista di cultura c/assica e medioe1ale lO (1968),
pp. 'i<J-"'1; 'Osservazioni sui testo del Timeo cicc:roniano, ibid. II ( 1969),
PP. 25 1-5-i: M.S. Celentano: 'Qualche osser\'azioni su due passi parallc:li di
Platome Cicerone, Plat. Tim. 29b, Cic. Tim. 7', ibid. 15 (1973). pp. 5-17;
and A Franzoi: 'Osservazioni sulla traduzione ciceronian a del Tim eo di
10 INTRODUCTION
Calcidius, the version of Cicero being classified among the latter's works. See
also M. Gibson: 'The Study of the Timaeus in the Eleventh and Twelfth Cen-
turies'. Pensamiento 25 (1969), pp. 183-194.
5 I. V. Kordeuter and C. Labowsky: Meno interprete Henrico Aristippo
(Plato Latin us I) (London, 1940) and L. Minio-Paluello: Phaedo interprete
Henrico Aristippo (Plato Latin us 2) (London, 1950).
52. Kordeuter and Labowsky: op. cit., pp. ix-x.
53. Kordeuter and Labowsky: op. cit., p. 5 ff.
54. Kordeuter and Labowsky: op. cit., pp. xviii-xix.
MEDIAEVAL PLATONISM 15
57. The view of Klibansky: op. cit., p. 27 that Calcidius' translation and
commentary transmit a non-Neoplatonic variety of Platonism to the Middle
Ages is not, I think, borne out by the evidence. See the discussion on p. 421
ff.
MEDIAEVAL PI.A TON ISM 17
SH. Certain Greek authors of late antiquity were also translated into Latin.
Sec hc:low.
59. The old collection of C. Becker: Catalog/ bibliotbecarum antiqui
(Bonn. IHHS), with additions by J. de Ghellinck: 'En marges des catalogues
de~ hiblioth~ques medievales', Stud/ e testi 41 (Miscellanea Ebrle 5) (Cina del
\'aticano. 1924). pp. 331-38. is still useful. However. it must be sup
plcmentcd hy the modern regional studies. M. Manitius: Handscbriften an-
liker Autoretl in mittelalterlicben Bibliotbekskatalogen (Leipzig, 193'5) is an
attempt to map the transmission of classical literature - proceeding author
hy author- through the Middle Ages. See B. Bischoff's review in Deutsche
l.iteratur-Zeitung 57 (1936), pp. 649-653. G. Glauche: Scbullekture In Mit-
le/after. Elllstebung und Wandlungen des LektUrekanons bis 1200 nacb den
Que/le, dargestellt (Miinchen, 1970) is a modern survev with good
hihl iograph y.
18 INTRODUCTION
62. Prudentius: De Praed. Contra lob. Scot. (PL 115, 1294 A-B).
63. w. Hartmann: Manegold von Lautenbach, Liber contra Wolfelmum,
herausgegeben von W. H. (Weimar, 1972), pp. 42,9-10; 48,16-19; etc.
6-i. Another factor which must be taken into account is the frequent use of
florilegia during the Middle Ages. Thus, it is often difficult to determine
whether a given author quotes an earlier writer having had direct access to
the texts. or whether he is citing the author through the intermediary of a
collntion of extracts. On these florllegia - which can be of Christian or
pagan works - see E. M. Sanford: 'The Use of Classical Latin Authors in the
Lihri Manuales', Transactions and Proceedings of the American
Philological Association 55 (1924), pp. 190-248; B. L. Ullman: 'Tibullus In
the Mediaeval Florilegia', Classical Philology 23 (1928), pp. 128-174;
'Classical Authors in Certain Mediaeval Flori/egia ', Classical Philology 27
(1932). pp. 1-42; F. Diekamp: 'Fiorilegien', Lexikonfur Tbeologie und Kir-
cbe 4 (Freiburg i. Br .. 1932), pp. 44-45; M. Faulhaber: 'Katenen', Lexikonfur
Theologie tmd Kircbe S (Freiburg i. Br., 1933), pp. 888-89; J. de Ghellinck:
'Diffusion, utilisation et transmission des ecrits patristiques', Gregorianum
l'f (1933). pp. 356-400; Le mouvementtbeologique du Xlfr steele (Brux-
ellcs/Paris, 1948), pp. 20-36. Among these collections, the most famous is
perh:tps that of Eugippius based on Augustine. See P. Knoell: Eugippii Ex-
~erPfa ex Operibus Sancti Augustini (CSEL 9/1) (Vindobonensis, 1885); M.
Schanz. C. Hosius, G. Kriiger: Gescbicbte der romiscben Literatur 4/2 (Miin-
l'hen, 1920), pp. 586-88; G. de Plinval: 'Eugippius (saint) moine latin du V<-
20 INTRODUCTION
ii
9t. A hrid account of the doctrine and its textual evidence can be found in
\'\' D. Ross: Plato's Theory uf Ideas (Oxford. 1951). p. 142 ff. P. Merlan:
'(ifl'ck Philosophy from Plato to Plotinus'. The Cambridge History of Later
Greek and Ear(J' Mediet,al Philosophy, edited by A. H. Armstrong (Cam-
bridge, 196'7). pp. 14-38 and J. Dillon: The Middle Platonists. A Stud} of
Platonism HOB. C. to A. D. 220 (London. 1977 ). pp. 1-11 describe the doc-
trinc in connection with its later influence. See also the studies cited below.
9'l. Aristoxcnus: Elem. Harm. II, 30. The later accounts in Themistlus and
Produ~ seem to be based on this. Seen. 103.
9 6. L. Robin: La theorie plat(m/cienne des idees et des nombres d'apres
.-ln.,tote (Paris. 190M), p. 600.
.H INTRODliCTION
97. There is a useful survey of the various attitudes to the evidence regar-
ding Plato's esoteric doctrine in E. N. Tigerstedt: Interpreting Plato
(Stockholm. 1977), pp. 77-82 who distinguishes five approaches in all. In ad-
dition to the three described below. Tigerstedt notes the view of H. von
Stein: Sieben Bucher zur Geschichte des Platm1ismus. Untersuchungen iiber
das System des Plato und sein Verhii/tniss zur spiiteren Theologie und
Phllosophie II (Gottingen. 1864), p. 76 ff. that the unwritten doctrines are
essentially identical with those in the dialogues. together with another more
modern compromise position.
98. H. Cherniss: The Riddle of the f..'arly Academy (Berkeley. CA. 1945)
and Aristotle's Criticism of Plato and the Academy (Baltimore, MD. 1944).
99.Zeller:op, c/t.,1lfl.pp.416, 712,947,and950.
100. Robin: op. cit., pp. 601-602.
GREEK PLATONISM y;
lO I. ). Stenzel: Zahl und Gestalt bel Pia ton und Arlstoteles, 3. Autlage
(Bad Homburg, 1959).
I OZ. Ross: op. cit., p. 149.
10:\. H.-). Kramer: Arete bel Platon und Arlstoteles. Zum Wesen und zur
Geschichte der platonlschen Ontologie (Heidelberg, 1959) and Der Ursprung
der Gelstmetaphyslk. Untersuchungen zur Geschlchte des Platonlsmus
Zll'ischen Platon und Plotln (Amsterdam, 1964).
I 04. K. Gaiser: Protreptlk und Pariinese bel Pia ton. Untersuchungen zur
Form des platonlschen Dialogs (Stuttgart, 1959) and Platons ungeschriebene
l.ebre. Stud/en zur systematlschen und geschichtlichen Begrundung der
V:'issenschaften in der platonischen Schule, 2. Autlage (Stuttgart, 1968). The
lau~:r work contains a substantial appendix giving all the testimonia in an-
cient sources regarding the unwritten doctrines.
IO'i. Kramer: Arete bel Platon und Arlstoteles, p. 22 ff. The most signifi-
cant texts in this connection are Plato: Phaedr. 278b-c and Epist. VII, 34Ib-
.3-i'ic.
106. On this interpretation see further J. Wippern: Das Problem der
tmgeschriebenen Lebre Pia tons. Beitriige zum Verstiindnis der platonischen
Prinzipienphi/osopbie, herausgegeben \'On). W. (Wege der Fnrschtmg 186)
marmstadt, 1972).
36 l:'llTRODl!CTION
114. For the reasons why these doctrines should be central to Neoplatonic
thought and. at least implicitly, to Plato himself see below.
II '5. Plato: Rep. VI. S09d, etc.
116. Plato: Tim. 27d.
I 17. Plato: Sopb. 246b.
118. Plato: S;mp. 211a- b.
119. Plato: Pbaed. 102d.
120. Plato: Lys. 217d.
121. Plato: Parm. 132d-l33a.
GREEK PLATONISM 41
sively (as divided). Thus, with the first group of thinkers the in-
tuitive and discursive modes of philosophy are pursued in
cooperation with one another, whereas with the second group
the two modes of thought often proceed along independent
paths.
From the genetic viewpoint, we find that the various
philosophical schools of late antiquity such as the Neoplatonic
and the Stoic appreciate the dualism of spiritual and material
and the threefold relation of spiritual to material to different ex-
tents. The attitude of the Neoplatonic school has already been
described. Here, the unity of the transcendent and immanent
relations is stressed to varying degrees and, when the unity is
heavily emphasized, the contradiction is handled by the notions
of continuum and metaphor; but when the unity is less em-
phatic, the contradiction is removed by understanding the con-
traries as distinct principles or by inserting a mediator between
them. In short, the Neoplatonic philosophy of late antiquity is a
dualism with tendencies to monism. The attitude of the Stoic
school is in many respects the opposite of that of the
Neoplatonic. With them, the transcendent and immanent rela-
tions are represented by the alternation between the two direc-
tions of the tonic motion, their unity being guaranteed by the
replacement of the duality of spiritual and material with that of
active and passive which are alike material. Thus, the Stoic
philosophy of late antiquity can be viewed as a monism with
tendencies to dualism. The influence of their doctrines upon
Neoplatonism is extensive and well documented - the most
significant legacy being the emphasis upon monism which the
earlier school transmits to the later - and it is this influence
which leads modern scholars to speak of the 'syncretism' of
Neoplatonic thought. However, such a term should only be
employed with caution when the writers of antiquity
themselves believed that the Platonic and Stoic traditions were
interdependent from the time when Zeno of Citium left the
GREEK PlATONISM
131. For reasons which have already been stated in the earlier discussion.
the second classification contains only four categories.
132. Seep. 41 ff.
GREEK PLATONISM 47
134. The following table represents the conclusions of the next paragraph
in summary form:
Ill. I Cicero
2 Seneca
1/2. ~ Gellius
.f Apuleius
5 the Asclepius
A Censorinus
B Doxography of Ambrose
C Doxography of Augustine
II. 6 Calcidius
7 Macrohius
8 Martianus Capella
9 Boethius
D Marius Victorinus
E Firmicus Maternus
F Favonius Eulogius
G Servius
H Fulgentius
I Priscianus Lydus
App. X Varro
The Christian writers Calcidius and Boethius are included for reasons
stated on p. 22. For Varro seep. 809 ff.
GREEK PI.ATONISM 49
15<;. Thb corrt:sponds 10 the division into Part I and Part II. Sec the table in
n. 15-1.
I:\(>. This n>rrcsponds to the division between chapters (I, 2, j, etc.) and
l'Xcur~us (A, B. c. ctc.)See the table inn. 134.
1 -~- This corresponds to the division into Part Ill and Part 1/2. See the
tahlt-inn.l:\1.
50 INTRODUCTION
138. This corresponds to the division between the main text and the
bibliographical notes at the beginning of each chapter.
Part 1.1
Middle Platonism
Cicero
1. 1 INTRODUCTION
II. Ibid. V, 32-33. Cf. Cicero: Luc. 121 where the speaker will adhere
neither to one view nor its opposite: 'at one moment this view seems more
probable, at anot!ler moment that view' (modo hoc modo il/ud probe~bilius
tidetur) and Tusc. Disp. V, 83 where the Academic school 'determines
nothing itself yet examines all sides of a question (nibil ipsa iudicCII, sed
lmbetur in omnis parlis).
12. Cicero: Luc. 111. This point is well brought out by A. Michel: 'Ciccron
et les sectes philosophiques. Sens et valeur de l'eclectisme academique'. Eos
57 (1967-68), pp. 106-109.
13. See pp. 58-59.
14. See H. Diels: Doxograpbi Graecl, co/legit recensult prolegomenis in-
dicibusque instru:.-:it H. D. (Berlin, 1879. reprinted Berlin, 1965), p. 181 ff.
Diels calls this collection Vetusta Placita to l'Ontrast with the second-century
Placita of Aetius.
CICERO 61
world. celestial phenomena, the soul, and body with one book
devoted to each subject is the basis for the doxographies which
one finds in Cicero and Varro. I 5 In the first century B.C. these
doxographies were put to two distinct uses according to the
philosophical aims of the collector: either a negative one by
skeptics such as Carneades, who desired to muster all the
authorities in order to show their disagreement with one
another, clear evidence of the unattainability of truth and for
the necessity of 'suspended judgment' (btO'Xtl); or a positive one
by constructive thinkers like Antiochus, who employ the same
material in order to refute all positions except the one which is
to be favored .16 Obviously, the same doxography could be used
either way, and Cicero himself reports how Antiochus
employed the Carneadea Divisio, a classification of
philosophical views regarding the chief good, in the service of
his own nonskeptical system of ethics. I 7 The doxographies in
Cicero's works are often elaborate and tend to be used in the
positive sense of clearing the way towards the most probable
position, a good example being the collection of opinions regar-
ding the nature of soul in Tusculanae Disputationes I. 18 Here,
the views of Plato, Xenocrates, Aristotle, Aristoxenus, and Zeno
are considered in sequence, leaving Cicero with the conclusion
that only a divine being could decide which are 'true' (vera) and
19./bid. I, 23.
20. Cicero: De Nat. Deor. l, 25-41.
2 I . Cicero: De I.eg. III, 14.
22. See Cicero: Tusc. Disp. V, 8-11; De Fin. IV. 3: and V. 88-89.
2.~ Cicc:ro: 1'usc Disp. I. 8. Sec p. S9.
24. Cicero: Epist. ad Aft. XIII. 19.
CICERO 63
2'i. On the Ciceronian dialogue and its influence seeR. Hirzel: Der Dialog.
Ein literarbistoriscbe Versucb I (leipzig, 1895) p. 457ff. and II passim; M.
Huch: Le priambule dans les oeuvres pbilosopbiques de Ciciron. Essa/ sur Ia
genese et /'art du dialogue (Paris, 1958); P. L. Schmidt: 'Zur Typologie und
l.itnarisierung des friihchristlichen lateinischen Dialogs', Cbristianisme et
formes litteraires de l'antiquiti tardir.oe en occident (Entretiens Hardt 23)
(\andoeuvres-Geneve, 1977). pp. 101-190 and 'Formtradition und
Rcalitatshezug im friihchristlichen lateinischen Dialog', Wilrzburger
.labrhiicher fiir die Altertumswissenscbaft, Neue Folge 3 ( 1977), pp.
2ll-22'i; and A. Michel: 'Dialogue philosophique et vie intc.'rieure. Cicc.'ron,
~l'ncqul', saint Augustin'. Helmantica 28 ( 1977), pp. 353-376.
26. The structure of De Ffnibus is therefore the following. Book I: first
dialogue (ethics of Epicurus); Book II: first dialogue continued (Stoic refuta-
tion of Epicurus); Book Ill: second dialogue (Stoic ethics); Book IV: second
dialogue continued (Antiochean refutation of the Stoics); Book V: third
dialogut' (ethics of Antiochus followed by Stoic refutation of Antiochus).
2"". See Augustine: Civ. Dei XIX. 1-3 (CCSL 48. 657-664).
64 MIDDLE PLATONISM
schools in such a way as to suggest that they are all, despite dif-
ferences of terminology, teaching the same doctrine, as An-
tiochus maintained,2S yet both approaches make extensive use
of the doxographical method. It is also possible to bridge the
divide between the two positions by laying special emphasis
upon the notion of probable truth and including in the latter
category many of the views of dogmatic philosophers. There is
considerable evidence that Cicero's New Academicism has
deviated from the Greek skepticism of Carneades in precisely
this way, although it is difficut to say whether Cicero is in-
novating himself or following Carneades' successors
Clitomachus and Philo.29 As A. Weische has observed: 'Die
pret the N~w Academy as being mildly dogmatic was to obscure the tru~ ex-
tent of the later school's deviation from tradition. J. S. Reid: M. Tullii
Cicermzis Academica. The Text Revised and Explained by}. S. R. (London,
IHHS), pp. 57-60 went further in suggesting that Philo's historical view of the
Ac:ademy was that there had always been a contrast between its exoteric
teaching (skepticism) and its esoteric doctrine (dogmatism), in which case
Philo is the basis for Augustine's view of the history of the Academy worked
out in Contra Academicos Ill. If this interpretation is correct, it would cer-
tainly explain the bitterness of Antiochus' polemic against Philo. since the
postulation of exoteric and esoteric traditions simultaneously makes
nonsense of Antiochus' own view of the deviant character of the New
Ac:ad~my. It would also explain the hostility which Augustine (as a follower
of Philo's historical interpretation) clearly reveals towards Antiochus in the
same work. Unfortunately, the Ciceronian texts (Luc. 60 and 139) which
Rdd uses to support this hypothesis arc capable of more than one interpreta-
tion. On the history of Academic skepticism see further V. Brochard: Les
.,ceptiques grecs (Paris, 1887); L. Credaro: Lo scetticismo degli Accademlci I-
ll (Milano, 1893); A. Goedeckemeyer: Geschichte des grlechischen Skep-
tizismus (Leipzig, 190';); P. Couissin: 'L'origine et !'evolution de l'tnoxit',
Retue des etudes grecques 42 ( 1929). pp. 373-397; L. Robin: Pyrrhon et le
scepticisme grec (Paris, 1944 ); 0. Gigon: 'Zur Geschichte der sogenannten
i\euen Akad~mi~. Museum Helvetiwm I (1944), pp. 47-64; M. dal Pra: Lo
scetticismo greco (Milano. 19';0); C. Moreschini: 'Attcggiamemi scettici ed at-
teggiam~mi c.Jogmatici nella filosofia accademica'. La parola del passato 24
( llJ69), pp. 426-436; and C. L. Stough: Greek Skepticism. A Study in
l:jJistemo/ogy (B~rkdey, CA, 1969). Th~r~ has b~en a r~cent revival of in-
tnest in the thesis of an esmeric dogmatism which p~rsisted throughout the
history of the A<:adcmy. this thesis being a by-product of th~ investigation of
esotc.:ricism in the ancient Academy itself. Seep. 32 ff.
66 MIDDLE PLATONISM
30. Weische: op. cit., p. 80. Festugiere: op. cit., p. 368 also notes the easy
transition from skepticism to eclecticism.
31. Sec p. 55.
;U. Sec p. 61.
:B. See Cicero: Acad. 17-18 and 43: De F/11. V, 7 ff.; De Nat. Deor. I, 16-17
and 33. Differences of doctrine between the schools are noted at Acad. 26;
33: and 35 ff. This view is by no means as preposterous as some modern in-
terpreters suggest, since in Antiochus' (and Cicero's) time the only
Aristotelian works in circulation were his exoteric treatises. There is con-
siderable evidence that early Stoicism drew much from these exoteric works
which in their turn were exceptionally close to later Platonism; so that a
reader of the first century B.C. would be more impressed by the continuity of
doctrine than by the differences. For an excellent discussion of this point see
}. Pepin: Tbeo/ogie cosmique et tbeo/ogie cbretien11e (Ambroise, Exam. /, I,
/-4)(Paris, 1964 ), pp. 138-139.
34. Cicero: De Off/c. I, 2.
35. Cicero: De Fin. IV,; and IV, 15; Tusc. Disp. IV, 6.
CICERO 67
.i6. Cicero: De Pin. IV, 3-19: De Leg. I, 37: and TtiS(:. Disp. IV, 6.
_;: Cicero: De Leg. l, 53-55 and De Offic. Ill, 20.
:\H. On the influence of the skeptical tendency see, however, C. B. Schmitt:
Uceru Scepticus. A Study of the Influence of the Academica in the
Renllissance (The Hague, 1972), p. 18ff. and E. N. Tigerstedt: The Decline
mut Fall of the Neoplatonic Interpretation of Plato. An Outline and Some
Ohsermtions (Helsinki, 1974), pp. 12-13.
:\9. Sec Cicero: Pro Mur. 63. For the letters sec references in P. Boyancc:
'Trois citations de Pia ton chez Ciccron', Hom mages aM. Renard (Coi/Pctin11
f._utomus I 0 I) ( Bruxelles, 1969), pp. 126-I.U. Reprinted in P. Royancc:
Etudes sur l'humanisme ciceronien (Bruxelles, 1970), pp. 24H-255.
tO. Sec CommentClrio/um Petitionis 46 (of Cicero's brother Quintus) and
<,>uintilian: lnst. Oral. X, 1. 123.
68 MIDDLE PLATONISM
4 I. Cicero: Aead. 7.
42. Cicero: Lue. 139.
4~. Cicero: De Leg. I, ~9 Perturbatrieem autem harum rmmium rerum
Ac:ademiam, bane ab Arc:esila et Carneade recentem, exoremus ut sileat.
Nam si inNISI!I'if in baec quae sa lis scite nobis instructa et amposita tiden-
tur, nimias edet minas. Quam quidem ego placare cuplo, sulnmJI!ere mm
tmdeo.
44. Other passages expressing Cicero's support for Plato's doctrines in-
clude De Fin. I, 7 and V, I; De Leg. Ill, I; Tusc. Disp. 1, 39.
45. Sec Cicero: De Oral. I, 47 and Ill, I;; Episf. ad Fam. IX, .22. For
references in this and the next two notes I am indebted to the admirable
study of P. Boyance: 'Le platonisme a Rome. Plat on et Ciceron', Association
Guillaume Bude, Co11gres de Tours et Poitiers, Actes du c:o11gres (Paris,
1953 ), pp. 195-2 21. Reprinted in Boyance: Etudes sur /'buma11isme eicero-
'lien, pp. 222-24 7.
46. See Cicero: Ctlto Maior I~ and 41: De Divin. I. 78: De Fin. V, 50;
Tuse. Disp. I, 39 and IV, 44: Epist. ad Fam. I. 9.
47. See Cicero: Brut. 24: De Fin. V, I.
CICERO 69
1. IS STOIC TENDENCIES
and logic. 76 The use of the former order to structure the New
Academic critique of Antiochus' system in the Lucul/us suggests
that this is the arrangement of Philo, while the use of the latter
bv an Old Academic spokesman in the Academica, together
\,:ith supporting testimonies in Seneca77 and Augustine 78 both
of which clearly go back to Varro as a source, 79 indicates the
origin of this arrangement in Antiochus. The ancient evidence
unanimously declares that the formal tripartition of philosophy
stems from the early Academy, and that it resulted essentially
from an historical analysis.so Thus, regarding the Philonian
order, Diogenes Laertius informs us that in the earliest times
philosophers discoursed only on physics (the Presocratics), to
which study ethics was later added (by Socrates), and finally
logic (by Plato).SI Concerning the Antiochean order, we find
analogous testimony in Augustine: philosophy was originally
divided into the two branches of ethics and physics, the former
achieving its finest development in Socrates, the Iauer in
Pythagoras. Plato then united the two (thereby perfecting
philosophy) to which he added logic.82 The contexts in which
H~. This theme goes back to the Stoa, early Aristotle, and ultimately Plato's
Timaeus. In general see G. P. Conger: Theories of Macrocosms and
Jficmcosms in the History of Philosophy (New York. 1922): H. Hommel:
'Mikrokosmos'. Rbelnlscbes Museum, Neue Folge 92 (1943). pp. 56-89; R.
Alkrs: 'Microcosmos. from Anaximandros to Paracelsus', Traditio 2 (1944),
pp ..~ 19-Hr'; A. Olerud: L 'idee de nwcrocosmos et de microcosmos dans le
Timt'e de Pltlton. Etude de mytbologie compt~ree (Uppsala, 1951 ); M. Kurd-
zialek: 'Der Mensch als Abbild des Kosmos', Miscellanea Mediaevtllitl 8
( 1'>-t ). pp. 3S-i"i; and I. Munoz Valle: 'El principio de Ia simpatia universal y
Ia corrdacion entre el macrocosmo y el microcosmo en Ia anrigua Grecia'.
Ri1ista tli studi classici 23 ( 197S ), pp. 210-220.
HH. On these relations see pp. 4 2-44.
78 MIDDLE PLATONISM
God soul
World Man
T
matter + body
I
T +I
(macrocosm) (microcosm)
!
Two points should be made concerning this schema: first,
although the relations between God and matter or soul and
body can be interpreted as transcendent or immanent in either
case, that between the world and man is strictly only a transcen-
dent one. This is because the world is an aggregate of its parts,
the totality itself not being a separate principle from the parts
which comprise it. However, if the relation between the world
and man is transformed into the relation between God and man,
then this relation can be interpreted as both transcendent and
immanent. The second point is that all the relations can be inter-
preted both Stoically - as existing between active and passive
material principles- and Platonically- as subsisting between
active spiritual and passive material principles. Most of the
writers whom Cicero used as his sources deliberately tread a
path which is midway between Stoicism and Platonism, so that
CICERO 79
1.2 ETHICS
H9. See van den Bruwaene: La tbeologie de Ciceron pp. I O-Il who argues
that there is no real transcendence of causes in Stoicism nor in Cicero who
follows their teaching on these questions. Yet it is a mistake to interpret the
Stok and especially the Middle Stoic notion of cause in too restricted a man-
ner. Already in the earlier Stoa there is a tendency to replace the old
dichotomy of active (fire, air) and passive (water, earth) principles with that
of active (pneuma) and passive (fire, air, water, earth)- see Athenaeus of At-
talia~ doctrine reported by Galen: llltrod. s. medic. 9 (SVF II. 416)- and
this becomes more pronounced in Posidonius and other Stoics nearer to
Cicero's own time. In other words, there takes place a gradual spiritualiza-
tion of the pneuma. Furthermore E. Brehier: Cbrysippe et l'mlcien stoicisme
( Parb. Second Edition 195 I), p. 127 has shown that the Stoic theory of
causality is basically an attempt to solve the traditional Platonic problem of
participation between material and spiritual: see his analysis of Philo ludaeus:
/Je FuRaet lment. 13 (SVF II, 760) where the Stoic 'quality' (7tot6v) is treated
;h equivalent to the Platonic Form. In \'iew of the seamy evidence, it is dif-
tkult to sav how far Antiochus- the immediate source of much of Cicero's
lloctrine ~has gone In this direction, but clearly the transition has begun.
90. On the literary relation between Cicero's works and the originals by
Plato see Hirzel: op. cit. l, p. 463 ff. This writer points out that Cicero's debt
to Plato in De Republica and De Legibus is not, of course, restricted to the
lktlogues of the same names. For example, the eschatological elemem in the
lorrner work is probably influenced mostly by Plato's Pbaedo.
80 MIDDLE PLATONISM
'J-1. Cicero: /Je Rep. III, :H est quidem vera lex recta ratio. naturae con-
gntens. t1Ufu.m in rmmis, crmstans sempiterna, quae t'ocet cui officium
iuiJeltdo. tetcmdo a fraude deterreat. quae tamen neque probos frustra
iuiJtt aut l'elat. nee improbos iubendo cmt tetcmdo mm,et. b11ic fegi nee
" 11 rugari fas est. neque clerogari ctfiquid ex bac licet, neque tota af>rogari
fJutest. nee tero a111 per senatum aut per populum softi hac lege possumus.
111 ''/11<' est Cfllll<'l'elldus e.\1Jfanator aut lntcrpres Sextus Aelius, nee erit alia
h.\' 1/r,nae alia :ltbenis, alia mmc alia postbac, sed et omnes gentes et omni
lt' 111 /lllre una lex et sempitenw et imnutafJi/is crmtinebit, Wlllsque erit com-
lltunis lfUasi magister et imperator omnium deus: ilfe legis bulus imentor,
cltscefJiatur, Ialor: cui qui mm parehit. ipse se fugiet ac llctturmu lmmiuis
' 1Sf1<'1"11C/IIIs ...
82 MIDDlE PlATONISM
l)5. Ibid. Ill. 36 'For why dse docs God rule man. the soul body, reason
lust, an~er, and the other evil dements of the souP (cur igitur deus bomini.
cmimus imperat corpori, ratio libidini iractmdiaeque et ceteris vitiosis
eiusdem animi partibus?). Note that thc analogy of ruin and ruled is extend-
ed even to within the soul itself, for Cicero is hen: followin~ Plato's triparti-
tion of thc soul ;u Rep. IV. -1:\6b ff. The other passa~e is Cicero: De Rep. IV, I
'To me indent it seems as mud1 worse as the soul is more excellent than thc
body' (mibi quidem ftmfo !'itletur qtumto praestabi/ior est animus cor-
pore).
l)6. Ibid. Ill, 3. The word 'reason' (ratio) does not actually occur in the
CICERO 83
text which is here fragmentary. Yet the usually synonymous term 'mind'
(mens) is present. and the context makes the nature of the missing element
dear.
<r. This passage is preserved by Augustine: Contra Julian. IV, 12 (PL 44,
~6~) who decides on the second interpretation. He explains the context by
saying that Cicero was describing the weak state of man at birth and his
gradual acquisition of civilization and the arts, this process being the result of
a certain divine fire of Intelligence and mind' (quidam divinus ignis ingenii
et mentis) implanted in him. Of course, the whole discussion is interpreted as
orthodox Platonism by Augustine.
9H. On this work see Clement of Alexandria: Strom. V. 12 (SVF I, 264).
99. See Plutarch: De Alex. Virt. I, 6. 329a (SVF I, 262) on Zeno, Stobaeus:
/:'clog. I, 184 (SVF II, 527) on Chrysippus, and Diogenes Laertius: Vit. Pbilos.
\'If. 138-139 (SVF II. 634) on Posidonius.
I 00. Diogencs Laertius: Vii. Pbilos. VII, 88 uses language very similar to
Cicero's in De Republica Ill when describing the Stoic notion of law: 'the
~ommon law. that is right reason which pervades all things. identical with
~~us. this ruler of the order of things'(6 v611oc; 6 Kow6c;, 6a1tEP tativ 6 6p9oc;
Aoyoc;, 0Ul1tUVtOlV tpX,611EVOc;, 6 aUtO<; WV tt'i> ~li, Ka9TJYE116VI tOUt(!l tijc; tOOV
ovtrov OIOtKl\aEroc; 6vn). Similarly Cleanthes' Hymn to Zeus in Stobaeus:
84 MIDDLE PLATONISM
tion of the reason or law diffused through the cosmos will be,
ontologically speaking, a combination of the Platonic incor-
poreal reason with the 'artisan fire' (nup tEXVlK6v) of Stoicism,
while the relation of this law to the individual things through
which it is diffused will be a combination of Plato's theory of
participation with Stoic materialistic causality. I oI That this is
the case is indicated by the further developments regarding the
theory of law which occur in Cicero's De Legibus, where the
main argument is explicitly set out as a sequel to the construc-
tive notion of law expounded by Laelius in the previous
work.J02
Eclog. I, 25 (SVF I, 537) refers to 'the common reason which pervades all
things' (Kmvoc; A.6yoc; 6c; Sla nav<rov QlOlT~). See also Cicero: De Nat. Deor. I,
36 (SVF I, 162); Minucius Felix: Octav. 19, 10 (SVF I, 162); Lactantius: lnst.
Div. I, S (SVF I. 162); Diogenes Laertius: Vit. Phi/os. VII, 128 (SVF Ill, 308);
and Plutarch: De Stoic. Repug11 9, 10.3Sc (SVF Ill, 326). It is interesting that
all these passages equate the law with God, whereas me passage of De
Republica places God In some way prior to the law as its creator. This may be
a purely literary mode of expression which also occurs sometimes in other
Stoic writers, or else it may imply a distinction between transcendent and Im-
manent principles in a more Platonic manner. On the Stoic theory of law see
further G. Watson: 'The Natural Law and Stoicism'. Problems in Stoicism,
edited by A. A. Long(London, 1971), pp. 216-238.
101. See pp. 78-79 and n. 89.
102. Cicero: De Leg. I, 20 and I, 27.
103. Referring, no doubt, to Panaetius or Antiochus.
CICERO s;
human mind, being law.' IOi It is easy to see that Cicero here
returns to the framework of the earlier treatise, for once again
he is postulating a principle of reason which is not only imma-
nent in the world or macrocosm but also in man or
microcosm. los The latter aspect is developed further in the next
few paragraphs of the text, but with a subtle change of emphasis
which might pass unnoticed, for Cicero no longer speaks of the
immanence of the macrocosmic reason in the microcosm, but of
the microcosmic reason itself, law being redefined as a 'natural
force - the mind and reason of an intelligent man.'I06 Soon,
however. we return to the macrocosm, when the speaker
reminds us that any discussion of the nature of justice must
begin with that supreme law which existed ages before any
written system of jurisprudence.I07 In these opening
paragraphs, then, we find Cicero postulating the existence of
reason or law in three different relations: as absolute reason im-
manent in the macrocosm, as absolute reason immanent in the
microcosm, and as individual reason immanent in the
microcosm.
But a little further on, our attention is shifted to the cor-
responding transcendent relations, since it is quickly agreed by
all parties to the discussion that everything is governed by the
p<nver or reason of the immortal gods.Ios This compels us to ad-
mit that 'that animal which we call man, provident, wise, com-
plex. endowed with intelligence and memory, full of reason and
judgment, has been created by the supreme God with a certain
IOt. Un:ro: /Je l.eg l. 18-19 lex est ratio summa. insila in natura. quae
iuiJet ea tfllllefacienda sun/. probihetque nmtraria. Eadem ratio cum est in
humin is mente nmfinnclla et pe1fecta, /e., est.
IO;. ~ote the phrase 'this same reason' (eadem ratio) which indicates that
011 l' and the same reason is immanent in both macrocosm and microcosm.
I 09. /hid. l. 2 2-2.~ em/mal hoc prmidum sagax multiple.\' aczlftan memor
plenum ratirmis et consilii, quem trJcamus bominem, praec/ara quadam
condicione generatwn esse a supremo deo. So/tun est enim ex tot animan-
tium generilms a/que naturis particeps mlirmis el cogilalionis, quom
cetera sin/ omnia expert/a. Quid est tllllem, non dicam in bomine sed in
omni cae/o a/que terra, ratione ditinius? Quae quom ado/evil atque perfec-
t a est. nomitwtur rile sapienlia. Est igitm. qtwnimn nibil est rulimze
me/ius. etlqU(' est el ill bomine el ill deo, prima lmmini cum lleo rulionls
sot'ielcts. Inter quos au/em ratio, inter eosdem eliam reclcl rulio communis
est: quae ('Um sit /e.--.:, lege qtmque nmsociali homlues cum dis puttmdi
sum us. Inter quos fHJP'ro est commuuio legis, iuler eos nm11111111io /uris est.
Quihus uulem baec suul inter eos communia, ei citilatis eiusdem babendi
sunt. Si tenJ isdem imperils et Jmfeslalihus parent, multo elictm magis.
Parent au/em huic caelesti discripliorzi menlique ditinae el praepotenti
deo.
110. Ibid. I, 24. The theory is a reminiscence of Plato's Tlmaeus. See P.
CICERO 87
113. Ibid. II, 8 Ita principem legem i/lam et ultimam men tem esse ... om-
nia ratione aut cogentis aut vetantis del.
114./bid. II, 11. The text is partly conjectural at this point.
IIi. 1/Jitl. II, ((,Quid est enim terius quam neminem e.~se oportere tam
stulte adrogantem, ut in se rationem et mentem putet inesse, in caelo mtm-
doque non putet.~ Aut ut ea quae tix summa ingenii ratione conprebendan-
tur. nulla ralirme mm,eri putet?
116. Other passages in the second book of De Legibus dealing with the
transcendent and immanent relations of reason and law are ibid. ll, I 0 and II,
13.
CICERO 89
117. There are also some passages in De Legibus III, for example III, 2-3
and Ill. 12. But these basically repeat the same material.
118. See Cicero: De Rep. III, 33.
119. See Cicero: De Leg. II, 8 and II, 10.
120. See Cicero: De Rep. Ill, 33 (law, reason); De Leg. I, 18-19 (law,
n:ason); I, 22-23 (law, reason); II, 8 (law, reason); II, 16 (reason); etc.
I 2 I. It may be useful to add a diagram indicating the various modes in
which rlason is manifested in De Republica and De Leg/bus.
T+I
1--- T+l T+
I
world
~ man
1.22. Fcstugiere: op. cit., pp. 425-433 and 459.
90 MIDDLE PLATONISM
cond hook: (i) using one source (Reinhardt), (ii) using a number of sources
(Pohlenz. Finger), (iii) using one source of a compendium character (Philipp-
son~. Festugii:re: op. cit. p. 384, n. 1 considers that the problems will never
the resolved, but that the investigations of Reinhardt and Philippson have
made definite progress by distinguishing two parts of the work: De Nat.
Df!(}l'. II. 4-72 probably based on a compendium. and ibid. II. 73-167 follow-
ing a continuous treatise.
132. Naturally Cicero. as a Roman pagan, believed in a multitude of gods.
However, he follows the universal practice of late ancient philosophy In see-
ing all the lower gods as manifestations of a supreme one. It is this highest
God with which our investigation is concerned.
I 3 3. See Cicero: De Rep. Ill, 3 3. Also see pp. 80-81.
13-.. See Cicero: De Leg. !, 18. Also see pp. 84-85.
135. Cicero: De Fin. Ill. 73. The equation between God and nature is
discussed at greater length by van den Bruwaene: La theologie de Cictfrmz,
pp. J"72-182 and 248 ff. The most recent discussions of Stoic physical theory
:1re S. S:1mhursky: Physics of the Stoics (London, 1959); F. Solmsen: Cleanthes
()I' Posidonius? The Basis of Stoic PIJ)'Sics (Amsterdam. 1961 ); J. Christensen:
l:W. Cicero: De Nat. Denr. l, 52. Cf. ibid. II, 16; II, 127; and Ill, 28. For
the notion of God as a transcendent cause in the Stoics see Diogenes Laertius:
l'it. Pbifos. VII, 137 (SVF II, 526) and Stobaeus: Ec/og. I. 184 (SVF II, 527).
The texts indicate two tendencies: (i) to consider the active cause as a
pneuma of fire and air operating on the passive elements water and earth. Sec
texts cited inn. 142, (ii) to view the active cause as a pneuma transcending all
four elements and operating upon them. See Galen: lntrod. s. medic. 9 (SVF
11. -116); Diogenes Laertius: Vit. Pbilos. VII, 135-137 (SVF II. 580); and
l.ucan. Scbol. Bern. IX. 578. Tendency (ii) seems to be mainly in the later
Stoks and is especially characteristic of Posidonius. However. tendency (i) is
perhaps predominant in Cicero's reports of Stoic doctrine. As van den Bru-
waene: Cie~fron: De Natura Deorum, Lit1re I. p. 28 notes. this is an argument
a~ainst the belief that Posidonius is the sole source of Cicero's understanding
of Stoic physics.
IHl. Cicero: De Nat. Deor. II. 77-78.
1-t I./bid. II, 57-58; II, 81; II, 83-84; and II. 87.
1t2. Cicero: Acad. 39. Cf. Cicero: De Nat. Deor. II, 91-92 and II, 117-118.
For fin: as a transcendent cause in the Stoics see Plutarch: De Stoic Repugn.
96 MIDDLE PLATONISM
41, 1053b (SVF II, 605); De Comm. Not. 36. 1077c (SVF II, 1064); Arius
Didymus: Epit. Phys. fr. 29 (SVF II, 642 = DG 465, 7-10); and Diogcnes Laer-
tlus: Vit. Philos. VII, 139 (SVF II, 644).
143. Cicero: De Nat. Deor. II, 117-118.
144. See Posidonius in Luc. Scho/. Bern. IX, 578 'For what other abode
does God have than the elements which he names. Posidonius the Stoic says
that 'God is an intellectual pneuma pervading the whole of substance'. that is
to say earth, water, air, heaven' (Quae enlm aHa est del sedes nisi e/ementa
haec quae dicit? Aft etlim Posldonius Stoicus: 9e6c; tan 7tVEUJ.1a voepov
l>li;Kov l>l'ancianc; oua(ac;: deus est spiritus rationalis per omnem dlffusus
materiam, hoc est terram aquam aera caelum). Sec nn. 89 and 139.
145. Pepin: Tbeologie cosmique et theologle chretlenne (Ambroise, Exam.
/,I, 1-4), pp. 241-247.
CICERO 97
116. Ck<:ro: De Nat. Deor. II, 40; II, 9192; and II, 115 (fiery nature of
h<:an:n): ibid. l, 36; 11, 55; and De Rep. Vl, 17 (the heaven as God). Cf.
l>iogcncs laertius: Vit. Pbi/os. Vll, 139 (SVF II. 644) and VII, 148 (SVF l. 163
and II. 1022). Cleanthes complicates the picture by placing his ruling part in
lht Sun. Sec Diogenes l.aertius: Vlt. Ph/los. VII, 139 (SVF I, 499).
li~. Cicero: De Nat. Deor. II, 118. Cf. Philo Iudaeus: De lncorr. Mundi
2')-1, .., (SVF II, 61 1); Aetius: Plac. II, 9. 2 (SVF II, 609 = DG 338bl618);
Plutarch: De Stoic Repugn. 41. 1053b (SVF 11, 605). Panaetius (to whom
Cic<:ro rt:fers in the passage quoted) denied this theory. See Diogenes laer-
tius: l'it. Pbilos. VII. 142.
11!-1. Sec: Reinhardt: Poseidonios, pp. 234-239 and Kosmos und Sym-
{lat/Jie. Neue Untersuchungen fiber Poseidon los, pp. 92-111.
111). Festugiere: op. cit., pp. 397-398 and 417-418.
98 MIDDLE PLATONISM
162. For an analysis of these arguments seeP. Boyance: 'Les preuves stoi-
ciennes de !'existence des dieux d'apres Ciceron', Hermes 50 (1962), pp.
4 5-71. Reprinted in Boyancc: Etudes sur /'buma11isme ciceronien, pp.
301-334. The writer disagrees with the assessment of earlier scholars and em-
phasizes Cicero's personal contribution to the development of these
arguments.
163. Cicero: De Nat. Deor. II, 21-22. These three arguments are also
documented by Sextus Empiricus: Adv. Math. IX, I 04 (SVF I. I I I) = i; Ibid.
IX. 85 (SVF I, 114) = ii; ibid. IX, I 10 (SVF I, 113) =iii. A more complex ex-
ample of an argument from microcosm to macrocosm occurs at Cicero: De
Nat. Deor. II, 29-30.
164. Ibid. II, 45. The argument is presented in rather confusing combina-
tion with another based upon the definition of God as that than which there
is nothing more excellent in nature. Sec n. 157. It is also presented by
Diogenes Laertius: Vit. Pbi/os. VII, 142-143 (SVF II, 633).
CICERO 101
in res fluas. ut alteru esset efflciens, altera uutem quasi buic se praebens,
eaque efficeretur aliquid. in eo quod efficeret rim esse censebant. in eo
emtem quod efficeretur tantum modo materiam quandam; in utroque
tamen utrumque: neque enim mater/am ipsam cobaerere potuisse si nulla
l'i crmtineretur. neque tim sine aliqua materia; nibil est enim quod mm
alicubi esse cogatur. sell quod e.\ utroque. id lam corpus et quasi
qualltatem quandam nom/nahant ...
2A. earum igitur qua/ita tum sunt aliae principes a/iae ex his ortae. prin-
dpes sufllrmius modi et simplices; ex his autem ortae tariae stmt et quasi
multiformes. itaque aer (hoc quoque utimur enim pro Latino) et ignis et
aqua et terra prima sunt; ex his autem ortae animantium formae earum-
que rerum quae glgmmtur e tena. ergo 11/a inilia et ut e Graeco t'ertam
e/ementa dietmtur; e quibus aer et ig11is nuwe11di rim babe1ll et efficiendi,
reliquae partes accipiendi et quasi patiendi, aquam dico et terram. quln-
tum genus, e quo essen! astra mentesque, singulare eorumque quattuor
quae supta eli.,-; dissimi/e Aristoteles quodda m esse rebatur.
2B. Sed sublectcmt putant omnibus sine ulla specie atque carentem omni
ilia qualitate (j'aclamus e11im tractcmdo usittltius boc verbum et tritlus)
mater/am quandam. ex qua omnia expressa atque effecta sint. quae Iota
omnia accipere possit omnlbusque modis mutari atque ex omni parte eo-
que etiam interire, non in nibilum sed in suas partes, quae infinite secari
ac ditidi possltll. cum sit 11ihil onmlno In rerum mllura minimum quod
dil'idi nequeat.
173. Alexander of Aphrodisias: De Mixl. 223, 25 (SVF II, 441) and 224, 32
(SVF II, 310). On the Stoic theories of mixture see H. A. Wolfson: The
Pbi/osophJ1 of the Church Fathers I. Faith. TriniiJ, Incarnation (Cambridge,
MA, 1956), pp. 372-386; Samhursky: op. cit., pp. Il-17 and I2I-123;).
Pepin: 'Sti/la aquae modica multo infusa vino, ferrum ignitum, luce per-
fusus aer. L'origine de trois comparaisons familieres a Ia theologie mystique
medievale'. Miscellanea A. Combes I (Divinitas, II) (Roma, 1967), pp.
344-355; and R. B. Todd: Alexander ofAphrodisias on Stoic Physics. A Study
of the De Mixtione with Preliminary Essays, Text, Translation and Com-
mentary(Lciden, 1976), pp. 29-73.
174. For the various types of mixture see Stobaeus: Eclog. I, 153 (SVF II,
471 ). They are 'juxtaposition' (napa8ea1c;), 'mixture' proper (lli~l<; of solids
or Kpdmc; of liquids), and 'fusion' (al)yxumc;). In the first case, there is no real
l'omposition since each <.onstituent retains its identity, e.g. stones in a
mosaic. In the last case, all the constituents lose their own characteristics,
e.g. in a drug. Thus the Stoics concentrate on the intermediate kind as their
paradigm of physical relations.
175. See Clement of Alexandria: Strom. VIII, 9 (SVF II, 349) 'causes to one
another' (aUi)A.mc; a ina). See Samhursky: op. cit.. pp. R 1-88.
176. See Alexander of Aphrodisias: De Mixt. 2I7, 27 (SVF II, 473) 'being
preserved along with their own qualities' (we; aimi aq>~OJLEva JLEta nov
oiKeiwv nmoti)twv). See Brehit:r: op. cit.. pp. I 14-14 I.
CICERO 105
185. Galen: lntrod. s. medic. 9 (SVF II, 416); Diogenes Laertius: Vii.
Philos. VII, 13'H 37 (SVF II, '580); and Luc. Schol. Bern. IX, '578.
186. Sec Galen: De Nat. Fac. II, 4 (SVF II, 410); De Mult. 3 (SVF II, 439):
Alexander of Aphrodisias: De Mi:~:t. 224, 14 (SVF II, 442): De Anim. 26. 13
(SVF II, 786); and Nemesius: De Nat. Hom.;, 6258 (SVF II. 418).
187. Plutarch: De Stoic. Repugn. 43. 10'53f (SVF II, 429): Galen: De Elem.
sec. Hippocr. I, 6 (SVF II, 408) and In Hippocr. de Nat. Hom. I (SVF II, 409).
188. Seep. 94 ff. and n. 139.
189. Diogenes Laertius: Vii. Philos. VII, 150 (SVF II, 482).
190. See Plutarch: De Comm. Not. 38-39. 1079a-d (SVF II, 483-484 and
CICERO 109
IH9). For an illuminating discussion of this question see Sambursky: op. cit.,
pp. HH-9H.
19 I. See Plato: Tim. 53c ff.
19.2. Cicero: Tusc. Disp. 1, .2.2.
19:\. Cicero: De Fin. IV, 1.2.
19-l. See Pepin: Tbeo/ogie cosmique eltbeo/ogie cbretiemze (Ambroise, Ex-
am./, /, 1-4), pp. 206-247.
110 MIDDLE PLATONISM
196. See Sextus: Adr1. Math. X . .3 (SVF II. SO';) for 'interval' (BuiatlUta) ap-
plit:d to space; Stobaeus: Eclog. I, 106 (SVF II, 509) for the same notion ap-
plkd 10 lime. Reid: op. cit., p. 1.31 considers that only a reft:rence to space is
imtnded. the main aim of the passage being refutation of the Atomists' con
cept of void.
197. Sc:e Plutarch: De Comm. Not. 37. 1077e (SVF II, 465); Alexander of
Aphrodisias: De Mixt. 216, 14 (SVF II, 473)and 223,25 (SVF II, 441).
198. Set: Ac:tius: Plac. I. 18. 5 (SVF I, 95 = DG .H 6b 1113 ). II, 9. 2 (SVF II,
h09 = DG .HHb 16-18): Sextus Empiricus: Adr. /1-lclth. IX, 332 (SVF II. 524 );
Achilles Tat ius: In trod. H (SVF II, 610); and Simplkius: hz D(' Caelo I. 9. 2f!.:j,
.?H-285. 2 (SVF II, 535).
I<Jt.>. Cicero: De Ntlf. Deor. II, I 18. For the influence of Panaetius upon An
liochus' physics se~ Strache: op. cit., pp. 2021 and Luck: op. dt., p. H.
112 MIDDLE PLATONISM
200. See Cicero: De Nat. Deor. l, 39 and Seneca: E"pist. 92. 30 (SVF II.
637).
20 I. See pp. 99-100.
CICERO 113
102. This whole account should be compared with Calcidius report of the
Stoi1.: theory of maner at/n Tim. 292. 294, 17-.295, 14 (SVF I, 88) 'Zeno fur-
ther maintains that this essence is finite and the one common substance of all
existing things. and that it is also divisible and mutable in every respect, since
it~ parts change although they do not perish in the sense of passing from ex-
istence to nothingness. But just as is the case with innumerable different
forms made out of wax, so he contends that neither form nor shape nor any
4uality at all is attributable: to matter the foundation of all things, although it
is always joined to and coheres inseparably with some quality. And because it
is without beginning or end- it does not come: to be from non-existence nor
is it reduced to nothing- it has from eternity a spirit and force which moves
it rationally sometimes as a whole and sometimes in part, this being the: cause
of the frequent and violent changes in the universe. Moreover, he holds that
this moving spirit is not nature but a rational soul which bestowed life on the
sensible world and adorned it with the beauty by which it is now distinguish-
ed. They call the world a blessed living creature and God' (Deinde Zeno bane
ipsam essentiam jinitam esse dicit zmamque earn communem omnium
quae sunt esse substantimn, diziduam quoque et usque quaque mutabilem;
partes quippe eius Lerti sed 11on interire, ita ut de existentibus consumantur
in nibilum. Sed ul innumerabilium diversarum, eliam cerearum,
Jigumrum. sic nequejormam 11equejiguram nee ullam omnit~o qualilatem
proprhun fore censel jundamenti rerum omt~ium silz,ae, coniut~ctam
ltmun esse semper et inseparabiliter cobaerere alicui qutllilati; cumque
tam sine urtu sit quam sine interitu, quia neque de notl exislente subsistit
nee co11sumetur in nihilum, non deesse ei spiritum ac 11igorem ex aeter-
nilclle. qui 11WlJeat eam rationabiliter lolam inlerdum, non numquam pro
Jmrtirme. quae causa sit tam crebrae tamque lebemenlis universae rei con-
tersirmis; spiritum porro motitum ilium fore non naturam, sed an imam,
et quidem rationabi/em, quae vivijicans set~silem mundum e:~:ornaverit
eum ad bcmt qua mmc 11/ustratur venustatem. Quem quidem beatum
animal et deum appellant).
114 MIDDLE PLATONISM
203. See Cicero: De Rep. VI, 9 and De Nat. Deor. II, 84.
204. See Philo ludaeus: Quod Deus sit immut. 35 (SVF II, 458).
205. See Alexander of Aphrodisias: De Mixt. 224, 14 (SVF II, 442).
206. See Philo ludaeus: Quod Deus sit immut. 35 (SVF II . .J58); Quaest. et
So/ut. in Gen. II, 4 (SVF II, 802); Sextus Empiricus: Adt. Math. IX, 149 (SVF
II. .f54); Nemesius: De Nat. Hom. 2, 'i40A-B (SVF II, 451); and Simplicius: /tz
Categ. R, 269, 1-l-16 (SVF II, -!52).
207. See Galen: De Trem. Palp. Com'. 6 (SVF II, 446).
208. See Philo ludaeus: De Sacrif Abel et Cain 68 (SVF II, 4'i3) and Alex-
ander: DeMixt. 224. 1-4 (SVF II, .J42).
CICERO I I '5
209. See Philo ludaeus: Qrmest. et Sol. in Gen. II, 4 (SVF II, 802) and
Act ius: Plac. IV, 21. 1-4 (SVF II, 836 = DG 410a2 5-4 II a24 ).
210. St:e Stobat:us: Eclog. I, I '53 (SVF II, 471 ).
2 I I. St:t: pp. I 05-106.
2 12. Plato: Tim. 52d-'53b.
116 MIDDLE PLATONISM
arc now lost, although the one writer who seems least relevant
is Panaetius who was the principal source of De Officiis.l.~H
Panaetius' view that the soul consists of a pneuma of air and
fire, which represents orthodox Stoicism, is noted without
criticism early in the longer section of the argument for immor-
tality . .:!.~') Less sympathetic to Panaetius, however, is an appen-
dix to the argument where the Stoic view that souls survive
bodies for a certain length of time but eventually perish is ex-
amined and rejected. Cicero here notes the inconsistency of a
philosopher who, although expressing reverence for Plato, con-
tradicts his idol on a most fundamental point by arguing that the
manifest birth of souls also implies their death . .Z4o Furthermore,
there is an obvious reason why Cicero would need to avoid
Panaetius in approaching the doctrines of the Phaedrus: the lat-
ter had actually denied the authenticity of this dialogue .HI
we know 'by natural instinct' (natura) that the gods exist and
can Jearn by 'reasoning' (ratio) about their nature, so also 'by
the agreement of all peoples' (consensu nationum omnium) we
believe that souls endure and can learn by 'reasoning' (ratio)
about their nature and place of abode.243 The distinction bet-
ween notions grasped instinctively and demonstrated by argu-
ment is Stoic in origin, and we may conclude that Cicero
understands the relation between the two kinds of knowledge
in the manner peculiar to this school.244 Thus, the preconcep-
tion can either be strengthened by the process of reasoning, or
else can be employed as the basis for further deductions, the lat-
ter being on account of their epistemological genesis
unassailable truths. Cicero shows his interest in both these kinds
of argument, on the one hand by strengthening the instinctive
knowledge of the soul's immortality with the aid of Plato's
famous proof that the soul which is self-moving and therefore
eternally moving is immortal,245 and on the other by
demonstrating the divinity of the soul from the fact that just as
the order of the cosmos indicates that it has its origin in a divine
cause so do the products of human art testify to the presence of
divinity in man,246 or from the fact that since the definition of
reason as that than which a greater cannot be thought evidences
its wholly divine character thus the presence of this reason in
man indicates that the latter contains within himself an element
of divinity .247 It will be seen that in such arguments it is the
2-13. Cicero: Tusc. Disp. I, 36. The same distinction of preconception and
reasoning together with the analogy between God and the soul underlies
ibid. I. 70-71.
2H. Seep. 131 ff.
2-iS. Tusc. Dtsp. I. 53-54. There is an analogous argument regarding God
:tl ibid. I, 65-66.
2-+6. Ibid. I, 62-63. That the belief in a divine cause of cosmic motions is a
rrcmnception in the Stoic sense is indicated by Cicero: De Nat. Deor. II, <i.
2i...,. Cicero: Tusc. Disp. I, 64-65. For the notion that reason is 'that than
124 MIDDLE PLATONISM
which no greater can he though!" (icl. quo ne ... qulcquam maius inl1/e!!,i
potest) see Cicero: De Nat. Deor. II, 2122.
248. See Cicero: Tusc. Disp. 1, 67-70. At De Leg. II. 28 two levels of
blessedness are apparently established for souls: immortality (for all men) and
divinity (for the good and brave).
249. Cicero: Tusc. Disp. I, 60.
250. Ibid. I. M.
251./bid. I, 66.
CICERO 12<;
2<>2. Sec Alexander of Aphrodisias: De Anim. IIH. 6 (SVF II, 823) and
lamblichus: De Anim. in Stobaeus: Eclog. I, 367 (SVF II, 826). For the role of
the ruling part' (~yE~OVIK6v) see Aetius: Plac. IV, 4, 4 (SVF II. 827 = DG
:I'JOa'5-13) and Diogenes Laertius: Vii. Pbilos. VII, I 10 (SVF II, 828).
26:1. See Plato: Tim. 69d ff.
26--J. Cicero: Tusc. Disp. I, 75. Cf. De Rep. VI. 14.
128 MIDDLE PLATONISM
.26H. Sc:c: Arius Didymus: Epit. Ph)'S. fr. 39 (SVF II, 809 = DG 471, 18-24);
Ac:tius: Plac. IV, 7, 3 (SVF II, 810 = DG 393al-7); and Diogenc:s Laertius: Vit.
Philos. VII, I '57 (SVF II, 811 ).
.269. Cicero: De Fin. IV, 14 ff.
2"'0. Ibid. IV. 28.
2"' I. 1/Jid. IV, .2'7 .
.!" 2. Ibid. IV, 16.
130 MIDDLE PLATONISM
1.4 LOGIC
2""'6. See J. Pepin: "Que l'hommc n'cst rien d'autre que sun arne." Ohscr-
,.ations sur Ia tradition du Premier A/cibiade', Rerue des etudes grecques 82
( 1969), pp. 56-70 who cites Clcanthes in Epiphanius: Adr. Haer. Ill, 2. 9 (SVF
I. 1'16 = DG 592, 21-29).
r-:r. Scepp. 101-106.
2":'8. As suggested by Dillon: op. cit., p. 98,n. I.
132 MIDDLE PLATONISM
287. Sextus Empiricus: Adv. Math. VII, 241-247 (SVF II, 65).
2HH. Sextus Empiricus: Adt. Math. VII. 248 (SVF II, 6'5) I\UTUA111tTLKiJ ot
i:anv n ano (mapxovro~ Kai ~~:ar'auro TO (mapxov EVU1tOjljlU'YilEV11 Kai
EVU7t0qlpaytajlEV11, 6noia OUK civ YEVOITO ano llil (mapxovro~. The same
definition is given by Cicero: l.uc. 18 tisum igitur inpressum effictumque ex
eo unde esse I qua/e esse non{msset ex eo unde non esse I.
289. Cicero: Luc. 17.
290. This point is somewhat controversial. many scholars maintaining that
CICERO 135
292. On the relation between the 'ruling part' (1)y&JlOVlK6v) and com-
136 MIDDLE PLATONISM
prehension see Diodes Magnes in Diogenes Laenius: Vit. Pbilos. VII, 52 (SVF
II,71).
293. Cicero: De Fin. Ill, 17 explicitly translates Kat<iATJijllc; as eomprehen-
sio or pereeptio, although the former occurs most frequently in his accounts
of Stoicism.
294. The term 'sensation' (aio9rrmc;) therefore has a wider meaning than
passive reception of sensory impressions. See Aetius: Plae. IV, 8, 12-9, 4 (SVF
II, 72 and 78 = DG 396b3-25) and Galen: In Hippoer. de Med. Offie. (SVF II,
75) where the consequence that all sensations are true is brought out.
295. See Aetius: Plae. IV, ll, 1-5 (SVF II, 83 = DG 400al-401al0);
Plutarch at Olympiodorus: In Phaed. 156, 8-10 (SVF II, I 04 ); and Diogenes
Laertius: Vit. Philos. VII. 53.
296. In conjunction with the comprehension. therefore, the 'compelling'
(KataArptnK6c;) of the presentation will also take on a passive sense. See pp.
I:BI:\5.
297. According to Galen: De Hipp. et Plat. Plae. V, 3 (SVF 11. 841),
Chrysippus argued that the Logos was a 'collection' (d9pmo~ta) of common
concepts.
298. See Aetius: Plae. I. 6, I ff. (SVF II, 1009 = DG 292a20 ff.) and Diodes
Magnes at Diogcnes Lacrtius: Vlt. Phi/os. VII. 52 (SVF II, 84).
299. Cicero: De Fin. Ill, 33.
CICERO 137
perception, but on the other she endows the mind only with
rudimentary concepts of the most important things. This
passage clearly describes the same theory as in the other Cicero-
nian texts, although the distinction between sensory and mental
impressions adds a new element to the picture.308
.~OH. Cicero: De Fin. V, 59. See further Cicero: De Fin. II, 46: De Leg. I. IH
:uH.I I. 33: Tusc. Disp. Ill, 2. The doctrine in these texts and Cicero's deriva-
tion of it from Antiochus have heen discussed by G. Luck: Der Akculemfker
.llztiocbos, pp. 40-4 l and Boyance: 'Ciceron et le Premier Alcibiade', pp.
260-262. Both authors stress the difference between the position of An-
tiochus and Cicero - for whom the common concepts are implanted in the
human soul, even if inchoately, from the start - and that of the Stoics -
Wht-rt they an~ developed only later in life. However, the Stoic position has
htTome \'err ambivalent bv Cicero's time, as we have already seen on p. 133
If and so it is unwise to press this point too far. Fur a more explidtly Stoic
account of the genesis of knowledge see Cicero: De FiP1. III, 21.
140 MIDDLE PLATONISM
own and seems to have been at least partially its basis. The first
description occurs in the Lucu/lus where the character of that
name expounds Antioch us polemic against the New Academic
skepticism, and begins by positing the 'judgments' (iudicia) of
the senses as certain, provided that (i) the subject is in a healthy
state and (ii) all obstacles have been removed.3t4 This last re-
quirement defends the theory against problems raised by the
skeptics concerning the oar which appears bent in the water,
and so on. Furthermore, just as those objects which are perceiv-
ed by the senses yield clear presentations, so do those which are
not perceived by the senses but 'by a kind of sensation'
(quodam modo sensibus).315 Examples of this are: (i) 'this is
white' or 'this is sweet', and (ii) 'that object is a horse' or 'that
object is a dog'. 'Such things we hold to be comprehended now
by the mind and not by the sense' (animo iam haec tenemus
conjJ1'ehensa non sensibus).316 Next comes a series of percep-
dcals with these presentations in various ways: (i) they are seiz-
ed for immediate use, (ii) they are stored away 'as the sources of
memory' (e quibus memoria oritur), or (iii) they are collected
according to their likenesses 'from which are formed the con-
cc.:pts of things which the Greeks sometimes call "notions" and
somctimes "preconceptions" ' (ex quibus efficiuntur notitiae
rerum. quas Graeci tum &vvoiac; tum npoA.i)\jiEtc; vocant). This
final group. when reason and logical proof have been added and
when reason has heen perfected through these various stages,
produces 'wisdom' (sapientia). It is easy to see that a new and
potentially significant element has entered into the argument
for. hy introducing the notion of a comparison between the
presentations according to their 'likeness' (similitudo). An-
tiochus seems to open the way to a systematic theory of univer-
sals).! I
.~11. See the: passages from Cicc:ro's Topica discussed on pp. 13l-133. I in-
tlrpret thl' text as showing the point where thl' transition to univt"rsality has
h~:~:n an:omplished. However, there is undoubtedly more to the argument
than that. Set" Reid: op. t:/1., pp. 212-213 who compares Diogem:s Lacrtius:
l'il. Pbilos. VII, S2-S3 and Sextus Empiricus: Adv. Matb. Ill. 40. IX, 393 and
\1. .:!'iO. All St"xtus' passages contrast knowledge which is obtained 'by im-
rnnliat~: dt:ar impression' (Kati.t nepilttwcnv ~vapyfl) with that which is ob-
tainld hy 'transference' (f.1Etal3acn<;) from immediate clear impression. the
lmn taking place in three ways: 'by similarity' (6f.lOlWtlKW<;). 'by composi-
1ion ltmauv9enKci><;). or 'by analogy' (avaA.oytattKci><;). By immediate clear
imprnsion Wl' conceive 'the whitt"'. 'thl' bitu::r', and so on. By transfcrenct"
1\'l' concdve Socrates himself from his picture (similarity). the hippocentaur
tn,m horsc: and man (composition). and the Cyclops from an ordinary man
I analog)'). Diogenes Laertius' passage contrasts sensory knowledge:, for exam-
pll- 'tht" white:', 'tht rough' with rational knowledge based upon demonstra-
1iun' (AOY((.l oi: tci>v 5t'ano5ei~ew<; OUVUYOf.lEVWV). for l'Xamplc tht" existc:nce of
till' gods. 'Thing!! nmceived' (tci>v yi.tp VOOUf.lEVWV) can he 'by immediate im-
prc:"ion' (Kata nepintwcnv). 'by similarity' (Ka9'6f.lm6tnta). 'by :malog(
11\Ut'civaA.oyiav). 'by transposition' (Kata f.lEta9ecnv), 'by composition'
(1\ura ouvllemv). or 'by contrariety' (Kat'~vavtiwcnv). Cict"ro's argumc:nt at
/Jl' Fin. Ill. .:H clearly renects the: samt" traditions. It will be noted that in
144 MIDDLE PLATONISM
truth has already been said to arise from the senses, so that a
completely transcendent role for the Forms is apparently ex-
cluded. Secondly, the statement that sensation is not even ade-
quate to perceive the so-called sensory realm suggests that
truth. even in the sense world, is dependent upon the mind's
knowledge of the Forms. We seem here to be faced with two
contradictory epistemological views brought together in a
single passage: the Stoic comprehension together with Platonic
intellectual knowledge.
The introduction of Plato's theory at this point suggests that
the standard of intellectual truth is no longer the immanent one
described in the first group of Ciceronian passages. Antiochus,
hy equating intellectual knowledge with the perception of the
Forms, seems to open the way towards a transcendent standard
of truth. But we must return to Cicero in order to see whether
such a theory is further developed.
did not look at any person as the source for the likeness; but in
his own mind resided some surpassing form of beauty at which
he gazed intently, and according to whose likeness he guided
his art and hand. Thus, just as there is something perfect and ex-
cellent in forms and shapes: an intellectual form with reference
to which an artist depicts those things which do not appear to
the eye, so we perceive the perfect form of eloquence with our
mind but seek its copy with our ears. These forms of things are
called "Ideas" by Plato, that most eminent teacher and master
not only of thought but of diction. He says that they do not
become, but exist eternally, being sustained by reason and in-
telligence, while other things arise, perish, change, decay, and
do not remain long in the same state. Whatever therefore is to
be discussed rationally and methodically must be reduced to its
ultimate form and type of its class'330.
(iii) 'But you say "such a man never existed". I agree. For I
am discussing what I seek and not what I have seen. I return to
that Platonic Form or Idea of which I spoke and which,
although we do not see it, we can grasp with our minds. For I
am not seeking some eloquent person, mortal or transitory, but
that thing the possession of which makes a man eloquent. This
.~50. Cicero: Oral. 7 ff. Atque ego in summo ora/ore fingendo la/em in-
.fiil"mabu qualisfortasse nemo fuit. non enim quaero quisfuerit, sed quid sit
illud quo nibil possil esse praestantius, quod in pe1petuitate dicendi non
Sllt'/Je atque baud scio an lllllltfUtl111, in aliqua autem parte eluceat ali-
quando, idem apud alios densius apud alios fortasse rarius. sed ego sic
statuo. nibil esse in ullo genere tam pulchrum, quo non pulcbrius id sit
unde illud ut ex ore aliquo quasi imago exprimatur; quod neque oculis ne-
Cflle auribus neque ullo sensu percipi potesl; cogitalione ttmle11 et mente
mmp/ectimur. itaque et Pbitliae simulacris, quibus nibil in illo genere
fn!tfeclius tidemus. et iis pic/uris, quas nominmi, cogitare tamen
/}()ssumus pu/cbriora. nee tero ille artifex, cum fttcetet lmis formam aut
.llh1erNte. crmtemplabatur aliquem e quo similitUtlinem duceret, sed ips ius
in mtute insidebat spedes fmlcbritudinis eximiu quaedam. quam intuens
in eaque defixus ad illiu.~ similitudinem artem et manum dirigebat. ut ig
148 MIDDLE PLATONISM
is none other than eloquence itself, which nobody can see ex-
cept with eyes of the mind'331.
(iv) 'In the first place, the soul has memory and at that an in-
finite memory of things without number. Plato wishes to inter-
pret this as recollection of a previous life, for in the book entitl-
ed Meno, Socrates asks some young boy various geometrical
questions about the measurement of a square. Although he is
young and the questions are easy. the boy replies in such a way
that, proceeding step by step, he arrives at the same conclusions
as he would if he had studied geometry. From this Socrates
wishes to conclude that learning is nothing other than recollec-
tion. This topic is developed with more care in that conversa-
tion which he held on the very day he departed this life, for he
teaches there that anyone who seems in all matters to be
uneducated, shows in responding to a skilful questioner that he
is not at that point learning such things, but recognizing them by
recollection. Nor is it possible in any other way for us to possess
frt'>m childhood the innate and so to speak impressed concepts
called "notions" of so many and such important things unless
the soul had grown strong in the knowledge of things before it
':\2. Cicero: Tusc. Disp. I, ';7-58 Habet primum memoriam, et eam in-
jinitam remm innumerabilium. qumn quidem Plato recordationem esse
mit t>itae super/oris. nam in i/lo libro, qui irzscribitur Menon, pusionem
quendmn Socrates interrogat quaedam geometrica de dimensione
qumlrali. ad ea sic il/e responder ut puer, et ramen ita faclles interroga-
fiones stml, ut gradatim respondens eadem pert,eniat, quo si geometrica
didicissel. e:r quo efficltmlt Socrates, ul discere nihil a/iud sit nisi recordari.
quem locum multo etiam ac:curatius explical in eo senmme. quem habuit
eo ipso die. quo excessit e l'ila; docet enim que,wis, qui omnium rerum
l'lltlis esse t'ideatur, bene irzterrogtmtl respmzdentem dedarare se mm tum
ilia discere. sed reminiscendo recognoscere, nee t'ero fieri ul/o modo posse.
111 a jmeris tot rerum lllque tante~rum insitlls et quasi nmsig,wtas in mzimis
noti(mes. qtulS f:vvoiac; tocant, baberemus. nisi animus, ante quam in cor-
pus intnu,isset, in rerum cognitione l'igulsset. cum que nibil esset ... , ut om-
llibus locis a P/atcme disseritur- nibil enim putat esse, quod oriatur et in-
tereat, idque solwn esse, quod semper tale sit quale est (iotav appellat ille.
nos spec/em) -. non potuit tmimus htlec in corpore inc/usus adgnoscere,
tognita attulit; ex quo tam multarum rerum cognitionis admiratio
lo/litur. neque ea plmze 11/det tmimus. cum repente in tam insolitum tam-
que perturbatum domicilium inmigratil. sed cum se co/legit atque
/'('Ct'l!tllit. tum adgnoscit ilia reminisc:endo. itct nibil est aliud discere nisi
recurdari. Ego autem maiore etiam quodammodo memoriam admiro1' ...
150 MIDDLE PLATONISM
333. The first sentence of Cicero: Tusc. Disp. I. 59 (last sentence of text
(iv)) suggests that the writer has reported a theory without implying his per-
sonal approval. Thus, the theory of Forms in texts (ii) and (iii) may represent
his own conviction, whereas the version of it in (iv) may not. However,
Cicero may simply be affirming once more that, as a New Academic, he con-
siders all such doctrines probable rather than certain. Sec pp. 58-60.
334. For the terminology mens, animus see nn. 316, 320, and 323.
335. According to L. & S. contineri + ablative is a common expression in
Cicero for 'be contained in, be composed of, be supported by'. This seems to
be the meaning here.
CICERO 151
.:\36. The latin could imply (i) before the soul has entered this body. or (ii)
hc:fore the soul has entered body as such. Thus (i) might only signify that the
~oul has acquired its knowledge in a previous incarnation. However, the
remark at Cicero: Tusc. Disp. I, 58 that the soul cannot know the Forms fully
in an incarnate state shows that the writer intends sense (ii) here.
~~ -r. These passages on the theory of Forms have been extensively discuss-
ed in the modern literature. Sec especially W. Theiler: Die Vorbereitung des
Neup/atonismus, 2. Auflage (Berlin, 1964), pp. 16-19 and 38-43; luck: Der
.lkatlemiker Antiochos, pp. 28-44: Boyancc: 'le platonismc a Rome', pp.
2!1-245; W. Burkert: 'Cicero als Platoniker und Skeptiker. Zum
152 MIDDLE PLATONISM
Seneca
2.IINTRODUCTION
I. Seneca's influence during the Middle Ages was sustained (although not
really substantial until the twelfth century) and the reasons for this have been
investigated by modern scholars. A. Momigliano: Contrlbuto all storia deg/1
studi classici (Roma, 1955), pp. 13-32 has shown that there is no evidence
th;u the legend of his conversion to Christianity was current before the four-
teenth century, and so Seneca's reputation must have stemmed on the one
hand from the praise bestowed upon him by certain early Christian writers
like Tertullian and Lactantius, and on the other from the existence of some
apocryphal correspondence with St. Paul first mentioned by jerome which
became connected with the authentic Epistulae in the eleventh century. At
all events it is Seneca the moralist who is influential, although there is
C:\'idence for his use as an authority on natural science in the twelfth century.
For a good general survey of his influence see G. M. Ross: 'Seneca's
Philosophical Influence'. Seneca, edited by C. D. N. Costa (london, 1974),
pp. 116-165 who deals with three periods: pagan antiquity (influence on
Pliny's Natura/is Historia, Gellius, and Macrobius), Christian antiquity (Ter-
tullian. Lactantius, Martin of Braga, and Isidore of Sevilk). and the Middle
155
156 MIDDLE PLATONISM
12. This will especially be the case if the Influence of Posidonius on Seneca
is as great as some scholars suggest. See A. D. Leeman: 'Seneca and Posi-
donius. A Philosophical Commentary on Senela: Epist. 102, 3-19', Mne-
mosyne S ( 1952), pp. 57-79 and 'Posidonius the Dialectician in Seneca's Let-
ters', ibid. 7 ( 1954), pp. 233-240: M. Laffranque: 'Scnt:que et le moyen stoic-
isme', Aetas del Congreso lnternacional de Filosoffa en (onmemoraclon
de Seneca II (C6rdoba, 1966 ). pp. 185-19S: and other works cited inn. 8.
13. Seneca: Epist. 89, 8.
14./bid. 6S, 11-12.
15. Seneca: Nat. Quaest. IV 8, 6.
16. Seneca: Epist. 82, 9.
SENECA 161
2.21 THEOLOGY
(London. 1977), p. 121, n. I suggests that the Senecan passage reflects the
tcac.:hing of Eudorus via Arius Didymus' Epitome which may also be true. At
all events. the order presented by Seneca is more characteristic of the
Platonic than of the Stoic tradition. The second point is that of the three sub-
jcns Sencc.:a, to a greater extent than earlier writers, emphasizes the primacy
of ethics as a philosophical discipline. Thus, even the study of physics is pur-
Mil"d primarily with ethical ends in mind. See L. Thorndike: A History of
Jlagic tmd Experimental Science I (New York, 192.3). p. 101; Stahl: 'Die
.\'atura/es quaestiones Senecas. Ein Beitrag .. .' pp. 425, 428-429, 431-434.
H2H.~. 446 ff.; and F. P. Waiblinger: Senecas Naturales quaestiones.
Griecbisches Wissen und r6miscbe Form (Munchen, 1977), pp. 19-28. This
~hould he borne in mind throughout our remaining discussion. Thus, when
we c.:oncern ourselves exclusively with Seneca's physics, we are actually shif-
ting the center of gravity away from the writer's own viewpoint .
.H. Seneca: Epist. 89, 18.
166 MIDDLE PLATONISM
.. 1. Sec n. 39.
-!2. Sec n. 39 .
.f:\. Sec n. 40 .
.fi. Sec n. 39.
i';. Seneca: Nat. Quaest. II, 45. 1-3 .
.. 6. Ibid VII, 25. 2. The reference ro 'air' follows Haase's reading of the
text where Gerckc and Oltramare read 'breath' (anima). Fonunately. bmh
:1moum to the same thing: the Stoic corporeal pneuma which contrasts wirh
the incorporeal power described next. On the details of Seneca's physical
thc:orysecpp. 176-179 .
.. ., . Seneca: De Benef IV. 7. I. Cf. De Otio <;, <;,
168 MIDDLE PLATONISM
5 I. Seneca: Epist. 4 I, 2 prope est a te deus, tecum est, intus est. Ita dico,
l.ucili: sacer intra nos spiritus sedet, malorum honorumque nostrorum
obsencltor et custos; hie prout a nobis tractatus est, ita tws ipse tractat.
Ron us tero t.tir sine deo nemo est: an potest aliquis supra .fortutultn nisi ah
11/o adiutus exsurgere? 1//e dat consilia magnifica et erecta. In mwqtwque
tirontm bonorum '(quis deus incertum est) habitat deus'. The quotalion is
from Virgil: Aeneid. VIII. :\'52.
52. Seneca: Nat. Quaest. VII. 30. 3-4 Quota pars operis tanti nobis com-
170 MIDDLE PLATONISM
mittitur? Ipse qui isla tractat, qui condidit, qui totum hoc fundavit dedit-
que circa se, maiorque est pars sui operis ac melior, effugit ocu/os; cogita-
tione l'isendus est. Mu/ta praeterea cognata numini summo et vicinam sor-
tita potentiam obscura sunt aut fortasse, quod magis mireris, oculos
nostros et implent et effugiunt. Cf. ibid. I. pr. 3.
S3. Stahl: 'Die Naturales quaestiones Senecas. Ein Beitrag .. .', p. 437 'Der
deus impliziert nicht mehr materia. Dieser unbcgriindete, wie
selbstverstandlich erscheinendc Ubergang von monistischem zu
dualistischem Denken'; p. 438 'Die Annaherung des r()mischen Stoikcrs an
platonische Denkformen'; p. 439 'Seneca entwirft hicr in platonischer
Bildersprachc cin Reich der Transzendenz', etc.
S4. G. Scarpat: La Lettera 65 di Seneca. Secunda edizione (Brescia, 1970),
pp. 146-154. Both Scarpat and the previous author usc the important
Epistula 65 as part of their evidence regarding Seneca's philosophical posi-
tion, although their arguments are based on many other texts as well. The dif-
ficulty with Epistulu 65 (to be discussed in detail below) is that its self-
declared Platonism docs not seem to reflect Seneca's regular viewpoint.
SENECA 171
'i5. All four classes are listed by Sextus Empiricus: Adv. Math. X, 218 (SVF
11, 331) 'Of the things which are "something" they say that some are cor-
poreal. some incorporeal. Four kinds of incorporeal are listed: expression,
void, space, and time' (tcilV yap twci>v q~aoi tci ~tv Elvat o<i>~ata tci lit
aoci>~ata, tci>V St aoro~citrov ttooapa &iBn Katapt6~0UVtal WI; AeKtOV Kai
K&vov Kai t6nov Kai xp6vov). For the 'expressions' as incorporeal see further
Sextus Empiricus: Adr. Math. VII, 38 (SVF II, 132); Sextus Empiricus: Adv.
.Hath. XI. 224 (SVF II, 170): and Alexander of Aphrodisias: In Top. IV. 30 I,
I 9 (SVF 11. 329). For time and the void see Arius Didymus: Epit. Phys. fr. 2'i
(SVF 11, 503 = DG 460, 18-461, 3) and Diogenes Laertlus: Vit. Phi/us. VII,
140 (SVF I, 95).
'i6. See pp. 823-82').
'i7. The oldest doxography seems to be that upon which Cicero depends at
172 MIDDLE PLATONISM
De Nat. Deor. I, 30 (DG 5.37a2-9) 'In the Timaeus Plato says that it is impossi-
ble to name the father of the world; in the Laws he declares that one should
make no inquiry at all regarding God's nature. Further, he wishes God to be
understood as without body' (in Timaeo patrem buius mundi nominari
11eget posse, In Le~:um autem libris quid sit om11ino deus anquiri oportere
non censeat. Quod vero sine corpore ullo deum vult esse (probably Cicero
himself is responsible for the addition of the Greek word aaro1-1aTov after the
end of the quotation.)). This doxography- which H. Diels its editor entitled
Vetusta Placila - is probably the basis of the later Placita of Aetius who
speaks of incorporeality in the following Platonic contexts: Plac. I, 3, 21 (DG
288a4-6 cf. b4-6) 'A Form is an incorporeal substance in the thoughts and im-
aginations of God' (i6ta 6 OUa{a clCJroi!UTO<; ~V TOi<; V01'!1!UCJ\ Kai Taic; cpav-
Taoiatc; TOU 9eou). (Cf. Plac. I, 10, I (DG 308a16 and b16)); Plac. l, 7, 31 (DG
304b26-30 cf. a26-30) 'God is intellect, a separate Form. By "separate" one
means unmixed with any matter and associated with nothing corporeal'
(vouc; ouv 6 9e6c;, xwplaTov E6oc; TO 6 xwptaTov aKouta9w TO cll!lYc; ncia11c;
0All<; Kai l!fl6vi TWV CJW!!UT\KWV CJU1!1t1tAEyi!SVOV). See also the doxographies
in Hippolytus: Pbilos. 19 (DG 567, 14 ff.) and Galen: Hist. Pbilos. 16 (DG
608, 16 ff.) both of which explicitly contrast Platonic and Stoic viewpoints.
58. See Diogenes Laertius: Vit. Pbilos. VII, 134 (SVF II, 299) 'They say that
there is a difference between principles and elements. Principles are
ungenerated and indestructible, elements are destroyed at the conflagration.
Moreover, the principles are Incorporeal and formless, the elements have
been formed' (6tacptpetv 6& cpamv O.pxac; Kai aTotxeta' Tac; !lEV yap dvat
cly&VT\TOU<; Kai acp9cipTOU<;, Ta 6 CJTOl'X&ia KaTa TTtV bC7tUpWCJ\V cp9&ipa9at.
cilAa Kai clCJW!!dTOU<; dvat Tci<; apxac; Kai al!6pcpouc;, Ta 6 1!&1!0P<PWCJ9at).
That the principles discussed here are the primal active and passive causes
seems to be shown by comparing the following texts: Sextus Emplricus: Adv.
Math. IX, 76 (SVF II, 311) discussing the reasons for the view that there is 'a
SENECA 173
certain power which pervades the universe ... there exists, then, a power
which is self-moving in itself, and this must be divine and eternal' (&UvaJ.L{v
nva 6t'atmi~ 7tEij)Ol'rTJKUiav ... fan tt~ cipa Ka9'tautl')v autOKtVTJTO~ &UvaJ,1t~.
iitt~ liv EiTJ 9Eia Kai ai6to~)- thus, the Stoic active cause is 'eternal'; Arius
Didymus: Epit. Pb_vs. fr. 20 (SVF I, 87 = DG 457, 25-458, II) reporting the
doctrine of Zeno, Chrysippus, and Posidonius that 'the substance of all things
is primal matter, which is totally eternal' (ouaiav 6& Elvat tl')v tcilv llvtwv
7tQVT(I)V 1tPolTTJV UATJV, taUTTJV 6& 7tciaav ai6tov)- thus. the Stoic passive prin-
ciple is also 'eternal'. In both these texts the notion of 'eternal' corresponds
to that of 'ungenerated and indestructible' in the passage of Sextus Empiricus.
Cf. Arius Didymus: Epil. Pbys. fr. 21 (SVF II, 413 = DG 459. 7) 'the princi-
ple, Logos, and eternal power'(~ clPXil Kai 6 A6yo~ Kai ~ aioto~ &UvaJ.Lt~); fr.
29 (SVF 11, 528 = DG 465, 1-3) on the creativity of Zeus; and fr. 37 (SVF 11,
S99 = DG 469, 18-25) on the cosmic cycles.
59. The following process may have taken place in the minds of the dox-
ographers or their immediate sources. It was orthodox Stoic doctrine that the
active and passive principles were 'eternal' (ai6tot) or more precisely
'ungenerated and indestructible' (aytVTJtot Kai ciq>9aptot). See Plutarch: De
Stoic. Repugn. 38, 1051f (SVF III, Antipater 33) on the indestructibility of
<;od. However, the same terminology had also been employed by the
Platonists to describe God and the Forms, and had been associated in other
texts with the Parmenidean One. See Aetius: Plac. IV, 7, S (DG 393al2) on
the God of Pythagoras and Plato; Arius Didymus: Epit. Pbys. fr. I (DG
i-l7a8-19) 'Besides all living creatures there is an ungenerated and indestruc-
tible living creature ... the Form is an eternal substance, the cause and princi-
ple of each thing being what it is' (7tapa 7tQVta ~<\)a ~<\)OV aytVTJtOV Kai
liq>9aptOV ... Elvat 0& tl')V !6tav af6tOV oua(av, a!t(av Kai apxl'Jv toii fKa<JtOV
e:lvat totoiitov, ora eativ autl'!); Hippolytus: Philos. 11 (DG 564, 19-20); and
174 MIDDLE PLATONISM
ps.-Piutarch: Strom. 5 (DG 580, 24) on the One of Parmenides. This led to an
assimilation of the Stoic and Platonic positions to such an extent that even
the attribute 'incorporeal' - which fitted the metaphysical principles of
Platonism but was somewhat inconsistent with the physical theory of the
Stoics- began to be applied to the active and passive principles of Stoicism.
This is perhaps documented by the text of Diogenes Laertius cited in the
previous note. The process of assimilation was no doubt aided in the minds
of the doxographers by the fact that the Stoics already postulated incor-
poreality for expressions, space, time, and the void.
60. See pp. 161-162.
61. Seneca: C(msol. ad Helv. H. :\ and Nat. Qtwest. VII. 2 c;. For these
passages see pp. 166-167 and 820-822. There is also an apparent reference to
incorporeality in the lost De Superstitione (quoted by Augustine: Civ. Dei VI,
10 (CCSL 47, 181-183 ): 'Shall I tolerate either Plato or the Peripatetic StraU>,
of whom one maintains that God is without body, the other that he is
without soul?'(Ego feram aut Platonem aut Peripateticum Stratonem,
quorum alter fecit deum sine corpore, alter sine animo?).
SENECA 175
67. Cf. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 93 (Augusrine: Civ. Dei VI, 9 (CCSL 47, 178-181))
for lhe inrerprelalion of Liber. There are no exacl parallels lO Seneca's imer-
prerarions of Hercules and Mercury in rhe exram Varronian fragmems.
68. Seneca: De Benef IV, 8, 2 'Whichever way you rurn, you will see God
coming ro meel you. Norhlng is void of him, and he fills his own work'
(Quocumque te flexeris, lbi ilium tJ/debis occurrentem tlbi; 11ihil ab 1/lo
vacat, opus suum ipse implet).
69. This Sroic (and wilh Amlochus also Plalonic) physical lheory has been
described in connecrion wilh Cicero on p. 90 ff. Seneca's version adds
norhing lo rhe rradilional scheme.
70. Seneca: Epist. 65, 2 'Our Sroics, as you know, maimain rhal rhere are
rwo principles in rhe universe from which all lhings are made: cause and mar-
rer. Mauer remains inerl, prepared for all lhings yel des lined lO idleness. if no
one moves il. Cause however, by which we mean reason, forms mauer. rurn-
ing il whichever way h wishes, producing various rhings from h. Thus, rhere
musr be, in rhe case of each lhing, something from which il comes, and rhen
somerhing by which ir comes ro be. The Iauer is rhe cause, rhe former rhe
mauer' (Dicunt, ut scis, Stoict' nostri duo esse in re1um natura ex quibus
omnia fimtt. causam et mater/am. Materia facet ine1s. res tld nnmia
parctta, cessatura sf nemo mor,eat; ,ausa autem. id est ratio, materiamfor-
mtlt et quocumque tult terstlt, ex /1/(l ttlr/(l opertl pmducit. Esse ergo debet
wulefiat aliquid, deinde a quo fiat: hoc causa est. 1/lud nwterill).
SENECA 177
-1. /IJid. 65, 23-24 'Indeed all things are composed of matter and God.
<iod controls that which surrounds him and follows him as ruler and leader.
For that which acts, namely God, is more powerful and worthy than matter,
which is passive in relation to God. God's place in the world is analogous to
soul's place in man' (nempe unltersa e:'C materilt et ex tleo constam. Deus
isla tempera/ quae circumfusa rectorem sequuntur et ducem. Potent/us
autem est ac pretiosus quod facit, quod est deus, quam materia patiens del.
!}llt'm in boc mundo locum deus obtinet, bunc in homine animus).
""'2. Seen. 70.
-~.Seen. 71 and Seneca: Epist. 89, 16 'The physical part of philosophy is
divided into two: corporeal and incorporeal. And each of these is divided in-
to its own levels, so to speak. The topic of corporeals is divided first into
these levels: things which produce and things which are produced from
them. The latter consist of the dements. The topic of elements itself, as some
think. is undivided, but according to others, is divided into matter. the cause
whil"h moves all things, and the clements' (Ntlfum/is pms pbilosopbiae in
duo sdnclitur, corpora/ia et incorporaliCI; utraque dividtmtur in suos, ut
ita diaun. grtulus. Corpo,.,tm locus in bos primum, in ea quae faciunt et
tJuae ex bis gignuntur - gignuntur autem elemenftt. Ipse de elementis
locus. ut quiclam putant, simplex est. ut quidam. in materiCim et causam
IJIIIIIianwtetlfem et element a ditiditur).
""'-f. Seen. 70.
""'5. Seen. 71.
7 6. Seneca: Epist. 65, 12 'But we now seek the primary and general cause.
This must be simple, since matter is also simple. We ask what the cause is. It Is
the reason which is active, that is to say God' (Sed nos nunc primam et
swneralem quaerimus causam. Haec simplex esse debet; nam et materia
simp{(,, est. Quaerimus quid sit causa? ratio scilicet faciens. id est deus).
-::o-,. See nn. 71, 76 and Seneca: Nat. Quaest. J, pr. 16 'How powerful is
God? Does he form matter himself, or does he employ what is already there?
Which comes first; does reason determine matter. or matter reason?' (quan-
tum deus Jmssit; mater/am ipse sibi fonnet an data utatur; utrum utro sit
/Jrius, materiae supervenerit ratio an materia ration/).
178 MIDDLE PLATONISM
to one another, books 1-11 dealing with contrasting roles of fire, books lii-IV
A with water, books IV 8-V with air, and book VI with earth.
HH. For fire and air see ibid. V, 6, 1-2, for fire ibid. III, 13, I, and for air
ibid. II, 4. I.
H9. See Seneca: Epist. 65, 24 and De Olio 4, 1-2.
90. Seneca: De Vit. Beat. B, 4.
180 MIDDLE PLATONISM
97. It is perhaps W. Theiler who deserves the most credit for bringing
Seneca's Eplstulae 58 and 65 to the attention of students of the history of
philosophy in late antiquity. His important book entitled Die Vorbereitung
ties Neuplatonismus, 2. Auflage (Berlin/Zurich, 1964) includes a lengthy
opening chapter which is primarily an expanded commentary on these two
letters. My own discussion owes more to his account than can be
acknowledged in detail as well as to the later treatments of E. Bickel: 'Senecas
llrie.fe <;R und 6<;. Das Antiochus-Posidonius-Problem', Rheinisches Museum,
:">Jeue Folge I 03 ( 1960). pp. 1-10 and Scarpat: op. cit., p. I 03 ff.
98. Seneca: Epist. 58, 6-8. It is as difficult to find English equivalents for
ouaia and 6v as it is to find Latin ones, and so I have opted to leave the Greek
terms (as well as Seneca's Latin equivalents) untranslated at this point, allow-
ing their meaning to emerge from the general context of the argument.
However, the renderings of l'lv = quod est as 'being' or 'the existent', and of
6vm = quae sulll as 'beings', 'existents', or 'things' can be accepted provi-
sionally.
182 MIDDLE PLATONISM
(v) It can mean 'things which exist in the usual sense of the
term' (quae communiter sunt). Examples of these are the ob-
jects which most immediately concern us: men, cattle, proper-
ty.J07
(vi) The sixth meaning is 'things which are quasi-existent'
(quae quasi sunt). Examples of these are the void and time.tos
This complex ontological classification by Seneca - it is the
most detailed example surviving from this period - has been
extensively discussed in the modern scholarship, attention be-
ing focused on two principal questions which are obviously not
unconnected: what are the sources of the scheme, and what en-
tities precisely come in each of the six divisions? E. Bickel at-
tempts to trace the doctrine back to Plato's Timaeus alone, the
existent of class (i) signifying the unchanging model of which
there can be an irrefutable account, that of class (ii) the
Demiurge, that of class (iii) the transcendent Forms embraced in
the intelligible living creature, that of class (iv) the immanent
Forms entering into the Receptacle, that of class (v) the sensible
world, and that of class (vi) matter. 109 The establishment of
these parallels is a striking example of scholarly ingenuity, yet it
must be admitted that - if we read the Senecan text with the
care which it deserves - some of the identifications seem forc-
ed. Thus, the equation of Plato's unchanging model with the ex-
istent of class (i) represents a viable interpretation of the present
passage, but that of Plato's Demiurge with the existent of class
(ii) fails to explain the peculiar character of the Senecan God as
that which surpasses all other beings; that of Plato's transcen-
dent Forms with the existents of class (iii) seems to conflict with
Seneca's clear statement that the Idea is the 'shape' (facies) of
the object which is being depicted: in other words it is the im-
110. Although he admits that the use of Plato Is not simply direct but
mediated through Posidonius.
Ill. P. Hadot: Porpbyre et Victorinus(Paris, 1968), pp. 156-16.3.
112. According to Hadot, a confusion has been imported into the scheme
by Seneca in giving as illustrations of the 'things which do not exist' which
form one species of the genus 'something' imaginary things like centaurs. As
emerges from a careful study of Sextus Emplricus: Adv. Math. I, 15-19 (see
Hadot: op. cit., p. 162,n. I), the Stoles considered these 'things which do not
exist' to be the incorporeals: space, time, the void, expressions. This group
was opposed to 'things which exist' exemplified by the corporeal realities of
Stoic physics. Both these groups were then subsumed as species of the genus
'something. Yet this is not the end of the classification, since the latter group
was opposed to 'the not something' exemplified by imaginary things such as
chimaeras. Finally, both these groups were subsumed as species of the genus
'concepts', That Seneca has confused the first two genera in the Stoic scheme
186 MIDDLE PLATONISM
(rtot6v), 'state' (7tCoc; ~xov), and 'relative state' (rtpoc; ti 7tCoc; ~xov)
would be expected to appear .114
It would seem that Hadot's interpretation of Seneca's on-
tology as a mixture of Platonic and Stoic elements is substantial-
ly correct. One might perhaps only take issue with his accep-
tance of the view that the existents of classes (iii) and (iv) repre-
sent the transcendent and immanent Forms respectively .115
Thus, in a metaphysical sense it seems clear from Seneca's own
description that the contrast between Idea and Form is not
equivalent to that of first and second intelligibles which occurs
later in Albinus' Didasca/icus.116 Rather, the contrast is bet-
ween the pattern contained in a natural object and the outline
derived from that pattern embodied in an artifact which im-
itates it.117 Even if Seneca believes that the Idea is contained in
the divine mind as seems likely on the basis of remarks
elsewhere, 118 this takes us nowhere beyond the position of An-
119. For Posidonius see Bickel: op. cit .. pp. 1-20, for Antiochus see
Theiler: op. ell .. p. 37 ff., and for Eudorus see Dillon: op. cit .. pp. 135-13 7. A
detailed examination of the various possibilities can be found in Scarpat: op.
ell .. pp. 94-101.
120. For general bibliography on this Epistula seen. 97.
SENECA 189
124./bid. 65.7-8.
125./bid. 65.9-10.
126. Ibid. 6<;, ..., /lis quintam Plato adicit exemplar. quam ipse '/dean
tmcat; hoc est enim ad quod respiciens artijex id quod deslinabal ejfecit.
Nibil cmtem ad rem pertinet utrum joris balJeut exemplar ad quod rejerat
oculos em intus. quod ibi ipse nmcepit et posuit. Haec exemplar/a rerum
omnium deus intra se babet rwmerosque Utlitersorum quae a~entla sunt et
modos metlte nmplexus est; plenus bls fiJ!.W'is est quas Plato 'ideas' ap-
pe/lat. imnorlales, inmut(lfJiles, inf"ligabiles. ltaque homines quidem
pereunt. ipsa cmtem JJunuttlitas, cui quam JJomo ejjitll{llltr, permanet. et
bominibus /aboranliblls, interetmtibus, ilia nibil palitur.
SENECA 191
It is possible that one should :>lso connect I matt~rial and class (vi) on the basis
of Epist. '5H, 22-23. However, the language is so imprecise as to render the
equation hazardous. At all events, classes (i) and (v) of the earlier scheme have
no obvious relations with the later one.
194 MIDDLE PLATONISM
2.33 CONCLUSIONS
134. Pla10 does not postulate a final cause in any systematic way.
However, Seneca is prepared w complete his scheme at this point, Epist. 65.
I 0 bono nulla cuiusquam boni invidia est recalling Plato: Tim. 29e aya9Q>
of: otiOEic; 7tEpi OOOEVOc; oOot7tOTE eyyiyvETQl cp96voc;.
135. The problem of Seneca's sources for the scheme in Epistula 65 is
analogous with that regarding the sources of Epistula 58. See pp. 187-188.
136. For illustrations of these see nn. 57. 58 and 59.
SENECA 195
Gellius
3.1 INTRODUCTION
199
200 MIDDLE PLATONISM
according to nature'" (q>li01) by using etymology as the starting point for ex-
amining the natures of things. Nigidius fragments have been collected by A.
Swoboda: Publii Nigidfi Flguli operum re/iquiae (Vienna, 1889).
II. Gellius: Noct. Attic. I, 3. I 0-29. Cicero is also mentioned in connection
with his adaptation of Panaetius at Ibid. XIII, 28, 1-4, although on this occa-
sion the reference is a more favorable one.
12. Ibid. Ill, 10, 1-17. Among other references to Varro's scientific
sheories, Gellius cites his geometrical definitions at ibid. I. 20, 1-9; his discus-
sion of the physiology of birth at ibi,l. Ill, 16, 6-14; and his definition of an
axiom at ibid. XVI. 8, 6.
13./bid. V, 12. 13. ThereferenceistoVirgil: Georg. IV, 6-7. That Virgil's
poetry is full of valuable philosophical and scientific doctrine is a notion very
characteristic of Gellius' discussions, and is also elaborated to fantastic
lengths by writers of later antiquity such as Macrobius and Servius both of
whom knew Gcllius. It is to a large extent a projection into the Roman con-
20-l MIDDLE PLATONISM
21. Ibid. XVI. 8, 1-17. For another discussion of logic see Ibid. XVI. 2,
1-13.
22. A useful brief survey of the state of our knowledge regarding Plato's
writings in this period can be found in P. de Lacy: Plato and the Intellectual
Life of the Second Century A.D.'. Approaches to the Second Sophistic (Papers
presented to tbe I 05th Annual Meeting of the American Pbilologi,al
Association). edited by G. W. Bowersock, (University Park, PA, 1974) pp.
1- Ill.
23. Gellius: Noct. Attic. II, 18, 2-3.
20H MIDDLE PLATONISM
1. The influence of Apuleius upon later antiquity (pagan and Christian) and
the Middle Ages has been studied from at least partial viewpoints by a number
of modern scholars although there is no single adequate treatment of the
whole question. This influence can be assessed from one point of view by ex-
amining the manuscript tradition. The philosophical works were transmitted
separately from the rest of the corpus - the two groups only being reunited
in the fourteenth century - and for the manuscript tradition of the former
one may consult: P. Thomas: Apulei Platonici Madaurensis opera quae
supersuntlll (Leipzig, 1908). pp. v-xiv and J. Beaujeu: Apulee. Opuscules
philosophiques et fragments, texte etabli, traduit et com mente (Paris, 197 3),
pp. xxxv-xliv. The remains are scanty before the eleventh century, but
thereafter the number of manuscripts increases rapidly. One of the most in-
teresting of the early survivals is the Leidensis Vossianus I 0 (first noted by
Beaujeu: op. cit., p. xxxix) in which the Apuleian philosophical works occur
together with Cicero's translation of the Timaeus and Calcidius' commen-
tary. The influence of Apule ius can also be assessed by collecting the quota-
tions or references in later writers. For brief surveys of the influence of the
philosophical texts see C. Weyman: Studien zu Apuleius utzd seinen
N(lCbahmern (Sitzungsbericbte der Bayeriscbetz Akademie der
Wissenschajten 1893/2) (Munchen, 189.'\), pp. 3Hl-.'\B';: S. Costanza: Lajor-
trma di Apuleio tzell'etii. di mezzo (Palermo. 1937); E. H. Haight: Apuleius
and his Influence (New York, 1927); and C. Moreschinl: Apuleio e it
Plutonismo (Firenze, 1978), pp. 219-266. Among examples of the use of
Apuleius by later writers might be mentioned: (i) Ancient pagan writers. a)
Definite citations. Fulgentius, the Lucani Scholia Bernensia (see Beaujeu: op.
215
216 MIDDLE PLATONISM
H. The Metumorpboses.
9. Apuleius: II pol. I 0. Cf. ihid. 1.~ and 4 I; and F/or. IS.
218 MIDDLE PLATONISM
10. See A. D. Nock ct A.-). Festugiere: Corpus Hermeticum II. Texte etab/i
et tratluit Paris. 1946), pp. 2 ';9 and 277.
II. Cassiodorus: lnst. II, 3, 12 and Isidore of Seville: Etym. II, 28, 22.
12. Sec ). Rcdfors: Ec/Jtbeitskritiscbe Untersucbtmg der apuleiscben
Scbriften De Platone rmd De mundo (Lund. 1960), p. ;, n.2.
13. The scholarship on this question has been summarized by Sullivan: op.
cit .. pp. 9-14 (who accepts authenticity) and Beaujeu: op. cit .. pp. vii-viii
(who rejects it).
APULEIUS .219
22. Three dialogues are cited by name in the Apologia: the Pbae(/rus
(Pbaedr. 247b-c at Apol. 64), Timaeus (Tim. 82a-86a at Apol. 49-50). and
Laws (Leg. XII, 955d-956a at Apol. 65), the first and last including Greek
quotations, the second involving paraphrase. There are also unmistakable
quotations in Greek of the Alcibiades I (Ale/b. I. 121e-122a at Apol. 25) and
Epistula II (Epist. II, 312e at Apol. 64) although neither text is identified by ti-
tle. More allusive references are to the Symposium (Symp. 180d at Apol. 12
;md -~vmp. 202e at Apol. 43). Charm/des (Charm. 157a at Apol. 26), and
rimaeus (Tim. 59d at Apol. 4 I). Other works of Apuleius draw freely upon
Plato's doctrine without the use of direct citation, for example De Platone et
eius Dogmate employing the Phaedo, Phaedrus, and Tfmaeus, and De Deo
Socratis using the Symposium and the pseudo-Platonic Epinomis. Of course,
it is possible to argue that in passages where Apuleius is drawing freely upon
Plato's doctrines he may not be using the dialogues themselves but some in-
termediate doxographical sources. Apuleius' use of such materials being in-
dicated by a quantity of other evidence. However. it is perverse to imagine
that he derives his knowledge of Plato entirely from compendia, since the
quotations in the Apologia, his own activity as translator of the Phaeclo, and
the independent evidence of the availability of the dialogues during the se-
nmd century. all point to familiarity with the original texts.
23. Apuleius: Flor. 18.
222 MIDDLE PLATONISM
27. Porphyry: VII. Plot. 14, 12 and Priscianus Lydus: Solut. ad Cbosr. pr.
42, 9-10. The reference to Lavin/ in the latter text is almost certainly a scribal
corruption of Alv(b)lni, in which case the passage is further evidence for the
association of Gaius and Albinus. See J. Whittaker: Parisinus Graecus 1962
and the Writings of Albinus', Phoenix 28 ( 1974), pp. 326-328.
28. Proclus: In Tim. I, 340, 24 and Galen: De Anim. Morb. 8, 41. Galen
refers to his early studies not with Albinus but with an unnamed disciple of
Gaius. Albinus is, however, specifically mentioned at Galen: De Propr. Libr.
2, 16.
29. Seen. 23.
30. Especially the reference in Proclus: In Tim. I, 340, 24. It should be
noted that it is the link between Galus and Albinus which is certain, and not
the link between Galus and the Didascallcus, since Albinus' authorship of
that work Is not fully established. All manuscripts of the treatise attribute it to
a certain 'Aiclnous', but it has been customary among modern scholars to
treat this subscription as the result of a scribal error for 'Aibinus' at some
point in the tradition. See the discussion of J. Freudenthal: 'Der Platoniker
Albinos und der falsche Alkinoos', Hellenisliscbe Studien III (Berlin. 1879),
p. 242 ff. The arguments for the identification of 'Aicinous' and Albinus are
the following: (i) the putative scribal corruption noted above, (ii) similarity of
doctrine between the Didasca/icus and testimonia regarding Albinus In Ter-
tullian and Proclus, and (iii) similarity of style between the Didasca/icus and
another indisputably authentic work of Albinus entitled the lsagoge. This
generally accepted view has, however, been challenged recently by M.
Giusta: 'AA.j3ivou 'EnttOf..ll't o 'AAKtv6ou dt5aaKaAtK6~'?, Alii della Ac-
wdemia delle Scienze di Torino, Classe di scienze morali, storicbe e
/ilologicbe 95 (1960-61), pp. 167-194 and J. Whittaker: 'Lost and Found.
224 MIDDLE PLATONISM
SS. As Regen: op. cit.. p. 51 ff. and Beaujeu: op. cit., p. xxiii ff. have noted,
the presence of such schemata and their agreement with one another in all
the works of the Apuleian corpus are factors which speak forcefully in favor
of the authenticity of the disputed texts.
S6. Apuleius: De Deo Socr. I, I IS Plato omnem naturam rerum, quod
eius ad animalia praecipua pertifletll, trifariam divisit censuitque esse
summos deos. Summum, medium et infimum fac intel/egas non modo loci
APULEIUS
the nature of the middle and lowest levels by turning to the text
of De Platone et eius Dogmate. This informs us that 'the kinds
of animate beings themselves are divided into four species, of
which one is of the nature of fire such as we see in the cases of
the sun. moon, and other heavenly bodies. Another is of the
quality of air - Plato calls this the race of demons. The third is
composed of water and earth: a mortal and corporeal race
divided into a species "dwelling in the earth" and a species
"dwelling on the earth" - thus have I translated yyetov and
niyetov - the former comprising trees and other plants which
pass their life rooted to the ground, the latter those creatures
which the earth nourishes and sustains'. S7 Since the fourth
species announced at the beginning of the passage turns out to
he a subdivision of the third, we seem to have a triadic schema
corresponding to that in the previous text. In this case we have
discovered the nature of the middle and lowest levels described
earlier together with the additional fact that each of the three is
characterized by at least one physical element.
The theory that the world of animate beings is divided into
gods who are fiery. <.lemons who are aery. and mortals who are
watery and earthy is attributed by Apuleius to Plato. However,
there is certainly no authentic text by the latter which outlines
such a theory. What Apuleius seems to have done is to combine
disclusicme terum eliam naturae dignitate, quae et ipsa neque uno neque
gemino modo sed pluribus cemitur. Ordlrl tamen manifeslius fuit a loci
clispositicme. Nam proinde ut maiestas postulabat. diis inmorta/ibus
caelum diccuit.
';'7. Apuleius: De Plat. I. I I, 204 lam ipsa animantium genera in quat-
ltwr species ditiduntur. qua rum una est ex natura ignis eiusmodi qut~lem
solem ac lunam videmus ceterasque siderum stel/as, alterum e.x aeria
Cftllllilate - bane etimn daemcmum dicit -. tertium ex t~qua terraque
nmlescere; et mortale genus corporum ex eo dividi terrenum atque terrestre
- sic enim yyttov et btiyttov censui nuncupanda - terrenumque esse ar-
lmrum ceterclrumque frugum, quae bumi fixae titam trahunt, terrestr/Cl
tero quae alit ac sustinet tel/us.
2:\0 MIDDLE PLATONISM
necessarily memioning all three terms) are De Deo Socr. 4, 127; 6, 134; 12.
146-13,148;andDeP/at. 1,12,206
62. Apuleius: De Deo Socr. I, 116- 3. 124 quos quidem deos cae/itespar-
lim visu usurpamus, alios intellectu vestigamus. Ac visu quidem cernimus
'tos, o clarissima muP~di /lumina, /abeP~tem caelo quae due ills ammm' ...
Est aliud deorum genus, quod natura visibus nostris denegavit, nee non
lumen intel/ectu eos rlmabundi contemplamur, acie mentis acrius con-
temp/antes. Quorum in numero sunt ill/ duodecim situ nominum in duo
tersus ab Ennio coartati: 'Juno, Vesta. Minerva, Ceres, Diana, Venus,
!'rJars. I Mercuri us, Jovis, Neptunus, Vulcanus, Apollo' ceterique id genus ...
Quorum parePltem, qui omP~ium rerum dominator atque auctor est,
solutum ab omnibus nexibus patiendi aliquid gerendive, nulla tice ad
a lieu ius rei munia obstrictum. cur ego nunc dicere exordiar ....
232 MIDDLE PLATONISM
63. Cf. Plato: Leg. XI, 930~:-9.~ Ia and ps.-Piato: Epin. 9R4d.
64. Plato: Tim. 4Ia.
6S. Ibid. 28c.
66.1bid. 4Ia.
67. Ibid. 3Rc-d and .Jod-4Ia.
APllLEil!S H3
The third Apuleian schema is, like the second, not totally in-
dependent of the original tripartition of reality. However. in
this case we find not a further triadic subdivision of its highest
term but rather a dyadic subdivision of its middle term. This
constitutes a triad when juxtaposed with a revised interpreta-
tion of the lowest term. According to De Deo Socratis: 'In a cer-
tain sense, even the human soul is called a demon while it yet re-
mains in the body. "Is it the gods who place such ardor in our
minds, Euryalus, or baneful desire arising to each as his god"?
Thus also a good desire of the soul is a good god. Thus, some
maintain, as I have already said, that those who have a good
demon - that is a soul perfect in virtue - those blessed ones
are called "eudaemones". You may call this a "genius" in our
language, a translation which I shall hazard even if it is not a
good one ... In a second sense, the human soul which has com-
pleted its earthly service and retires from the body is also a
species of demon. This was usually called a "lemur" in the old
Latin language, as I discover69 .... There is however another
68. Apuleius' distinction of the invisible and visible gods occurs again at
De Deo Socr. 4, I 28.
69. It is clear that within this second class of demons- human souls after
their carthl\' incarnation - further triadic subdivision is visualized. Thus.
Apulcius co~tinues his analysis by suggesting: 'Among these "lemurs" who
have hcen allotted the care of their descendants and rule their domain with a
quiet ami tranquil divinity is the so-called "familiar Jar". However. those
who hccause of their evil deeds in life have no abode and are punished by
unccrt:Jin wanderings and a kind of exile, the kind who rcpresem a vain tcr
ror for the good but a serious one for the bad, are normally called 'larvae''.
23-1 MIDDLE PLATONISM
'9. This state of affairs is not unconnected with the fact that we must draw
these later schemata from De Pia tone et eius Dogmate primarily whereas the
earlier schemata occurred mainly in De Deo Socratls. We have already noted
that there is a considerable difference in style between these two works.
Thus, De P/atone et eius Dogmate often reads like the hasty exposition of
partially digested handbook material, whereas De Deo Socratis is a careful ac-
t:ount of Apuleius' own religious beliefs. Seep. 217.
HO. Apuleius: De Plat. I, 5. 190 lnitia rernm esse tria arbitratur Plato:
deum et materiam (inabsolutam infonnem, nullt1 specie nee qualitatis
significatione distinctam). rerumqueformas. quas iota<; idem l'ocat [inab-
solutas infonnes, nulla specie nee qualitatis significatione distinctas]. I
h;l\e presented here the two possible versions of this text, J. Beaujeu reading
the sement:c together with the phrase in parentheses, P. Thomas reading it
together with that in brackets. For the significance of these different versions
seep. 2H6 ff.
23H MIDDLE PLATONISM
HI. The triadic schema of God, Matter. and Form which occurs not only in
Apuleius but in many other writers of late antiquity has been extensively
discussed in modern scholarship. See C. Baeumker: Das Problem der Materie
in der griecbiscben Pbilosopbie. Ein bistoriscb-kritiscbe Untersucbung
(Munster, 1890), p. 114 and n. 2: Theiler: op. cit. p. 1'i ff.; Will: op. cit., pp.
96-97; A. -J. FcstugiC:re: 'Lc Compendium Timaei de Galien'. Retitle des
etudes grecques 65 ( 1952), pp. JO'i-114; J. H. Waszink: 'Observations on Ter-
tullian's Treatise against Hcrmogcnes', Vigiliae Cbristitmae 9 ( 19'i'i), p. 130;
H. Dorrie: 'Die Frage nach dem Transzendenten im Millelplatonismus', Les
sources de P/otin (Fondation Hardt, Entretiens sur I'Antiquite class/que 'i)
(Vandoeuvres-Geneve, 1960), p. 205 ff.; ). Pepin: Tbeologie cosmlque et
tbeo/ogie cbretiemze (Ambroise, Exam. /, I, 1-4) (Paris, 1964), pp. 17-58:
Beaujeu: op. cit., pp . .254-.256: Dillon: op. cit., pp. 410-411; and Moreschini:
up. cit., pp. 69-70, 166, 174, n.ll6, and 178 ff.
APULEIUS 2.:\9
92. See if1id. 30c-31 b: 39e; and 50c-d. For an excellent discussion of these
passages in Plaw seej. PC:pin: 'Elements pour une histoire de Ia relation entre
l'intelligence et l'intelligible chez Platon et dans le neoplatonisme'. Re11ue
fJIJit~Jsopbique 146 (1956), pp. 42-43 and Tht!o/ogle cosmique et thtfologie
cbretienne (Ambroise, Exam./, 1. 1-4), pp. 22-24.
242 MIDDLE PLATONISM
93. For details regarding the doxographical tradition one should consult-
in addition to the work of H. Diels cited inn. 41 -the following studies: H.
Diels: 'Stobaios und Aetios', Rheinisches Museum 36 (1881), pp. 343-350;
Uberweg und Praechter: op. cit., pp. 10-26; ). Burnet: Early Greek
Philosophy, 4th edition (London, 1930), pp. 31-38; 0. Regenbogen:
'Theophrastos von Eresos', Paulys Realencyclopiidie der k/assischen Alter-
tumswissemchaft, Suppi.-Band 7 (Stuugart, 1940), col. 1536ff.: E. Zeller:
Outlines of the History of Greek Philosophy. 13th edition revised by W. Nes-
tle and translated by L. R. Palmer (London, 1931 ), pp. 4-8; A.-). Festugiere: La
riL,ilatiotz d'Hermes Trismegiste II: Le Dleu cosmique (Paris, 1949). pp.
345-369; A. Solignac: 'Doxographles et manuels dans Ia formation
philosophique de saint Augustin', Recherches augusliniennes I (Paris, 1958),
pp. 113-148; J. B. McDiarmid: 'Plato in Theophrastus' De Sensibus',
Phnmesis 4 ( 1959). pp. 59-70: 8. Wyss: Doxographie'. Reallexikon fiir An-
like zmd Christentum 4 (Stuttgart, 1959), col. 197-210: C. H. Kahn: Anax-
imarzder atzd the Origirzs of Greek Cosmology (London/New York, 1960),
pp. 11-24: G. S. Kirk and J. E. Raven: 7'he Presocralic Philosophers. A
Critical History uith a Selecliorz of Texts (Cambridge, 1962). pp. 1-7: I.
Opelt: 'Epitome'. Realle:~ikon fiir Antike zmd Chtisletztum 5 (Stuugart,
1962), col. 950-952: and W. K. C. Guthrie: A History of Greek Philosophy 1:
The Earlier Presocratics and the Pythagoreans (Cambridge, 1967), pp. xiii-
xiv.
APlJLEillS
writc:rs of the period that its presence in both Taurus and Apuleius is insuffi-
cient to establish a ddinitc connection between them.
I 0 I. In this list of doxographers I have included not only writers earlier
than Apukius but also contemporary and later ones. Although the latter arc
naturally not to be included among his sources, they are nevertheless
testimonies to the persistence of the tradition. The same reasoning moti\ates
my inclusion of Christian writers in the list of doxographers.
102. Hippolytus' account of Plato's teaching has aroused some interest
among scholars. See fur example the treatments in Dillon: op. cit., pp.
t liH lt and Moreschini: op. cit., pp. 178-185.
246 MIDDLE PLATONISM
Since the triadic schema of God, Matter, and Form was such a
commonplace of the doxographical tradition, a writer like
Apuleius could clearly have picked up the theory during any
elementary course in Platonism. Furthermore, perhaps this
discovery illuminates the earlier question whether God and the
Forms should be identified since the doxographers may well
have disseminated a definite view even in the absence of a clear
teaching on Plato's part?
I 03. The list of references to the threefold schema of God, Mauer, and
Forms should be supplemented by certain passages in the literature which
refer to a fivefold or sixfold schema. These Iauer seem to represent an expan-
sion of the simpler theory in order to include more Aristotelian elements. See
Seneca: Epist. 65, 3-10; Porphyry in Simplicius: In Phys. I, I. 10.35 - 11,3;
and Proclus: In Tim. I. 2, Iff. For a discussion of these texts sec Theiler: op.
cit., pp. 19-23.
APLJLEILJS
108. In the case of Albinus, the identification of God and the Forms seems
to have resuhed from an attempt to combine the demiurgic God of Plato and
the self-cognitivt: God of Aristotle. On this development see pp. 260-26.~.
109. Aetius: Plac:. I, 10, I (DG 308al6-17, 308b20-21) and I, 10, 3 (DG
309a2-4 ). Cf. ibid. I, 3. 21 (DG 288a4-6 and b4-6).
110. Hippolytus: Pbi/os. 19. 2-3 (DG 567 ,12-15).
Ill. Ps.-justin: Cohort. 7 (PG 6, 256A). That the author refers to God's
thoughts is suggested by Cyril of Alexandria who paraphrases the text at Con-
tra Julian. II (PG 76, <; 7 30).
APULEILJS
although the writer finds himself faced with exactly the same
contradictory statements as the previous authors, he postulates
the interesting hypothesis of a chronological evolution in
Plato's thought to reconcile them.
4.257 CONCLUSIONS
112. Apuleius: De Plat. l, l), 199 Sed illmn, jontem animarum omnium,
cae/estem cmimam, optimum et sapientissimam 11irtute esse genetricem,
subsert,ire etiam fabricator/ deo et praesto esse ad omt~ia i1wenta eius pro-
nun fiat.
APUl.EilJS 2';1
must also be the origin of demons. This means that the celestial
soul must be prior to the demonic class of the first schema and
to at least two classes of the third schema, its relation to the se-
cond and fourth schemata being more problematic. Finally, the
natural processes have also not been included in the earlier
schemata, although their character is such that they can only be
inserted at one point in the order of things. namely immediately
prior to the Matter of the fourth schema.tt3
The sources of the fifth schema are not difficult to specify.
Apuleius once again attributes the theory to Plato and, although
there is perhaps no single text from the dialogues which con-
tains all the necessary information, most of its elements can be
derived from a combination of passages. The text begins by
referring to a primary soul which is the source of all other souls,
a notion derivable from the Pbilebus where Socrates establishes
an analogy between macrocosm and microcosm: 'Whence does
our soul originate ... unless the body of the world which has the
same elements as our bodies although in all respects more
beautiful also has a soul?' (n68sv ... A.aj36v, sinsp ~f) -r6 yr. -roO
nav-roc; aro~a f~\iluxov <>v huyxavr., -ratmi yr. fxov -rou-r4> Kai fn
nav-ru KaA.A.iova ).tt4 That this universal soul has been created
by God is stated in the Timaeus where the Demiurge is said to
I 13. That the passage refers to a triadic schema of the kind described
would no doubt be contested by Moreschini who maintains that the intentcl
of the last line signify not God's creative labors but his thoughts or the Forms
in the divine mind. See his discussion atop. cit., pp. R6-87. This interpreta-
tion seems to me somewhat forced and only justifiable on the assumption
that the doctrine of Albinus: Didasc. 14, 3 can be equated with Apuleius'.
Sint:e the flimsy character of the 'School of Gaius' hypothesis makes this
equation questionable lO say the least, it seems best to interpret the present
passage in its most natural and non-technical sense.
114. Plato: Pbileb. 30a. The reference to the soul as 'source' ifons) pro-
h:lhly recalls Plato's ltTJYl'l at Pbaedr. .Z4;c. However, Plato speaks of a source
of motion and not of a source of souls.
252 MIDDLE PLATONISM
And the primary substances or essences are the first God, the
mind and the Forms of things, and the soul', 117 while another
states that 'Plato holds that the primary goods are the highest
God and that mind which he also calls vouc;'.11s These two texts
mention three terms which are by now familiar to us together
with a new term of uncertain meaning which is given in both its
Greek and Latin forms. The first God of course corresponds to
the highest God of the second schema and the God of the
fourth. the Forms are obviously identical with the Forms of the
fourth schema, and the soul can with equal certainty be iden-
tified with the soul of the fifth schema. The new element is the
mind. and regarding this we have to ask some important ques-
tions. Assuming that Apuleius intends this mind to be identified
with the Forms either as representing their totality or as a prin-
ciple which contains them, 119 do we equate the mind or Forms
with the first term in the schema: God, with the third term:
soul. or with neither? If the third possibility holds true, then we
are dealing with a further triadic schema which must somehow
be aligned with the earlier ones; but if the first or second
possibility holds true, then we have not so much a further
schema as a revised statement of existing doctrine. There is
perhaps no clear answer which can be extracted directly from
the Apuleian texts, and so we are once again impelled towards
possible sources or analogous statements in other writers in our
search for clarification.
1.20. The: Grc:ek term vouc; is diffkult to translate: hy a single: English word,
since in some texts it signifies a principle but in others it approximates to a
function. I have adopted two terms: 'intellect' and 'intelligence' to reflect
this ambivalence of meaning. In Plato the Iauer sense seems 10 predominate,
while in the doxographers and Neoplatonists the: reverse: is the: case.
12 I. Plato: Pbaed. 97b-c.
122. Plato: Leg. XII, 967h-c.
APULEIUS 255
aloof, devoid of intelligence' (ci>c; cii.118G>c; KiVT'Iatv Kai ~roi]v Kai '1/UXi]V Kai
cpp6V11atV ~ pq.&iroc; neta811a611E!Ja r(j> navrel.roc; 6vn 111'1 napeivat, 1111& ~iiv
auto J.111BE cppoveiv, cil.l.a OEJ.IVOV Kai aytov, VOUV OUK fxov, ciKtVllTOV ~atoc;
dvat;) However, even in this passage the close relation of intelligence and
soul is retained. On the whole doctrine see). H. Loenen: De Nous in bet
Systeem van Plato's Philosophie (Amsterdam. 19S I).
129. Aetius: Plt1c. I. 7. 3 I (DG 30-la 1-6 and b-23-27). Other references to
Plato's interpretation of intellect in Aetius occur at ibid. I. 3. 21 (DG 288a2
and b2-3) 'God is the intellect of the world' (6 &eeoc; vouc; ~OT! TOU KOOI!OU);
ibid. 1. 10, 3 (DG 309a 1-4) 'Plato maintains that the Forms are substances
separate from matter, existent in the thoughts and imaginings of God, that is
to say. intellect' (0/.<itrov xroptatcic; ti;c; lil.11c; ouaiac; rae; lBtac; uno/.aJ.IPcivEt
EV toic; VOtll!at Kai taic; cpavtaaiatc; TOU IJEOU, TOUTtan TOU VOU, U(jlEOt<i>aac;);
and ibid. 1.11,2 (DG 309a I S-17 cf. b 13-14) 'He considers the more important
cause to be "that through which". that is the efficient cause. which is in-
tellect' (KUPIWTEpov Bi: t'IYEiTat TO ucp'ou' TOUTO & ~v TO 7tO!OUV, 6 &an vouc;).
130. Ibid. l, 3. 8 (DG 282a 16). cr. ibid. 1. 3. B (DG 281 aB-12 and b6-to).
APlii.EiliS 257
ancients 'held the One to be above being and the source of being' (le unum
enim me/ius ente putantes eta quo le ens). On the former text seeP. Merlan:
From Platonism to Neoplatonism, 3rd edition (The Hague, 1968), pp.
96-140, and on the Iauer R. Klibansky and C. Labowsky: Procli Commen-
tarius in Parmenidem, Pars ultima adhuc inedita interprete Guillelmo de
Moerbeka. Ediderunt praefalione et adnotalionibus instmxerunt R. K. e/ C.
L. (London, 195 3 ). p. 86 and P. Merlan: 'Greek Philosophy from Plato to
Plot in us'. The Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medietal
Philosophy, edited by A. H. Armstrong (Cambridge, 1967), pp. 3032. In ad-
dition, E. R. Dodds: 'The Pannenides of Plato and the Origins of the
Neoplatonic One', Classical Quarterly 22 (1928). pp. 129-143 traces the in-
fluence of Speusippus' theory through the Neopythagorean tradition
represented by Eudorus and Moderatus.
133. It should also not be forgotten that Aristotle. another member of the
early Academy. desnibed his first principle as vouc; at Metaph. A 7.
1072bl4-30. etc.
AI'ULEIUS 259
134. Cicero: A cad. 29. For a full discussion of this text seep. 101 ff.
.260 MIDDLE PLATONISM
telligence' (Zftvrov 6 ~tW\Koc; vouv K60f.10U 7tupwov) and Varro: De Ling. Lat.
V. 59 (SVF I. 126) 'According to Zeno ofCitium the seed of animals is that fire
which is soul and intelligence' (sive, ut Zenon Citieus, animalium semen ig-
nis is. qui anima ac mens).
l.:\8. Albinus: Didasc. 10. 2-3. On the interpretation consult the following
studies: Witt: op. cit .. pp. 114-144; H. Dorrie: 'Zum Ursprung der
neuplatonischen Hypostasenlehre', Hennes 82 (1954), pp. 331-342; loenen:
Alhinus' Metaphysics. An Attempt at Rehabilitation. pp. 296-319 and 35-56:
II. Diirrie: Albinos. platonischer Philosoph des 2. Jahrhunderts'. Paulys
Realencyclopadie der klassiscben Altertumswissenscbajt. Suppl.-Band 12
(Stuttg:lrl, 1970), col. 14-22: J. Mansfeld: 'Three Notes on Albinus', Theta-Pi
I ( 19"'2) pp. 61-80; and Dillon: op. cit .. pp. 280-285.
262 MIDDLE PLATONISM
139. There has been considerable debate among modern scholars on the
question how many levels of intellect are postulated in Albinus' system. The
text which is at the heart of the controversy runs as follows (Didasc. 10, 2):
'Since intellect is better than soul, and intellect in activity which knows all
things simultaneously and eternally is better than intellect in potentiality. and
more beautiful than this is the cause of this and whatever might exist superior
to these. this would be the first God which is the cause of the eternal activity
of the intellect of the whole world' (brEi lit wuxilc; volic; fiJ..L&ivrov, voli lit toG
tv liuvaJ..LEt 6 Kat'tv&py&tav ncivta vo<i>v Kai dJ..La Kai fiEi, mutou lit KaUirov 6
ainoc; TOUTOU Kai on&p av ~n avrot&pro TOUT(I)V U(jl&OtT]KEV, oumc; av EiT] 6
npciltoc; 9&6c;, aittoc; unapxrov TOU ad tv&py&iv t(i> vq> TOU OUJ..Lnavtoc;
oupavoli). According to Witt: op. cit., pp. 128-129 there are three principles
above the level of soul: intellect in potentiality, intellect in activity, and the
cause. The interpretation of Dorrie: 'Zum Ursprung der neuplatonisc:hen
Hypostasenlehre', pp. 339-340 and 'Albinos. platonischer Philosoph des 2.
jahrhunderts' col. 20 is along the same lines. These scholars therefore expand
the number of principles and suggest that Albinus' first principle- prior to
the intellect in activity - is an anticipation of the Plotinian One. According
to Loenen: 'Albinus' Metaphysics. An Attempt at Rehabilitation'. pp. 305-309
there is only one principle above the level of soul: the cause. since intellect in
potentiality is only introduced hypothetically while intellect in activity cor-
responds to the highest phase of soul. The interpretation of Mansfeld: op.
cit .. pp. 61-67 develops this thesis further. These scholars accordingly reduce
the number of principles and bring Albinus' theory c:loser to the traditional
teaching of Plato and the doxographers. It is the view of the present writer
that the reductive interpretation makes the best sense of the text quoted and
avoids the need to introduce an elaborate hierarchy of principles which has
no relevance to the rest of Albinus' doctrine. However, the most appropriate
scholarly attitude is perhaps one of caution in regard to the whole question.
APLILEILJS 263
4.276 CONCLUSIONS
4. )4 The Demons
4.36 Matter/Forms/Numbers/Body
4.31 GOD/FORMS/MIND
143. Apuleius: De Plat. I, 6, 193. Cf. De Mundo 30, 3';7 'the ruler of all
things and father, whom only our thoughts perceive with the eyes of the
soul' (rex omnium et pater. quem tantummodo em/mae (JCIIIis nostrae
cogitationes tJident).
144. Apuleius: Apol. 64. Cf. De Plat. I, 5. 191 God's nature 'is impossible
to reveal to many' (in multos eam ermntic1ri non posse).
14<;. Apuleius: De Plat. I, <;, 190. Cf. Apol. 64 'speakable by nobody'
(nemini effabilis); De Deo Socr. 3. 124 God's nature 'has a greatness so in-
credible and ineffable that it cannot be expressed even a little owing to the
poverty of human language' (maiestatis incredibili quat/am nimietate et in-
effablli not! posse penuria senrwnls human/ quat,ls oratione 11el modlce
conprebendi). It should be noted that Apuleius says that God can be grasped
APUlEilJS 267
(quid sit deus ... tacere), 146 he stresses that the first principle lies
bevond the perceptive grasp. The contradiction between these
tw'o positions is reconciled either by postulating a special man-
ner of perceiving God 'intermittently, just as a bright light
flashes in the deepest darkness' (interdum, velut in artissimis
tenebris rapidissimo coruscamine lumen candidum inter-
micare)l47 or an indirect manner of perceiving him 'through the
traces of his divine works' (divlnorum operum vestigiis).14H On
all these points, Apuleius reveals himself to be a follower of
philosophical tradition, for the notion that God is perceptible
bv thought rather than sense is fundamental to Plato's doc-
trine, 149 the idea that God is ineffable can be derived easily from
the Parmenides, 15o Symposium, 151 Timaeus, 152 and Epistula
VIII'B and - as scholars such as E. R Doddsl54 and A.-J.
Festugierel55 have demonstrated - was established as a com-
Tyre (op. cit.. pp. 109-115). Celsus (op. cit.. pp. 115-123), Numenius (op.
cit., pp. 123-132), and the Cbaldaearz Oracles (op. cit., pp. 132-135).
Festugiere identifies as a significant feature of all this literature the coupling
of two apparently contradictory notions: (i) that God is the object of in-
tellect, and (ii) that God is unknowable. See op. cit., p. 98 (Aibinus), op. cit.,
p. 131 (Numenius), and op. cit., pp. 132-133 (Cbaldaean Oracles). He ex-
plains this contradiction by suggesting: 'II faut ici observer que Ia langue
philosophique platonicienne manquait d'un terme special pour designer ce
qui est seulement organe de J'intultlon mystique ... D'ou vient que le meme
mot vou~ sert a Ia fois pour designer l'organe normal de Ia connaissance des
vorrni ct l'organe d'intuition mystique qui entre en contact avec l'av6rrrov'
(ufJ. cit .. pp. 138-139). The writer is certainly correct regarding the teachings
of :"..umenius and the Clmldaean Oracles. although Albinus actually refers to
<iod only as 'ineffable' (c'ippTJTO~) and not as unknowable, so that the con-
tradiction in his case is considerably lessened.
156. See Plato's account of the moment of intuition at Epist. VII, 341c
suddenly, like a fire kindled by a leaping spark' (t~aiq>VTJ~, o{ov ano nupo~
7t'l<'iitaavtoc; t~aq>9v q>roc;).
IS"'. Sec Plato's simile of the Sun at Rep. VI. SORb 'which the Good has
gl'Jlcratcd as an analogy with itself (OV taya9ov tyEVVTJO&V avciA.oyov E:aut<iJ).
158. For further discussion of the ineffable and related notions in late anti-
quity see P. Boyance: 'Fulvius Noblllor et le Dieu ineffable', Revue de
/Jbi/ologie 29 (1955). pp. 172-192; and Moreschini: op. cit .. pp. 162-178 and
198-199.
270 MIDDLE PLATONISM
l"''i. For the notion of God as 'one' in the second century see R. Braun:
Deus Christianorum. Recherches sur le l'ocabulaire doctrinal de Tertu/lien
(Paris. 1962), pp. 67-68. For cbt&pi~&Tpoc; which is a hapaxlegomenon see
Beaujeu: op. cit., p. 256 and Moreschini: op. cit., p. 199.
1"6. On the importance ot' Apuleius' careful delineation of the
metaphysical transcendence of God - which in many ways parallels the
treatment by Albinus: Dldasc. 10, Iff. - see B. M. Portogalli: 'Sulle fonti
della concezione teologica e demonologica di Apuleio', Studi classici e or/en-
tali 12 ( 1963), pp. 229-230. Portogalli raises the important question of possi-
ble Aristotelian influence over the notion of metaphysical transcendence in
this period.
177. Plato nowhere brings together these three essential attributes of a
transcendent metaphysical principle, although an attentive reading of the
1'imaeus (especially combining Tim. 27d-29a on the Demiurge and Paradigm
with ibid. 38b on the nature of time and Ibid. 52a-b on that of space) would
reveal such a transcendence clearly enough.
178. There is no need to repeat the results of our earlier discussion of this
question. On the absence of metaphysical transcendence in the earlier latin
tradition seep. 153 and ch. 1, n. 343 (for Cicero). pp. 833-835 and app .. nn.
"".f- '76 (for Varro), and p. 187 and ch. 2, n. 118 (for Seneca). On the earlier
history of incorporeality in the Platonic tradition of late antiquity see pp.
l""l-3andch. 2, nn. 5759.
1'79. See the important study of F. Cumont: 'jupiter summus exsuperan-
tissimus', Archivfiir Religlonswlssenschaft9 (1906), pp. 323-336.
272 MIDDLE PLATONISM
180. According to Cumont: op. cit.. pp. 323-336. Ba'al Sam in was believed
to reside in the sphere of fixed stars, so that his cult was primarily an
astrological one. The identification of the outermost cosmic sphere with the
supreme God had been suggested earlier by Cicero: De Rep. VI, 17, and it ac-
quired a new vogue in the teachings of certain Chaldaean and Syrian cults of
the imperial period. See Statius: Thebaid. IV, 515-516 and Lactantius
Placidus: In Thebaid. IV, 515-516. That Apuleius accepts this theory is sug-
gested not only by his use of the Greek De Mundo which locates God similar-
ly at the periphery of the cosmos (ITEpi K60110U 6, 398b7 tni tile; avrotci.tro
xropac; {l)pua9at = Apuleius: De Mundo 25, 344 sacrata caeli penetralibus),
but by his explicit reference to the 'Chaldaeans' (Chaldaei) as a source of
astronomical information at De Deo Socr. 1, 117. and by the tripartite
classification of gods into 'supermundane' (ultramundanus), 'heavenly'
(caelicolae), and 'intermediary' (medioximi) in De Platone which recalls
schemata attributed to the Chaldaeans by other sources. To Cumont's results
we should perhaps add two observations. First, Apuleius' version of this
theory differs from the earlier one in that his supreme deity is not the sphere
of the fixed stars itself but a metaphysical principle whose operation is
primarily manifested in this sphere. This makes his doctrine strikingly similar
to that of Aristotle who believed that the Unmoved Mover was metaphysical-
ly transcendent yet somehow present at the periphery of the universe. See
Aristotle: PbJs. VIII, 10, 267a21-b8. Secondly. Apuleius interpretation of the
first God as the summus exsuperantissimusque deorum of oriental cult is not
necessarily inconsistent with his view that it is equivalent to the
supercelestial place of Plato's Phaedrus. See Festugic~re: La revelation
d 'Hermes Trismegiste 11: Le Dieu cosmique (Paris, 1949), pp. 514-515 and
Regen: op. cit., pp. 97-98.
181. Apuleius: Apol. 64; De Deo Socr. 3. 124; and De Plat. I, 5. 190.
APUI.Eil!S 273
God is indeed the cause of all things which happen in the world,
but he achieves this not through any direct intervention but
through the exercise of an 'unwearied power' (iitputoc;
MvaJ.Ltc;) from afar. God has taken for himself the highest sta-
tion, and the body which is nearest to him 'draws off most from
this power' (IJ.QAlO'tQ OS moe; autou tile; OUVQj.I.E(I)c; cmoA.aUEl)
while the next nearest draws less and so on. When we say that
'the divine pervades all things' (bti 7tQV OUKVEia9at 7tE(j)UKEV to
eetov), we mean that things share to different degrees in the
divine power. Thus, it is more fitting to say that it is 'the power
established in heaven. (~ v oupavq> OUVQI.llc; lopujJ.tVll) which
provides the stability of each thing from afar rather than
something which achieves this directly by approaching and per-
vading its objects. just as the Great King remains unseen in his
capital, yet sees and hears all things by means of the agents
which he dispatches to various places, so does God govern the
world which is subject to him. It is appropriate that he 'should
be established in the highest place' (7ti tile; avrotatro x.c.i>pac;
iop0a9at) while the heavenly bodies are moved by 'the power
which pervades the whole cosmos' (~ ouvaj.l.tc; oui toO OUIJ.7tav-
toc; K60J.lOU BtitKouaa). In the same way, makers of machines
are able to produce a complex series of movements as a result of
a single ingenious trigger mechanism.
My paraphrase has remained deliberately close to the text of
this rather discursive presentation, and so it may be useful to
state in a single sentence what the principal argument is. In
brief, the author of the treatiset9o distinguishes two aspects of
God: his transcendence in relation to the world (indicated first
190. The authorship and date of the Greek De Mundo have not been deter-
mined with certainty, although nobody maintains that it is an authentic work
by Aristotle. According to W. L. Lorimer: The Text Tradition of Ps. -Aristotle
De Mundo together with an Appendix containing the Text of the Mediaer,al
Latin Versions (Oxford. 1927). p. I. it was the: work of an otherwise
unknown author between A.D. 40 and A.D. 140, the latter date being furnish-
APtJLEH.JS 275
cd by its priority to the Latin version of Apuleius and the former by the occur-
rence of the phrase ci>an&p O.t.u~A.&t which appears in literature around
Plutarch's time.
191. God has the 'highest and primal station' (avc.i>"tano Kai npc.i:ml fopa,
nepl K6af,lOU 6, 397b25); he is 'in heaven' (ev oupavcp Ibid. 6, 398a2-3); he is
'in the highest place' (em n\c; avomitro xropac; ibid. 6, 398b7-8).
192. Things caused by God are 'far away' (n6ppro Ibid. 6, 397b24); 'nearer
... farther' (to d.TJaiov ... to f.lEt'EKEivo ibid. 6, 397b28-30); 'at the greatest
distance' (ev anoataG&l ni..&iOTlJ Ibid. 6, 397b30-31 ); 'nearer and farther' (ey-
YIOV <E Kai nopprottpro ibid. 6, 397b35); 'at the greatest distance' {toic;
nJ..eiatov ciq>&atfiK6mv ibid. 6, 398a:n.
19.:\. The divine element 'pervades all things' (Eiti nav OllKVEia9at ibid. 6,
,Wra:B); 'pervades the whole world' (ota toi:i GIJfl7tUVtoc; KOOflOU OlllKEIV
ihid. 6. 598b8).
19'l. Things caused by God are 'full of gods (9ewv nJ..ta ibid. 6,
W""b 17-18); they 'draw off the divine power' (<iic; ouv<if,l&roc; anoJ..au&t ibid.
6. W7b28-29); they 'participate in its benefits' (Wq>&A.&iac; f.!E<aAaf,ll}<ivovm
ibid. 6, 398a I).
195. oua(a at ibid. 6, 397b20.
196. Mvaf.ltc; at ibid. 6, 398a2-3.
19'. Mva1-uc; at ibid. 6, 397b 19; 6, 397h23; 6. 397b28; and 6, 398bR.
198. wq>tl..&ta at ibid. 6, 39rb31 and 6. 398a I.
276 MIDDLE PLATONISM
199. See especially M. Heinze: Die Lehre t'Om logos in der griechischen
Philosopble (Oldenburg. 1872). p. 174 and E. Zeller: Die Philosophie der
Griechen in ibrer gescblchtlichen Entwicklung Ill. I (Leipzig. 1923 ), p. 664.
Other s<.holars have added minor details or modifications to this interpreta-
tion, although much of the more detailed Quellenforschrmg has produced
unconvincing results. See W. Capelle: 'Die Schrift ''onder Welt. Ein Beitrag
zur Geschichte der griechischen Popularphilosophie'. Neue jahrhiicher fur
das klassische Altertum I 5 (1905). pp. 529-568; M. ). Lagrange: 'l.es
pcripatcticiens jusqu':l I' ere chrctienne'. Re11ue Thomiste 32 ( 1927), p. 202 ff:
). P. Maguire: 'The Sources of Pseudo-Aristotle De Mundo. Yale Classical
Studies 6 (1939), pp. 147-162; G. Verbeke: L 'etrolulion de Ia doctrine du
pneuma du stoicisme as. Augustin. Etude phi/osophique (Louvain, 1945),
pp. 138-141; Festugiere: La revtflation d'Hermes Trlsmegiste II: Le Dieu
cosmique, pp. 160-164; M. Adriani: 'Note sui trattato llpi K6aJ.LOU', Rivista
di fi/ologia e di istruzione c/assica 30 ( 1952), pp. 208-222; and S. di Cristina:
'L'idea di ouvaJ,w;, ncl De Mundo e nell'Oraliu Cld Graecos di Taziano',
Augustinianum 17 ( 1977), pp. -485-504.
200. Aristotle: Phys. VIII . .J. 25.fh7 ff.
201. Ibid. VIII. 5. 257a:H 258h9.
202. Ibid. VIII, 6. 259a6- 19.
203. Aristotle: De Caelo l, 9, 279a 18-22.
204. Aristotle: Phys. VIII. 10, 267h I '7-26.
205.1bid. VIII, 10, 267b6-9.
206. Aristotle: Metaph. A. 7. I 07 2a26-h I.
207. Sec: pp. 107-108.
208. Seepp. 113115.
APllLF.IliS
bodies which are next after them in the present passage. Fur-
ther, an analogous transformation of the Greek occurs in the
fifth sentence where the statement that the power established in
heaven provides the stability of all things is translated by replac-
ing the relatively vague phrase 'provides stability' with the
more explicit 'provides stability through itself and through
others' (per se et per alios opem salutis adferre). Here, Apuleius
refers to the two ways in which God sustains the existence of
other things, presumably contrasting a direct intervention in the
causal process with operation through intermediaries such as
celestial gods or demons. Finally, the same transformation of
the original is indicated in the seventh sentence where the state-
ment that the power which pervades the whole cosmos moves
the heavenly bodies is translated by replacing the vague phrase
'the power which pervades the whole cosmos' with the more
precise words 'those powers which God distributes through all
the parts of the world' (eas autem potestates per omnes partes
mundi orbisque dispendat). Here, the substitution of the plural
'powers' (potestates) for the singular of the original suggests
that the notion of degrees has given way to that of a hierarchy,
especially since there is evidence for applying the plural term to
demons elsewhere in the Apuleian corpus.
219. The nature of providence is further defined at ibid. II, 23, 253 'The
supreme God does not only consider all these activities by means of his
thoughts. but he surveys the first. middle. and last. and rules the things which
he: knows intimately with the unl\'ersality and continuity of providential
ordering' (summus deorum ctmcta haec non solum cogitationum raUone
crmsideret, set/ P''ima, media, ultima obeat conpertaque intime prol'ldae
ordinatimzis tmitersitate et constantia regat) .
.220. For fate see further Apulcius: De Mundo 38 ..F2 'The Greeks like to
Gill fate EillUPilEVTJ because of a certain sequence of interrelated causes, they
l'all this decree 7tE7tPWJlEV11 because all things are defined in our universe and
then~ is nothing undetermined in this world. They also l'all it j.IOtpa because it
is composed of parts' (Fa tum autem Graeci EillUPJ.1EV11V a tractu quodam in-
ticem etll/sarum se continentium tolunt diet; decretum idem 7tE1tPWJ.1EVTIV
clicunt. quod unmia in hoc statu rerum deflnita sl'lt nee sit in hoc mundo
aliquid interminatum: idem fatum j.IOtpav tmcm11. quod ex pmtibus con-
stet).
221. The posteriority of fate to providence is also indicated in certain
other texts of the period which seemingly reflect the same teaching. See p .
., .... _.and ch. 6. n 232.
282 MIDDLE PLATONISM
224. Plato: Pbaed. 115a; Tim. 89c; Leg. IX, 873c and X. 904c.
22S. Plato: Leg. IX. 873c.
226. Plato: Tim. 30b-c.
22"'. Ibid. 41e.
228. The doctrinal parallels between these three works (and Apuleius)
were first noted by A. Gercke: 'Eine platonische Quelle des Neuplatonismus'.
Rbeiniscbes Museum 41 ( 1886). pp. 266-291. For a comparative study of the
lloctrincs of providence and fate in these authors sec Dillon: op. cit., pp.
:'120-.U6. See also for the individual writers E. Valgiglio: Ps.-Piutarco. De:
Fa to. lntroduzione, testo crltico, traduzi(me e nmwzento (Rom a. 1964 ); A.
Siclari: L 'mztropologia di Nemesio di Emesa (Padova,l974). pp. 266-301: G.
Vcrhckc: ct J. R. Moncho: Nemesius d'Emese, De Natura Hominis. Traduction
cle Burgundio de Pise. Edition critique avec rme introduction sur /'an-
thropotogie de Nemisius par G. V. et]. R. M. (Leiden, 19"5), pp. lxii-lxxxv:
:mll J. dt"n Boeft: Calcidius on Fate. His Doctrine and Sources (Lei den,
1'-TO), pp. R-46.
284 MIDDLE PLATONISM
Apulciu!> elsewhere reveals a love of such antitheses. Sec for example Apol.
6'1 where God is described as 'the artificer without artifice, the consoler
without concern, the begetlcr without generation' (sine opera opifex. sine
cum sospitator, sine propagt~tione genitor).
2'i I. Cf. Alhinus: Didasc. H. 2 'Matter in itself exists without shape, quali-
ty. and form'(aun'w f> Ka9'aurt)v ciJ.top(jl6v tE unapxEtv Kai cinmov Kai avEi-
f>r.ov).
2'i2. Plato: Phaedr. l47c. Apulcius has already shown his interest in this
passage hy using it at A pol. 64.
2'i:\. Hippolytus: Phi/os. 19 (D(i <;67. I<;). Apulcius did not know this text
;tlthough he had access to the tradition which it represents.
.290 MIDDLE PLATONISM
2'iR. Plato: Tim. 39e (living things) and ibid. SIb (elements).
2'i9. It is impossible to give a complete list of the references to Forms in
Plato's writings or to classify these references since (i) Plato generally avoids
the rigid technical terminology whose presence would invariably permit us
to identify the occurrence of a Form, and (ii) Plato's thought seems to have
undergone :m evolution in which his notions regarding the kinds of Forms to
be postulated may have changed. However, the following passages are the
main ones referring to the types of Form discussed above. a) Moral Forms
(qualitative): Pbaed. 7Sc-d; 76d; Parm. 130b; 130e-13la; Symp. 21lc;
Phaedr. 247d; Rep. V, 476a; V. 479a; and Epist. VII, 342d; b) Mathematical
Forms (qualitative): Pbaed. 75c-d; Pann. 130b; 130e-13la; Rep. V. 479b;
Rep. VI, 'i JOe; and Epist. VII, 342d; c) Forms of natural objects (substantial):
Pbileb. I 'ia; Tim. 39e; S lb; and Eplst. VII, 342d. The following texts contain
the most important general discussions of the range of Forms: Pann. 130a-e
(moral and mathematical Forms assumed, Forms of natural suhstances ques-
tioned, l'orms of negatives rejected); Rep. X, 'i96a (Forms of all general terms
postulated); lpist. VII, 342d (the fullest list of l'orms including moral and
mathematical Forms, Forms of natural substances, and others); and Aristotle:
Jletapb. A. 9. 990a33-993a I 0 (discussion of various arguments which deter-
mine the range of Forms). For a detailed analysis of this question sec W. D.
Ross: Plat(} 's Theory of Ideas (Oxford, I9'i 1). pp. 24, 84-85. and 16'i ff.
260. Arius Didymus: !:'pit. Phl'S. fr. I (DG 447al-27). Cf. Alhinus: Didasc.
12, 1-2. .
292 MIDDLE PLATONISM
26"i. Plato: Tim . .29b and .J8e. Cf. Arius Didymus: !:.'pit. Pbys. fr. I (DG
..f..f-a2-"i. 19-21 and bl-3. 12-22).
266. Plato: Tim. 50d-c:. Cf. Arius Didymus: Epit. Pbys. fr. I (l)G 447a9-11
and h8-12).
26-. Arius Didymus: Eplt. Pbys. fr. I (DG 447a9-l.~) 'just as many impres-
~ions arise from a single seal and many images of a single: man, thus many
natures of sensible bodies arise from each single: Idea' (ov tp61tOV 5i:
CHppayiooc; llltlc; tKilUYEiU yiV09Ul 1t0A.J..ci KUi OUXVclc; iK6vac; EVOc; QVOp6c;,
of,twc; Kai llttic; tKaat'lc; icSeac; aia811trov aro!llinov cpuaL<; 1tUil1tA'19⁣).
llowc:vc:r, Arius docs not speak of the impression of individual Forms - ;ts
Pbto docs in the passages from the Timaeus - hut simply of individual
naturc:s.
26H. Sec n . .2:\6.
269. Another text dc:aling with the: causality of the: Forms is Apulc:ius: D
Plat. I. 6. 193-194. This speaks of individual things as (i) possessing in-
dividual Form. and (ii) taking their origin from the: Paradigm. Here Apuleius
dlarly follows Plato once: again. although the reference is not to the: Timaeus
- whc:rt Plato speaks of th!.' 'Receptacle:' (tmocSoxli) ;ts receiving Form rather
than of individual things doing so - hut perhaps to passages such as Phaefl.
~8d-c:: I 02d; and 103b.
294 MIDDLE PLATONISM
270. I think that it is possihlc to suhstitute 'translendc:nt Form' for the Idea
and 'immanent Form' for the: individual Form. By so doing, the: rc:lationship
of this part of Apuleius theory to the doctrines already dc:scrihed will
hecomc more apparent. See pp. 279-280 and 285-286.
2'1. Apuleius: De Plat. I. 5. 190.
272./hid. I. 6. 192.
27 3. Ibid. l. 6. 192-19 3. The use of exemplum in this sense: is not
documentc:d hc:fore Apuleius. However. the: analogous non-metaphysical
usage of the: term is l'ommon enough in writers of the classical pc:riod. Sec L.
and S. s.v.
274. Apuleius: De Plat. I. 6, 19:~.
275./bid. I, 6. 194.
APULEil!S 295
2""'6. Ibid. I. 6, 192- I 93. For earlier illustrations of the usc of exemplar in
this sense see Cicero: Tim. 6; Seneca: Epist. 58, I8-I9; 65, 7-8; etc. Cf. n.
2 ...~.
27""'. cr. n. 270.
2""'8. Apuleius: De Plat. I. S. 191. On the use of figum in the tec.:hnkal
sense of immanent Form sec Moresc.:hini: op. cit., pp. 200-20 I .
.2-:'9. Apuleius: De Plat. I. 6, 193.
280. Ibid. I, 6, I 93. Species is one of the standard terms used hr Cicero to
render the technical term Eiooc; into latin. Sec Cicero: Acad. 33; Drat. I01;
Tusc. Disp. l, 58, etc.
28 I. Cf. n. 270.
296 MIDDLE PLATONISM
288. Plato: Tim . .J8e-53c. All the Greek passages to be quoted below arc
llrawn from these pages with the exception of those marked with an asterisk.
As always, Apuleius does not simply follow one text but integrates ap-
propriate references to others from time to time.
289. Cf. n. 270.
290. Plato: Rep. VI. ';08e. The term iota does not seem to he used in a
29H MIDDLE PLATONISM
purely transct:ndcnt sc:nst: in tht: Timaeus, although that text tmploys the
regular synonym Ei&oc; thus. See Tim.'; le-d.
291. Plato: Tim . ..jBe.
292. Arius Didymus: Epit. Pbys. fr. I. (DG ..j.f':'a 19-2..j .).
293. Cf. n. 270.
29..j. Plato: Tim. ';Oe. On the multiplicity of terms which Plato employs to
designate the immanent Forms see F. M. Cornford: Plato 's.Cosmology. The
Timaeus of Plato trans/tiled tl'ilh t1 Rtmning Commentary (London, 1937),
p. 186. nn. 1-2.
29';. Plato: Tim. ';2d. Cf. ibid. ';Od and'; I a.
APULEILIS 299
wav with forms and numbers' (oihro Bti t6n; 7tEq>UK6ta taOta
rrp&tOv 5tEOX.TJIJ.aticrato Ei5Ecri tE Kai cipt91J.oi<;)] .296
(iii) species I ytvo<;, dtSo<;
[So that which is to receive in itself all kinds must be free of all
forms' (5u) Kai ncivtrov EKto<; Ei5rov dvm X.PEci>v to til ncivta
EK5E~61J.EVOV tv aut~ YEV11)297 /'Similarly' that which is duly to
receive throughout its extent and repeatedly the likenesses of all
the things eternally existing must in its own nature be free of all
kinds' (taU'tOV ouv Kai 't~ til 'tOOV 7tclV'tOOV ciEi 'tE OV'tOOV Katil nav
tautou 7tOAAclKl<; ciq>OIJ.OlCOIJ.ata KaA.ro<; IJ.EAAOV'tl OEX,Ecr9m navt-
rov EKtO<; aut~ npocriJKEl7tEq>UKEVal 'tOOV EitSrov )]298
The following seem to be the Greek originals of Apuleius'
terms for both the transcendent and the immanent Forms:299
(i)forma I itSta
A. Transcendence
['So that which provides truth to things known and the power
of knowing to the knower you must call the "Form" of the
good' (toOto toivuv to ttiv ciA.iJ9Etav naptx.ov tot<;
YIYVOOOKOIJ.EVOt<; Kai 't~ ytyVOOOKOV'tl tiJV OUVaiJ.lV cino5t5ov tiJv
tou aya9o0 i5tav q>ci9t dvm*)].3oO
B. Immanence
['If there is to be an impression representing different things,
that in which the impression is to take place cannot be well
prepared unless it is free of all those forms which it is to receive
from elsewhere' (o,lK av iiA.A.ro<;, EK'tU7tOOIJ.ato<; crEcr9aliJ.EAAOV-
toc; iBEtv nmKiA.ou naaa<; notKtA.ia<;, touT'auto f:v <!>
EKTU7t0UIJ.EVOV evicrtatm ytvon'liv rtapEOKEUaOIJ.EVOV EU, nA.tiv
tradition into his account. Thus, parallels between the two texts
permit us to use the one in interpreting the other and to clarify
certain obscure features of the doctrine of the Forms' causality .
vouc; as acies mentis is, however. influenced by Ciceronian texts like Tusc.
Disp. I, 45. For the interpretation of transcendence by Plato see the discus
sion on pp. 269-272 and 286-287. It is perhaps worthy of note that Apuleius
declares the subordinate gods to be without beginning as well as without end.
He must therefore understand the narrative sequence of Plato's Timaeus in
an atemporal manner.
319. See Cicero: De Nat. Deor. II, 60 'It was thought that whatever confer-
red great benefits on the human race must be a result of divine benevolence
towards men' (quidquid enim magnam utilitatem generi adferret bumano
id mm sine dilina bonitate erga homines fieri arbitrabantur). For the Stoic
and Varronian equation of God and aether see pp. 96-97 and 831-835.
However, one must remember that Apuleius' notion of the gods involves a
real metaphysical transcendence. Thus, the periphery of the aether indicates
the place where their power is manifest and not the elemental nature of the
divine substance.
320. Apulcius: De Deo Socr. 2, 120. Cf. De Plat. I. 10, 202. Beaujeu: op.
dt .. pp. 206-209 and 261 rightly notes that Apuleius' discussion of the visible
gods and the astronomical theory implied is based partl)' upon Plato's
Timaeus (especially Tim. 38c-39e) and partly upon Cicero's De Natura
Deorum (especially De Nat. Deor. II, 49-56) together with a few
reminiscences of Peripatetic teachings.
Al'liLEil'S 30S
.~21. Apuldus: De Plat. I, 11, 203. The placing of the heavenly bodies in
anual phy~ical spheres renects the cosmology of Aristotle rather than that of
Plato .
.~22. Ibid. I, 11, 203. Cf. Apuleius: De Den Socr. I, 118; De Plat. l, 11,
20-J; De Mundo I, 290; 2, 293; 4. 297; ami 21, .B6. The notion of a feeding
of the heavenly bodies is not Platonic but Stoic. Sec Cicero: De Nat. Deor. II,
tO; II, H5; II, 92; II. IIH; etc.
525. For the equation of fire and aether see Apuleius: De Deo Socr. 8. 138;
for their distinction De Plat. I, HI, 2Q5. The aether is described in l>eripatetic
terms as a fifth clement at De lWtmdo 1, 291.
_J,2t. Apuleius: IJe P/(11. I, II, 20:\ and De Mundo 2, 292.
52'i. Apuleius: De Mundo 2. 292-295. The phrase 'the back of the acther'
n
luetberis dorsum) which Apuleius uses to translate the bnqHiV&lQ toO OUJ.L
1tUVTO~ oupavoii of the original (ps.-Aristotlc: n&pi K6a)lOU 392a I H) is a
reminiscence of Plato: Pbaedr. 24 7b.
306 MIDI>l.E PLATONISM
ltO. See ibid. 41d 'Thus he spoke. and turned again to that same mixing
howl in which he had mixed and hlt:nded the universal soul' (taut'EinE, Kai
nul.tv bri rov np6tEpov Kpatilpa, tv c!> t~v toii navroc; 111ux~v KEpavvuc;
f.tuoyEvl. Apuleius' modification prohahly results from interpreting this
p;tssa~e in the light of Plato: Phileb. 30a and Phaedr. 2-i;c.
-~II. See pp. 250-253, 259-260 and 263-264 .
.H2. An interpretation along similar lines is suggested by Moreschini: op.
cit .. pp. H6-H'"' and I 54-I 55, although his support of the thesis hy appealing
10 Albinus: Didasc. 169, _U is not convincing.
3--t 3. Apuleius: Apol. 4 3; De Deo Socr. 6. 132; and De Plat. I, I I, 204. The
term mediu.\imi whkh m:rurs in the last passage mentioned is a traditional
titk for gods of intermediate status although not always explicitly for
dlmons. See Senius Danielis: In Armeid. Ill. 131 and VIII, 275 where
Apukius is cited.
.HO MIDDLE PLATONISM
344. Apulcius: De Deo Soc:r. 13. 148. Some of these attributes are mention-
ed elsewhere. One should compare the discussion of rhe demons' aerial
bodiesat/bid.6.132:9.140-lil:and/JePiat.l,II.204.
:\45. Apuleius: De Deo Soc:r. 6. 133-134. On the functions of demons see
also Apol. Hand De Plat. I. 12. 206. Apuldus' demonologicalthcories have
been extensively discussed in the secondary scholarship. for example by Por-
togalli: op. cit .. pp. 227-24 I; Regen: op. cit .. pp. 3-22 (with special reference
to the Apologia); Moreschini: op. cit.. pp. 19-42 (mainly concerned with the
Metamorphoses); and Dillon: op. cit .. pp. 317-320. Beaujeu: op. cit .. pp.
183-201 is a masterly historical discussion of the background to Apuleius'
doctrine.
APLJLEHJS 311
quaepiam ... non usitata vox nee humana)350 or using 'a sign
which is the apparition of the demon itself' (signum ... et ipsius
daemon is species)35 I - descriptions blending negative and
positive elements. The latter finds expression in his statements
that they are 'always free of the shackles and bonds of the
human body' (semper a corporis conpedibus et nexibus
liberi)352 - here their distinguishing mark is a status mediating
transcendence and immanence - or that they are 'guardians
assigned to individual men during their lifetime' (in vita agenda
... custodes singulis additt),353 coming to our aid when were-
quire 'not counsel but revelation' (non consilio sed
praesagio),354 who 'take us from here and bring us as their
charges to that judgment when our earthly lives are past' (vita
edita . . . rap tare iiico et trahere veluti custodiam suam ad
iudicium)355 -where the distinguishing mark is a causality ex-
ecutive in relation to the higher providence. The discussion of
the demons never embodied contains elements definitely deriv-
ed from Plato together with notions whose origins are more
doubtful. That demons can manifest themselves by means of a
voice or a sign, that they are assigned to men during their ear-
thly lives, and that they accompany them on their journey into
the hereafter are all ideas which can be extracted from Plato's
dialogues.356 Furthermore, the distinction between reasoning
3';o. Apuldus: De Deo Socr. 20. 16S. The reference is w Socrates' demon
said to be in this categorr.
:\S I. Ibid. 20, 166. Here. the reference is to Minerva's appearance as a
demon to Ulysses.
3S2.11Jid. 16, IS"! .
.3S.3. Ibid. 16. ISS.
3SI. Ibid. Ji. I Si. Cf. ibid. 16. ISS ;md 18. 162 (Socrates' demon).
3SS. Ibid. 16, ISS .
.3S6. For the demonic voice of Socrates see Plato: Apnl. 40h-c 'the sign of
the god ... the customary sign' (To Tou 6eou OT]J.IEiov ... To Eiw6oc; OT]J.IEiov). An
association between demons and men both now and in the afterlife is describ-
APllLEJliS 313
ed in many passages of Plato. See especially Pbaed. 107d; Polit. 271 d; Rep.
X. 6 17d-e; X. 620d-e; and Leg. IV, 713d-e.
3'i~. See Plato: Phaedr. 24.:id 'So much more beautiful did the ancients
consider the madness which comes from God to he than the sanity which
derives from man' (t6oq> KaA.I..tov 1-1aptupouatv oi 7taA.alOi 1-1aviav
O(J>(j)poouVTJ<; tliv EK 9EOii til<; 7tap'av9pro7trov ytyVO!!EVTJ<;). Plato's text in-
dudes a word-play on llaV\Kll!llaVttK~ - the Iauer being reflected in
Apuleius' praesagium.
3'iH. That demons produce visible manifestations of themselves is an idea
also of Plutan:h who speaks of the Socratic demon as so doing. Plutarch: De
(;en. Socr. I 0, 'iHOc. I hope to demonstrate below that the other
characteristics attributed to this class of demons result from Apuleius' desire
to establish higher and lower demonic groups analogous to the higher and
lower di\'ine groups .
."t'i9. Apuleius: De Deo Socr. 15. 153. It is specifically the second group
memioned hdow which is the object of terror to the had. To anompllsh this
function they would obviously have to he visible or at least sensihlc.
.314 MIDDLE PLATONISM
and 'Love' (Amor). See ibid. 16. 155. Love is also mentioned without precise
'ktermination of its status at Apuleius: Apol. 12; F/or. 10; and Mel am. IV. 2R
ff. A~ examples of demons after embodiment we have Amphiaraus. Mopsus.
Osiris, and Asdepius. See Apuleius: De Deo Socr. 15. 153-1 'i-1.
36S. Sec pp. 311-313 .
.:'166. Apulcius: De Deo Socr. 17, l'i7. This was noted by P. Vallette:
I. 'Apologie d'Apu/ee (P:tris, 190R), p. 246.
:\6:-. In fact, Apuleius often obscures the wider distinction between gods
and demons themselves by applying the term 'god' (deus) in different con-
texts to demons never embodied. demons after embodiment, and demons
currently embodied. For the t1rst see Apuleius: De Deo Socr. 2. 121-122 and
.w. 166 where the same spiritual being, Minerva, is described as an invisible
god and as a demon respectively. For the second see ibid. I 'i. 153 where the
316 MIDDLE PLATONISM
term 'god' is applied 10 disembodied human souls which have led excellent
earthly lives and even 'honorifically' (honoris causa) to disembodied souls of
uncertain moral status. For the 1hird see ibid. I 5, I SO-l 5 I where the term
'god' is applied lO currently embodied human souls. All this reflects not only
the looseness of the classical terminology for various spiritual heings but the
fluid structure of Apuleius' ontology based on the multiple unfolding of the
unitary divine power.
368. Ibid. I 5. 150-152. I have detected no significant difference of mean-
ing between the two Latin terms - animus and anima - which Apult:ius
uses to speak of this principle. That hoth are employed in similar contexts is
indicated hy a comparison of the following sets of passages: (i) Apuleius: De
Plat. II. 22. 25 I with De Mumlo I, 288 and 30, 357 (the eyes of the soul); (ii)
De Plat. II, 9, 2:H with ibid. I, 13, 207 and I, 18, 216 (the rational pan of the
soul); and (iii) De Deo Socr. I 5, I 52 wilh De Plat. I. 17. 217 (the conjunction
of the soul and the body). The flexibility of usage follows a tradition of Latin
philosophical writing at least as old as Cicero. See ch. I, n. 255.
369. Apulcius: De Plat. I. 9, 199. For the immortality of the soul cf. ibid.
II. 20, 2-19 and II, 23, 255; and De Deo Socr. 4, 126 and 15, 151. For its
separation from the hody d. De Plat. II, 21, 250-251. For its generation cf.
De Deo Socr. I 5, 151. The last parallel raises difficulties of interpretation
since the words cmmiumque gigrzerzlium esse seuiorem are amhiguous and
could mean either 'it is foremost among all things which come to be' or 'it is
prior to all things which come lO be'. If the latter interpretation is correct,
then Apuleius believes the soul to he eternal in the past as well as in the
furure. In this case we must translate the words quodammodo cum homine
Al'l' I.E I LIS .:H7
Rignitur ("the soul is ill some way born with the man') at ibid. I 'i. I 'i I with
tmphasis upon the italicized words. It is difficult to be sure which of the two
intc:rpretat ions is t'orrect .
.:\70. Apuleius: De !Hundo 31. 3'i9 .
.Pl. Apuleius: De Plat. 1. 13. 207. Thc: tripartition of thc: soul is also
discussed at ibid. I, 18. 216-218 and II, L 22'i ff .
.~"'2. P1aw speaks of the soul as 'immortal' (a9avato~) at Pbaed.
10'ie-106d; 114d; Phaed1". 24'ic-e; Rep. X, 6llb; etc.; as 'self-moved' (to
auto KlVOUV) at Pbaedr. 24 'ic-e; and as tripartite at Rep. IV. 4 39d ff.; IX.
'i~ lc-'i72a; IX. 'i80d ff.; and Tim. 69c-72d. He does not seem 10 have refer-
rtd to the soul explicitly as incorporeal although this notion was established
318 MIDDLE Pl. A TONISM
4. 36 MA TTER/FORMS/NUMBERSIBODY
5~'i. Sec Plato: Tim. S2b The Receptacle "is tangible without the aid of sen-
sation but with a kind of bastard reasoning, and is scarcely an objelt of belief'
taGto Of: J.u:t"civata9naiac; cintov i..oyta~C\.J nv1 v69<p, J.16ytc; mat6v). In this
passage. the ant6v leads to Apuleius tactu, the A.oytaJ.I<!> TIVI v69<p to his
aclultera opinirme, ;md the mat6v perhaps to his opinione cogit(lfi(mis.
Tim~. we achieve the Latin writer's notion that matter is ambivalently the ob-
jen of sc:nse. That it is also ambivalently the object of thought may have bec:n
suggc:stc:ll by Plato's statc:ment a little earlier in the text that the: Receptacle
"participates in a puzzling way in the intelligible and is difficult to grasp'
(J.IEtCIAUJ.II}<ivov OE cl1tOPWtaTQ 7tl) tOU VOTJTOU Kai OUOUAWtOtaTOV) .
.~~6. Apulcius: De Plat. 1, 5. 192.
320 MIDDLE PLATONISM
.~83. See the notes of Beaujeu: op. cit .. p. 261 and Morcschini: op. cit .. pp.
81-tH.
384. Apuleius: De Plat. I. 7. 19-i.
APULEilJS
.~H;_ For other discussions of this Platonic theory see Dlogenes Laertius:
Vit. Philos. Ill. 70-75; Albinus: Didasc. 13. 1-2; and Calcidius: /11 Tim. 20.
~ I . I 0 ff.
~H6_ The comparison with syllables may have been inspired by Plato: Tim.
-IHb-c.
~H"'. Plato speaks of the powers contained in the Receptacle at ibid. 52c
'Aut hccausc it was filled with powers which were neither similar nor balanc-
td. there was no equipoise anywhere in it. It was everywhere swayed
unnenly and shaken by those things, and by its motion shook them in
return (oui Ot tO llTJ8'61-1oiwv c'iuvliJ.lEWV J.l~TE iaopp6nwv EJ.17tlJ.l7tAaa8o.t
Kat'ouotv auti\c; iaoppon:Eiv, aH'aVWJ.laA.wc; 7tUVTU TO.AQVTOUJ.lEVT]V OE{Ea8at
lltv U7t'EKEivwv aut~v. KIVOUJ.lEVTJV B'o.u nO:>.. tv EKEi~o. OEiEIV ). The process by
whkh the Demiurge confines the powers within the geometrical shapes is
:\24 MIDDLE PLATONISM
described at ibid. i6c And God has harmonized in due proportion and ab-
solutely perfected the ratios of their numbers. motions. and other powers'
(Kai 51) Kai TO tt:i>V avaA.oyu:i>v !tEp( TE ta nA.Ji9TJ KUi tac; KtviJaEtc; KUi tac;
a Hac; liUVUIJEtc; navmxu TOV 9E6V ... un"au-rou OUVT]p1J6a9at mOta ava
A.6yov). On Plato's notion of power see also Theaet. I i6a; Soph. 248b; Tim.
:'d:t; l.eg. X. HH<Jh; etc.
:\88. See Plato: Tim. 52e where the Receptacle is everywhere swayed
unc\"enly" (clVWIJUAWc; 7tUVT1J taAQVTOUIJEVT]).
58lJ. See ihitl. i6c where numbers" (nA.li9TJ) are associated with "powers'
(liuvaiJEtc;). The connection between matter and multiplicity is also emphasiz-
ed by Xcnocratc:s. Sec Actius: Plac. I. 3. 21 (DG 2H8b 15-18).
390. It will be obvious from the above account that the notion of matter
APlilEIUS 325
~.111 Plil"ll b quite: consistent \Vith Plato's view. Only the: tc:rm materia itself ( =
lJAlll rc:calls Aristott:lianism.
5'>1. Apukius: De Plat. I.~. 19';-196. Cf. Plato: Tim. ')3c-S7d.
592 Apull"ius is more: explicit than Plato regarding the identity of these:
Ill hc:r prindples.
:W 3 Apuleius also states that 'the bodies of ani mate and inanimate things'
(cmilnalium et inunimantium corpora) are fashioned from the elements.
Sec De Plat. l. 8. 196.
326 MIDDLE PLATONISM
the totality of fire, the whole of air, and the entire earth' (exom-
ni aqua totoque igni et aeris zmiversitate cunctaque terra esse
factum), these elements being 'placed within one another and
connected among themselves' (ex se intra se apta et conexa
esse).394 This world fills the whole of space since there is 'no
place left in which another world could arise' (nee relictus
locus, in quo a/ius), and it occupies the whole of time because
'a perpetual youth and inviolate strength have been assigned to
it' (ei adtributa est perpetua iuventas et inviolata
va/etudo).395 Furthermore, he describes its shape as having 'the
resemblance of a beautiful and perfect sphere' (instar pulchrae
et perfectae spbaerae), its proper motion being not one of the
six kinds of rectilinear motion but 'the rotation of reason' (ra-
tionabi/iter volvere).396 In all this Apuleius follows the doctrine
of Plato without significant addition from the later traditions.397
However, on one final question a definite interpretative
stance is taken since the Latin writer attributes two views regar-
ding the origin of the world to his predecessor: 'And sometimes
Plato says that this world is without a beginning, but sometimes
that it has a beginning and has come to be. It has no commence-
ment or beginning because it has existed always, but it appears
to have arisen because its substance and nature is composed of
those things which have the characteristic of becoming' (Et
hunc quidem mundum nunc sine initio esse dicit, alias
originem habere natumque esse: nul/um autem eius exordium
atque initium esse ideo quod semper fuerit; nativum vero
videri, quod ex his rebus substantia eius et natura constet,
quae nascendi sortitae sunt qua/itatem).39B By raising this
399. For general studies sec C. Baeumker: 'Die Ewigkcit dcr \'felt hci
Plato'. Phi/nsopbiscbe Monatsheft 23 ( 1887). pp. 'H 3-<;29:). Baudry: Le pro-
IJ!i!me de f'origine et de l't!temittf du mrmde dam Ia philosophie grecque d'
Platrm ti /'ere cbretienne (Paris, 1931 ); W. Spoerri: 'Encore Platon et
I'Oril:nt', Retue de pbllologie 31 (19<;7). pp. 209-233; and M. Baltes: Die
Weltentstebtmg des platonischen Timaios mtch den ant/ken lnterpreten I
(lciden. 19"'6). Specifically for Apuleius' view of the question stc Beaujcu:
ufJ. cit .. pp.262-26:~; Dillon: op.l'it., pp. 2f2-2-H. 2H6-2H~. and :\I<;; and
:\loreschini: np. cit .. pp. H3-H<;. Only Beaujeu appreciates the real suhtlety of
Apuldus' interpretation .
.foo. See Aristotle: De Caelo l, 10, 280a30-32.
WI. Sec Xenocrates: fr. 54 (and Aristotle: De Caelo 1. I 0. 279b3 2-280a2).
t02. It is clear from Apulcius' statements in this passage that the two
moments in the cosmogonical process - the disorderly qualities in matter
Uht originotl elements) and the qualities arranged according to geometrical
proportion (the configured elements)- are conceptually but not temporally
distinct.
-f03. See ch. 3. n. 25.
:UB MIDDLE PLATONISM
404. Sec Plutarch: De Anim. Procr. 10 16d-e (noted by Beaujeu: op. cit., p.
265).
-105. See Taurus in Philoponus: De Aetem. Mundi VI, 8, liS, 8.
5
The Asclepius
'i.l INTRODUCTION
329
330 MIDDLE PLATONISM
21. Ibid. 20-21. The parallel Coptic version hegins in the middh: of chapter
21'
22. Ibid. 22.
2.~. 1/Jid. 23.
2-t. /bit/. 24-26 .
.!S. Ibid. 27-29. Tht parallel Coptic version ends early in l'hapter 29.
How-,~r
~ ~ . th ere
ts
a separate extract covermg
part o f c h apter. 41.
.336 MIDDI.F. PLATONISM
26./bid. 30-;U.
2-:'./IJid. .33-36.
28. Ibid. .3'7-38.
29. /hid. 39--40. In the foregoing summary I have included onl}' the main
arguments of the Asclepius so that its underlying logical structure might
become apparent. For a more detailed analysis sec Fcstugiere: La ritelalion
d 'Hermes Trismegiste II: Le Dieu cosmique. pp. 18-27.
30. T. Zielinski: 'Hermes und die Hermetik'. Archil! fiir Religions-
\Vissenscbaft 8 ( 190S). pp. 321-372. The shorter texts would he (i) Asclep.
1-14. (ii) ibid. 14-27. (iii) ibid. 27-37, and (iv) ibid. 37-41.
THE ASCLEPIUS B7
of Platonism in the third and fourth centuries A.D ..~-i That the
work does indeed belong to the Platonic current in the history
of philosophy is indicated by the author's emphasis upon the
radical transcendence of the divine.:\o; In this respect his posi-
tion is similar to that held by Apuleius and other Platonists ap-
proximately a century earlier. However, that the work must
also be associated with the Stoic tradition in the history of
thought emerges from the writer's insistence upon the thorough
immanence of the divine .36 On this point he diverges from the
standpoint held by the most influential Platonists of that era.
Finally. that the work is a notable example of syncretism bet-
ween the Platonic and Stoic doctrines in the history of
philosophy is demonstrated by the author's interest in the rela-
tion of macrocosm to microcosm.37 On this question again he
deviates from the position of Apuleius and his contemporaries.
It is obviously necessary to take account of these various in-
fluences in interpreting the structure of the Asclepius'
philosophical system.3H
W. All these: aspects have been noted in connection with Apuleius. See pp.
266-269.
iO . ..tsclep. 16, 3 I 'i. I '7 mente sola intel/egibi/is.
II. Ibid. 29. 336. 6-7 hominem sola inte/legentia mentis inlumimms. Cf.
ibid . .U ..HI, 20-21 and 4 I, .'\'i3. 2. For the theme of illumination in the
<ircek corpus cf. Corp. Herm. I, 32. 19, 5; IX, 3. 97, 10-11; Xlll. IH. 20H, 5;
;md XIII, 19, .20R. 17 together with F. J. Klein: Die Lichtterminologie bei
Pbilon ton ..tlexand1ien und i11 den hermetiscben Scbriften. Unter-
sucbungen zur Struktur der religiosen spracbe del' bel/e11istiscben M)'stik
!Lcidcn, 1962).
-i2. Sensus = 'intellect'. Comparisons with the Greek version in the
340 MIDDLE PLATONISM
know you, with reason that we may pursue you in our thoughts,
and with knowledge that we may rejoice in knowledge of you
. . . this knowledge of your greatness is alone the reward of
humanity'H. Here, the writer reveals three aspects of the
human being's knowledge of God: first, the association between
knowledge and illumination; secondly, the fact that illumina-
tion- as indicated by the occurrence of words like 'favor', 'en-
dow'. and 'reward' in the text - is dependent upon divine
grace; and thirdly, the division of knowledge and illumination
into definite stages. -H.
Papyrus Mimaut and with the Coptic version of Nag Hammadi Codex VI in-
dicate that set~sus represents the Latin translator's habitual rendering of the
original vouc;. See Scott: op. cit. Ill, p. 290; Nock and Festugiere: op. ell., p.
363; Mahe: op. cit. I, pp. 148-149 and 162-163; and Parrott: op. cit., p. 380.
4.~. Asc/ep. 41, 353. 1-355, 4 gratias tibi summe, exsuperantissime; tua
enim gratia tan tum sumus cognitionis tuae lumen consecuti ... condonans
nos sensu, ratione, itlle/legentia: sensu, ut te cognouerimtls; ratione, 111 te
suspicion/bus indagemus; cognitimle, ut te cognoscentes gaudeamus ...
haec est enim humana sola gratulatio, cognitio maiestatis tuae. This
passage comes from the final prayer of the Asclepius and can be compared
with the Greek and Coptic versions. For discussion of the religious sen-
timents expressed see R. Reitzenstein: Die bellenistiscben Myst-
erienreligimlen nacb ibren Grundgedanken tmd Wirkungen, 3. Auflage
(Leipzig, 1927). p. 285 ff. and P. A. Carozzi: "Hoc lumine salvati ltw
(Asclepius 4 I)". Perennitas: Studi in onore di A. Brelicb (Roma, 1980). pp.
ll'i-138 in addition to the works cited in n. 4 2.
+4. There has been considerable discussion concerning the precise
epistemological values of these three stages although the Asclepius, the
Papyrus iHimaut, and Nag HamnUidi Codex VI. 7 all explain them quite ade-
quately in the respective texts. See Scott: op. cit.. p. 291; Nock and
festugicre: ofJ. cit., p. 399: Klein: op. cit .. pp. 17'7-180; and Mahe: op. cit., p.
l.f8 ff.
THEASCLEP/US 341
-t';. Asclep. 3. 298, 21-299. 2 divinitatis etenim ratio dit,ina sensus inten-
tirme mJsn1ula torrenti simi/lima est fltwio e summo In pronum praecipiti
rajmcitate current/: C/IW efficitur, ut intentionem nostrtlm mm solwn au-
dhlllium tenm1 tre~ctantium ipsorum celeri telocitate praetereat.
t6. Ibid. 19. 318. 12-17 sublimis etenim ratio eoque diti11ior ultra
lmminum mentes intentirmesque crmsistens. si 11011 attentiore aurium obse-
lfl//() rerlu1 loquentis acceperis, trcmstolabit et tmnsfluet aut magis rej7uet
suique se frmtis liquor/bus m iscet.
t~. All the dements contained in this definition are traditional (Piatonk
and Stoic). Sec Plato: Tim. 6""b; Aetius: Plac. IV. 19, I (DG 40~. 22a and b
.H2 MIDDLE PLATONISM
ff.); Seneca: Nat. Quaest. II. 6. 5. etc. For more parallels see Scou: op. cit. Ill.
pp. 13;\-134 and Nm:k and Festugicrc: op. cit.. pp. 375-376.
48. Asclep. 20. 320. I 5-321. 9 nullo e.\ his no minibus eum definite nun-
cupabimus. sl enim I'O.\' boc est - ex ai!re spiritu percusso smws dec/arcms
omnem hominis roluntatem rel sensum, quem forte ex senslbus mente
perceperit. cui us nominis Iota substantia pauds conposita syllabis definita
atque circumscriptct est, ut esset in bomine necessarium tocis auriumque
commercium - simul etiam et sensus et spiritus et ai!l"is er omnium in his
aut per haec aut de hi.~ nomen est totum dei: non enim spero totius
maiestalis effectorem (mmiumque rerum patrem rel dominum uno posse
quanll'is e muftis conposito nutuuJmri nomine. hunc terrJ imromitwm rel
poilus omnhwminem siquidem is sit rmus er omnia. ut sit necesse aut om-
nia esse eius nomine aut ipsum omnium nominibus nuncupari.
49. For God as nameless in the Greek corpus see CmtJ. Herm. V. I. 60, -1;
lactantius: Dit. blst. I. 6. 4 (CSEL 19. 19. 18) and IV. 7. 3 (CSEL 19. 293. I).
50. For God as many-named in the Grlc:k corpus sec: Corp. Herm. V. 10,
6-1.:\-10.
THE ASCLEPIUS 343
'S.2211 TRANSCENDENCE
51. Asclep. 41, 353, 3-354, 2 nomen unum, quo solus deus est benedicen-
dus religione paterna. This passage also comes from the final prayer of the
Asclepius, and so a comparison with the Greek text of the Papyrus Mfmaut is
possible. In the latter we read that God has an 'unspeakable name' (acppaatov
ovo!la). On the notion of ineffability in the Hermetica see A. D. Nock: 'The
Exc:gesis of Timaeus 28c'. Vigilfae Christianae 16 ( 1962), pp. 79-86.
52. This aspect has been noted in tonnection with Apuleius. Sc:c pp.
269-2-,2.
53. Asclep. R. 305. 10; 20, 321. 12; and 26. 331. 20. Cf. Corp. Herm. II,
l"i.5H.ll;VI,J,72,4-5;andX,3,114,7-H.
::,~. Asclep. 2, 298. 4 and 20, .321. 7. Cf. Corp. J/erm. XVI, 3, 23.3. 1.
5"J.Asclep. 1,296, l0and2,297,23-24.
S6.Jbid. 30,338. 19.
"i-.lbid. 16.315.17and41,353. l.Cf.Corp.Herm. 1.31, 18,9.
58. Asclep. 41, 353. I. The: attribute: 'highest' is absc:nt from the: text of the
corresponding Coptic version.
344 MIDDLE PLATONISM
5.2212 IMMANENCE
'5lJ. Ibid. 31. 339. 23. Cf. Corp. Herm. IV. 8, '52, 12 and XI. 20, I '55, 13.
60. Asclep. 27. 332. 11-12. Cf. Corp. Herm. II, 4, .B. 1-2; V, 10, 64, 5-6;
and XI. 16. 154, 1-2.
61. Asclep. 2lJ. 336. 5. Cf. Corp. Herm. XII. 23. 183. 12-13.
62. Asclep. 29.336. 5. Cf. Corp. Herm. XII, 23. 183. 13.
63. Asclep. :\I. 339. 26.
64.1bid. :H. 339. 2'5-26. Cf. Corp. Herm. \'. 10. 64. 13.
6'5. Asclep. 27. 3.U. 10.
66. Ibid. 14. 313. 17. Cf. Corp. Herm. VIII. 2. 88, 2 and XVIII. 9. 252. 3.
6"".Asclep. 14.313.16-17and26.331. II.
68. l"'tl. 30. 338. 16. Cf. Corp. Herm. 11. 12. 37. f and X. l'f, 120, 2.
69. See pp. 269-272.
THE ASCLEPIUS 345
his mind will be filled with all goods. However, it may be more
correct to say that his mind will be filled with the one good
which contains all, there being a reciprocal relation between the
notions of unity and totality: 'All things are of one and the one is
all things since these are so connected with one another that it is
impossible to separate them'. 7 0 It is important to note that,
when the Hermeticist speaks of the reciprocal implication of
unity and totality, he is referring not simply to a relation bet-
ween two concepts- 'one' and 'all'- but to the association of
cause and effect- God and his creation. This is indicated clear-
ly in the later passage where Hermes argues that God can be
described with the names of all the things which he creates -
either hy applying his name to all of them or all their names to
him - 'because he is himself both one and all'. 71 Here we learn
two facts: first, that unity represents God and totality his crea-
tion and secondly, that God can be described as unity or totality
because he is identical with his creation .
~o. Asclep. I. 296, 11-13 rmmia unlus esse emf unum esse omnia; IICI
enim sibi est utrumque cone.'l:tan, ut separari alterum ab utro non possil.
U Cm11. 1/erm. Xll, H. 1"'7. S; Xlll. 17, 207, IH; Xlll, IH. 20H, 3: and XVI. 3.
2.U. IH-.n.3 . .3.
"'I .hclep. 20 ..U I. 7 siquidem is siltmus et omnia.
~ 2. For the Stoic (or syncretistic Stoic and Platonic) position sec p. 9.3 ff.
(Cicero) and p. 168 ff. (Seneca). Of course, the Stoic doctrine holds that God
is hoth transcendent and immanent. However, the: transcendence is not
metaphysical in this case:. Sec: pp. 96-97 (Cicero) and pp. 170-174 ff. (Seneca).
346 MIDDlE PlATONISM
13. Asclep. ;H. 344, 22-23 om11it1 enlm deus et t~b eo omnia et eius omnit1
tolu1lft~tis. Cf. ibid. 2. 298, 3--i .
..,4. Ibid. 2. 29". 23-29H. I mm enim lmc di:~:i. omnia unum esse etunum
omnia, utpote quae in (Tea/ore Juerint omnia. antequam creasset omnia?
Cf. ibid. 14, 3 I 3, "-9.
7';. This pre-existence of created things in God is presumably - along
rr;Iditional Platonic lines- as Forms in the divine mind. For the appearance
of this latter notion in the Asclepius sec pp. HS-350.
""'6. Sec n . ..,3.
"7. !Md. 26 . .'d I. 12-1-i 'For the will of God has no hq.:innin~. It is the
same and as it is eternally. Indeed. the plan of God's will is equivalent to his
nature' (toltmlfiS etenim dei caret initio, quae emlem est et. sinlli est, sem-
piterna. dei enim 1/ctlum nmsilium ('Sf tolunttltis). Cf. Corp. Herm. X. 2.
113. 11-12.
THE ASCLEP/l!S .:\-!7
"'8. Asclep. 8, 30S, 12-1 'i For the will of God itself is the highest comple-
tion. since he realizes his willing and completion at the same instant of time'
(toluntas etenim dei ipsa est summa perfectio, utpote cum t.oluisse et
pe1:{ecisse 11110 eodemque temporis puncto conp/eclt). Cf. Corp. llerm. XIII.
19.208, 1-f-l'i .
... 9. Asdep. 20, 321, 9-11 'He is absolutely filled with the fertility of hoth
M:xes: always pregnant with his will and always giving hirth (utraque sexus
fenmditate plenissimus. semper tmluntatis praegmms stwe parit semper).
That creation is both unchanging and temporal was dearly grasped by Scott:
op. L'it. Ill, pp. 184 and 192-193.
HO. That God transcends time (as opposed to hc:ing eternal in time) is not
explicitly stated in the Asclepius, although this notion is undoubtedly im-
plkd hy the essentially Platonic theology expounded there. Cf. Corp. Herm.
XII. 2~. 183, I~- J.i 'there is no time in relation to God' (OUT xp6vo~ 1tEPi tov
96v Eon).
HI . .lsclep. 2. 298. 1-2 nee inmerito ipse diet us est om11ia. cui us membra
sunt omnitl.
.'\48 MIDDLE PLATONISM
82. This <:ombination of Platonic and Stoic nOiions would not really be
no\'cl, but simply a reflection of tendencies in second-century (and also
e;arlicr) thought.
8.'\. Sec pp. 25 "'-250. The Hcrmeticist uses the: terminology: deus. genera
(species. formae). mundus. That mundus = uA.n is indicated at ibid. 11. 315.
1-5; lL .H5. 20; and 17,515. 2-L
8-i. Ibid. 32 . .Ho. 16-21 omnis ergo sensus dit>i11ilatis simi/is inmobilis
THE ASCLEPIUS 349
implkd not only by the terminology itself but by the details of the Hermetic
theory of Forms to be studied below.
92. To the theory of Forms presented in the: L;uin work it is Corpus
Hermeticum XVI which furnishes the most striking parallels. Sec: the follow-
ing passages in relation to each of the categories listed below: (i) Cmp. Herm.
X\'1. R. 2.~-1. 20-235. 2; (ii)/bid. XVI. 9. 235. 3; (iii)/bid. XVI, 17,2:\7. 11-12;
(iv) ibid. XVI. I 5, 236. 18-26; and (v) ibid. XVI, 17. 237. 12 H.
9:~. Sec: Nock and Festugiere: op. cit .. p. 360 (commenting on Asclep. i.
300, i-10) 'Au surplus, toutle passage est tres embrouille, et je doute que
I' auteur se soit compris lui-meme'.
9-!. The main passages are: Asdep. 3. 299 ..'\--!, 300, 18 (text I); ibid. 17.
-~ 16. 'i-18. 318, 2 (text II); and ibid. 34. :H.f, 1.~36. 347. 3 (text Ill).
9'i. IIJid. 3. 299. 131 5 (text I) 'Nature imprints Forms upon matter
through the: four elements' (natura autem per species imagilums mundum
fJerqtulttuorelementa). Cf. ibid. 36. 346. 10-3-!7, 3 (text Ill).
96. Ibid. 4, 299, 19-300, 7 (text I) 'The species of gods produces from itself
individual gods, the species of demons and similarly that of men produces in-
dividuals like itself' (genus ergo deorum ex se deorum faciel species.
de~enumum genus. aeque hom inurn ... sui similes species gener(lt). The: usc:
of these two types of Form follows the tradition of Platonic doxography. See
pp. 290-292.
352 MIDDLE PLATONISM
97. Ibid. 4. 299. 17-19 (text I) and ibid. 4, .300, 10-12 (text 1).
98. Ibid. 35, 345, 10-11 (text III).
99. Ibid. 17, 3 16, 11-13 (text II) and ibid. 35, 345, 24-:H6, 2 (text Ill).
100. Cf. ibid. 35. 345, 13-15 (text III) and Ibid. 35, 345. 24-346. 2 (text Ill)
-higher Form; ibid. 35, 345, 19 (text Ill) and ibid. 35, 346, 4-6 (text Ill)-
lower Form: ibid. 17, 316. II (text II)- uncertain status.
I 0 I. Cf. ibid. 34, 3H, 20 (text Ill) and passages mentioned in no. 96 and
98.
I02.1bid. 4, 299, 19-300,2 (text I) and ibid. 4, 300,8-18 (text 1).
I 03. JfJid. 4, 299. I 8-19 (text I) and Ibid. 4. 300, 10 (text 1).
10-f.lbld. 35. 315, 11-316. 6(1ext Ill).
I 05. Ibid. 17, 3 16, 12 (text II); ibid. 17. 3 16, 17-:\17. I (text II); and Ibid.
.'\5, 345. 18 (text III).
106. Ibid. 35. :H5. 17-20 (text III).
I 07. Ibid. 4. 300, 8- I 8 (text 1). For the distinction of transcendent and im-
manent Forms in earlier Platonism see pp. 18 I ff. and 293 ff. The
Hermeticist 's use of idea for the immanent Form at ibid. 17, 316, 17 deviates
somewhat from this traditional theory.
108. Ibid. .H. 344, 19-22 (text III) 'This so-called sensible world is the
receptacle of all the qualities or substances of sensible Forms. None of these
THE ASCLEP/l!S
thin~s can have life without God' (hie ergo sensibilis qui dicitur mundus
receptaculum est omnium sensibilium specierum qua/ittltum 11e/ cor-
purum. quae omnia sine deo regetari mm possunt). If the ambiguous quae
of the last clause refers to species rather than corpora, then the argument is
that (;od docs not merely preside over the instantiation of the Forms hut a<.-
wally gives them existence. Seen. 110.
109. IIJid. -~- 299. 11-13 (text I) 'Matter has been prepared by God as the
ren:ptade of all kinds of Forms' (mundus aulem praeparatus est a deo
receptaculum omnifonnium specierum).
110. /!Jid. .B. 343. 2-8 (text Ill) 'just as this so-called place outside the
world (if there is such a thing- which I do not believe) would have to be fill-
ed. I think. with intelligible things similar to the divinity of that place. thus
the ~o-called sensible world is filled with bodies and living creatures similar
to ih nature and quality' (sicttfi enim quod dicitur exlrCI mundum, si tamen
est ttliquid (nee istud enim credo), sic babeo. plmum esse inte/legibilium
remm. id est ditinitati suCle simi/lum, ut hie etiam sensibi/ls mundus qui
tlicitur sit plenissimus corporum et Clnimalium 'wturae sue1e el qua/itali
crmtenientium). It is quite clear from the context that the author postulates
two lnds of reality: the 'intelligible world' (intel/igiiJilis mu11clus (ibid. .34 .
.-\H. 1-i )) comprising God and the higher Forms and the 'sensible world' (se11-
siln'lis numdus (ibid. 31 ..HL 19)) comprising matter and the lower Forms.
The implication of the main passage is therefore that the higher level of reali-
ty can only he a realm filled with metaphysical principles, and not a realm of
l'lllpty physical space as visualized in the traditional Stoic doctrine of the sur-
round in~ void.
I I I . S~:e n. I 07.
112./hid. 19.319.1-S.
MIDDLF. PLATONISM
There now seems little room for doubt that the traditional
doctrine of the three principles is a fundamental philosophical
motif of the Asclepius. It is also clearly established that two of
these principles are ultimate in the sense that neither can he
reduced to the other, even if some modern interpreters have at-
tempted to find a monistic position expressed.l24 However, the
11-1. Thus, Scott maintained that of the components into which he divides
tht 1n:atise Asclepius I ( 1-14) and Asclepius III (I 6-41) are monistic while
Asclepius II ( 14-16) is dualistic in character. Furthermore. he argued that
e\'en Asclepius II ( 14-16) holds its dualism in a restricted form. See Scott: op.
cit. 111. pp. 82, 87, 123. In accordance with this thesis, Scott suggested that
Asclep. :\. 299. 11-13 (sec n. 109) meant not that God simply ordered matter
hut thai he actually created it (Scott: op. cit.. p. 22); that Asclep. 14. 314, 3-4
.\Iauer is therefore able to produce alone. without joining with another prin-
cipk' (baec itaque sine alieno comeptu est sola generabilis) does not imply
re:llly independent causality on matter's part (Scott: op. cit., p. 87); and that
.t.~clep. 19. 320, 5 (seen. 118) was inserted into the argument by an inter-
polator who misunderstood its real significance (Scott: op. cit., p. 123). Of
toursc. thl' interpretation of these texts along such lines is only possible in
nmjunction with the thesis that the Asclepius is composed of several smaller
lr~::nbes. However, the notion that they expound a monism is held by Scott
to he supported (i) by the presence of the one-all doctrine (Asclep I, 296.
I 1-12 and 20. 321. 7) which seems to contradict dualism; and (ii) by clearly
monistit st:ucments in the Greek treatises (Corp. Henn. Ill, I, 44, 2-3 and
XII. 22, 183, 7-8) and testimonia (Iamblichus: De Myst. 8, 3. 265, 6-7 cf. Pro-
dus: In Tim. l, 386, 10-11). See Scott: op. cit., pp. 10, 22, and 138. In reply
to I his interpretation one must say that the thesis of the Asclepius' composite
structure is if not untenable certainly not demonstrated. Furthermore. the
prestnte of the word receptaculum in Asclep. 3, 299. Il-l:\ indicates that
tht author may be thinking of Plato's (mo6ox11 which has not previously been
intcrprtted as caused by God. In addition. the statement of ibid. 14, 314, 3-4
that mattt:r is an independent source of causality must be taken at face value
in the abst:nce of definite evidence to the contrary. Finally. the notion of an
interpolation at ibid. 19, 320, 5 cannot be maintained without the highly
spt:culative thesis of tht: work's multiple authorship. We must therefore con-
dude that. despite the undeniable existcnct: of monistic tendencies in the
<in:ek trt:uises, the Asclepius remains in the tradition of Platonic dualism.
MIDDLE PLATONISM
135. Ibid. 31. 339. 1113. At Ibid. 30. 339. 1-3 the mobility of time is said
to begin and end in Eternity's immobility.
136. Ibid. 31 ..H9. l-i-20. The whole argument regarding the relation of
Eternity and time is of great subtlety (ibid. 31. 339. 8-18). In brief it runs as
follows: (i a) time is moving, (i b) Eternity is immobile, (i c) since time's mo-
tion is cin:ular it is also immobile in a sense; (ii a) time has a circular motion
from and towards Eternity (held to be a restatement of (i c)), (ii b) Eternity is
Immanent in time. (ii c) Eternity has a circular motion from and towards itself
(resulting from the combination of (ii a) and (ii b)). This argument shows that
the relation between Eternity and time is one containing moments of both
transcendence and immanenl'C: transcendence in (i a) and (i b). immanence in
(ii b), and transcendence: and immanence in (i c). (ii a), and (ii c). Historically
speaking. it represents a combination of the Platonic notion of a transcendent
relation between eternity and time (see Plato: Tim. 37d where the eternity of
the Living Creature is the paradigm of the heavenly bodies' temporal motion)
and the Aristotelian notion of their immanent relation (sec Aristotle: De
Cae/o l, 9. 279a25-2H where eternity is the sum of all time constituted by the
heavenly bodies' rotation). There is no definite literary evidence of the com-
bination of these two texts by the Hermeticist. although either he or his
source has subconsciously made the doctrinal synthesis.
1r. Asclep. 30.338. 11-12.
THE ASCLI:"Pf{fS 361
15H. Tht relation of God as Etc:rnitv to time is of a similar kind. Sc:e n. I ~6.
I W . .lsclejJ. 16. 31 ;, 13-1 'i. . .
lHl./hid.l-.5l'i.22-2-f.
362 MIDDLE PLATONISM
J(,J. To a great extent this depends upon the interpretation given to God's
bisexuality. On the notion of the 'malc-fem:tle' (appEv69T]A.uc;) sec J. Kroll:
/Jie J.ebren des Hermes Trismegistos (Beitriige zw (iescbichte tier
l'bilusopbie des Mille/alters 1.2 . .2-i) (Munster. 191.~). pp.; 1-S.f; Scott: up.
cit. Ill, pp. 135-1)8; Nock and Festugiere: op. cit. I. p . .20; Festugiere: La
l't'tt!latiml d 'Hermes Trismegiste IV: Le Dieu incomm et Ia gnose. pp. 4 351;
and Fcstugiere: Hermelisme et mystique paienne, pp. 2'57 -260. From the
nidence assembled by these modern scholars. it seems that the notion ap-
pears in at least three contexts: (i) Ancient religions of Egypt and Greece. See
the texts assembled by Scott: op cit. Ill, pp. 135137; (ii) Stoicism. See
l>iogcnes of Babylon in Philodemus: De Plet. 15-17 (DG S48bi4-S50b8 =
SVF Ill Diog. 33): Varro: Logist. Curio fr. 2 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VII, 9 (CCSL
-1-. 19:\-Jl)..j )); and Firmicus Matern us: Matb. V, pr. 3: (iii) Pythagorean ism or
:'1-lcopythagoreanism. Sec ps.-lambl. Tbeol. Aritbm. 53. 21, 4, I. leaving aside
c.atcgory (i) whose position was later interpreted according to the
philosophical views implied by categories (ii) or (iii), it should be noted that
the notion of a bisexual God means something different in category (ii) and
catc.gory (iii) respectively. In the former it signifies the God immanent in the
world. that immanence being inrerpreted as the union of active (male) and
passin (female) prindph:s. In the latter it signifies that God who transcends
and is immanent in the world, the transcendence being represented by the
priority of the. monad (male) to the dyad (female) and the immanence by the
production by the monad of the dyad. Since the Asclepius is a synthesis of
hoth Stoic and Platonic or Pythagorean notions, it is difficult to say which of
thcsl approaches dominates in the Hcrmeticist's mind. The same can be said
of other references to the 'male-female' in later eclectic sources like
Ps Aristotle: nEpi K6o).IOU 7. 40 I b2 ( = Apuleius: De Mundo 37, 372) and
Corp. flerm. I, 9. 9. 16.
366 MIDDLE PLATONISM
162. Asclep. 39. 349, 19-350, 6. Part of this text is preserved in the Greek
by Lrdus: De Mens. IV, 7, 71. 1-4 it tif: Ei~-taPilEVfl tori Kai it Ei~-taptl'J tvpyta
ij autoc; 6 9oc; ij llEt'EKiVfiV TETQYilEVfl Katci 7t<i.VTWV oupaviwv T Kai
tntyEiwv !lEta tftc; tivayKflc; r<i~tc;.
163. In order to simplify the argument I shalllaht:lthe various 'definitions'
as follows: (i a) quam Ei~-taPilEVfiV ... tincta, (i h) effectrix rerum. (ii a) deus
summus. (ii h) lib ipso ... deus. and (i c) omnium cae/estlum ... disciplina.
The reason for my division into type (i) and (ii) is explained below.
THE ASCLEPIUS 367
Seneca: De Benef IV. 7. 1-2 (SVF II, 1024 ); Diugenes Laertius: Vit. Pbi/os.
VII. I ;\';-1 ;\6 (SVF I. 102 and II, ';80); and Alexander of Aphrodisias: De Fato
ll. 191. .'\0 (SVF II, 94';).
171. See Ps.-Plutarch: De Fato 2, S68e; Nemesius: De Nat. Hom. 38.
"1S3Bff.; and Calcidius: In Tim. 144, 182. 16-183. I. On Calcidius' doctrine
see pp. -i"7-i-17S.
172. AsclefJ. 19. :\18, 22-:\19. II. The section dealing with the uusi;~rch
Fate is preserved in Greek at Lydus: De Mens. IV. 7, 70. 23-24.
1"'.~. In this astronomical passage it is clearly Jupiter alone who could
signify the highest God. Fate is contrasted with this Jupiter.
1"1-1. Asc/ep. -tO. 3S I. .~-1-i.
THE ASCLEPIUS 369
I"'<;. In this an:ount of the three principles their relation to Eternity cor-
re'p<mds to their relation to God. God and Eternity are co-extensive.
1-(,. lfJid. -tO, 3'S I. 1-t-22.
I"'"'. See pp. 366-368.
370 MIDDLE I' LA TON ISM
god' (ipse enim sol ... secundum etenim deum bzmc crede).IB'i
What are we to make of this discrepancy?
The answer to this question lies in the association of the
world and the sun according to the Hermetic philosophy. Thus,
that these are not really independent of one another is indicated
(i) by the world's government of all physical processes utilizing
the instrumentality of the sun; 11!6 (ii) by the identity of function
between the two: just as the world is 'dispenser of life' (vitae
dispensator)IB"' so is the sun 'ruler of vital processes' (guber-
nator vitalium); 1ss and (iii) by the analogy of the sun's illumina-
tion of the world and intellect's illumination ofman.IH9 Of these
points the last is especially revealing about the Hermeticist's
philosophical beliefs.
In particular. it is clear that he subscribes to the common
teaching that the world is a 'living being' (animaf),190 and this
implies in its turn that the world consists of a body and a soul.
The latter doctrine is explicitly stated in at least one passage
where God is described as the ruler of the world, its soul. and
the world's contents.l91 Furthermore he assents to the tradi-
tional notion that this soul is 'the container of all sensible
Forms' (receptaculum ... sensibilium omnium specierum), 192
thereby indicating that the principle represents a source of
IR'i. Ibid. 29, .'\36. 16-3.~7. 3. Cf. Corp. Herm. XVI. 6. 234. 4-6: XVI. 12,
235. 25- 236. 3; XVI, 17, 237, 11-14. etc.
186. Asclep. 3. 299. 4-'i and 30. 3:P. 23-338. 2.
IH7. Ibid. 30. 3;\7. 2;H3H. I. Cf. ibid..'\. 299 . ."1-4 and 27. 332,4-5.
lRR.Ibid. 29.337. 12-li.
189. lbitl. 18,317. 1-il'i.
190. Ibid. 29. 337. 'i.
191. IIJid . .'\. 299. 'i-7. The: phrase: meli tem et ips ius emimae here: could
mean either 'of the world and its soul' or 'of the world and the soul itself'.
Howc:\c:r, in hoth cases the reference is to a universal and not an indi\idual
soul. Sc:e also ibid. 2, 298. 12-13 and 3. 298. P -19.
192.1bid. 32. 3-iO, 21-23.
THE ASCLEP/US
llH. Ibid. 32, 341, 9-13. The world soul is des<:ribed with varying ter-
minology: (i) anima [sc. cae/i or mtmdi] (see ibid. 2. 29M, 12; 3. 29H. 19;
and .~. 299, <;-6), (iil sensus mtmdi!sensus mundtmus (see ibid. 32, 340.
21-22; :H. 341. 10; and 32, 342. 2),and (iii) intellectus mtmdi (see ibid. j2,
.~12. 1 ). Regarding (ii) two ohservations are required: first, that sensus is the
translation of the Greek vou~ (see nn. 42 and R<;-R6) and secondly, that
rdlrences 10 the world soul as ljiU"/.J(Iartima and vour:,lintellectus are equally
common in syncretistic literature (see ch. 1, n. 2';<;, ch. I. n. 316 and app .. n .
.~H).
llJ1. Ibid. .U. 342. 1-S.
19'\. Tht: author adds a note saying that we plrcc:ive the intelligihl<: gods
more clearly than the sensible om:s (magis en im ipsos sen tim us quam eos).
IWl. A note is added that the sensihle gods accomplish ;til things in sensi-
hk nature, acting one through another' VJer sensibi/em rwturam conficitmt
om nit~, lifter per alterum):
.374 MIDDLE PLA TONIS~I
197./bid. 19,318,5-21.
198. Festuglere: Henm!tisme et m;stique paienne, p. 12S suggests the
possibility that the intelligible gods are distinct from the ousiarchs to be men-
tioned below. This would follow from understanding specierum principes
dii as 'gods who rule (are prior to) substances (transcendent substances)'.
these latter being interpreted as equivalent to the ousiarchs. However,
Fcstugiere: op. cit .. p. 12S, n. 19 and 128, n. 30 rightly rejects this com-
plicating factor not supported elsewhere by the text. In short, it seems clear
that (i) specierum principes dii, (il) princeps ouaia<; (accepting the likely con-
jecture ouaia(<;) of Ferguson), and (iii) ouauipXTJ<; all refer to the same thing
or things.
199. These will he immanent ami not transcendent Forms.
2011. This substance will correspond to their immanent Form.
20 I. That the phrase utriusque originis cons/miles suae indicates that the
sensible gods are constitmed (i) by their dependence upon the intelligible and
(ii) by their association with a material body is convincingly suggested hy
:-.Jock and Festugiere: op. cit. II. p. 375.
202. On the meaning of 'ousiarch' (oumapxTJ<;) see FestugiC:re: Hernu!tisme
THE ASCLEPIUS 375
ouauipxTJ~ est Iuppiter ... so/is ouauipxTJ~ lumen est ... XXXVI
quorum vocabulum est Horoscopi . .. horum ouauipxTJ~ vel
princeps est, quem navt61J.opq>ov vel omniformem vocant ...
septem spbaerae ... babent ouauipxa~. id est sui principes,
quam fortunam dicunt aut EiiJ.apiJ.EVTJV . . . aer vero . . . est
autem ouauipxTJ~ buius secundus . .. )203 From these remarks
the following additional information is obtained: (i) Various
specific examples of (a) intelligible and (b) sensible gods are
given; and (ii) the gods of group (b) are shown to be
astronomical in character.
Modern scholarship has rightly compared the Hermeticist's
theological schema with similar systems expounded by late
Platonic writers - Porphyry, Iamblichus, and Sallustius.2o4
Although the latter often differ in detail, they frequently contain
the two fundamental aspects of the Hermetic hierarchy of gods:
first, they contrast groups of intelligible and sensible gods and
secondly, they establish correspondences between particular in-
telligible and sensible gods.2oc; That the Hermeticist's
theological doctrine agrees with the teachings of such
etmyslique pt~ienne, pp. 127 130. The writer instances some important texts
of lamblichus' De Mysterits which speak of the relation between intelligible
'ctust's (npxai) and the sensible: 'substances' (ouaiat) which they govern. Sec
/Je .~~~st. VIII. I, 260, 14-16 and Vlll. 5, 268, 6-8. These parallels are
\'alidatt'd by the fact that lamblichus is throughout this discussion referring to
thl' Egyptian or 'Hermetic' philosophy. The only difference between
lamblichus and the Latin writer is that the latter interprets oua!a + npxit as
suhst;mct ... ruler' rather than as 'substance ... caust''. Sec Fcstugicre: op.
cit .. p.l21.n.2.
l.O!t.Asclep. 19.31H,22-319,11.
204. See Festugiere: op. cit., pp. 123-125 where parallel texts are listed
and ~ummarized. For our purposes the most interesting among these an~
ptrhaps Porphyry: De Regr. Anim. fr. 6, 33" 7-34" 26; fr. 8, 36" 'i-37" 6:
and Sallustius: De Diis et Mundo S. 10, ; . 6, 12, 23. For the lamblichean
parallel seen. 202.
l.O'i. Fcstugicre: op. cit .. p. 126.
376 MIDDLE PLATONISM
206.Asclep. 18.317,21:\18.2.
20""./hid. 23. 32'i, 7-H.
20H. /IJid. 22, 321, 6-"" and 23 ..U'i, IH-19. This pr~sumahly rd~rs 10 their
predominantly fiery composition.
209. /hid. :\H, 319.9-10.
210. ibid. 35 ..:\45. 22-24. s~e pp. 353-354.
21 I. /hid. r ..'\:\2. 12-1.~. Th~ text goes on 10 sp~ak of a further 'Piutonian
Jupiter' (/uppiter Pluton ius) who prcsid~s onr earth and s~a.
212. Fcstugiere: op. cit .. p. 12'i.n. 20 and Nock and F~stugier~: op. cit. p.
:\H-t both obser\'c that the Jupitcr(s) mentioned in this passag~ arc sensible
gods contrasting with th~ Jupiter of Asclep. 19, 31 H. 22-23 who is an intdligi-
hlc one. llowenr. Scoll: op. cit. Ill. pp. 107-110 argu~s with equal plausibili-
ty that th~ Jupiter(s) of th~ lat~r passag~ arc int~lligiblc gods equivalent to the
missing ousiarchs of the earlier one.
THE ASCLEPilfS 377
Juppiter Caelum
2. 1./111/('11 Sol
Pa ntrnnorpbos 1/omscopi
<>n the lJUestion of luppiter see aho\'1:. If !uppiter P/utrmlus is also to he in-
duul'll in the sd1ema. then a sixth pair of intelligible and sensible gods must
hl adlku.
~78 MIDDLE PLATO:'IIISM
Jupiter is the first and the (sensible) world the second god,ll-i or
(ii) because the (sensible) world is the first and the (sensible) sun
the second god_ll'; However, there are obvious drawbacks since
with (i) the (intelligible) Jupiter considered as the first god, the
sensible sun cannot be described as second but only as third;
and with (ii) the (sensible) world considered as the first god, the
(sensible) world cannot also be described as second but only as
first. Perhaps the only solution, then, is to consider the series of
intelligible gods as a whole as the first god so that either the
(sensible) world or the (sensible) sun can be described as second.
This brings us to the further conclusion that, since both the
world and the sun are described as the second god in one ac-
count. while representing the first and second members of the
series of sensible gods in the other, then the world and the sun
arc both second either (i) because the (sensible) world and the
(sensible) sun are not completely distinct from one another, or
(ii) because the members of the series of sensible gods as a whole
are not distinct from one another. Of these solutions it is (ii)
which seems to he the most compelling since it not only treats
the relations between all members of the series of sensible gods
identically but it considers those relations as analogous with
those obtaining within the series of intelligible gods.
That the series of intelligible gods as a whole can he con-
sidered as the first god and the series of sensible gods as a whole
as the second god is an interpretation which is further sup-
ported by certain minor features of the account. Thus, regar-
ding the intelligible gods, the fact that Jupiter occurs more than
once suggests that the members of the series are not completely
distinct from one another,l16 while the identification of one
221. Asclep. 7, 301. 2 'man is double' (homo duplex est); ibid. II. 309. 5-6
'that double entity which is man' (id utrumque, id est homo); and ibid. 22,
324. 18 'God made him of both natures' (ex utraque natura amposuit). At
ibid. 22, 323. 2S the writer states that man has been constituted of the two
natures 'in equal proportion' (pari fa11ce).
222. For ditina see ibid. 10. 309, .~; 22, :U3, 2S: and 22. 32-i, 18; and for
hwmma, ibid. S. 302. 3.
223. For aetema see ibid. 8, 306, 4; and for mortalis, ibid. 8, 306, 4; 10 .
.'\09 ..~:and 22.324. 19.
22i. For animus/corpus see Ibid. 6, :~02, 20-303. 5 and H. 306, 2-S.
22S. for oucnti>ST]c;/uA.tK6v- mundammz sec ibid. 1. 304. 2-6 and 8, 305.
I S-:\06. 2. Scott: op. cit. pp. Hand 49 is quite correct in noting that the term
oucnti>STJc; carries a Plawnic connotation here, for the writer is speaking of the
nmjunction of intelligihk (substantial) and sensible (phenomenal) in man.
This Platonism underlies all the forms of the present dualism. However, hy
the same token Scott: op. cit. pp. H7-148 cannot be supported when he
argues that ibid. 22 ..U3. 2:~32-L 4 refers only to the conjunction of higher
and lower kinds of matter.
THE ASCLEP/l!S j81
22Cl. ll>id . ...,_ jOi. .2-6 et eius una fUll'S simplex. quae. ut Gmeci aiunt.
oumw&n<;. quam tocamus ditinae simi/itudinis formam; est autem
quadmplex, quod i/AtK6v Graeci, nos 111/IIUitmum dlcimus. For the Platonic
smse ofoumw&n<; sec: also CmtJ. Herm. 11. 'i. j3. 5--J: IX. 'i. 98. 13-1": and
XIII. II. 206. 12- U.
2r . .-lsclep. 10, 308, .23-309. I parte. qua ex anima et sensu. spiritu at-
Cflle raliflllf! ditilllls est. te/ut ex e/ementis superioribus. inscendere posse
l'ideatm in L'tle/um. parte tero mundana. quae constat ex igne et terra,
aqua et ai!re, mortalis resistat in terra.
228. 1/Jid. II. .~09. 2j-_'\ 1o. 3 quatemls eum utriusque partis elementis
cminuulterte esse formatum, numibus el pedibus utrisque bi11is a/Usque
nntmris memiJris. quibus inferior/, id est terreno, mmulo desertiat, i/lis
teru fJartilnts qua/tum anlmi, sensus. memoriae atque prol'identitte,
Cfltarum ralio11e cu11cta ditina norit e1tque suspiciCit. A more: c:laburatc ac-
l'oum of the: rc:lation between c:lc:mc:nts in the higher and luwc:r parts occurs
at Cflrp. 1/erm. I, 1'7. 12 . .20-13. 2.
382 MIDDLE PLATONISM
the two parts differ in comparison with the previous text. Final-
ly. in certain passages the Hermeticist turns from the various
conceivable subdivisions of human nature - which are com-
plementary but not equivalent to one another - to focus upon
Jhe character of the higher part alone. ThY.s. . . b~Jnforms us that
fhe~!oit--ot'-inte!,!et -d~~ends as far as .its twm~ in
h~229 that-7~J:l.QJ_m~.d~JiJ,lJlle.cLtn . ~ror despite its
(~ion with rhe marerjat .z.~o and that its divine character con-
trasts with the purely human intellect based upon the memory
of earthly events.Ht
(see Numenius: fr. 52 (Caki<.lius: In Tim. 296,298. 13-297, 299. II) 'God is.
as Plaw maintains, the beginning and cause of goods, matter of evils ... and if
the world arises from matter. it is surelr made from a nature which was
formerly evil' (Deum quippe esse - ut etiam Platoni 11idetur - initlum et
causam bonorum, si/tam malorum ... Quod si mundus ex silva, certe fac-
tus est de existente olim natura maligna)). The positive viewpoint reflects
the Stoic position (see Cicero: Cato Maior 77 'I believe that the immortal
gods scattere<.l souls into human bodies, so that there might be those who
might tend thl' earth and contl'mplate the heavenly order' (credo deos inmor-
tales spars/sse mtimos in cmtmra lmmcma. ut essen/ qui terrtts tuerentur
quique cae/estium ordinem contemplantes ... )). A similar ambivalenet: oc-
curs in the: Greek Hermetic treatises: for thl' negative: view see Corp. Herm.
VI, 3. 7'1, 6-10: VI, 4. 74, 17-18; and VII, 3. 82,4-6, etc. and for the positive
i!Jid. VI. 2 ... ;\, I 1-12; IX, 4. 98. 4-7. etc The tt."nsion between pessimistic an <.I
optimistil' views of the cosmos in the Hermetictt has been exhaustively
studied hy Festugierc: La retelflfirm d'Hermes Trismegiste ll: Le Dieu cosmi-
que. pp. x-xiii and pe~ssim who traces both tendencies ultimately back 10
Plato.
242. Asclep. 3 7. 34 7. 8-10. Cf. ibid. 2.-\ ..US, 8-1 I.
243. ibid. 23. 325, 20-326, 2 'The forms of the gods which man makes are
composed of two natures: of the divine which is purer and much more
divine. and of that which occurs among men - the matter' (species vero
tleorum, qutts conformal humanitas, e:r: utraque 11t1tura confonnatae sunt;
ex ditina, quae est purior multoque ditinior, et ex ea, quae intra homines
est, id est ex materia) and ibid. 37. 347, 15-18 'Since thev were not able to
fashion souls, they evoked the souls of demons or angeis ami introduced
them into their statues with holy and divine rites' (quoniam animasfacere
mm poterant, etJocatlles ttnimas daemmrum 11el a,ge/orum eas indiderent
imaginihus sanctis ditinisque mysteriis). For further details of this theory
see ibid. 24, 326, 10-15 and 38. 349. 9-1 S.
2'14. Ibid. 23. 325. 6-10.
THE ASCLEPIUS 385
21 'i. Ibid. 2, 297. 17-18 Every human soul is immortal' (omnis humana
inmortalis est anima). The statement reads like a translation of Plato;
Pbaedr. 2..j 'ic 'All soul is immortal' (IJIUX~ ndaa a9civato<;).
216. Asclep. 2, 297, 18-19. Cf. ibid. 25. 329, 5-8.
21"'7. Ibid. 12 ..HI, 8-9 futurae aetemitatis spes. Cf. ibid. 22 ..'n4. 16 and
ibid. 29 . .~:\6, 10-11.
218. Ibid. 28. 335. 2 aeternae poenae.
219. /hid. 28, 334. :\-6 'A~ soon ;ts the soul has departed from its body, it
will pass for judgment and examination of its worth into the power of the
supn:me demon' (cum fuerit ani mae e corpore facta (/iscessio, tunc ar-
fJitrium e.\'amenque meriti eius trm1siet in summi daemonis potestatem).
This passage is one of the few in which demons enter in a structurally signifi-
ctnt way into our writer's system. The reference to a .mmmus dmmwn -
which is not paralleled in the Greek version of the same passage in Lydus; De
.Hem. 1\', 149. 167. I 7-21 -is interpreted hy :'~Jock and Festugicre: op. cit ..
p. -~85 as applying to Mithras. Whatever the identity and role of this divinity
b. then.- is no doubt that he operates strictly under the control of the supremt
<;od, who is ebewhere stated to determine the destiny of souls. See nn. 250
and 251.
386 MIDDLE PLATONISM
5.35 CONCLUSIONS
Cireek K60ilO<; = (i) 'adornment'. (il) 'world'. while in latin mundus = (i)
pure'. (ii) 'world'. On the theory of macrocosm and microcosm implied here
scech.l,n.87.
EXCURSUS A
389
;\90 MIDDLE PLATONISM
~trikin~ parallels between De Die Nat. 4-13 and the fragments of Actius'
Placita and, since the former text seemed to him excerpted from Varro's
t.ngistoricus Tubero de Origine Humana, postulated an earlier doxography
upon which both Varro and Aetius depended: the 'Vestusta Placita'. The ex-
istence of :1 doxographical source prior to Censorious and Aetius seems nr-
t:tin. although the precise relation to Varro's lost text is unclear. On the dox-
ographers see pp. 242-244.
1~-This work is quoted at Censorious: De Die Nat. 2, .2. ~othing further is
known about it, and it is possible that its subtitle should be de Muneribus.
The l:mer would certainly fit better with the context of Censorious' citation.
IL This work is quoted at ibid. 9. 1. judging from the agreement between
its tilll- and the subject matter of Censorious at this point. Dicls: op. cit., p.
IH6 ff. concluded that the work was the source of De Die Nat. 4, 1-13.6 as a
wholl". The debt to Varro is acknowledged by most modern scholars,
although there is some debate about Its precise extent within the section con-
cc:rnnl. Among recent discussions see Franceschi: op. cit., p. 417; H.
Dahlmann und R. Heisterhagen: Varronische Stud/en l. Zu den Logistorici
fAhbandlungen der Akademie der Wissenschaften und der Literatur in
.llainz. gei.~tes- unci sozialuiss.-K/asse 19')7/4) (Wicsbadcn, 1917), p. 24: ).
H. Waszink: 'La creation des animaux dans Lucrcct:'. Rezue beige de
fJIJi/o/ogie et d 'histoire 42 ( 1964 ). p. ')I ff.; ). Mansfcld: The Pseudo-
lliPJmn-Citic Trctcl n&pi ti}60J.IIi6wv cb. /-II emd Cireek Pbi/osopby (Assen.
llJ-1 ). p. IHS ff.; and Rocca-Serra: up. cit., pp. ix and 42-4 3.
1<;. This work is quoted at Censorious: De Die Nell. 17, IS. Parallel
testimony in Augustine suggests that much of the argument at ibid. 17. 2 ff. is
derived from it. Sec Franceschi: op. cit .. p.594 ff.
I Cl. The: hypothesis is advanct:'d hy Rocca - Serra: op. cit. p. ix that the
digression on music at Censorinus: De Die Nat. 10, 1-15, 6 is dl"rived from
I his work.
1"'. Al'l'ording to Franceschi: op. cit., pp. 59+407 certain passagt:'s in Cen-
\orinu': De Die Nat. f"1, 2 ff. have bt:'en influenced by Varro's De Lingua
/.a/ina.
392 MIDDLE PLATONISM
Hexameron I, 1, 1-4.
397
MIDDLE PLATONISM
lengths has human conjecture gone that some, like Plato and his
followers, have established three principles of all things: God,
the archetype, and matter. They assert that these are incorrupti-
ble, uncreated, and without beginning; that God is not the
creator of matter but, by looking towards the archetype, that is
to say the Idea, after the manner of a craftsman, he made the
world from matter- this matter which they call UAfl being said
to have provided the causes of their becoming to allthings;2 and
that the world also is incorruptible and neither created nor
made. Furthermore others, like Aristotle in discussions with his
disciples, have postulated two principles: matter and form, and
together with these a third called ''the efficient" to which it was
permitted serviceably to accomplish whatever task he thought
should be undertaken. But what is more inappropriate than to
connect, with these thinkers, the eternity of his work with the
eternity of the omnipotent God; or to declare that the work
itself is God so that divine honors are conferred on the heaven,
the earth, and the sea? From this it follows that they should hold
the parts of the world to be gods, although concerning the
world itself there is no shortage of dispute among them. Thus,
Pythagoras asserts that there is one world, while others main-
tain that there are innumerable worlds, as Democritus writes, a
thinker to whom the ancients assigned the greatest authority in
nee qui rzumerr1s nee qui locus aut vita possit aut cura conprehendi, si-
quidem mtmdi aestimatione vo/ubilem rutundum ardentem quibusdam
incitaltlm motibus sine sensu deum comeniat intellegi, qui alieno. non suo
motu feratur. This Latin text bristles with ambiguities which I have attemp-
ted to resolve in my translation. although at certain points it is difficult to ad-
vocate any single rendering with confidence. There is another English ver-
sion in J. ). Savage: Saint Ambrose. Hexameron, Paradise, and Cain a1ld
Abel (The Fathers of the Church 42), translated by].]. S. (Washington. DC,
1961).
2. The translation of Savage: op. cit. p. 3 reads: 'to have given the power of
creation to all things' but is probably incorrect. In most philosophical tr:tdi-
tions known to Ambrose matter does not confer an aclite power on things.
AMBROSE W9
natural science. Aristotle presumes to say that the world has ex-
isted and will exist always, Plato however venturing to con-
clude that it did not always exist but will always exist. Yet many
writers testify in their works that the world did not always exist
and will not always exist. What estimate of the truth can there
he amidst such disagreements of the philosophers? For some
state that the world itself is a god - since it seems to contain ac-
cording to their view a divine mind, while others maintain that
the world's parts are gods,3 still others that both these notions
are correct. But with such theories one can comprehend neither
the form of these gods, nor their number, nor their place, nor
their life, nor their concerns. Indeed if we conceive the world
thus, we must view it as a god who rotates, is spherical, is fiery,
and impelled somehow to motion; and one who is devoid of
understanding and driven by an external force and not his
own':i
3. The translation of Savage: op. cit., p. 4 reads: 'Some, indeed, state that
the world itself is God, inasmuch as they consider that a divine mind seems to
he within it. while others maintain that God is in the parts of the world;
others still, that He is in both - in which case it would be impossible to
<.ktnmine what is the appearance of God. or what is his number, position.
life. or activity'. By interpreting these different views as varieties of
monotheism the translator appears to achieve :1 consistency with earlier
remarks in the text, yet the Latin genitive plural deorum ncar the end of the
passage shows that at lcast one of the views must he polytheistic.
-~- On Ambrose's own Christian theory of first principles - which he
dnelops as a rt:sponsc to the pagan ones- see the following studies: J. C. M.
\'an \'\'inden: st. Ambrose's Interpretation of the Concept of Matter.
l'iglliae Cbristiarzae 16 ( 1962), pp. 205-215; 'In the Beginning. Some Obser-
vations on the Patristic Interpretations of Genesis I, I'. ibid. 17 ( 1963), pp.
IO'i-121; some Additional Observations on St. Ambrose's Concept of Mat-
ter', ibid. IR (1964). pp. 144-14'i:J. Pepin: 'Echos de theories gnostiques de
Ia matiere au debut de l't:\ameron de saint Ambroise'. Romanitas et Cbris-
licmitas. Studia I. H. Waszink oblata, ediderunt W. Boer, etc. (Amsterdam.
I<r 3) pp. 2'i9-27 3 and 'Exegese de In principio ct theorie des principes dans
l'Examermr (I. 4, 12-16)', Ambrosius Episcopus (Alii del Congresso 11lterna-
400 MIDDLE PLATONISM
etudes latines 34 ( 1956), pp. 220-239; P. Hadot: 'Piaton c:t Plotin dans trois
sermons de saint Ambroise', ibid. 34 (1956), pp. 202-220; and G. Madec:
Sai111 Ambroise et Ia philosophie (Paris, 1974), pp. 109-132. However,
whatever may be the case elsewhere, the opening chapters of the: Hexameron
seems to present doxographical Platonism only.
14. Pepin: op. cit .. pp. 45-58 and 533. The relationship between the dox-
ographies of Ambrose and Hippolytus had also been noted by M. Klein:
Meletemata Ambrosiana: M.ythologica de Hippolyto, doxographica de Ex-
amerifontibus, Diss. (Konigsberg, 1927). On Hippolytus' doxography seeR.
E. Witt: Albin us and tbe History of ;'t/kldle Pillion ism (Tremsac:tions of the
Cambridge Philological Society 7) (Cambridge. 1937). pp. 96-97; C.
Moreschini: Apuleio e II Plutonismo (Firenze, 1978), pp. 178-185; and J.
Dillon: Tbe Middle Platonists. A Study of Platonism 80 B. C. to A. D. 220
(London. 19"'7), pp. 4 10-414.
EXCURSUSC
LXXXIII, Q.46
40.:\
404 MIDDLE PLATONISM
3. I han: di\'ided this text into sections and subsections according 10 prin-
ciples to be justified below.
AUGUSTINE 'lOS
perish and everything which does come into being and perish is
said to be formed in accordance with them.
(i c 3) Funhermore, the soul cannot contemplate them unless
it is rational and unless by that part of it through which it excels
- the mind or reason itself - as if by some interior and
intelligible face or eye. And even as far as the rational soul itself
is concerned, it will not be each and every one but only that
which has become holy and pure that is described as suitable for
this vision, in other words that which holds that very eye by
which those things are seen healthy, whole, serene, and similar
to the things which it aspires to behold.
(ii a) What man who has religion and is imbued with the true
religion would dare deny, indeed would not confess, even if not
yet capable of contemplating such things, that everything which
exists - that is everything which is contained in its genus by a
specific nature in order that it should exist - was made by God
the creator; that through his agency everything which lives has
life; and that the universal preservation of things and the order
itself by which that which is subject to change maintains its
temporal course in a definite measure are contained and
controlled by the laws of the highest God?
(ii b) When this has been established and agreed, who would
dare to say that God has made everything irrationally? And if
that cannot truly be said or believed, it only remains that
everything was made according to reason. Not that a man was
made according to the same reason as a horse - for that is
ridiculous to believe - but each individual thing was created
according to its proper reason.
(ii c I) And where could these reasons be thought to exist ex-
cept in the very mind of the creator? For he did not contemplate
anything lying outside himself so that he might produce what he
produced in accordance with it - to believe such a thing would
indeed be blasphemous. Thus, if these reasons of all things to be
created or already created are contained in the divine mind, and
406 MIDDLE PLATONISM
if nothing can exist in the divine mind which is not eternal and
immutable, and if Plato called these primary reasons of things
Ideas; then not only do the Ideas exist but they exist truly
because they are eternal and remain self-identical and im-
mutable, while it comes about by participation in them that
everything which has existence exists whatever its precise
nature may be.
(ii c 2) But the rational soul, among those things which were
made by God, is superior to everything else. It is closest to God
when it is pure. and as much as it adheres to him in charity so
much is it suffused in a certain way by him with that intelligible
light and having been illuminated perceives those reasons not
through corporeal eyes but through that ruling part of itself by
which it excels - that is through its intellect - and becomes
most blessed in the vision of them.
(ii c 3) As we have said, these reasons may be called Ideas,
forms. species, or reasons. it being granted to the many to call
them whatever they wish, but to the very few to see what is the
truth' .4
<;. For studies of the doctrinal content of the quaestio see the following: H.
Meyerhoff: 'On the Platonism of St. Augustine's Quaestio de Jdeis', New
Scholasticism 16 (1942) pp. 16-4<; and A. Sollgnac: 'Analyse et sources de Ia
Question De ldeis'. Augustinus Magister (Congres International Augusti-
n len, Paris. 21-24, septembre I 9 54) I (Paris, 1954 ), pp. 307-31 <;.
6. As parallel examples of the way in which Augustine will argue to the
same metaphysical doctrine successively from different viewpoints see De
Ord. II, <;, 16 (CCSl 29, II ';-116) and De Vera Relig. 24. 4';- .~8. 71 (CCSL 32.
21 '5-234). In these cases the doctrine of the Trinity is the culmination of
philosophical and Christian philosophical arguments respectively.
7. The notion that one can deduce a philosophical truth from the univer-
sally held bdiefs of mankind is Stoic in origin. Augustine could have found it
in texts like Cicero: De Nat. Deor. II. 5 - where the existence of the gods is
demonstrated- and Cicero: Tusc. Disp l, 36- where it is the soul's survival
after death which is shown.
8. The notion that one can argue from a charalteristic of the microcosm to
AUGUSTINE 409
12. Cf. Hippolytus: Pbilos. 19 (DG 567, 14-15). Apuleius rna) have drawn
the same t:ondusion from this doxo~raphy or its sourt:e. Sl'C p. 2H9 and t:h. 4.
n. 25:\.
13. Cf. Cicero: Om/. 10; De Rep. Ill. 33; Arius Didymus: Epit. PIJys. fr. 1
(DG 447a8-9 and b7-8); Plotinus: Emz. Ill, 7 /45/3, l-2; IV, 7/2/8, 42-43; etc.
The Plotinian passages cited in this and the next few notes refer explicitly to
Intellect and therefore implicitly ;1lso to the Ideas.
14. Cf. Cicero: De Leg. ll, 8; Aetius: Plac. l, 3. 21 (DG 288a4-6 and b4-6); I,
10, 3 (DG 309a 1-i}.
15. Cf. Plotinus: Enn. l. 3 /20/ 4. 9-12; III, 9/13/ I, 8-10; etc. On the Ploti-
nian citations see n. 1.~.
16. Cf. Cicero: Oral. 10; De Rep. Ill, 33; Plotinus: Emz. Ill. 7/45/3. 15-17;
IV, 7/2/8, 42-43; etc. On the Plotinian citations seen. 13.
17. Cf. Cicero: Orat. 10; Aetius: Plac. I, 10, 1 (DG 308bl7-20); Arius
Didymus: Epit. Phys. fr. 1 (DG 447a3-4 and b2-3); Plotinus: Enn. l, 2 /19/2,
3-4; V, 8/31/7, 23-24; etc. On the Plotinian citations seen. 13.
18. Cf. Cicero: Oral. 10, 101; Plotinus: Enn. Ill, H 13015, 10-12; V, 3/49/
3. 9-13; etc. On the Plot in ian citations seen. I 3.
19. Cf. Plotinus: Enn. I. 2 /19/4, 13-15; V, 3 /49/ 3. 9-13: etc. On the Ploti-
nian citations seen. I.-\.
AllGlJSTINE 411
eye (ilium ipsum oculum quo videntur ista, non per corporeos
oculos) (i c 3. ii c 2);20 they are perceived by a soul which is
similar to them (simi/em his rebus quas videre intendit, deo
proxima) (i c 3. ii c 2).21 Finally. among examples of these Ideas
are included the species of man and horse (ii b),22 perhaps
together with their individual instances (singula igitur propriis
sunt creata rationibus) (ii b)23 and presumably together with
other natural species, these last two points however not being
stated with the clarity we might desire.
This interesting quaestio contains some peculiarly Augusti-
nian features although it is primarily a compilation of doctrine
from earlier sources, these being identifiable with virtual cer-
tainty as at least three in number: Cicero,2-J doxographic.l';
20. Cf. Plotinus: Eml. V, I /10/ I, 32-33; VI. H /39/ 19, 1-3; etc. On the
Plotinian citations seen. 13.
21. Cf. Hippolytus: Philos. 17 (DG S69. 14-1 S). On the importance of Hip-
polytus doxography for Augustine's predecessor Ambrose see pp. 401-402.
22. Cf. Actius: Plac. I, 10, I (DG 308bl8-20); Arius Didymus: Epil. Phys.
fr. I (DG H7aS-16 and b4-8); Plotlnus: Eml. V, 9/5/ 12, 1-3; VI, 7 /38/8, S-8;
etc.
2.'\. Cf. Plotinus: Enn. V. 7 /18/ I, 18-21; V, 9/S/ 12. 3-10; etc. It is not cer-
tain whether Augustine is saying that each individual has an inditidual
rlason or simply a specific one. If the former is the case his theory is definite-
ly influenced by Plotinus ar this point.
2. On Augustine's use of Cicero sec M. Testard: Saim Auguslfn et Ciceron
111 (Paris, 1958) and H. Hagendahl: Augustine and tbe Latin Classics uith a
Contribution on Vm.,.o by B. Cardarms (Goteborg. 1967). pp. i79-58R.
Thesl writers are mainly concerned with explkil citations of Cin:ro rather
than unacknowledged doctrinal influences. but it is obvious that an ahun-
dann of the former makes the frequency of the latter very likely.
25. See P. Courcelle: Late Latin Writers and tbeir Greek Sources,
translated by H. E. Wedeck (Cambridge. MA. 1969) pp. 192-194; Solignac:
Analysl' et sourn:s de Ia question De /deis', pp. 313-315 and 'Doxographies
tt manul'ls dans Ia formation philosophique de saint Augustin'. Recherches
412 MIDDLE PLATONISM
writers. and Plotinus.26 From the first source come the ap-
plication of the term 'reasons' to the Ideas, and the notions that
they are eternal. contained in the divine intellect, immutable,
sources of form to transitory thing, and perceived by the soul's
rational part.2 7 Parallels in the doxographers can be found to
the description of the Ideas as forms; to the notions that they
are themselves unformed, eternal, contained in the divine in-
tellect, sources of form to transitory things, perceived by a soul
which is similar to them; and to the inclusion of natural species
among the Ideas.2s From the last source come the hesitancy
regarding the application of the term 'reasons' to the ideas; the
notions that they are eternal, truly existent, immutable, and
sources of form to transitory things; that they are perceived by
the soul's rational part, by a soul which is pure, by the soul's eye
and by a soul which is similar to them; and the inclusion of
natural species among the Ideas and also their individual in-
- - - - - - - - - - XXIII/2 - - - - - - - - - -
STEPHEN GERSH
VOLUME II
ix
U>NTENTS
X
CONTENTS
xiii
C<>NTENTS
Conclusion 779
X\"i
COi\JTENTS
Bibliographies 843
Bibliography 1 845
Bibliography 2 855
Bibliography 3 859
Bibliography 4 861
Bibliography 5 869
Bibliography 6 871
xvii
6
Calcidius
6.1 INTRODUCTION
421
NEOPI.ATONISM
philosophic: antique durant le haut moyen age', Settimane di studio del Cen-
tro Italiano di Studi sui/'Aito Medioel'O 22 (La cultura antica nell'occidente
Iatino dal VII all" XI secolo, Spoleto 18-24 aprile 1974) (Spoleto, 1975), pp.
17-54 (notes on Calcidius' position in the mediaeval Platonic tradition in
general). On the diffusion of manuscripts and references in library catalogs
see E. Mensching: 'Zur Calcidius-Oberlieferung'. Vigi/iae Cbristianae I 9
( 1965), pp. 42-56 and M. Gibson: 'The Study of the Timaeus in the Eleventh
and Twelfth Centuries', Pensamiento 25 ( 1969), pp. 183-194. for specific
periods see P. Courcelle: Ambroise de Milan et Calcidius'. Romanitas et
Cbristianilas. Studi" I. H. Waszink obla/(1, edidenmt W. den Boer. etc.
(Amsterdam. 1973). pp. 45-53; G. Mathon: 'jean Scot Erigene. Chalcidius et le
probleme de l':lme universe lie (A propos des Annotationes in Martianum 7.
I 0)', L 'hom meet son destin d 'apres les penseurs du moyen age (Acres du fer
Ctmgres lnternatimwl de Philosopbie Medierale. Loutaiu-Bruxel/es 28
amit--1 septemb,e /')58) (lou,ain/Paris, 1960), pp. 361-3 7'5; T. Gregory:
Plutonismo Mediel'ale. Studi e ricerche, (Roma, 19'58), pp. '53-I SO; and
M.-D. Chcnu: La theologle au douzieme slecle. 3me edition (Paris, 1976). pp.
IIH-128.
-~- See especially the manuscripts Escorialensis S. Ill, 5 (eleventh century).
Vatic:mms 3815 (ele\'enth century), etc.
CAI.CIDil!S
partly cited by name and partly not cited by name in the com-
mentary, while their employment is partly direct and partly in-
direct on the author's part. The following are of special
significance: 11
(i) Sources cited by name
a) Plato
Leaving aside the base text of the commentary, the passages
drawn from Plato's dialogues include: 1) from the Theaetetus.
the comparison of the mind to a wax tablet; 12 2) from the
Parmenides, a statement about the participation of things in
Forms; 13 3) from the same work, a statement that the world of
Forms is both one and many; H 4) from the Phaedrus, the argu-
ment that all soul is ungenerated and indestructible because it is
self-moving; 1; 5) from the Theages, the description of Socrates'
16. Plato: Theag. 128d :It C:alcidius: In Tim. 2"i"i. 26;\, 20-264. 2 (quota-
tion).
17. Plato: Rep. VI "iORb-c at C:alcidius: In Tim. 242. 2"iR, 7-9 (allusion).
18. Plato: Rep. VII, "i14a ff. at Calcidius: In Tim. 349. 340. 11-14 (allu-
sion).
19. Plato: Rep. VI, "i09d-"i lie and VII. "i33d-"i3.fa at C:dcidius: In Tim.
3.:i2, 334. 20-335.4 (paraphrase).
20. Plato: Leg. X. H93h ff. at Calcidius: In Tim. 262, 268, 19-269.4.
21. In addition. the following points should be noted regarding Calcidius'
citations of Plato: (i) Passage "i) is incorrectly cited as being from the
Euthydemus; (ii) There arc: citations of Plato: Sopb. 263e at Calcidius: In Tim.
104, 1"i.'\, 23-24 and Symp. 202e at Calcidius: In Tim. 132. 174. "i-7 without
mentioning the texts by name:; and (iii) At ibid. 128, 171, .j and 2"i-t. 262. 21
the Epinomis is apparently cited as Plato's Pbilosopbus.
22. For a complc:tc: (:tllhough not annotated) list of citations of Plato sc:c
Switalski: op. cit .. pp. 1-I-18.
CALCIDIUS 427
c) Philo Iudaeus
One passage is taken from Philo: from De Opificio Mundi,
the interpretation of the scriptural phrase 'In the beginning God
made heaven and earth' as signifying that, just as he first created
an intelligible man and then according to that archetype the
bodily man, God made certain incorporeal and intelligible
substances as the Forms or exemplars of the visible firmament
and earthY' This passage accurately portrays Philo's teaching
but, since it is paraphrase rather than quotation and moreover
the only Philonic citation in Calcidius, it is impossible to say
whether it is taken directly from the Greek.31 However, since
the passage is embedded in a discussion which the commentator
has probably drawn from a Christian exegete, modern scholars
without exception consider it to be an indirect citation.32
d)Numenius
One passage is drawn from Numenius: from an unidentified
work, a discussion of first principles in which the Stoic theory is
refuted by using the combined Pythagorean and Platonic doc-
trine. This latter posits as parallel sets of contraries: monad and
dyad, God and matter, good and evil, providence and necessity,
and good and evil souls; the nature of each pair being coeternal
and together productive of things, the relation within each pair
a combination of the resistant and cooperative.33 Whether
Calcidius made use of the original text is difficult to determine
with any certainty, since of Numenius' own work only a modest
collection of fragments now remains.3 .. It is for this reason that
:\0. Philo lu<.laeus: /Jc Ofnf Mundi I. I '5-I (, and 46. l.~.:i at Calcidius: /n
Tim. 2-.8. 282, 8-11 (paraphrase).
:\I. The title of Philo's work is not mentioned hy Calcidius.
:\2. That exegete is Origen. See Switalski: np. cit .. p. 45; van Winden: op.
cit .. pp. 60-66: and Waszink: op. cit .. p. 280.
-~-~- Numenius: fr. 52 = Calci<.lius: /11 Tim. 29'5. 2'P . ..,-299. 301. 20
(paraphrase or qumation).
:\i. Numenius' principal work w:ts entitled nepi t'ciya8ou (see Eusehius:
PraC'fJ. Etang IX.-.. I).
CALCIDilJS -129
~<;.van Winden: op. cit., pp. ~6-37, 104-105, and 116-117. According to
van Winden, the explicit mention of Numenius' name here shows that - in
contrast to other passages where he is cited through an intermediary - his
actual text is being used by Cakidius.
36. J. H. Waszink: Studien zum Timaioskommentar des Ca/cidius 1. Die
crstf! Hiilj~e des Kommelllars (mit Ausnahme der Kapital ii/Jer die Wcltseele)
(Leiden, 1964 ), pp. 24-25. According to Waszink, since Calcidius does not
normally name his immediate sources. the explicit reference to Numenius
here indicates that an unnamed intermediary is being used.
:\7. Calcidius: In Tim. 276, 280, 1-278, 283, 16.
:\H. That the source is Origen's Commentary on Genesis is shown by cir-
cumstantial evidence. At Calcidius: In Tim. 2..,7. 281, 16-282, 6 there is a
rderen<.e to the doctrine explained at Origen: De Prine. II, ~- 6. The latter
text in its turn refers to a more detailed treatment in the Commentary.
430 NEOPLATONISM
39. The parallel versions are those of the Septuagint, of Aquila, and of
Symmachus. the collection of which had been accomplished in Origen's Hex-
apia. For a full discussion of the significance of their quot:ltion hy Calcidius
see van Winden: op. cit., pp. 52-ii.
40. Calcidius: In Tim. 44. 92.6-50. 100. 2.
J,J.Jhid. 59.106.17-91. 144.12.
42. To illustrate the relation between these two texts. the following sum-
mary of Plato's astronomical theory may he studied. (Calcidius: In Tim. 7.'\.
121,6-122,2 cf. TheoofSmyrna: Expos. Rerum Math. 143. 7-17):
Plato etium in /me ipso Timaeo nA.at(J)V Of: btl TEAl tiic:; noA.tteiac:;,
primam allitudinem a terra us- Atyrov <'i~ova llEV nva ~ui toi:i n6A.ou
que ad lunarem circulum. secrm- onjKovta o{ov Kiova, htpav Of:
dam usque ad so/em /iquido iJAUKUTTJV Kai <'itpaKTOV, toile; OE
dimensus est, etiam in Polilia ttvac; nepi toi:itov KoiA.ouc:; i;v
mm o1'dinafi(mem modo com- ciA.A.tlA.mc; iJPJ.LOOJ.Utvouc; aq>ovo6A.ouc;
memorans planetum, sed tcic; t<i>v <'iatprov aq>aipac;, ~ J.LEV t<i>v
si11gu/orum magnitudines nA.avroJ.Ltvrov, &Ktoc; ~f: J.Liav t<i>v
te/ocilates, etiam co/o,-es. hoc: est cinA.av<i>v &vtoc:; autiic:; 7Ipttxouaav
splendores ac serenitates. notans, tac; <'iA.A.ac; OTJA.oi of: tftv ta~tv t<i>v
axem cae/item fuso circu/osque aq>mp<i>v lita t toi:i J.LEyt9ouc; t<i>v
a.wm ambie11tes tam extimos et <'iatprov &Kaatou Kai ota toi:i
CALCIDillS 4.31
'i I. In addition to the remarks above regarding Philo and Origen. the
following testimonies should be noted: for Numenius and Aristotle, Eusebius:
Pmep. Ettmg. XIV. 'i. 8: for Adrastus and Plato: Porphyry: '" Ptol. Harm.
'J6. 1-6: for Porphyry and Numenius: Proclus: bz Tim. l, 77, 21-24: and for
Porphyry and Adrastus: Porphyry: '" Ptol. Ht~rm 7, 24-8. 'i and 96, 1-6.
Tlu~r~ is also som~ evidenc~ for Orig~ns knowledge of Numenius and Por-
phyry's ofOrigen. All these relations may be tabulated briefly:
i6. Ibid. 7, 60, 4-61, 9. This list seems to comprise a series of topics for
possible discussion - which suggest themselves as one reads through the
Timaeus - rather than a structured analysis of a work already composed.
Thb is indicated by the fact that Calcidius book terminates at topic (xiii).
whill: the: dedicatory letter implies that the break was due to the author
himsdf. A more detailed analysis of the discussion of topics (i)- (xiii) has been
made: hy van Winden: op. cit., pp. 10-28.
ii. Waszink: Studien zum Timaioskommentar des Calcidius I. Die erste
1/iiljte des Kommentars (mit Ausnahme der Kapitel uber llie Weltseele) -
rc:).:arding chapters 8-25, 32-50. and 92-118.
iH. \'an Winden: op. cit.- regarding chapters 268-3ii.
ilJ. J. den Boeft: Calcldlus on Fate. His Doctrine and Sources (Leiden.
19-tl)- n:garding chapters 142-190. and Calcidius on Demm1s (Commen-
tarius cb. Irr-J 36) (Leiden. 1977)- regarding chapters 127-136.
60. J. R. O'Donnell: 'The Meaning of Silt'CI in the Commentary on the
1"itnaeus of Plato by Chalcidius', MedlaetJa/ Studies i (194i), pp. 1-20 is a
study of a single doctrine in this way.
436 NEOPI.ATONISM
61. See p. 24 2 ff. for a detailed analysis of the three principles in dox-
ographic writers (with special reference to Apulcius).
62. Calcidius: In Tim. 307,308, I.f-309, 2.
63. Ibid. 30';, 306, 11-306, ;\07, 19. With Calcidius' account of a principle
should be compared Aristotle's analysis at Metapb.!:l. 1. 10 12b34- 2; 10 13b3
from which certain concepts have been derived (especially the notion that a
principle is a 'limit' (7t&pac;- limes}). Calcidius' notion that a principle must be
eternal is derived perhaps from both Plato: Pbaedr. 24<;d and Aristotle: Pbys.
I. 6. 189a30-31 and Metapb. B, L 1000h26-27.
M. Calcidius: In Tim . ."107, 308, 2-13. In this passage Calcidius adds two
subordinate points to tht" argument: first, that principles should not arise
from something else or from one another; and secondly. that principles have
traditionally been held to comprise one active and one passive. With the first
point should he compared Aristotle: Phys. l, ';, 188a27-28, and with these-
cond ibid. I. <;, 188a 19.
65. Calcidius: In Tim. 307, 307,20-308, 2.
CAlCIDIUS 437
6.2ITHENATUREOFGOD
~2. C.akidius: In Tim. 176, 204, S9. In order to facilitate the ensuing
analy~is. the text can he divided into seven basic statements:
(vil P1incipin cumta quae stmt et ipsum mundum c:ontineri regique
fJrincipaliter quidem a summo deo,
(i) qui est summum bonum
(iii l u/trt1 omnem substantlam omnemque twturam.
(iv) aestimtltione intellectuque melior.
(vii) quem cuncta expettml,
( ,. J cum ipse sit plentle perfection is
(ii Jet nullius societatis indiguus.
~.~. A! ibid. .:\9. 88, 1117 God is described more explicitly as 'unity'
<singularitas).
~.!. Cf. ibid. 39. 88, 11-17; 188, 213. ';;and 319, 31';, 20. AI ibid. 188,
2 12. 22-213. 2 God is described as the source of substance to other things
Whik soul is called '!he third substance' (tertia substantia) after God and
pro,idencc. The clear implication is that God is substance here.
440 NEOPLATONISM
75. Cf. the descriptions of Apuleius (pp. 266-272) and the Ascleplus (pp.
343-344). Whereas Calcidius seems to present a systematic survey ofdivine
auributes - suessing his positive transcendence (i. ii). his negative
transcendence (iii, iv), the basis of his causality (v). his efficient (vi). and final
causality (vii)- the earlier accounts are confined to literary reminiscences of
Pla10.
76. van Winden: op. cit.. p. 221 also distinguishes a third sense of substan-
tia in Calcidius: 'substratum'. But that is obviously not a possibility at this
point in the argument.
77. This would correspond to the teaching of Plotinus and other
Neopla!Onists. Plotinus often speaks of the One as beyond 'substance' (ouaia)
without specifying whether it is essence or existence which is being denied.
See l:.'tm. lll, 8/30/10, 26-32; V, 1/10/7, 17-24; V. 3/~9/10, 34-39; V, S /.U/
6, 1 ff.; etc. However, other passages clarify the position by stating that it is
possible to speak of the One as existent provided that this is done in :1 non-
predicative manner. See l:'nn. V, 3 /49/ 13. 24-31; V. S /32/ 6, I ff.; V. S /32/
13. 11-13; and VI. 7/38/38. 1-9. This Plotinian interpretation of the One's
transcendence of substance is developed by Porphyry: In Pe~rm. XII. 22-27
and Marius Victorinus: Adt'. Arium lll, 7, 9-17.
78. This would reflect an uncritical reading of Plotinus and other
Neoplatonists. It might also reflect an interpretation of earlier
Neopythagorean referenles to the One's transcendence of substam:e whose
exact meaning was perhaps as unclear to Calcidius as it is to us. Seen. 80.
CALCIDIUS 441
-9. Plato: Rep. VI, ';09b. This pa~sage is often interpreted by the
:'ljcoplatonists in conjunction with Plato: Parm. 1-llc. Sec Plotinus: Em1. V, I
/101!~. 12"'.
HO. See Moderatus at Simpllcius: In Pbys. I, 7. 230, 34 ff. and Brontinus at
syrianus: In Metapb. N, I, 165. 33 ff. The wording of these passages suggests
that Moderatus and Brontinus - following a tradition which circumstantial
l"\'ilkncc has traced back to Eudorus (first century B.C.) - combined the
Pythagorean theory of the One and the Dyad with Plato's teaching. Among
tht many modern works of scholarship on this question see especially: E. R.
Dodds: 'The Parmenides of Plato and the Origins of the Neoplatonic One',
Classiml Quarter~y 22 (1928), pp. 129-143; A.-J. Festugiere: La reVI!Iation
d'Hermes Trismegiste IV: Le Dieu inconnu et Ia gnose (Paris, 1954), pp.
I H:\ I; J. Whittaker: "EntK&tva vou Kai otiaiac;. Vigiliae Cbristianae 23
II %9). pp. 91-104; 'Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology', Symbolae
Osloenses -44 ( 1969). pp. 109-125; 'Neopythagoreanism and the Transcen-
<knt Ahsolutc', ibid. 48 (1973), pp. 77-86; and Dillon: op. cit., pp. 115-135
and :\H-:\51.
Hl.SccCmtJ. Herm.ll.'i.33.-i;ll.12.37.'-9;Vl,-l.7-t,21-7'i.1:andXIl,
I. l-1. 1-2.
H2. Stc nn. "''7. "'H and 79.
H.~. Sec Spcusippus: fr. 3-le (Aristotle: Metapb. N, 5. 1092a9 ff.) 'The One
it~t'lf is not even an existent thing' (J.lTJlif; ov tt &ivat to fv atito) and in Proclus:
111 Parm. interpr. G. de Moerbeke -tO. 1-2 'They think that the One is higher
than hc:ing' (Le unum enim me/ius ente putantes). However, concrete
nidtnl'c for linking Speusippus with the Neopythagorc:ans of the first cen-
tury A.D. b totally lacking: sec Dillon: op. cit .. p. 12.
442 NEOPI.A T<>NISM
84. See Numenius: fr. 16 (Eusehius: Praep. Etlmg. XI, 22 ..'\-'i) 'It is suffi-
cient for the Good to he the principle of being ... the demiurge of being will
certainly be the Good itself' (CxpKEi tO aya9ov ouaiac; ElVa! CxPX.~ .. -~ 7t01J fatal
Kai 6 tile; ouaiac; 5TJJ.UOUpyoc; autoaya9ov). We must observe that - in addi-
tion to amhi\'alences in the passage already quoted - other Numenian texts
identify the Good and being. See Numenius: fr. 17 (Eusehius: Praep. Etang.
XI. 18, 22-23) 'the first intellect which is called "Being in itself'' (6 l.lEVtOl
nprotoc; voiic;, oanc; KaA.Eital auto6v). The account of the relation between
the Good and being in fr. 2 (Eusebius: Praep. Er. ang. XI. 21. 7-22) perhaps
mediates this contradiction. On Numenius' theological system as a whole see
H.-C. Puech: 'Numenius d'Apamee et les theologies orientales au second
siecle', Melanges]. Bidez II (Bruxelles, 1934), pp. 745-778; E. A. Leemans:
Studie over den Wijsgeer Nume,zius van Apamea met Uitgave der
Fragmenten (Brussel, 1937). pp. 34-43; R. Beutler: 'Numenios', Paulys
Realencyclopadie der klassisc:ben Altertumsurissenscbaft, Suppi.-Band 7
(Stuttgart, 1940), col. 664-678; Festugiere: op. cit.. pp. 123-132; E. R. Dodds:
'Numenius and Ammonius', Les sources de Plotin (Fondation Hardt, Entre-
liens sur I'Antlquiti c/assique 5) (Vandoeuvres-Geneve, 1960), pp. 1-61; G.
Martano: Numenio d' Apamell. Un precursore del neoplatonismo (Napoli,
1960), pp. 21-49; H.). Kramer: Der Ursprung der Geistmetapbysik. Unter-
suchungen zur Gescbicbte des P/atonismus zuiscben Platon und Plotin
(Amsterdam, 1964), pp. 63-92; D. ). O'Meara: 'Being in Numenius and
Plotinus. Some Points of Comparison', Pbronesis 21 (1976), pp. 120-129;
and Dillon: op. cit., pp ..'\61-:n9.
85. See Porphyry: Sent. 26, I 5, 9-1.'\ 'the non-being which is above being'
(to im&p to ov I..! it ov) and In Purm. XII, 'i 'The higher is the One without be-
ing' (KCxKEivo 1.1EV v civoumov). Porphyry employs a special term for this
transcendence of being- interpreted along the lines described in n. 77 -
namely 'priority to being' (to npooumov ). See 111 Parm. X, 23-25.
86. den Hoeft: Calcidius 011 Fate. His Doctrine and Sources, p. 89 also
distinguishes a third sense of inte/lectus in Calcidius: the (hypostasis of) In-
tellect. But this is not really distinct from the second sense in this context.
CALCIDil!S
IX. 24-26; and IX, 34- X, 16. Porphyry has a special term for this
transcendence of intellection - parallel to that used for transcendence of be-
in~- namely 'pre-intellection' (npoEVVOEiv,npotvvma). See Se11t. 26. I 5, 8-9.
93. Especially the notion of intellect which is object to itself at Aristotle:
De Anim. III. 4. 430a8-9 and Metaph. A. 7, 1072bl9-20. For Plotinus'
specific response to this seen. 96.
94. See Numenius: fr. 22 (Proclus: In Tim. Ill, 103, 28-32) 'Numenius iden-
tifies the first god with the "Living Creature itself" and says that it has in-
tellection by operating in conjunction with the second god' (NoulltiVlo<; li
tov 11v npciltov Kata to '6 tan ~<j)ov' tattEl Kai IJlTIOlV tv npoax.ptiaEl toil
liwtpou voEiv). Numenius dearly indicates that the first god is not intellec-
tive in its essential nature, although elsewhere he adheres to the more con-
ventional Platonic doctrine of his day that the first god is 'intellect' (voil<;).
See Numenius: fr. 16 (Eusebius: Praep. Evang. XI, 22, 3-5), etc.
95. See Corp. Henn. II, 5 .H. -4-8 and II, 12. 37. 2-9 (the former passage
containing the interesting doctrine that God is unknowable macrocosmically
and knowable microcosmically because there is no duality in relation to
himself but duality in relation to man).
96. See Plotinus: Enn. V, I, /1019. 7-9: V. 3 1491 II, 25-30: V, 6 12-41 .~.
20-H: VI. 7/38/ 37. 1-32; and VI, 9/9/6,42-57. Porphyry: Se1lf. 43. 54.7-11
argues that 'it is necessary for the One to precede multiplicity. That Intellect
is multiple is clear, since it always has intellectual objects which are multiple'
(npo li tcilv noHcilv ClVIi.'YKTI Eival tO fv. <'>n li nona 6 VOU<; liJiA.ov. VOEi yap
aEi tO. VOtlJlata OUX, &v <'Svta ). Cf. Porphyry: In Pann. V, 9-10. For both
writers it is the duality of the intellective process (even when subject and ob-
ject are identical as in Aristotle) which makes it incompatible with the One's
nature. However, both also maintain that the One has an absolutely simple
form of self-awareness transcending this. See Plotinus: Enn. V. 4 /7/ 2. 15-19:
VI. 7 /38/ 39. 25-26; and VI, 8 /39/ 16. 30-35. Porphyry: In Parm. V. 8-35
speaks of a 'knowledge beyond knowledge and ignorance' (yvcilm<; &~ro
YVWOE(I)<; Kai ayvoia<;).
CAI.CIDILJS 445
9"'. The structure of this section of the commentary has been admirably
lksnihld hy van Winden: op. cit .. pp. 24-28.
IJH. This section is divided and placed at the beginning (Calcidius: In Tim.
26H. r.~. "'-2'74, 2'79, 7) and end (ibid. 321. 316. 14-354. 3.f5. 16) of the
Llbcussion.
IJIJ. This section runs frGm ibid. 2'75, 279, R-307, 309, 2.
100_ This section runs from ibid. 302, 303,9-320, 316. 13.
I 0 I. Apuleius doctrine of matter (derived from the doxographical tradi-
tion) should be compared. See pp. 318-321. At that point we noted the texts
from Plato's Timaeus relevant to the development of the theory.
4-i6 NEOPI.ATONISM
I02. Calcidius: In Tim. ;\20. ;H6, 8- I I. (Cf. ihid. :\21, 516, 21-2.'\ and 554.
328, 10-11 ). Texts drawn from the running commentary are noted in curved
parentheses ( ).
103. (ibid. 522. 3I7, 19-21).
IIJ.i. (JIJI'd. 34"'. 3.W. 3-6).
IO'i. (Ibid. 34'S. 336, 14-338, 6).
106. (1/Jid. 2"74. 278. 13-16).
Ill"". ibid. ;\19.311, J'7-19.Cf.i/Jid ..U0.3I6,II-13.
I08. Ibid. 3I9. 3I4. I9-520, 5I6. 1.~.
109./IJid. 520,516, I 1-1;\.
I 10. /hid. 3I2, 3 I I. 10-II.
CALCIDIUS -447
308a4-9 and b5-8 (need for the substratum to change). The fragmems of
Aetius chapter on matter do not allow us to parallel Calcidius' theory exact-
ly. yet the 'Platonic and Aristotelian' doctrine of the last passage comes very
close.
119. This doctrine was apparemly unique to Porphyry. See Philoponus: De
Aetern. Mundi XIV. ;\, 546, 5-11 'Porphyry in his commemary on the
Timaeus ... says that it is not matter which is moved with the traces in a
discordant and disorderly way ... but the bodies which ha,e already arisen
from matter and form' (6 youv nopq>upwc; tv toic; Eic; TOV TillatOV U7toll-
VTill<JlV ... ou tilv iiJ..11v Q>llalv ll&ta nov ixv&v to 7tAllllll&J..wc; &ivm Kal
(ltQKtroc; KlVOUil&VOV ... aHa l"Cx 1)511 f.~ iiJ..11c; Kai &iliouc; y&V61l&Va a<i>llata).
The importance of this parallel was first noted by Waszink: Timaeus a
Calcidin translatus cnmmentarioque instructus, pp. xci and 302 and van
Winden: op. c:it.. p. 251.
120. (Calcidius: In Tim. 352.342. 17-343. 20).
121. [Ibid. _l,OO, 302, 1-2]. Texts drawn from the: hiswrical survc:y are
noted in straight paremhcses [].
CALCIDilJS 449
I.H. Porphyry: In Tim. fr. ')I (Proclus: In Tim. I. .391, ') ff.) and fr. S6
(Prod us: In Tim. l, 456, 31-457, 11 ). Cf. Plotinus: Enn. I. 8 /') 1/7. 17-23; II,
1"'-19: III. -i/15/1. 8-17: and IV. 3/27/9.23-26.
'i /25/ 'i.
I:H. Sec n. 123. There is also a curious reference to matter obtaining its
~uhstance' (substantitt) from Form at Calcidius: In Tim. 344. 336. 7 which
nuy ht an undigested remnant of the true Porphyrian theory.
135. See accounts in Apuleius (pp. 286-292) and the Asclepius (pp.
5'i 1-354).
U6. Calcidius: In Tim. 25. 75, 1'7; 25. 76, 5-6; 105, 154. 10-11; and 119.
161. II.
1.~-. Ibid. 29. "'9. 9: 273. 278, S: 329. 323. 2-l; .3.37. ;HO, '); .337, 330, 16;
.~.~H . .'.~I. 6: .3W. 3.32. S: 339. 332. 11: :HI. 333. 19:3-43. 33S. 11-12: .3-t-i .
.~.~h. 6: .~f-. 339, 2: and 349, .HO. 10.
1:\H.Ihid. 272.276, 15:304,306. 6; 329.323. 12; 329,323, 25; .329, .324,
.~: .~:10. 32-i. IS; 335, 328, 13: 339. 332. II; 340. 333. 16; 344. 336.6: and
.~ .. - ..H9. 1.
I :W. /hid . ."d8 ..-\:12, I.
loJO.!IJid. 3:W. 332.8: 3-H. 336. 8; and 3-49. 340, 7.
It I. Ibid. 23. 74, 14-IS; H. 7S, 17; .U9. 323. 11-13: 330. 32S. 6-8; 339.
:I.U. 10: and .HO, 333. 14.
142./bid. 2S, "'~5.14-76.6and lOS, 154.10-20.
452 NEOPLATONISM
14~.1bid. 2'i, 75. 14: 2'i. 75. 17; IO'i. l'i4. II: 105, 154. 17; 272.276, 15:
~04.306,7:330,325,6;339.332, IO;and340,333. 17.
144.1bid. 329,323. 12; 329.323. 14; and 349. 340.23.
145.1bid. 272.276, 12-l'i.
146.1bid. ~04, 306. 7.
li7. Ibid. 27 2, 276, I 0-15 Quippe primum elementum tmit,ersae rei silt'a
est informis ac sine qualitate quam, ut sit mtmdus, format intel/egibilis
species; ex quibus, silta t1ide/icet et specie, ignis purus et intel/egibilis
ceteraeque sincerae substantiae quattuor. e quibus demum bae materiae
sensiles. igneae aquatiles terrenae et aereae. Ignis porro purus et ceterae
sincerae inte/legibilesque substarztiae species sunt exemplar/a corporum.
idelle cognominatae.
148. The circumstantial evidence would suggest that this 'intelligible
Form' (inte/legibilis species) corresponds to the Form of the Good.
CALCIDillS 45.'\
hodks has two distinct phases: first, the highest Form combines
with matterl-i9 to produce the Forms of the four elements, and
secondly the Forms of the four elements combine with matter
to produce the four physical substances. Although this exten-
sion of the traditional theory of Forms does not occur in any
Latin writers prior to Calcidius, it goes back ultimately to Aristo-
tlc:'s reports of Plato Iso- where the One performs the function
of the highest Form, the 'indefinite dyad' (ci6ptotoc; ouac;) that
of matter on both levels, and the Form-Numbers that of the
Forms of the four elements - and was later revived by certain
:\"eopythagoreans, Is I the Cha/daean Orac/es,152 and the
:'\eoplatonists.IS~ The commentator's documented interest in
Greek philosophical writers adequately explains his deviation
from the tradition of his own culture, and here once again it is
the influence of Numenius I'H and Porphyry I 55 - who identify
rhe Platonic One and indefinite dyad with the Aristotelian form
and 'intelligible matter' (uA.n vontit)- which is perhaps domi-
n;~.nt.
The second text can be presented in a summary fashion: (i)
Primary Form is a) 'without quality' (neque qualitate praedita),
and b) 'with quality' (neque sine qualitate). Since it is simple, it
cannot participate in a quality, and therefore it is a); but since it
docs not involve a privation, it is therefore b). (This last point is
compared with the case of a stone which has no privation of
fear. since fear or its absence have no relation to such an in-
animate object). Furthermore, since this Form is the cause of
quality in other things, it is therefore b). (This notion is il-
idcntifkd the Chaldacans' first god (the 'Once Beyond' (c'iTca~ tntKEtva)) with
the (;ood and their second god (the 'Twice Beyond' (Sic; tnEKEtva)) with the
lkmiur~e. Further, later Neoplatonic testimony indicates: (i) that the
Chaldaeans' Twice Beyond was dyadic (Psellus: H_vpot. 9. 74. 20-21 'It is call-
nl "Twice Beyond" bec.:ause it is dyadic' (KQAEitat of: oic; tnEKEIVQ, Ott
tiual\tK6c; tan)), (ii) that the Twice Beyond contained the plurality of Forms
(i!Jid. 9. 74. 17-20 'The "Twice Beyond" ... established the model of the
Forms for the world' (6 5& Sic; tntKetva ... npo0911KE t6v tli>v !Sewv tunov tcj>
KOO!l(!))). and (iii) that the plurality of Forms had a dyadic element (Orac.
O~t~ld. fr ..~I (Damascius: Dubil. et Solut. II, 63. 21-23) 'From these two
flows the bond of the first triad which is not really the first but that where the
intdli~iblcs arc measured' (t~ Ctll<poiv 1\i] tli>vSe pEEl tptdl\oc; Mila
npliH11-;/oua11c; oil nprot11c;, c'.tH 'ou ta VOTJtci llEtpEitat)). It therefore seems
likdy that Porphyry also used the Chaldaeans' theory to show that the
I hmiur~c was dyadic and embraced the plurality of Forms. On this basis both
Porphyry and the Ch"ld(letm Oracles - probably in agreement with
'\umcnius - must ha\'c believed in a dyadic clement in the Forms
lhlmscl\'cs. For discussion of these problems sec W. Theiler: Die
chaldiiiscben Omkel und die Hymn en des S_vnesios (Halle. 1942). pp. 1-9:
Fcstu~il-rc: /.(l revelation d'Hermes Trismtfgiste Ill. Les doctrines de l'dme,
pp. 'il-';9 and IV. I.e Dieu inconnu et Ia gnose. pp. I.U-1 :\';; H. Lewy:
Cba/daecm Oracles cmd 1'heurgy. Mysticism. Magic and Platonism in the
l.ater Roman Empire (Recherches d'archtfologie, de fJbilologie et d'histoire
I-~ HCairo, 19% ). Nouvt:llc edition par M. Tardieu (Paris, 19'H), pp. Ill';- I 1'7:
:tnlf P. Hadm: PorphJre et Victorinus (Paris, 196H). pp. 2SS-272.
NEOPLATONISM
.274. 10; 269, 271, 12; :md 3S4, 3H. IS)). 'intelligence' (intellegenthl (see
ibid. 269. 214, 4 and 270. 274. IS)). 'intellect' (intellectus (see ibid. 268,
2':'3. Hand 270, 27!, 16)). and 'will' (1'0/tmltl.~ (see ibid. 3S4. 344. 19 and
3S4, 54S, IS)); (ii) 'providence' (jJml'idf!lltitl, prospicientia, pr01idus (sec
ibid. 26H. 2~3. H: 26H, 273. II; 26H. 273. 13-14; 269, 274. R; 269. 274. 10;
3S4, 344. 19: and 3S'-1, 34S. 6)). On the metaphysical significance of
substituting such terminology for 'God' (deus) seep. 460 ff.
162. This division occurs at Plato: Tim. 47e where the previous material is
called 'the things crafted by mind' (til 5ta voii 5&5TU.ll0l/P"fll~Eva) and what
follows 'the things which arise from necessity' (tel 61'av6.yKT]c; y1yv6~eva).
The corresponding place in Calcidius is at In Tim. 268, 273, 7.
163. Seen. 161.
164. Calcidius: In Tim. 269.274, 12-14.
CALCIDiliS 459
ter would suggest that any such influences will be of a predominantly literary
rather than doctrinalldnd. See pp. 445-451.
172. Seen. 161.
173. Calcidius/11 Tim. 35-i. 345,5-10.
174. Plato: Tim. 53b.
175. For interpretation (i) see pp. 4-HJ-445: for (ii a) sec pp ... 57-459. Inter-
pretation (ii b) is the subject of the present section.
CALCIDil'S 461
1-6. Call'idius: In Tim. 330. 324, 24-325, I. At ibid. 340, 333. 16 he refers
to 'the Form of the intellect which is called the "Idea" {fntellectus species,
quae idea dicitur).
1""..,. fiJid. :\39. 332. 7. The statements in this and the previous passage that
Ideas arc eternal and perfect thoughts are perhaps significant, since at ibid.
162. 19 S. 1-18 God is said to know all things according to the nature of the
objects' (/Jm natura sua ipsorum): eternal things stably and transitory things
mUiahly. This theory contrasts with the view of later Neoplatonists that
things arc known according to thc nature of the subject. Sec Boethius: De
Cunsol. Philos. V, pr. 6, 13.
I""H. Calcidius: In Tim. 27 3. 278, 5-6.
l ... lJ. 1/Jid. :H2. 334. 2,'\-24. Cf. ibid. 349, 340,9-10. Obviously the notion
that thc first principle as a unity is equivalent to a single Idea is less pro-
hkmatic- given that Ideas are real existents- than the notion that as a uni-
ty it is t"quha1ent to a multiplicity of Ideas. On Calcidius' awareness of this
situation sec n. 20_11.
180. See pp. 252-264.
1HI. Sec Alhinus: Didasc. 9, I and Calcidius: In Tim. 339. 332, 510 where
iota I principalis species is defined in the same five ways: (i) we; ~&v npoc;
8E:ov VOTJOI<; autoO I iu:~:ta deum vero perfectus intellectus dei, (ii) we; 5& npoc;
llJ.Hic; VOTJtov nprotov 1 iuxta nos quldem, qui intel/ectus compotes sumus,
/Jrimum intel/egibile, (iii) we; 5& npoc; tliv UAT]V J,LEtpov I iuxta silvam modus
IJII'NS/11'llqllf! rerum corporearum atque Sill'eSirium, (iv) W<; 5& 7tpoc; tOV
nioSTJtov K6o~ov napa5&ty~a 1 iuxta mundum vero exemplum sempiter-
462 NEOPLATONISM
(ii h) e.~sentia
(iii b) aemulae bonitatis
(iii a) propter indefessam ad summum deum conversionem,
(iii b) estque ei ex illo bonita tis haustus, quo tam ipsa ornatur
t iii c) quam cetera quae ipso auctore bonestantur.
(i c) Hanc igftur dei voluntatem, tamquam sapientem tutelam
rerum omnium,
(i h) prrwidentiam homines t'ocant, non ut pier/que aestimant, ideo
dictum, quia praecurrit in t'idendo atque intellegendo proven-
tusfuturos, sed quia proprium
(i a) dlvinae mentis intellegere, qui est proprius mentis
<ii c) actus.
(i a) Et est mem del
Iii a) aetetna:
(i a) est igitur mens dei intellegendl
(ii a) aeternus
(ii l') actus.
lHS. With this account should be compared a curious report of Aristotle's
tllt'ology in which Form is described as a secondary principle consequent
upon (;od. Sec ibid. 2H7, 291, I 1-12 'He praises Form as a divinity, similar to
the highest God. dependent upon the complete and perfect Good. and
therl'fort ;m ohjcct of striving' (Speciem laudm ut summi dei simi/em
di1initatem plem> perfectoque nixam bono ideoque appetibilem). Here.
Cakidius is assimilating Aristotle's doctrine to the kind of Platonism which
ht himself espouses.
464 NEOPI.A TON ISM
19.'\. Porphyry: Sent. 41, 53,4-5. Cf. ibid. 36, 41, 12-13 and 36, 42,3-4.
<T l'lotinus: Emz. 1, 8/51/2, 21-23; V, 2/11/l, 16-18; V, 4/7/2, 3-4; etc.
19-!. Porphyry: Sent. 44, 57, 8. Cf. ibid. 43, 54, 12-16. Cf. P1otinus: Enn.
\'. 3 I -49 I'>. 21-48; V. 3 /49/8, 35-42; etc.
19'). Porphyry: Sent. 30, 20, 14-16. Cf. Porphyry: Hist. Pbilos. fr. 15
(Cyril: Contra lulian. I (PG 76, 549A-B)). Cf. P1otinus: Enn. I, 7 /54 I I, 1-19;
V. 6 I 241 '), 8-9; etc.
196. Porphyry: Hist. Pbilos. fr. 16 (Cyril: Contra /ulian. VIII (PG 76,
916B)). Cf. Plotinus: Enn. V. 8/31/12, 7-15; VI, 5/23/4, 13-17; etc.
19"'. Porphyry: Sent. 12, 5. 7. Cf. ibid. 31. 21, 9-16; Hist. Phi/os. fr. 16
!Cyril: Omtra lu/imz. Vlll (PG 76. 9168)) and fr. 18 (Cyril: Contra /u/ian. I
( P<i ...,6, 5528-C)). Cf. Plotinus: Enn. V. I I 10 /7. 1-5; V, ; I 32 /9, 26-32; etc.
198. Porphyry: De Regr. Anim. fr. 7, 35 25-29. Cf. Plotinus: Enn. VI, 8/
W 19. i2-48; VI. 8/39/13, 1-59; VI, 8/39/21, 8-19; etc.
_ 199. Porphyry: Hist. Pbilos. fr. 18 (Cyril: Contra lulfan. I (PG 76,
..,_'>28-C)). Cf. Porphyry: Sent. 44, 58, 8-9 and 44, 58, 23-24. Cf. Plotlnus:
l:nn. Ill.""! 14; /6, 1-12; V, 1/1014. 13-25; etc .
. 200. Porphyry: Sent. 30. 20. 13-14. Cf. Ibid. 13. 5, 10-11. Cf. Plotinus:
bm. V. 1/10/6,50-53: V. 6/2415. 12-19; VI, 9/9/2, 40-43; etc.
466 NEOPI.ATONISM
the Forms and called mind, and that the principle which is im-
manent in the Forms and termed providence, intellect, or will is
consequent upon a higher principle described as God. Thus, he
suggests a relation between God and mind involving both iden-
tity and subordination in referring to 'causes which are percep-
tible to divine providence' (causae, quae sunt perspicuae
divinae proz,identiae),2111 in his statement that 'God's finest
work is that which he thinks' (optimum dei opus est id quod in-
tel/egit),20l and by arguing that 'God's works are his thoughts
which are called "Ideas" by the Greeks- these "Ideas" being
the paradigms of natural things' (opera vero eius intellec.:tus eius
sunt, qui a Graec.:is ideae vocantur; porro ideae sunt exempla
naturalium rerum).l03 This combination of the notions that
the Forms are God's thoughts and therefore identical with him
and that the Forms are his works and thus subordinate to him
represents something of a deviation from the simpler theory
transmitted to the Latin tradition by the doxographers. On the
other hand it seems to echo certain doctrines of the Greek tradi-
tion such as Numenius' theory that the first god 'thinks by using
the second god additionally' (v npoaxpftcn:t mu cSwttpou
voEiv).!tH and Porphyry's interpretation of the Cba/daean
( Jracles according to which the first principle is both 'secreted
from (ap1t<ioat tautov EK) its secondaries and has 'power and
intc:llc:rt co-unified in its simplicity' (MvaJJ.tV ... Kat vouv f:v tfj
a7tAO't'TJ't't autou aUV11Vroa9at).20S In other words we are once
a~ain brought back to the favorite sources of Calcidius'
theological doctrine.
.!0-1. Numcnius: fr. 22 (Proclus: In Tim. Ill. 103, 28-32). Cf. fr. 21 (Proclus:
In lim. I. 303, 27-304, 7) 'The Demiurge of the world is double according to
him: thl' first god and the second' (6 Kat'a\rrov cSruuoupyo<; cS1tt6c;, o t&
rrptinoc; O&oc; Kai 6 cS&tit&poc;) .
.!O'i. Porphyry: In Parm. IX. 1-8. Calcidius' description of the intt:lligiblc
world as 'self-produced' (ex se genilus) at In Tim. 119, 164. II perhaps in-
nc:asls the likelihood that Porphyry is the crucial influence behind these doc-
trinn. The notion that spiritual principles arc self-originated seems to have
l'lllc:rt"d into tht' serious philosophical tradition with him. See especially Por-
phyry: flist. Pbllos. fr. 18 (Cyril: Contra luliatl. I (PG 76, S52 B-C)) where
lntt'llt'ct proceeds from the One as 'self-generated and self-paternal'
(UllTOYEVV11'!0<; wv Kai auto7tcitrop). On this doctrine see s. Gersh: From
lamiJiicbus to Eriugena. An Investigation of tbe Preblstory a11d El'olution
o( I be Pseudo-Dio1l)'Sian Tradition (Studietl zur Problemgescbicbte der an-
liken tuul mitle/alt~rlicben Pbi/osopbie 8)(leiden, 1978), pp. 305-307.
2 06. Calcidius: In Tim. 273. 277. 13-278, 7 and 330, 324. 19-23. The in-
lrodunion of thl' third term here indic;ues an important structural division in
<.alciuius' commentary as well as in Plato's text.
468 NEOI'LATONISM
207. Plato: Tim. 48e - 49a and 50c-d. Calcidius expresses himself am-
bivalently regarding the nature of the third term, sometimes identifying it as
'body' (corpus) and sometimes as 'Form' (species). See Calcidius: In Tim.
273, 277, 17 and 330, 324, 2 3. C. Baeumker: Das Problem der Materie in der
grlechiscben Phi/osophie. Eine historisch-kritische Untersuchung (Munster,
1890), p. 126 ff. notes that a similar ambivalence occurs in Plato's own text.
208. In the passages which follow, Calcidius sometimes interprets the
'father' as a single Form and sometimes as a plurality. This accords with the
philosophical principle discussed on pp. 455-457.
209. Calcidius: In Tim. 316, 313. 2. Cf. ibid. 3.~7. 330. 10-3:\ I, 4. In both
texts we find the father identified as the 'Demiurge' (opifex).
210. Ibid. 349, 34 I, 5-6 where the father is interpreted as the plurality of
Forms. Cf. ibid. 344, 336, 5-6 where he is understood as the primary Form.
211./b/d. 273.277, 17-18.
212./bid. .U9. 32j, 18-20.
CAlCIDilJS 469
21~.1bid. 330.324.23-325.8.
2lL See pp. 292-301.
.! I 'i. Plato: Tim. ';2e. Plato is referring to the Receptacle and the disorderly
qualitit's whereas Calcidius is concerned with matter and Form. However.
Plato's original notion occurs at Calcidius: In Tim. 352. 34.'\, I S-20.
2HJ. Simplicius: In Pbys. I, 3. 135, 1-9 'Porphyry ... showed that what real-
ly is is the Idea and that this is really substance, while the ultimate, primal,
~hapeless. and formless matter from which all things arise is indeed but not
among things which really are. It is conceived on its own and is potentially all
thing~ hut nothing in actuality. The composite of Form and matter, inasmuch
a~ it participates in Form is something and can be named according to its
Form. hut inasmuch as it depends upon matter and for this re;tson is in con-
tinuou~ tlux and change is not simply or stably' (6 nopqn)pto<; ... TO j.lEV yap
I~VTW<; OV Ct7tEq>JivaTO EtVal TTtV lotav Kai taUTTJV 6VTWI; Efva1 ouaiav, TTtV OE
U\'(!)!(i_rw 1tPWTTJV Uj.lOpq>ov Kal avEili&ov UATJV &!; ~<; Ta navta EOTiv Eivat J.lEV,
~ll]<'ii:v f>t Eivai TWV OVTWV. atmi yap eq>'taun;c; E7tiVOOUj.lEVTJ ouvaj.l&l j.lEV 7tav-
TU i:cniv, t.vEpyEi(,l 0& ouo&v. TO o& EK TOU Eioouc; Kai Tii<; UATJI; a7tOTEA&Oj.la
Kutroaov J.lEV Eioouc; J.lETE)'Et, KaTa ToliTo &ivai tt Kai 7tpoaayopEuEa9at KaTa
til cioo.;, Ka8'6aov of: Tii<; iiATJ<; Kai ota TaUTTJV tv auvEX.Ei puaEt Kai J.1Etal3oAlj
n,YXc.iw:t, 7tdl..tv wit imA<il<; llTJM13EI3aiwc; Eivat). It is clear that when Porphyry
t harannizes each of the three levels, he contrasts the existential and
Prtllil:ative senses of the verb 'to be'. This enables him to formulate a defini-
-170 NEOPLATONISM
tion of matter- which 'is' (Elvat 1-1tv- predicativc) and 'is not' (llTJliEv 5
Efvat tci>v ovtrov - existential) at the same time - without expressing a
paradox. Although Calcidius follows this definition of matter precisely: it 'is'
(est quidem) and 'is not' (nibil est eorum quae sun I), by failing to distinguish
the prcdicativc: and existential senses he leaves the paradox intact. That he
docs not distinguish these two senses is indicated by his alteration of those
clements in the Porphyrian doctrine which arc strictly predicativc to an ex-
istential sense. Thus, Ka9'oaov j.lEV Eiliouc; llEttXEI, Katli mum Eivai n Kai
7tpoaayopEuEa9at Katli to Eilioc;- in the first half of Porphyry's definition of
the composite - becomes cum enim sit imago tere existentis rei. tidetur
esse a/iquatenus - in the first half of Calcidius' definition of the sensible
Form. For purposc:s of comparison I have translated Porphyry's argument as
though it only contained the existential sense of Eivat in my main quotation.
The dose: relation between the Greek and Latin writers here was dislovcrcd
hy Badot: op. cit., pp. 163-16'5.
217. Calcidius: In Tim. 273. 278, 7; 349. 340, 21; etc.
218. Ibid . .U9, 323. 14; .U9. 323. 24: 337, .~30, 3: 344. 336.9: etc.
219.1bid. 329.324, 1-6.
220./IJid. BH. 331, 2.~-332, I. Cf. iiJid. .HS. 32H. 1213.
221. Sec pp. 292-301 and 3'5 1-354.
CALCIDH'S -!71
222. Calcidius: /11 Tim. 23. 74. l'i-19. A similar argument is made regar-
ding the divine genera at ibid. 26. 76, I I -.,..,.H.
223. Ibid. 23. 73. 6-7 and 23. 74. 20. The wider context of this argument
should be noted. Cakidius demonstrates that the world is without end with
three arguments: (i) its relation to its cause is ontological and not
chronological. (ii) there is no material left outside to destroy it. and (iii) it is
fashioned according to an eternal paradigm. It is dear that arguments (i) and
(iii) also prt)\'e that the world is without beginning. this point being indicated
by the final conclusion of ibid. 2'i. 76. 6 that it 'always was. is. and will be'
(semper fuit est erit).
224. Ibid. lOS, 154. IH. Cakidius comments that the world's and time's
beginnings arc simultaneous at ibicl. 10 I. IS 2. I I- I 3.
225. According to Produs: In Tim. I. 277, H- 10, this version originated
with Crantor and was also supported by Plotinus, Porphyry. and Iamblichus.
CAI.CIDil!S
We have already seen inch. 3, n. 25 that it was one of the four specific ver-
'iom of the: ~enc:ral thesis that the world's coming to be is non-temporal ad-
\ocatc:d by Taurus . .See also Albinus: Didasc. 14. 3.
226. Calciuius: In Tim. 23. 73. 10-12.
2r. Ibid. 23. ""3. 12-74.:\.
22H. See Aristotle: Phys. II. 2, 194a21-22.
229. See Porphyry: Sent. 12, 5. 6-8 'There is one life: of a plant, another of
an l'nsouled being. another of an intellectual one:; one: life of Nature, another
of ~out. another of Intellect, another of the Bevond' (iiAATJ yap ~coil q>Utoii,
~D. A.l] CJ.IIJIUXOU, iiA.A.n VOEpoii, iiUn q>UOECO<;,
ann \j/UXfi<;, aA.A.n voii, liAATJ tOii
f:ltf.I\Etvu). It goes without sayin~ that Calcidius' theory recalls the simple
'lholastk formulations illustrated above rather than the: complex doctrine of
474 NEOPl.ATONISM
236. Calddius: In Tim. 27. 7H, 2-11 Docetnos substantiam sfte, ut C'h'em
dicit, essentiam duplicem esse, unam inditiduam, alteram per corpora
dirltluam. Et imliriduam quidem esse eam, cui us generis sunt omnia aeter-
na et sine corpore. quae intellegibi/ia dinmtur. ditidutmt vero, quae cm-
poribus e.'\istendi causa est ... lgitm ex bis dualms ail opificem deum ter
tiwn genus essentiae miscuisse ldque medium /ocasse inter essentiam
utramque. This is an elaboration of Plato: Tim. ;\'ia.
2.'\7.Calcidius:/n Tim. 51. IOO,H-Jl).
238. See Waszink: Timaeus a Calcidio transltlfus commentarioque in
structus. pp. xci\' and 100. He suggests the possibility of Porphyry as an in-
termediary.
CAI.CIJ)J!IS
argument are not 'parts' in the normal sense of the term. Since
soul is a simple and incorporeal thing one cannot divide it into
physical parts at al1,239 the so-called 'division' representing
rather 'an analysis of its powers and the arrangement, so to
speak, of its faculties, activities, and functions' (consideratio est
tirium ordinatioque veluti membrorum actuum eius of-
ficiorumque).24o It is in this light that we are to understand the
more complex mathematical account which now follows, for
the parts of the psychic substance taken by the Demiurge as 1, 2.
3. 4, 8, 9 and 27 times the basic unit- which Calcidius arranges
along two sides of a lambda24t - represent two geometrical
series of four terms each namely 1, 2, 4, 8 and 1, 3, 9, 27 times
the basic unit,242 Furthermore, the fact that these series are
geometrical is of great significance, since such progressions
represent the law according to which a geometrical point leads
by fluxion - the point moves to produce a line, the line a sur-
face, and the surface a solid - to generate three-dimensional
physical bodies, such bodies being those which soul itself has
been created to animate.243 The source of Calcidius' account
The: usc of this figure to set out the series of numbers goes back to Crantor.
Sc:e Plutarch: DeAnim. Procr. 29, 1027d.
2-!2. Calcidius: lt1 Tim. 32. 82, 3-8.
2i3./bid . .H. 82,9-83. 19. Cf.lbid. 53. 101, 1-i-102, 8.
NEOPl.ATONISM
2-h. For th~ first point s~~ Prod us: In Tim. II. liO, I:;. Hi where Adrastus'
argum~nt that 'Plato, having r~gard for the n:ttur~ of things. compos~d soul
from allth~s~ int~rvals so that one might reach th~ cubic numbers. since soul
was to preside over bodies (nA.anov tiE npo~ nv qll)mv 6p<i>v <nv IVuxnv EK
7tQV!WV !OUtrov auv&atllO&V, iva npofl] llEXPl t<i>v at&p&ci>V apt81lci>V, cit&
arolllitrov aollEV11 npoatlitt~ ). For the second see ibid. II, 171, 4-9 'Adrastus
proceeded in this way. However. others rejected the lambda figure ... This is
the opinion of Porphyry and Severus' (Kai outro~ 6 Alipaato~ n&noillK&V.
clAAOl &f: nv A.a~8o&t8ii napu<tiaavto Kataypaq~i)v .. - OUt(l) M: Kai nopq~upto<;
Kai l:&uiipo<; a~toiiat ). The dependence of Calcidius upon Adrastus is careful-
ly discussed by Waszink: Studie11 zum Timaioskommentar des Calcidius I.
Die erste Hii/fte des Kommenlt~rs (mit Ausmtbme der Kapite/ iiber die
\Veltseele). pp. 1-30.
2iS. For the first point see Porphyry: 111 Tim. fr. 67 (Macrobius: In Somn.
Scip. II, 2. 14) where Plato is said to have included cubic numbers in soul to
indicate that it. although an incorporeal. 'fills the world's solid body' (mwuli
solidum corpus imp/ere). The doctrine here recalls Porphyry's general thesis
regarding incorporeals that thcy are (i) in themselves 'everywhert and
nowhere' (navmxou Kai ouliallOU) but (ii) 'by a certain disposition' (Ota8ta&t
toivuv 7t0l~) present in a specific body. Sec Porphyry: Sent. 27. 16. 1-16. For
the snond point see the passage cited in n. 244. Regarding the first point it
should also be noted that Porphyry's agreement with Adrastus is only super-
ficial sinle his full theory states that the indivisible is preSl'nt to the dividld
both indivisibly and dividedly while the divided is present to the indivisible
CALC)() II IS 479
hoth dividedly and indivisibly. See ibid. :B. ~6. 12-:\7. S. This explains the
apparently contlkting theory at De Abstin. II. 37. 2 where soul is s;1id to he.
:1lthough an incorporeal. three-dimensional in its own nature. For a more
dct:1iled discussion of the relation hetween soul and body in Porphyry see p.
c;; I ff.
2-t6. Cakidius: In Tim. S I. I S2, ~-S !psam tero animam in semet cotl
tertclc non utique corpora/i cmwersimw fcuta intellegendum. sed cogittl
tirmis recordatirmisque KJ'ris et anfrttctibtts parente sibi corfmre. This is an
dahoration (with quotation) of Plato: Tim. ~6e.
2-i'''. Calcidius: In Tim. 57. 101, Ui-HIS. IH. The translation b of Plato:
PIJaeclr. 21'h: li6a ami should he compared with Cit:eru's \'Crsion. Sec ch.
1. n. s-.
2-JH. See Waszink: Timtteus tt Ca/cidio trmulatus commemmioque in-
structus. p. 104.
4RO NEOPLA TON ISM
2S2. Calcidius: bz Tim. 92. 144, 12 ff. The following illustrative diagrams
arc provided br the manuscripts:
X
Plato's full doctrine is that soul is composed of indivisible and divided
substance, and of sameness and difference. See Plato: Tim. ~Sa.
253. Calcidius: In Tim. 92. 145,4-146, H.
lS-i. Ibid. 95. 147. 26-14H, 9.
25S.Ibid. 95. 1-48.9-11.
256. Some of Calcidius' remarks ahout the human soul will add to our
understanding of this theory. See pp. 488-490.
4H2 :"JEOPLATONISM
with Theo of Smyrna do not exist for all these passages. the
dependence upon Adrastus seems well established here as
elsewhere in the account of the world souJ..257
2'P. Sc:e Switalski: op. cit., p. 69; Waszink: Timac:us a Ca/cidio trcms/atus
nmmwntarioque instructus, p. 144 and Studien zum Timaioskommentar
des Calcidius l. Die erste Hiilfte des Kommentars (mit A usnahme der Kapitel
iJber die Weltseele), pp. 32.~6. Sec: also pp. 430-4 31.
2'5H. I shall nm examine in detail Calcidius interpretation of the: composi-
tion of the world body. This hegins :11/n Tim. 6. 61. 10 and ends at ibid. 22.
73 . .f. It includes both arithmetical' and 'geometrical' expositions which are
dependent upon Ad rastus. For the source question see Waszink: Studien zum
Timaioskommentar des Calcidlus I. Die erste Hiilfte des Kommentms (mit
Ausnahmeder Kapitel iJberdie Weltseele), pp. 31-36.
2'59. Cakidius: In Tim. 231. 21'5. :\-6. Cf. ihid. 2:\.:f. 24':'. 17-llJ.
260. Ibid. 232. 2i6, 92:H. 247. 12.
CALCJI>JliS
tl'Xt he notes that the four clements which compose the human
body are analogous to the physical constituents of the
cosmos.Z61 Most of these ideas are drawn from Plato's own text,
although the analogy drawn from the human soul's three parts
not simply to the political but to the cosmological realm is of a
kind favored by Stoic writers, while the description of man as a
small world' (mum/us bret,is) is derived from Aristotle.262.
6.~~ITHENATUREOFTHEHUMANSOUL
soul's unity would prncnt its blc:nding with body by interposition of par-
tides. and (iii) on the grounds that soul could not exist independently in such
;1 union. Of these three types of union (i) corresponds to the napci9EOl<;, (ii) to
the J.Li/;1<; or Kpdcn<;. and (iii) to the ounuot<; of Stoic theory. See pp. 101-105.
The parallel between this text and Priscianus l.ydus: So/ut. ad Chosr. I, 44,
15 ff. suggests a common source, this latter being in all likelihood the
Neoplatonist Porphyry. Porphyrr is known for his interest in the use of the
Stoic theorr of mixtures in ":onnection with the problem of relating the in-
corporeal and corporeal. Thus. at Sent. 33, 38. 1-5 he writes: 'This is neither
blending nor mixture nor association nor juxtaposition, but is a relation dif-
ferent to these' (OUtE OUV Kpdcrl<; f\ J.Li/;1<; f\ cruvooo<; f\ napa9EOl<;, aA.A.'~tEpo<;
tp6no<;). Porphyry's interpretation of this special relation which he derived
from Ammonius Saccas is reported by Nemesius: De Nat. Hom. 3, 592A -
608A. On these questions see H. A. Wolfson: The Philosophy of the Church
Fathers I. Faith, Trinity, Incarnation (Cambridge, MA, 1956), pp. 400-407;
E. R. Dodds: 'Numenius and Ammonius', Les sources de Plotin (Fondation
Hardt, Entretiens sur /'Ant/quite c/assique 5) (Vandoeuvres-Geneve, 1960),
p. 25; W. Theiler: 'Ammonios und Porphyrins', Porphyre(Fondalion Hardt,
Emretiens sur I'Antiquite classique 12) (Vandoeuvres-Geneve. 1966),
p. 104 ff.; H. Diirrie: Porphyrios' Symmikta Zetemata. lhre Stelltmg in
-~Jstem und Geschichte des Neuplatonisnms nebs/ einem Kommentar zu den
Fmgmenten (Miinchen, 1959), p. 5i; and Hadot: op. cit., pp. 3H and 4H5.
265. Calcidius: In Tim. 222,235,8-10.
266./bid. 222.235. 10-237.9.
267./bid. 1.23. 237. 10-l,'l,.
CAI.<:IDllfS 485
268. Ibid. 225, 240, 2-241. 2. The final argument is paralleled in Por-
phyry: De Anim. ad Hoeth. fr. 6 (l:usehius: Pmep. Etmzg XV. II, I) 'Against
him who states that soul is entelechy and understands that it is totally unmov-
l'd we should say that it moves' (npoc; lit tov EVTI:Atxemv tflv 'lfi.J'Xflv Ein6vta
Kai UKivrrrov 7tU VTEI..wc; ouaav Kl vEiv U7tEIAT\(jl6ta PTJTEOV) .
.!69. Calcidius: In Tim. 226.241.8-9. Cf. ibid. 262.268, 16-17.
2"70. Porphyry's definition was apparently shorter. See De Anim. ad
Hoeth. fr. 6 (Eusebius: Praep. Etang XV, II. I) 'self-moving substance'
(UtJTOKivrrroc; ouaia). Cf. Macrohius: In Somn. Scip. I. 14, 19.
r I. Suidas mentions a book of Porphyry entitled: Opoc; 'AptatotEATJV,
m:pi tou dvat tflv 'lfUXflv vteA.txemv (Porphyry was here following the lead
of Plotinus who had attacked the entelechy at Etm. IV. 7 /2/ 8\ 1-50). Other
t<:xts showing th<: influence of Porphyr)"s polemic are Nem<:sius: De Nat.
limn. 2. 560 B ff. and Prisdanus t.ydus: Solut. tid Cbosr. I, 44, .29 ff.
2"7.2. For this reason. Calcidius' quotations of Aristotle on p. 427 and nn .
.!<;and 28 may well he via Porphyry.
27.3. See nn. 264 and 168. The Porphyrian basis of the whole discussion is
d<:monstrated by H. Krause: Studia neoplatonica (leipzig, 1904), pp ..H-.34
and \l'aszink: Timaeus a Calcidio translatus commentarioque instructus.
-186 NEOPLATONlSM
pp. lxxv-lxxvii, xci-xcii. and 240-241. (Krause held that Porphyry's Quaes-
/i(mes Commixttle were used here, Waszink his Commefllary on the
Timaeus when~ doctrines from the Quaestiones Commi:'l:tae and De Anima
ad Hoetlmm were repeated). For a less convincing ar~umcnt that Calcidius
has drawn his material from an earlier Platonic source sec Dt>rrie: op. cit., p.
:Hand n. i.
2"'4. Since Calcidius says a great deal about divisions of the soul. he feels it
necessary to defend Plato against those detractors who accuse him of incon-
sistency. These argue that the Pbtledrus postulates a simple soul hut the
Timaeus a composite one (see Calcidius: In Tim. 228. 243. 13-18). Calcidius
replies that the division in the soul is a conceptual one only, somewhat
analogous to the presence of a ratio in a musical sound (see ibid. 228, 243,
18-244. 10). Thus, the situation with the soul is similar to that in the case of
the world. Sec pp. 471-473.
27S. Ibid. 213. 228, 18-20 cuius duple."< virtus. a/tera intellegens,
opinatrix a/tera. iuxttl qut1s sapie111ill cum disciplina et item prudentia
cum reclis opinionibus cont'lllescunt. Cf. ibid.. 140. 181, 1-3; 203, 222,
20-21; 207, 22S, .3-1.3; and 231. 24S. 13-14.
276.1bid. 137. 177. 14 ff.
Cr\LCJ[)JliS
aspect of the senses, local motion, and the part which nourishes
bodies' (appetitus sensuum locularis motus quaque corpora
nutritmtur) as he says in another.289 Since (i) human souls are
placed at their first creation in the heavenly bodies,290 (ii) the
planets are equivalent to the secondary gods to whom the task
of fashioning the lower parts of souls was delegated,291 and (iii)
the heavenly bodies are associated with psychic states in the
\vorld soul,292 we must therefore conclude that the lower parts
of the soul are acquired from the latter's planetary origin and
must also exist in the soul prior to its entry into any given ter-
restrial body. The counterpart of this thesis can be
demonstrated by considering the transmigration of the human
soul. Regarding this topic, Calcidius states that souls undergo
cycles of death and rebirth according to which each one can
either return to its celestial origin or enter into a higher or lower
state, 293 for a rational soul this elevating or debasing only taking
place within the range of human characters; 294 and that the en-
try into the lower state consists of 'the body's conjunction with
the remnants of vice: an incarnation made more brutal by in-
creasing the soul's blemishes from its previous life' (ad
titiorum reliquias accedente corpore incorporationem auctis
2H9. Ibid. 137, 177, 18-178, 7. At ibid. 255, .264, 11-14 Cakidius states
that God acted through intermediaries here because 'he could have no
assodation with matter' (nulla esset sibi cum corpore cond/iatio). See Plato:
Tim . .. lc.
290. C:alddius: In Tim. J:ll, 181, 9-12 and 200. 220, 10-17.
2<.J1./1Jid. l:\9.179.11-lland201..220. 18.
292. Sec pp. 481-48.2.
29:\.lbill. 196.117, 2';-.218, 7.
294. Ibid. 198. 219. 4-5. Here. he states quite deliberately that 'Plato does
not hold that a rational soul can assume the appearance and visage of an
animal lacking reason' (Plato mm putat rutimwbilem animam l'Ultum at-
tflle r1s ratione carentis anima/is induere). There is. however, no such state-
ment in Plato.
490 NEOPlATONISM
6.334 CONCLUSIONS
295./hid. 198.219.5-6.
296. See above.
297./bid. 139, 179, 19-180,2 and 187.212. 10-11.
298. In connection with the divisions of the human soul, the commenta!Dr
also makes use of Plato: Rep. IV, 4.~9d ff. on the tripartition Into 'rational'
o. oytO'TtKOV), 'spirited' (9UJ.10Et&&c;). and appctilin' (btt9UJlT)tlKOV). Sec nn.
281-282.
299. In connt:ction with the human soul's divisions. the commentator also
alludes 10 Aristotle: De Anim. II, 414a; 1-32 on the powers of the soul called
'nutrition' (9pE7tttK6v). appetition (OpEKTtKOV), 'sensation (aloennK6v).
and 'locommion' (KtVT)nKov Kata t6nov). Seen. 289.
CALC IDillS 491
.-\00. See Augustine: Ci11. Dei X, 30 (CCSL 47, 307-308) and Aeneas ofGaza:
Theophr. (PG 8';, 892B-893A). lamblichus and Hierocles also held this view,
hut these arc later writers not at issue here. On the question of transmigration
sec W. Stettner: Die Seelenuanderung bei Griechen tmd Riimern (Stuttgart,
193-j), pp. 72-7'; and H. Dorrie: 'Kontroversen urn die Seelenwanderung im
kaiscrzcitlkhen Platonismus', Hemres8'; (1957), p. 4.23.
30 I. The fullest description is at Porphyry: Sent. 29, 19, ';-13 where the
soul is said to have, according to its degree of purity, (i) when it is rational 'a
body close to immateriality and aetherial' (tyyuc; toii MA.ou Oci>lla, OnEp toti
TO ai8EplOV), (ii) when it resorts to imagination 'a soliform body' (to
i]l..tOEto&c;), (iii) when it becomes excited by sensible form 'a luniform body'
(TO OEAllVOEto&c;). and (iv) when it is attracted to the formless 'a body made of
moist vapors' (~ (ryprov civaeulltciaEwv auvEOtllK6ta). Cf. Porphyry: Ad
Gaur. II, 49, 14-21 and De Antro Nymph. 11. IL I ff. On the history of this
donrinc sec R. C. Kissling: 'The <'>XllllU-nVEUJlQ of the Neoplatonists and the
De lnsomniis of Synesius of Cyrene', American journal of PbiloiOg)' 43
( 1922), pp. 318-330 and E. R. Dodds: Proc/us, The Elements ot Theology. A
Retised Text uoftb Translation, Introduction cmd Commentm:v. Snond Edi-
tion (Oxford, 1963). Appendix II. pp. 313-.U I.
.~02. See Proclus: In Tim. Ill, 23L 18-:\2 .
.~03. Whether Numenius hdd this doctrine or not depends upon the inter-
pretation of (i) Numcnius: fr. B (Stohacus: Flori/. l, .-\74-37';) whlre evil i~
said to arise in the soul 'from its external attachments' (rmo tli>v f~w8Ev npo-
OIJlUOilEVWV). The meaning of this statement is uncertain unless the: 'at-
tachments' are to he understood in the light of (ii) Macrobius: In Sonm. Scip.
492 NEOPI.ATONISM
mentator has adopted the teaching from any one of these three
sources or a combination of them. However, the presence of the
definitely Porphyrian doctrine that rational souls cannot
migrate into animal bodies in a closely related context provides
strong circumstantial evidence that the notion of human souls
acquiring their lower parts from association with the heavenly
bodies is also derived from Porphyry here.304 Such a conclusion
certainly permits the hypothesis that Calcidius' entire account
of the higher and lower soul is Neoplatonic, although at this
point we are no longer in the realm of demonstrable certainty.
I. II. 12 where the soul 'puts on another aetherial envelope in each of the
spheres which lie below the heaven' (in singulis enim sphaeris quae caelo
subiectae sunt aetheria obr,olutione l'eslitllr). The diffit'ulty here is that
there is no agreement among scholars whether it is the teat'hing of :'llumenius
or Porphyry which is being reported. See pp. S 16-S 18.
304. Numenius agreed with most other Platonists- including Plotinus-
that transmigration into animal bodies was possible. See Numenius: fr. 49
(Aeneas of Gaza: Theophr. (PG 85, 8928)).
7
Macrobius
i. I INTRODUCTION
I. Since Macrobius was one of the most widely read pagan authors during
the Middle Ages, the task of describing his influence throughout this period is
of a magnitude to deter scholars. However. among the significant (although
partial) surveys already undertaken. the following should be consulted. M.
:\1anitius: Gescbicbte der lateiniscben Literatur des Mittelalters 1-111 (Miin-
chen. 19 I I- I 93 I) mentions Macrobius many times in connection with
specific mediaeval writers; P. Duhem: Le systeme du monde. Histoire des
doctrines cosmologiques de Pia ton a Copernic Ill (Paris. 191 S), pp. 62-71
describes the impact of the cosmological doctrines; M. Schedler: Die
Pbilosopbie des Macrobius und ibr Einfluss auf die Wissenscbaft des
christlicben Mittelalters (Beitriige zur Geschicbte der Pbilosophie und
71Jeologie des Mittelalters 1311) (Munster. 1916) studies the influence of the
metaphysical theories; W. H.Stahl: Macrobius, Commentary on the Dream of
Scipio. Translated with an Introduction and Notes (New York/London,
19';2). pp. 39-55 summarizes the earlier scholarship together with occasional
further observations; P. Courcellc: 'La postcrite chrctienne du Srmge de Sci-
flion ', Revue des etudes latines 36 ( 1958), pp. 205-234 traces Macrobius' in-
lhttnce in late antiquity; E. .Jeauneau: 'Macrobe source du platonisme char-
train'. Studi /Hedieta/1 I ( 1960). pp. 3-24 provides further information regar-
ding the influence upon the later Middle Ages; and H. Silvestre: 'Note sur Ia
sunic de Mac robe au moyen age'. Classica et Medit~etalla 24 ( 1963 ). pp.
I ~0-1 HO examines the writer's influence during the earlier and central Middle
Ages. From among the results of these researches. it is cmly possible here to
note those concerning (i) definite uses of Macroblus (evidenced by actual cita-
493
194 NEOPLATONISM
tual citation of the author's name or texts te,batim), (ii) references to his
strictly philosophical theories (as opposed to the more frequent appeal to his
astronomical and cosmographical teachings), and (iii) uses of either the
Saturnalia or the Commeutarius (in contrast to the grammatical treatise De
Differentiis). a) In late antiquity. Macrohius is quoted in connection with
arithmetic hy Boethius. b) In the Carolingian period. He is used by the com-
mentators on Martianus Capella- Eriugena. for the philosophical interpreta-
tion of mythology. for the exegetical notion of OKon6c;. for arithmetic. and
for the theory of the human soul; Martin of Laon. for the philosophical inter-
pretation of mythology; and Remigius of Auxerre, for the doctrine of the
hypostases. for arithmetic, and for the theory of the human soul - and by
the Ciceronian excerptor Hadoard, for the teaching regarding types of
mythical narrative (see B. Bischoff: 'Hadoardus and the Manuscripts of
Classical Authors from Corbie', Didascalltle. Studies in Honor of A.
Albareda, edited by S. Prete (New York. 1961), pp. 15-57). c) During the
tenth and eleventh centuries. He is employed by Pseudo-Bede: De Mundi
Constitulione, for the doctrine of the hypostases and for the theory of the
human soul (see E. Garin: Stud/ sui plutonismo medievale (Firenze, 1958).
pp. 36-4 3 ); by Bovo of Coney. for the doctrine of the hypostases. for
chemistry, for arithmetic, and for the theory of the human soul (see P.
Courcellc: La Consolation de Philosophic dans Ia tradition /itteraire.
Antecedents et posterile de Boece (Paris. 1967), pp. 292-295); by the
anonymous adapter of the Commentarius in the manuscript Bruxellensis
10066-7':1, for the analysis of the virtues (see H. Silvestre: 'Une adaptation du
commentaire de Macrobe sur le Songe de Scipion dans un manuscrit de Brux-
elles, Archives d'histoire tloctrinale et lftteraire du moyen dge 29 ( 1962),
pp. 93-101 ); and by Manegold of Lautenbach, for the doctrine of the
hypostases, for the theory of the human soul, and for the analysis of the vir-
tues (see T. Gregory: Platonismo medievale. Studt e ricerche (Roma, 1958),
pp. 17-30). d) During the twelfth century. He is cited by William of Conches,
for every aspect of his teaching in the first full scale commentary on his work
(sec E. )eauneau: 'Gioses de Guillaume de Conches sur Macrobe. Note sur les
manuscrits', Archives d'histoire doctrinale et litterai,e du moyen dge 27
(1960), pp. 17-23: 'La lecture des auteurs dassiques :ll'ecole de Chartres
durant Ia premiere moitic du X lie siecle. Un temoin privilegic: Les Glosae
super Macrobiu m de Guillaume de Conches'. Classical Influences on Euro-
pecm Culture A. D. 500-/500, edited by R. R. Bolgar (Cambridge, 1971 ), pp.
95-102; P. Dronke: Fabula. Explorations into the Uses of Myth in Medieval
Platonism (Mittellclfeinische Studien rmd Texte 9) (Leiden/Koln, 1974), pp.
I :~78); by Bernard Silvestris, for the teaching regarding types of mythical
narrative and for the theory of the human soul; by Abailard for the teaching
MACROBIUS 495
rl"garding types of mythical narrative, for the doctrine of the hypostases, for
the theory of the human soul, and for the analysis of the virtues; by Hugh of
St. \'ktor, for arithmetic and for tht: theory of the: human soul; by John of
Salisbury. for the interpretation of dreams; hy Alan of Lille, for the doctrine
of the hypostases, for arithmetic, and for the theory of the human soul; by
\'im:ent of Beauvais. for the theory of the human soul; and by many other
writers of the same period. According 10 criterion (i) above, we must exclude
from the list the tadt use of Macrobius in Ambrose and Jerome suggested by
P. Courcelle: 'Nouveaux aspects du platonisme chez saint Ambroise', Re11ue
ties etudes latines 34 (1956), pp. 220-239 (results which have in any case
been seriously questioned b}' M. Fuhrmann: 'Macrobius und Ambrosius',
Pbilologus 107 ( 1963). pp. 30 1-308), and the possible dependence of Servius
Danielis upon him maintained by E. Tuerk: 'Les Saturnales de Macrobe,
source: de Servius Danielis', Revue des etudes /ati11es 41 ( 1963 ). pp. 327-349.
\'fithout the application of criterion (ii), it would be necessary to discuss
writt:rs such as Bede, Dungal, Helperic of Auxerre, Regino of Priim, Abbo of
Fleury, Byrhtferth, Gerbert, and Adalbold of Utrecht; without the application
of criterion (iii), it would be necessary to discuss grammarians like Sedulius
Scott us. Of course, the importance of a writer during the Middle Ages can be
gauged not only by citations in other authors but by the manuscript tradition
of the writer's own works. On this latter aspect of Macrobius the following
may hl" consulted: A. La Penna: 'Studi sulla tradizione dei Saturnllli di
:\tacrohio', Annali della Scuolll Normtlle Super/ore di Pisa, Serie 2, 22
( llJ'5.-\), pp. 225-252; J. Willis: 'De Macrobii codice Montepessulano',
Rbeiniscbes Museum 97 ( 1954), p. 287 and 'De codicibus aliquot manuscrip-
t is Macrobii Saturnalill continentlbus', ibid. 100 ( 1957), pp. 152-164. Two
points regarding this manuscript tradition are worthy of note here: a) The
l"ditorial work of the Carolingian scholar Lupus of Ferrieres is happily
preserved in one manuscript of the Commentarius (see A. La Penna: 'Le
Parisinus latinus 6.P'O et le texte des CommentarU de Macrobe'. Retue de
fJbilologie et d'bistuire 24 ( 1950), pp. 177 -187); b) John of Salisbury's cita-
tions of the Sllturnalia show that he possessed an edition of the work more
lomplete than that now extant (see C. C. Webb: 'On Some Fragments of the
\'uturntllia ', Classical Review II ( 1897), p. 441 ).
496 NEOJ>LATONISM
with all three Macrobii of the Theodosian Code, proposing instead that with
a "Theodosius" who was pretorian prefect in A.D. 4.30.
~- Flamant: op. cit., pp. 96-126.
(,. Flamant: op. cit .. pp. 79-H.3.
-. Flamant: np. cit., pp. H7-91.
H. Flamant: op. cit .. p. 9 I. It should he noted th;u the dates suggested for
the composition of the two works are strictly dates after which they would
498 NEOPLATONISM
have been wrinen. This seems to be as far as one can proceed using imernal
criteria. Further arguments have been based upon the presence of political
conditions which would make the dissemination of manifestly pagan texts
possible. These are seemingly more speculative and suggest even later dates
for the treatises. See Flamant: op. cit .. pp. I 27- I .j I.
9. J. Willis: Ambrosii Tbeodosii Macrobii Saturnalia, apparatu critico
instruxit I. W. (leipzig, 1970). Cf. P. V. Davies: Macrobius, The Saturnalia.
Translated U'itb an Introduction and Notes (New York/london, 1969)
(made from the edition of Eyssenhardt).
10. Macrobius: Satum. II. I. 6.
I I. On the influence of these writers upon Macrobius see pp. <;I 1-i 1;.
12. On the symposium genre in late antiquity see Flamant: op. cit ..
p. 172 ff.
1.3. Macrobius: Satum. I. .3-i.
J.l. Ibid. I, 6.
li. Ibid. I. 7-10.
16. Ibid. I, I I.
MACROBJllS -499
55. "acrobius: In Srmm. Scip. I. 5, I. Points (vi), (vii), and (viii) com:s-
pond w the traditional criteria of the 'genre' (&iooc;). 'subject-matter' (UA11).
and 'purpose:' (OK07t6c;) mc:ntiont"d In introductions .
.~-1. Ibid. I. 5-6 .
.~'i. /hid. I.....,
0
.~6. IIJid. I. 8.
r. Ibid. 1. 9. This and the next fivt" chapters represent the first connected
1n::umcn1 of the soul.
:\8. /hid. I. I 0 .
.~9. /hid. I. I I.
10.1/Jid. I. 12.
I I. fiJi d. I, J:\.
12 Ibid. I, li.
1.~. IIJid. I. 15 - 11.9. Cosmography is discussed first, followed by
gl'ography.
H. /hid. 1!. 10.
l'i. IIJid. II. II.
16. 1/Jid. II. 12.
502 NEOPLATONISM
54. The following studies are the main general accounts of Macrobius'
sources: (i) For the Saturnalia. H. Linke: Quaestiones de Macrobii Satur-
naliorum fontibus, Diss. (Breslau, 1880); G. Wissowa: De Macrobii Satur-
naliorum fonlibus capita tria, Diss. (Breslau, 1880); G. Logdberg: In
Macrobil Saturnalia adnotatlones (Uppsala, 1936); and E. Tuerk: Macrobius
tmd die Que/len seiner Saturnalien. Eine Untersucbung iiber die
lli/dungsbestrebungen im Symmacbus-Krels, Diss. (Freiburg i. Br., 1962). (ii)
For the Commentarius. H. Linke: 'Uber Macrobius' Kommentar zu Ciceros
.\"omnium Scipionis . Phi/ologlscbe Abbandlrmgen, M. Hertz zum "'0.
(ieburtstage (Berlin. 1888), pp. 240-256 and K. Mras: 'Macrobius' Kommen-
tar zu Ciceros Somnium. Ein Beitrag zur Geistesgeschichte des 5.
Jahrhunderts N. Chr. . Sltzungsbericbte der Preussiscbetl Akademie der
Wissenscbaften, phil.-hist. KlliSse 6 (Berlin, 1933 ). pp. 232-286. (iii) For both
works. P. Courcclle: Late Latin Writers and their Greek Sources. translated
by H. E. Wedeck (Cambridge,MA, 1969), pp. 13-47. Unfortunately, much of
this scholarship- especially the older- confuses fact and speculation.
55. See Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I, 6, 2 and II, 2, I.
56. Ibid. l, 13.5 (to Plato: Phaetl. 62a-c, 64a. and 67d).
57. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. l, 12,7 (to Plato: Pbaed. 79c).
S04 :"IIEOPI.ATONISM
I. 2~. c; (to Phaedr. 246e-247a). Here the dialogue is not cited by name
although the Greek text is translated directly. Elsewhere in the Saturnalia
Wl' find only references to the dramatic settings of certain dialogues - see
Saturn. I, I, 3;1,1,5-6;1, 11,41;11, 1,2;andVJJ, 1,13;aselectionofanec-
dotes- see ibid. II. 8. 4-8; VII. 15. 3; and VII, 15, 15-16; and some
etymologies- see ibid. I, 17, 7; I, 23, 5; and I, 23, 7.
"'0. Macrohius: In Smmz. Scip. I. 13, 16. The anonymous treatise mention-
ed is almost certainly to be identified with Porphyry's De Regressu Animae.
According to F. Cumont: 'Comment Plotin detourna Porphyre du suicide',
Rezue ties etudes grecques 3 2 ( 1919), pp. 113-120 and Courcelle: op. cit., pp.
r--W the material from the Phaedo is derived indirectly. However, P. Henry:
Plotin eti'Occitlerzt. Finnicus Matenzus, Martus Victorinus, saint Augustin
et .\/aerobe (Lou vain, 1934 ), pp. 163-182 holds that the opposite is the case.
-I. Macrohius: In Somn. Scip. II, ~. 15. The reference is dearly 10 Por-
phyry's Commentarius in Timaeum. The pervasive influence of this work
on the Latin writer has heen underlined hy Schedler: op. cit., p. 85, n. 6;
Mras: op. cit .. pp. 238-251, 261-262, 265-268, 269-27~. and 281-282;
Courcelle: op. cit .. p. :f.f; Stahl: op. cit.. p. 197. n. ~I: Flamant: op. cit., pp.
ltH. 1-o ..~21-~22. 5555-ll. 561-562,l'tC.
"'2. It has been demonstrated that some of the citations of Plato in the
Satunw/i(i are derived through an intermediary. Thus, the reference at
Saturn. VII, I, 13 is via Plutarch: Quaest. Cmwit. 613d and that at Saturn.
'506 NEOPI.ATONISM
II. 8, 4-8 is via Gellius: Noel. Attic. XV. 2, 3. But this fact does not preclude
direct access to the original in addition, nor does it prove anything about the
usage in the Commentarius.
73. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. ll, 14,4 ff. (to Aristotle: Phys. Vlll,3.253a24
ff.) The title of Aristotle's work is not cited.
74. Macrobius: lnSomn. Scip. I. 14. 19.
7'5. Macrobius: Saturn. II, 8, 10-H (to Aristotk: Problem. 28, 7, 949b37-
950a 12). The title of Aristotle's work is not cited. There are various other
references 10 Aristotle in the Saturm1/ia- mostly in connection with minor
questions of physics- see Saturn. V, 18, 19-20; VII, 3. 24; VII, 6, 15;
VII,12,2'5-26; VII,l3.19-20; and VII,l6,34.
76. Sec Gcllius: Noel. Attic. XIX, 2, 5.
77. For a discussion of doxographies in late antiquity see pp. 242-244.
78. Macrobius: In Sonm. Scip. II, I 5, I ff. There has been considerable
scholarly debate on the identity of these Platonists. The most likely
hypothesis is that the reference is to Porph)ry whose De Anima ad Boetbum
(of which some fragments are preserved in Eusebius' Praepar,ltiO
l:'tangelial) was directed against the Peripatetic position. This is the view of
Schedler: up. cit .. pp. 54-65; Mras: op. ell., pp. 2"77-278; Courcelle: op. cit ..
p. i3: and Flamant: op. cit .. pp. 640-642.
79. It has been proven that certain other citations of Aristotle in the Satur-
nalia are derived through an intermediary. Thus. the reference at Saturn.
VII, 6. I '5 is \'ia Plutarch: Quaest. Comit. 650a and that at Saturn. VII, 13,
19-20 is \'ia Plutarch: Qtwest. Comit. 627a-b. This makes it seem that all
MACROBIL'S
~uch citations could be explained in the same way were the rele\'ant in-
u:rmcdiaries extant.
HO. Macrobius occasionally refers to 'Piatonists' (Platonic/) in general -
sec In Somn. Scip. I. I I . 4; I. I I, 9; II, 3. 14; etc. - and once each to Speusip-
pus- see Saturn. I. 17. 8 - and Xenocrates -see In Somn. Scip. I. 14. 19.
81. Macrobius: Satum. I. 17. 65 (Numenius: fr. 54). There is also an anec-
dote regarding Numenius' dream in which he was admonished for revealing
the Eleusinian mysteries through his philosophical interpretations. See
Macrobius: lnSomn. Scip.l, 2. 19(Numcnius: fr. SS).
H2. Macrohius' approximate contemporary Calcidius seems to have known
:"<<umcnius both from the latter's own works and from citations embedded in
Porphyry's. See pp. 42H-429.
H:\. See Macrobius: In Som11. Scip. I. 8, S where Plotinus is placed in a
special c:uegory amon~ philosophers together with Plato himself.
Ht. Ibid. II, 12.7-10 (to Plotinus: Em1. I. I /'HI I: I, I IS3/4-5; and I. I IS:\1
- ~- The Porphyrian title of this treatise Quid a11ima/, quid btmm (ti TO ~<j)ov
Kai tic; 6 tiv9pronoc;) is quoted.
HS. Macrobius: /11 Somn. Scip. I, 8. 3-11 (to Plotinus: Em1. l, 2 Ill) I I; I. 2
119/ 3: and I. 2 1191 6-7). The Porphyrian title De llirtutibus (m:pi ap&twv) is
4UOtcd.
iOH NEOPl.ATONISM
H6 . Macrobius: In Sonm. Scip. I. 13. 9-20 (to Plminus: Em1. I, 9/16/). The:
Porphyrian title: De voluntaria morte (nEpi t~aywyij<;) is quoted.
H7. Macrohius: In Smnn. Scip. II. 12, l~li (to Plotinus: Em1. II, I liO/ I
and II. I /40/3).
HR. Macrohius: In Somn ..kip. I. 17, H-11 (to Plotinus: Enn. II,.?. /14/ I).
H9. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I. 19. 27 (to Plotinus: Emz. II, 3 /52/3 and II .
.~ /52/ I 0). The Porphyrian title of this treatise: Si facitmt astra (Ei notEi tci
liotpa) is quoted. Cf. Macrobius: Saturn. I, 17. 3.
90. For the passages mentioned sec: Mras: op. cit .. pp. 2i l-2i3. 2i7-2iH.
260, 262. 273-27~: Henry: op. cit .. pp. 146-192: Courcdlc:: op. cit .. pp.
32-33, 37-38; and Flamant: op. cit .. pp . .399-400. 4ii-457. '56H-i73.
';90-591. 607-608, 634-63i.
91. A careful comparison of Macrobius' text. Plotinus: Em1. 1,2 /IW and
MACROBIUS
lorphrry: Sent. 32 was undertaken by Henrr: op. cit., pp. 154-162. He noted
that whereas Plotinus simp!)' interprets virtues such as wisdom. temperance.
~tc. on different levels, Porph)'r)' attempts to fashion a systematic order of
progression. Macrobius is closer to the latt~r. Furthermore. he noted the
following details occurring in both Porphrrr and Macrohius: (i) The notion
that the lowest virtues are political'. (ii) Phrases such as ad ration is nonnam
= m:pi to A.oytl;6JJVOV (Macrohius: In Somn. Scip. I. 8, 7/Porphyry: Sent. 32.
25. 8-9), quod semper idem est = taut6tllc; (Macrohius: In Somn. Scip. I. 8,
Hl/Porphyry: Sent. 32, 29, 6) instead of auA.6tllc; (Piotinus: Enn. I. 2 /19/7,
5 ). and prudenti" est mens ips" divina = oo~pia &e ytvrooKrov 6 vouc;
(Macrobius: 111 Somn. Scip. I. 8, tO/Porphyry: Sent. 32. 29, 4). This
lkmonstration is decisi\'e and - since it runs somewhat against his own
th~sis of a dominant Plotinian influence upon Macrobius - remarkably ob-
j~<.'tin. For a further comparison of the Plot in ian and Porphyrian discussions
of the virtues see H.-R. Schwyzer: 'Piotinisches und unplotinisches in den
'A~popJJai des Porphyrios', Plotino e II Neoplatonismo in Oriente e in Oc-
cidetlle (Atti del Convegno 11lternazimlale, Roma 5-9 ottobre 19""0 = Ac-
cademi" Nazionale de Lincei, Quaderno 198) (Roma. 1974), pp. 221-252.
For Macrobius' own treatment of this topic see C. Zintzen: 'Romisches und
neuplatonisches bei Macrobius. Bemerkungen zur 7tOA.tttK1) aptft in Comm.
in Somn. Sc:ip. l, 8'. Polite/a und Res publica, Beitriige zum Verstiindnis
tmt Po/itik, Rec/Jt utld StC~at in der Antlke, dem Andenken R. Stmks.
hlrausg~geben von P. Stc:inmetz (Wi~shaden. 1969). pp ..'\57-376.
91. This thesis is abl)' formulated by Flamant: op. cit., pp. 'i71-'i73. The
argument of Henry: op. cit., pp. 1'i3-l 'i4 that Macrobius' reference to the
ll'rs~ Plotinian style in itself proves direct knowledge of the original is in-
conclusive. since the latin writer could easily have derived this notion from
Porphyr(s Fila Plotini, as a comparison of the following texts indkat~s:
Manobius: In Som11. Scip. ll, 12, 7-8 P/otlnus, magis quam quisqtwm ter-
510 NEOPI.ATONISM
distinction between true and false images in dreams, 9:i for the
doctrine that the presence of mathematical structure in the cor-
poreal realm reflects the prior mathematical constitution of its
animating soul, 94 and for an interpretation of Minerva as signify-
ing that power of the sun which furnishes intellection to human
minds.9i Since with this author we approach a date closer to
Macrobius' own, it seems less necessary to entertain the
hypothesis that he has been transmitted through an in-
termediary .96 The only candidate for such an intermediate role
would be a Virgilian commentator dependent upon Porphyry,
although it cannot be demonstrated conclusively that this
much-discussed commentator ever existed.9 7
borum parcus ... sufJ copiosa t'erum densitClle dlsseruit = Porphyry: VltCI
Plot. 14 tv Of: t<!> ypciq>Etv auvtolloc; yf.yovs Kai noA.uvouc; J3paxuc; n: Kal
VO'IJI-\QCJI nA.EOvci~wv. Se~: the: rc:marks of Flamant: op. cit .. p. 569 on this
point.
9.'\. Macrobius: In Somn ..\"cip. I. 3. 17. Th~: title of the work from which
the citation is made is given as the Commentarii. Since Porphyry's point is
made in conjunction with the exegesis of a Homeric text. most scholars con-
clude that the reference is to the Porphyrian Qtwestiones Homeriale which
are extant only in fragmems. See Mras: op. cit .. p. 238: Courcelle: op. cit., p .
.'\i: and Flam:mt: op. cit .. p. 163.
94. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. II. 3. 1 S ( = Porphyry: In Tim. fr. 72). The
title of the work is givc:n.
95. Macrobius: Sa tum. I. 17. 70. The title of the work from which the cita-
tion is made is not given. However, since the passage is embedded in a con-
text strikingly parallekd by Senius: In Buco/. S. 66 who actually quotes the
title of his Porphyrian source. most scholars now believe that the reference is
to the: no longer extant treatise entitled Sol. Sc:c Courcelle: op. cit .. pp. 28-.'\ I;
F. Altheim: A us Spiitantike und Cbristentum I. 'Porphyrios' Schrift iiber den
Sonncngott' (Tiibingen. 195 1). pp. 1-25 and 138-152; F. Althcim und R.
Stiehl: Die Amber in der a/ten Welt Ill: Anfiinge der Dichtung, Der Son-
nengott. Huchre/iglonen (lkrlin. 1966). pp. 198-24 3: and Flamant: op. cit.,
pp. MS-66H.
96. Porphyry died around A.D. 325-326.
l)":". The :1uthorship of such a commentary h;ts bc:c:n at v:trious times :tsslgn-
ed to Marius Victorinus and Cornelius Labeo. See pp. S 15-516.
MACROHillS <; I I
I, 9. 3). The passages from Aeneid VI are used (i) In Macrobius: /n Somn. Scip.
I, 9: to describe the soul's departure from the body (Virgil: Aeneid. VI, 736).
its astral origins and incarnation (Virgil: Aeneid, VI, 640-64 I), and its attach-
ment to passions after death (Virgil: Ameid. VI, 653-655); (ii) In Macrobius:
In S(mm. Scip. I, 10: to interpret the devoured liver (Virgil: Aeneid. VI.
598-600), lxion's wheel (Virgil: Ae11eid. VI. 616-6I7), and other torments
(Virgil: tleneid. VI, 7-4.'\) as allegorical accounts of the soul's embodiment.
Hadot: op. cit., pp. 218-.230 has produced some evidence to suggest that the
author of this Virgil ian commentary was Marius Victorious.
12-i. Sec Flamant: up. cit., pp. 576-580 and 6.22. This writer accepts the
thesis of a Latin source for Macrobius discussion with certain reservations.
12';. According to the classification of sources offered on pp. ;02-503,
some of the writers in the first category will also appear in the third.
126. Manobius: In Somn. Scip. l, 11. 10- I. 1.2. I H.
127. The exact references are Porphyry: De Antr. lVympb. 21. 22.2-24.
MACROBILIS <;17
2-L .~and ibid. 28, 26. 26-28. 28. 6: Proclus: In Remp. II, 128. 26- 130. 1-4
an <.I iMd. 1.~ I, 8-14.
128. Macrobius: bl Somn. Scip. I, 12, 1-3. That this section alone is Nume-
nian is contended by R. Beutler: 'Numenios'. Paul;s Realencyclopadie der
klassiscben Altertumswlssenscbaft. Suppi.-Band 7 (Stuttgart, 1940), col.
(l-:o6-677; A.-J. Festugiere: /.a rer,elation d'Hermes Trlsmegiste III: Les doc-
trim!s de l'dme (Paris, 1953). p. 42, n. 2: J. H. Waszink: Timaeus a Calcldlo
translatus commentarioque instructus (Leiden, 1962), p. lvii, n.1; Studien
::um Timaioskommentar des Calcidius 1: Die erste Halfte des Kommentars
(mit Ausnabme der Kapltel iiber die Weltseele) (Leiden, 1964), p. 13. n.l;
and 'Porphyrios und Numenios', Porpbyre (Fonda lion Hardt, Elllretiens sur
l'..tntiqulte class/que 12) (Vandoeuvres-Geneve, 1966), p. 77: W. Theiler:
'Ammonios und Porphyrios', ibid. p. 122; M. A. Elferink: La descente de
/'{/me d'apri!s Mt1cro1Je (Leiden, 1968), pp. 8-28; P. Hadot: Porpbyre et Vic-
tor/nus I (Paris, 1968), p. 182, n. I :and E. des Places: Nmnenius. Fragments.
Tt.Yte etabli ettradult par E. des P. (Paris. 1973). pp. 84-8<;.
129. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I. 11, 10 and I, 12, 4-18. That this material
(IO~lther with ibid. I. 12, 1- 3) is Numenian is argued by E. A. Leemans: Studie
rJter den Wljsgeer Numenlus van Apamea met l!itgave der Fragmenten
IBrussel. 1937) pp. H-<;4 and I 04-1 I 0; E. R. Dodds: 'Numenius and Am-
monius'. Les sources de Plotin (Fmulatlon Hardt, Entretiens sur /'Ant/quite
classique <;) (Vandoeuvres-Geneve. 1960), pp. 8-10: H. de Ley: Mc1aobius
ancl Numenius. A Study of Macroblus. In Somn. I, c. 12 (Bruxclles, 1972),
pp. 2':"-';0: and Flamant: op. cit .. pp. S12-Sl3. <;46, and S49. n. 92.
'i1H NEOPLATONISM
130. See for example Mras: op. cit., p. 25'i and J. Pepin: 'La fortune duDe
Antm Nympbarum de Porphyre en Occident'. Plotino e II Neoplatonismo in
Oriente e in Occidenlt (Alii del Cmne.~no lnternazimwle. Rom a 5-IJ ollobre
197fJ) (Roma. 197-4), pp. 527-530.
131. See for example: de Ley: op. cit .. pp. I 'i-25 and Flamam: op. cit.. p.
'i52- for the Commentarius in Rempub/icam; Leemans: op. cit., pp. 47-48
and Elferink: op. cit., pp. 4-5 and 40- for the Commellt~lriu.~ in Timaeum.
That both Commentarii (together with De Antru Nympbarum) were used is
suggested by Courcelle: op. cit .. pp. 4 1-4 2.
1.32. Examination of the weight of these different solutions will have to
await the detailed analysis below. Seep. 571 ff.
13.-\. ~lacrobius: /uSmrm. Scip. I. 11, 5-~.
134. P1otinus: Etm. V. 211 II I. 1-22.
MACROBillS
152. For the first passage see Augustine: Cit. Dei VII, 7 (CCSL 47, 191-
192); ibid. VII, 28 (CCSL 47, 210-211 (Varro: Antiqu. Rer. Divin. fr. 230 and
fr. 263)); and Lydus: De Mens. IV, 2, 64, 18-65, 3 (Varro: Antiqu. Rer. Divin.
fr. 20 I ) - the last parallel including the title of Varro's work. For the second
passage see Tertullian: Adt. Nat. II. 12, 18 (CCSL I. 62 (Varro: Antiqu. Rer.
Ditin. fr. 2-lO)).
I B. Macrobius: In Sumn. Scip. II, 17, IS- 17. See Schedler: op. cit. , pp. 6-9
who also uses this schema as the hasis for a discussion of Macrobius'
philosophical doctrine.
I 54. On earlier uses of the tripartite schema see pp. 74-77 and 227-228.
Whereas earlier writers include the study of God and the Forms in the
physical branch of philosophy. Macrohius places it in the rational.
MACROBiliS 51:\
...,.21 RATlONALPHlLOSOPHY
(ii) 'This monad, which is the beginning and end of all things
but itself knows neither beginning nor end, is applied to the
highest God and distinguishes our understanding of him from
the plurality of things and powers subsequent to him. Nor
would you seek this monad in vain among the ranks below God,
for it also corresponds to Intellect generated from the highest
God which, unaware of temporal changes, exists always in that
single eternity co-extensive with it. Although the monad is itself
not numbered, since it is a unity, it nevertheless generates from
itself and contains within itself innumerable Forms of things.
Furthermore, by turning your mental vision a little you will
discover that this monad is applied to Soul, since the latter is
free from the contamination of physical matter and, being
dependent only upon its prior cause and upon itself in the
simplicity of its nature, admits no division into its unity when it
pours forth to the animation of the whole universe. You
observe how this monad, sprung from the first cause of things
and everywhere complete and always undivided, has maintain-
ed its continuity of power as far as Soul'. 158
(iii) 'The possession of extraordinary powers has accrued to
the number five because it alone embraces all things which are
and seem to be. We say that the intelligibles "are" and that all
15H. Ibid. l, 6, H-9 haec monas initium finisque omnium, neque ipsa
principii aut finis sciens. ad summum refertur deum eiusque intellectum a
sequenfium numero rerum et potestatum sequestrat, nee in inferiore post
dettm gradu frustra eam desidermeris. haec ilia est mens ex summo enata
deo, quae l'ins tempon11n nesciens in uno S('tl/fU!r quod adest nmsisfit
(l('l'fJ, cumque utpote una notl sit ipsa numerabilis. innumeras tamen
generum species et de se creal et intrc1 se nmfinet. inde quoque aciem
[wu/u/um cogitation is inc/inans bane monada reperies ad an imam referri.
anima enim aliena a siltestris contagione materiae. tan tum se auctori suo
ac sihi debens, simplicem sorfitanaturam. cum se a11imandae immensitafi
tmitersitatis infundat. nullmn init tamen cum sua unitate clitortium.
l'ides ut baec mona.~ orta a prima rerum causa usque aclanimam ubique
integra et semper inditi/dua crmtinuationem potestatis obtineat.
:'IIEOPLATONISM
I ';9. Ibid. l. 6. 19-20 ille1 tero quinario mtmero pmpriettls excepta poten-
tiae ullra ceteras eminenlis etenil quod so/us om11ie1 quaeque sunt quaeque
l'identur esse complexus est. esse autem dicimus intellegibilia. tiderl esse
corpora/ia omnie~ seu dit1i11um corpus babeant seu caducum. bic ergo
numerus simu/ omnia et supera et subiecta designat. aut enim deus sum-
mus est aut mens e.\' eo nata in qua rerum .~pecies crmli7le7llur. aut mundi
anima quae tmimarum omnium fims est, aut cae/estia sun/usque ad nos.
autterrena natura est. et si(' quinarius rerum omnium numerus impletur.
MACROBJliS
160. Ibid. 1, 1i. 2-8 bene autem unhersus mundus dei lemplum zocatur
pmpter i/los qui aestimmzt nibil esse a/iud deum nisi caelum ipsum et
n~t/estia isla quae cernimus. ideo ut summi omnipotentiam dei ostenderet
posse ti.'l: intel/egi. numquam tideri. quicquid bunwno su/Jicitur aspectui
hmplum eius toetltit qui sola mente com:ipltur, ut qui haec teneratur ut
temp/a, cultum tamen maximum de/Jeat c:ondilori. sciatque quisquis in
ustmt templi huius imluL"itm ritu sibi tit.rmlum .mcerdotis. untie et tflltlsi
quodam JntiJiia) praec:onio tantam bumano generi dirrillilclfem inesse
lestatur. ut unilersos siderei animi cognatimw tWIJilitet. twlcmdum est
lflloc/ boc loco animum et ut proprie el ut a/Jusire dicilur posuil. animus
528 NEOPI.ATO;\IISM
enim proprie mens est. quam dirliniorem anima nemo dubitat/il: sed non
nunquam sic et animam usurpantes vocamus. cum ergo dicit, bisque
animus datus est ex ill is sempiternis ignibus. mentem praestat intellegi, quae
nobis proprie cum caelo sideribusque communif est; cum tero aft, retinen
dus animus est in custodia corporis, ipsam tunc animam nominal, quae
tincitur custodia corporali, cui mens ditina non subditur. mmc qua/Iter
nobis animus. it/ est mens. cum slderibus communis sit secmulum theologos
disseramus. deus qui prima causa et est et NJcatur, wms omnium quaeque
sunt quaeque tltlentur esse princeps et origo est. hie superabtmdanti
maiestatisfecunditate de se mentem creavit. haec mens, quae vouc; rocatur,
qua patrem inspicit, plenam similltudinem senat auctoris, animam tero
de se creat posterlora respiciens. rursum anima patrem qua intuetur in-
duitur. ac paulatim regrediente respectu in jabricmn corporum incorporea
ipsa tlegenerat. habet ergo et purisslmam ex mente, de qua est nata, ra-
ticmem quod A.oy1K6v tocatur et ex sua natura accipit praebendi sensus
praebendlque incrementi seminarium, quorum tmum aia6T]nK6v alterum
(ji\Jt!K6v nuncupatur. sed ex his primum id est A.oy1K6V quod innatum sib/ ex
mente sumpsit, sicut rere divinum est, ita soils dhinis aptum; rellqua duo,
aia6T]nK6v et (ji\Jt!K6v, uta ditin is recedmtt, ita contenientia sunt caducis.
161 . Ibid. I. 14. IS seetmdu m hctec ergo cum e.\ summo cleo mens, ex
mente anima fit, cmima re,o et condat et titct compleat omnia quae se-
qmmtur, ctmctaque hie wms fulgor illumine/ et in tmirersis appareat. ut
in muftis specztlls per orclinem positis l'Uitus unus. cumque omnia nm-
tinuis succession/bus se seqmmtur degenerantla per ordinem ad imum
MACROBIUS "i29
facial aut ipse con tineal. ipsum (/enique lmem t'eteres tncmerunt. e/ aptul
lholol!,OS luppiter est mwuli anima. him illud est, Ah Jon~ prindplum.
Musac, lovis omnia plt:na. quod de tlmto poetae alii mutuati sunt. qui de
sideribus locuturus a cttelo In quo sunt sidera e:-.:ordium .~umendum esse
decernetls, ttiJ lme incipiendum esse memnrtll'it. hinc et /uno soror eius et
cmtiun.\' tocatur. est autem Juno aer. el dlcitur soror qui isdem seminibus
quibus caelum eliam aer fJrrJL't'eatus est, C(miun.\ quia aer subieclus est
caelo.
163. for these categories sec pp. 266272 and 338 ff.
16L Macrohius: Ill Smnn. Scip. I. 1-i. 2 (wxt i\').
MACROBilJS S:\ I
16';. Ibid. I. 2, l.f (text i). See Plotinus: Enn. V, 3/-i9/ 17. IS-.:\H; V, 6/2.f/
6, .U-35: Porphyry: DeAbstin. Ill. II. 3: In Parm. I. 32:11,3-4: II. 16-Ji: II.
Z2-2S; IV, 22-26 for denial of thought regarding the first principle:: sc:e
Plotinus: Enn, V, 5/32/6, 17-37; VI. 8/39/ 19, 1-6: Porphyry: De AIJstin. II.
3~. 2: Hist. Pbilos. fr. IS (Cyril: Contra /ulian. I (PG 76. S:i9A-B)): In Ptlrm.
I. 2-6: IX. 20-26 for denial of both thought and expression regarding it.
166. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I. 2. 1'5 (text i).
167. See pp. 266-269.
16H. See Plotinus: Enn. V. S 13216. 19-21; V.:; 1321 l:\. 11-17: VI, 8/39/
11.2S-26: Porphyry: In Parm. II . .f-8: IV, 7-9: IV. 19-22: Xl1.26-2"". We: can-
not enter into the subtleties of the: Plotinian and Porphyrian notions of the:
first principle's existence nor into the probable diffc:rc:n<:c:s between their
rc:sptnive views.
169. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I, 2, I S-16 (text i). Sec: Plotinus: Enn. Ill. H
1.~01 I 0. 32-3S: V, I /10/6. 8-1 S: V. 3 /-i9/ H. ~-H: VI. 8 /391 H. 1-6: VI. H /,1,9/
I I. - -H: VI. 9 /9/ S. 32-.H; Porphyry: His f. Pbilos. fr. IS (Cyril: Contm
S:\2 NEOPLATONISM
Julian. I (PG 76, S49 A-B)) for the notion that the first principle can be
known indirectly through its consequents. See Plotinus: Enn. V, 3 /49/ 12,
39-44; V, 5 I 3218, 7-8; VI, 7 I 38 I 16, 24-35; Porphyry: De Abstin. III, II, 3;
De Simul. fr. 2, 2 14-3 6 for specific use of the solar analogy in this connec-
tion.
170. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. l, 2, 16 (text i).
171. Ibid. I. 6, 20 (text iii); I. 14. I c; (text v): I, 17. 12 (text vi).
172. Ibid. l, 2, 14 (text i). Plotinus describes the first principle as 'God'
(9e6c;) in about twenty passages. Sec J. H. Slc:eman and G. Pollet: Lexicon
Plotinianum (leidenllouvain, 1980), s. v. 9e6c; c). For Porphyry's usage
which is perhaps more influential over Macrobius seen. 179.
173. Macrobius: hi Somn. Scip. I, 2, 14 (text i). 'The Good' (niya96v) is
one of the two most common titles of the first principle in Plotinus. See
Sleeman and Pollet: op. elf., s. v. aya96c; d). See Porphyry: His/. Phllos. fr. 15
(Cyril: Contra Julian. I (PG 76, 549A-B)); fr. 16 (Cyril: Colllra lulicm. VIII
(PG 76, 9168)); fr. 18 (Cyril: Contra Julltm. I (PG 76, S52B-C)).
174. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I. 6, 8 (text ii).
175. Ibid. I. 6, 18.
176. Ibid. I, 14, 6 (text iv). 'The One' (TO fv) is the second of the two most
common titles of the first principle in Plotinus. See Sleeman and Pollet: op.
cit., s. v. Elc; a). See Porphyry: De Abstin. I, S7, 3; II. 49, I; His/. Phi/us. fr. 15
(Cyril: Contra Julian. I (PG 76, 549A-B)); In Parm. I. 3-35.
MACROUIUS
182. Macrohius: In Somn ..kip. I. 1-4, 6 (text iv). See Plotinus: E'nn. VI. 8
/39/10. 32-.~'; 'fullness of power' (um:p~o/..i] tij<;liuvliJ.LEffi<;): ibid. V, 2/11/1,
..., -9 'it has overflowed and its supcrahundan(.c has produced another'
(unepeppun Kai to unepnJ..iipe<; auwu nenoiTJKEV c'iJ../..o): ibid. V. I /I 0/6, 4-8:
VI. 8/39/18, IR-22 'overflow' (EKpeiv, EK)(Eiv, etc.)
I 8;11. Macrobius: In Smnn. Scip. I. 6, 9 (text ii). Sec Plotinus: E'nn. I. 6 /1/7,
2';-28: I. 8 /';1/2, 21-22; V, I /10/6,22-28: V. 2 /II/I, 17-18: V, 3/49/12,
.H-38: V, '; /32/5,2-13: VI. 8/39/10, 18-21: VI, 8/39/16. 14-16: VI, 8/39/
16, 29-:Hl: VI, 9 /9/9, 4-6: Porphyry: De Abstin. ll, .\7, I: Hi st. Pbilos. fr. 1S
(Cyril: Contra lulicm. I (PG '76 S-49A-B)): Sent. 24. 14. ';-12.
184. Macrohius: In Somn. Scip. I. 6. 9 (text ii). See Plotinus: E'nn. I. 6/1/9,
18-Zl: III, 8 /30/9, 24-28: Ill, 9/13/ i. 1-9: V. '; /.U/ 8. 22-27: V. '; /32/9,
.~3-35: VI, 8 /39/ 19. 10-12: VI. 91914. H-26: Porphyry: Ad Gaur. 12. 50.
21-22: Sent. 31. 21. 9-1-i; ?II. 22, 2-8.
185. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I, 6, 9 (text ii). See Plotinus: Emz. II. 4 /12/
IS. 17-28; V, .~ 1'191 16, 1-';; V, 8/31/ I. 26-30 for the notion that there are
de~rees of powtr derived from the first principle. Porphyry: Sent. 3S. 40,
22-'f I. 3 alludes to the 'connection' (ouvantElV) between different levels so
dttermined.
186. Macrohius: In Smmz. Scip. I. l'l. 15 (text\'). A source for Macrohius'
application of this image cannot he found in either Plotinus or the extant
works of Porphyry. However. the fact that Proclus: In Tim. I, 262. 16-25: I.
314, 13-19; II. 2'1, 23-31; II. 112, 3-6 uses it in a similar way indicates its cur-
rency in ~coplatonic circles. He probably took this interpretation from Por-
phyry who is therefore likely to ha,e been Macrohius' source also. See Mras:
op. cit., pp. 2';8-2<;9.
187. See nn. 180-18';.
MACR<>BIUS
II. 1-49; VI, 4 /22/4, 1-3; Porphyry: /11 Pamz. XI. '5-XII, 23; XIV, 10-15;
Sent. 44. 58. 6-9; In Tfm. fr. 56 (Prod us: In Tim. I, 456, 31--i 57, II).
194. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I. 14, 4 (text iv). See Plotinus: Eml. ll, 9
/33/17, 6-8; Ill, 2/-17/1, 26-30; Ill, 6/26/6, 29-49; IV, 1/211 '5-7; IV, 2/4/1,
17-29; V, 2 /Ill 2. 19-20; V, 8 /31/9. 10-14; V. 9 1'51 '5, 29-32: V, 9 1'51 5.
i 1-4'5; V, 9/S/10, 9-10; Porphyry: Sent. 42, 53. 17~20; 43. 56,7-10.
19'5. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I, 6, 8 (text ii). See Plot in us: Enn. Ill, 7 /!'5/
3. 1-39; Ill, 7/4'5/6, 1-.~6; Ill, 7/4'5111. 1-20; IV,.~ /27/2'5. 13-17; V, 1/10/4,
10-30; V, I I 10/ II. '5-13; V, 9 1'51 5. 1-'5; Porphyry: Sent. 44. '57. 21-'58. 9
absence of temporal changes; Plotinus: Em1. IV. 3 /27/ 25, 13-17; IV. 4 /28/
IS. 2; V. I /I 0/ 4, I 0-30; V. I /10/ II. 5-13; V, 9 /'51 '5. 1-4; V. 9 lSI 10, 9; Por-
phyry: Sent. 44, 57, 21-58. 9 connection of 'eternity' (a!wv) and lntellt:ct;
Plotinus: Em1. Ill,"'! IHI 3. 1-:\9; Ill. 7 /4';/6, 1-36; Ill, 7/4';/ II. 1-20; VI, 2
1431 16, 6-7; Porphyry: In Tim. fr . .~I (Produs: /11 Tim. I, 2S7, 2-8) connec-
tion of eternity and Being; Plotinus: Enn. Ill, 7 /-iS/ 6. 1-36: Ill, 7 /4S/ II.
1-20; Porphyry: Sent. l-i, '58, i-9 the unity of content.
196. See pp. 266-272 and 343-344.
197. See nn. 193-19'5.
198. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I, 6, 8-9 (text ii). See Plotinus: Enn. V,
/10/7, 27-38; V, 3/49/7, 30-3<;; V, 3/i9/11. 1-:~0; V, R 1.~11 cj, H-1""; V, 9/'5/
S. 1-7; V,9 1'51 5. 19-29; VI, 2113121. 39-43; VI. 21-i:\122, 26-28; VI. '1581
3'5, 30-33: Porphyry: In Tim. fr. S I (Proclus: In Tim. I. .WL 2-8).
199. Macrobius: In Sonm. Scip. I. 2. 14 (text i): I, 6, 20 (text iii). Sec:
Plotinus: Enn. I. 6 /1/9. ~4-.:\7; I. 8 /5 II 2. I '5-21; II. 9 /35/ 17. 5-6; Ill. 8 /50/
H. 40--t8; Ill, 8 /30/ <J, 5S-5<J: V, 7 /18/ I, 1-26; V. 7 /18/3. 202:~; V, 9/S/ '5,
1-48; V, 9/516, 1-10; V. 9/6/8, 1-V. 9/6/ 14, 22; VI, 2 1-i.~l 2116-58; VI, 2
MACROBiliS 'i:\7
J..f!,/22, 1-3: VI, 7 /3H/2, 1-;6; VI. 7/38/3.22-33: VI, 7/3H/ H. 'i-32: VI, 7/38/
9. I-VI, 7 /3H/ II. H; VI."' /.'\8 12, 1-4: VI. 7 /38/ H. 11-23: VI, 7 /38/ 18,
1-'il: Porphyry: Sent. 10, .j, 7-8:22, 1.'\. 1.'\-16: 43, 'i4, 7-11: i3, 'i6, i-15; In
Tim. fr. 'i I (Proclus: In Tim. I, 394, 2-8).
200. Macrobius: In Sonm. Scip. I, 6, 8-9 (text ii). See PIOlinus: Emz. II, 9 I
33/1, 45-54; Ill, 7/45/3, 4-23; Ill, 8/30/8, 1-8; III, 8/30/8, 40-45; V, 6/
2.j /1,4-14;V,9/5/6,1-25;V,9/5/8, I-V,9/5/9,15;VI,2/43/2,1-3;
VI. 2/43/3, 20-25; VI, 2/43/20, 1-29; VI, 2/43/22, 6-11; VI, 7/38/8,
17-32: VI, 7/38/14, 1-23; Porphyry: hz Parm. XII, 4; Setrt. 22, 13, 13-14;
H. 57. 1-16; In Tim. fr. 52 (Proclus: In Tim. I, 422, 15-20). The Greek
Ncoplatonic doctrines presented here and in the previous notes are con-
siderably more complex than the Macrobian teachings which parallel them.
See P. Hadot: 'Etre, vie, pensce chez Plotin et avant Plotin', Les sources de
P/otin (Fondalicm Hardt, Entretlens sur I'Antiquite c:ltlssique 5)
(Vandoeuvres-Genhe, 1960), pp. 105-141; W. Beierwaltes: Plotin, Uber
Ewigkeil und Zeit (Enneade Ill, 7), ubersetzt, eingeleltet und kommenliert
(Frankfurt a. M., 1967). pp. 11-49; A. H. Armstrong: 'Eternity, Life and Move-
ment in Plotinus' Accounts of voii<;', Le Neoplatonlsme (Colloque lnterna-
titma/ du Centre Nalimwl de Ia Recherche Scientifique, Royaumont 9-13
juin 1969) (Paris, 1971). pp. 67-74: and K. Wurm: Substanz und Qualitat.
/:'ill Beitrag zur lnterpretalicm der plolinlschen Traktate VI, I, 2 und 3
<Berlin, 1973). p. 221 ff.
20 I. See pp. 286 ff and 3'; 1-354.
202. See nn. I 98-200.
20.'\. ~tacrohius: In Somn. Scip. I, J.j, 6-i (text iv). For the Plotinian and
Porphyrian parallels seep. 54 3 ff.
201. JIJid. I, 1-L: (text iv). See Plotinus: Enn. V, I /10/3. 12-16: V, ~ /'!9/
NEOPI.ATONISM
H. H-1';; V. 3 li91 H. l.Z-:\';; V. ;\ 1~919. 1-j<;; V. 9 1<;1 .-\. l0-.Z4: V, 9 1<;1 ;\,
.H-3<;: V. 915/'"!. 1-12: Porphyry: /JeRe~w- A11im. fr. 10. ;\7 21-24.
20<;. ArnmHn~o: to Numenius, the serond god or intellel't exists in two
modes: (i) as a unity- it remains direlted to itself and the prior principle, (ii)
as a dyad - it turns to the posterior which it simultaneously unifies and is
divided by. The transition from mode (ii) to mode (i) is tkscribcd in
Numcnius: fr. 12 (Eusebius: Praep. Etcmg. XI. 18. 6-10): 'When the god
looks and turns towards carh of us. it happens that our bodies arc quickened
and vivified by his attentive dispensations; but when the god returns to his
dtadcl, these things arc extinguished' (I}Abtovtoc; J.lCV ouv Kai bt&atpaJ.lJ.lEVOU
npoc; tlJ.lWV EKaatov toO S&ou auJ.113aiv&t ~Tjv t& Kai 13t<i>aK&a6at t6t& ta
a<i>J,lata Kllc5&uovta TOU 6&ou toic; aKpoi}OAIOJ.lOic;' J.l&Taatptq>ovtoc; eSt &lc; titv
autou 7t&plW7tltV TOU S&oii taiita J,li:V anoal3tvvua6at). It is mode (ii) which
corresponds precisely with the account of lntellert's production of Soul at
Macrobius: /11 Sonm. Scip. I. 14, 6-7 (text iv). Anording to Plotinus. Intcllcrt
remains dircned to itself and the prior principle and by so doing (mode i =
mode ii) generates the posterior. The inseparability of the two modes is
described in Plotinus: Emt. \'. l l l Ill. 1.-\-ll 'Sinrc it stands towards the One
in order to see it. it hcromes simultaneously lntellelt and Rdng. By thus
beroming like it, it repeats the latter's neative art' (E7t&i ouv l:atll npoc; auto,
iva iBn. OJ.lOU vouc; yiyv&tal Kai OV. outoc; ouv <i)v ofov &K&ivoc; Tel OJ.lOta 710l&i)
and ibid. V. -~I 49 I 7, 18-27 'By knowing itself, lntellert has its activity in
relation to itself and towards itself. If anything arises from it, this follows
from its own self intention. First it is intent on itself, and then it gives of itself
to another' (Eautov lipa vowv oiitw npoc; autc!> Kai ⁣ &autov titv &vtpy&tav
iaX&l. Kai yap &i tl &E, autOU, tel> ⁣ autOV tv tautc!>. &c5&t yap npwtov tautc!>,
&ita Kai ⁣ li).).o). In both these texts Plotinus goes on to contrast Intellect's
MACROHiliS
S6 (Proclus: In Tim. I. 4';7, 1-4); fr. 70 (Proclus: In Tim. II, 247, 21-2;\); fr.
75 (Prod us: In Tim. II, .~06, 8-11 ).
212. Macrohius: In Sonm. Scip. I. 14, 7 (text iv). Cf. ibid. I, H, 20; I. li, 9.
Sec Plotinus: Enn. I, 7 /51/ 3. 7-8; IV, 7 121 2. I-IV, 7 /2/ HI, 25; IV, I /2/ H~
43-46; IV, 7121 10. 1-2; Porphyry: Sent. 29. 18. IS-19, 4 contrast of Soul's
mode of existence with body's: Plotinus: Enn. IV, 7 /2/ 14, 6-H; Porphyry: De
Abstin. II, .P. 2; Sent. 17, R, 6-7 Soul as 'incorporeal' (aaw'-wm<;, c'iuA.o<;). Cf.
Plot in us: Enn. III, 6/26/18, 26-29.
213. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I, 6, 9 (text ii). See Plotinus: Etm. I, B /51/
4, 25-28; Ill, 6/26/1, 1-111,6/26/5.2 Soul free of'matter' (UATI); ibid. II, 9
/33/7/ 11-18; Ill, 6/26/1, 1-111,612615, 2; IV, 4/2H/2.:\, 1-48; IV, 6/-41/2.
1-25; Porphyry: DeAbstin. I, 30, 1-2; I. 31, I; Sent. I, 3. 4-5; 111 Tim. fr. 18
(Proclus: In Tim. I. 156. 26-31) Soul free of 'passhity' (nli911, nliaXElV,
ana9ti<;, anli9Eta, citpElttO<; etc.); Plotinus: Eml. I. 8/5114.25-28 Soul free
of 'evil' (KaK6v).
214.Macrohius:lnSomn.Scip.ll.l2,5.Cf.ibid.l.li,20;ll.13, 1-H.Sec
Plotinus: Enn. I. I /'i.~/ 2, 9-10; IV, 7 12/9, I 0-12: IV, 7 121 10, 24-2-:'; IV. I /2/
12, l-20; IV. 7121 14, 1-.:\; V, 1/10/1, 10-12; VI. I /22/10, 2H-:~0: Porphyry:
DeAbstitl. l, 30. 4-5; Setlt. 17. 8. 6-7.
215. Sec pp. 308-309.
216. Sec nn. 211-214.
217. Macrohius: In Somn. Scip. I. 6, 20 (text iii). See Plotinus: Etm. II, 9
/3.:\/3, 1-3: Ill, 5/SO/-L 9-13: III, 7/45/13.66-61 : Ill, 9113/3. 1-7: IV,.'\ 121/
I, I-IV, 3/27/ H. 60: IV, 3/27/ P, 12-28; IV, R /6/1,26-33: IV. 9/Rii, 6-H: V,
9/5/1-4,20-12: VI. 5/23/9, 12-13: Porphyry: DeAIJstiu. ll, :\H, 2: Sent ..-\i,
-i 3. 9-1 I.
21H. Macrohius: In Somn. Scip. l, 14,.., (text i\'). Sec Plotinus: l:'nn. Ill. -i
11516. 21-45: IV, I /21/14-22: IV. 21-i/2. 1-4: IV, H 1612. 1-53: IV. H /6/6.
MACROBiliS S41
6-16: IV, 8 161 ..,, 1-7: IV, 81617. 23-32: IV, R 161 R. 11-16: IV, 91RI 3. 10-16:
V. 111013. 17-20: V, 1110/7,42-49: V, 211111. 1R-2R; V. 612411, 16-IH; VI.
.., 13RI s. 21-25: Porphyry: De Regr. Anim. fr. 10. :n 21-21: In Tim. fr. 69
(Produs: In Tim. II, 214, 4-2IS. S).
2 19. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I. 6, 9 (text ii). Cf. ibid. II, IS. 11-12. See
Plotinus: Enn. I, I I 53 18, 9-23: II, 9 I 33 I 2, 4-1 0; Ill, 4 I IS 16, 30-45; Ill, 81
,'\015, 10-16; IV, 1121/8-21; IV, 214/2, 1-S5; IV, 312713. 7-29; IV, 31271
19. 1-.34; IV. 7 I 2 I 5, 35-38; IV, 7 I 2 I 13, 119; IV, 91812, I -IV, 91813,
29: IV, 91815. 1-28; V, I /1012, 35-38: V, 2111 II, 22-27; VI, 2143 16,
1-20; VI, 2/-i3122, 29-36: VI, 4122114, 1-5; VI, 713816, 1-21; Porphyry:
Sent. 31, 21, 9-15; 37, 42, 13-45, 8; In Tim. fr. 61 (Proclus: In Tim. II, 104,
30- lOS, 6). The Greek Neoplatonic doctrines presented here and In the two
previous notes arc considerably more complex than the Macrobian teachings
which parallel them. See H.). Blumenthal: 'Soul. World-Soul, and Individual
Soul in Plotinus', Le Neoplatonisme (Colloque International du Centre Na-
timzal de Ia Recherche Scientifique, Royaumont 9-13 juin 1969) (Paris,
1971 ), pp. 5S-66; 'Nous and Soul in Plotinus. Some Problems of Demarca-
tion', P/otino e i/ Neoplatmzismo in Oriente e in Occidente (Atti del Con-
tegno l'llernazirma/e, Roma 5-9 ottobre 19..,0) (Roma, 1974), pp. 203-219;
and W. Heileman-Elgersma: Soul-Sisters. A Comme1llary on Enneads IV. 31
1- I 1-H of P/otirws (Amsterdam, 1980), p. S7 ff.
220. See pp. 308-309 and 315- 31H.
22l.Scenn. 217-219.
222. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. 1, 14, 6-7 (text iv). For the Plotinian and
Porphyrian parallels seep. 543 ff.
2.n. Ibid. II. 3. II. Cf. ibid. I, J.f,.., (text iv); I, l:f. 15 (text v): Satum. VII.
'J. I"'. See Plotinus: Etm. Ill, R 1301 i. 10-IJ; IV ..-\ 127110 ..~S-i I; IV. 7/213.
:'IIEOPLATONISI\I
6-~5: IV. 7 /2/lJ. 10-13; VI. 2/1.~/6, 6-1 ~:VI. i /~8/4, .~;-~6; Porphyry: Sent.
1.1' 1~. 8-12.
22-t. Macrohius: In Somn. Scip. ll, 12. 10-1 I. Cf. ibid. I. 1-i. 19: II. 1.~. "7 -8;
II. 15, 12; II, 16,21-22. Sec Plotinus: Em1. 111,7/-15/13 ..~8; IV, 7/2/9, 1-9;
IV, i /2/11. 13: V, 1/10/1.6: Porphyry: DeAbstin. II. ~7. 1-2: Ad Gaur. 4,
~9.2~-25:-1.~1.2-i:Sen/. 19, 10,8-11:21.1~.6-12.
225. According to later testimony. Numenius ht:ld that soul's relation to
body as such involved degradation or corruption of the former. Thus,
Numenius: fr. 48 (1amblichus: De Anim. in Stobaeus: Flori/. l, 380) states that
among the three reasons for which souls descend to body - to purify lower
things, to amend their own characters. and w endure punishment- 'some of
the more recent thinkers make no distinction and, taking no account of the
purpose of these differences, conflate the incarnations of all the souls, by sug-
gesting that these are all evils. This is especially the case with the followers of
Cronius. Numenius, and Harpocration' (nvt<.; l>E tci.lv vErottprov oux outro<.;
litaKpivoucnv, OUK EXOVTE<.; lit OK07t0V ti;<.; Btacpop6TTJTO<.; Ei<.; taUTO auntoum
ta<.; EVOCilltaTWOEl<.; Tci.JV ()f..rov, KaKa<.; t'dvat naaa<; lillOXUPi~OVTat Kai
BtacpEp6vtro<.; o{ nEpi Kp6vt6v TE Kai Nou~tt1vtov Kai ' ApnoKpatirova ). The
doctrine stated at Macrobius: ft1 Somn. Scip. l, 14, 6-7 (text iv) that it is Soul's
downward motion and its degradation which is associated with its relation to
body seems to carry the same implkations. According to Plotinus, Soul's rela-
tion to body as such docs not involve degradation or corruption of the
former. Thus. Plotinus: Em1. II.~ /52/ 18. 8-1 ~: II. 9 /B/ 2. 10-18: 11.9 l!d/4.
1-22: II, lJ /~3/ -:-. 11-27: Ill . .j /15/ ~. 21-2"': Ill . ..j /15/-i. 2-7: IV,~ /P/9,
20-51 :trgue~ th:ll Soul :md human souls in their higher mmk generate the
posterior hy turning not towards them hut to the prior. It is true that texts
such as ibid. Ill. I /15/ I. 1:~: \', ~ 1-il)l"'. 25-:~~ contr:tst the relatively static
productivity of Intellect with the relati\'ely dynamic manner of Soul and ibid.
\', 2 Ill/ I. 18-28 even spe:tks of a 'desire for the lower' (npo9u~tia toG
XEipovo<.; ) in the Iauer case. Furthermore. there is an apparently mediating
MACROHWS 'H.'\
position bttwet"n tht'~e contrasting viewpoints expressed at ibid. Ill. 2 /.j.., I:.
211-28: 1\',: 121 1~. lllJ. Howc,er. Plotinus' dominant ,icw of the tausal
relation between Soul ;md it~ constquents i~ txprtssed in the first group of
passages.
226. Set: pp. "i;\8 and 5-.12.
2r.scenn.IHO-IH3.190-Il)l,ll)4,205.207.21H-21l).etc.
NEOPLATONISM
l.~9. The rdev:mt Porphyrian works are De Regressu Animae and the
Comme11farius in Parmenidem. Sec Hadot: op. cit., pp. 461--i""~.
2!0. In both the Cbaldaecm Omcles and :'1/umenius the first two principles
were intcllntivc. See Badot: op. cit.. pp. 9H. 1.!2-l .. o. 255-r 2. and
182-485.
2ll. \lacrohius: In Somn. SciJI. I. 6. H (text ii).
242. This is the interpretation of Stahl: op. cit .. p. 10 I and the present
author, p . .:;25.
2-t;\. Plotinus: Emz. \'l. H /39/ 16. 15-16 will only dcsaihe the first
hypostasis as 'like an intellect' (oiov vouc;).
NEOPI.ATONISM
25'i. lydus: De Mens. IV, <;.2, 110, 18-.22 'In his commentary on the
Oracles. Porphyry holds that the God worshipped by th<. Jews corresponds
w the "Twke Beyond" or the Demiurge of Wholes. For the Chaldaean the
Iauer is second to the "Once: Beyond" or the Good' (6 J.IEVTOI nopcptiptoc; tv
n!J UltOJ.IVtiJ.Ian nilv A.oyirov TOV oic; EltEKEtva TOUT&an TOV TWV OA(I)V
OTJJ.Itoupyov Tov napa 'Jouoairov TlJ.IWJ.IEvov Eivm a~10i, ov 6 Xal..cSaioc;
OEUTEpov Q1t0 TOU Qlt(l~ EltEKElVa, TOUTE<JTl TOU aya9oii, ewA.oyEi ). Plotinus:
Enn. II, 3 15.2/9, 6-": II. 3 /S2118. 8-16: V, 915/5, 19-.29 also identifies the
lkmiurge and Intellect.
.256. Proclus: In Tim. I. 431 . .20-2.~ (Porphyry: In Tim. fr. 53) .
.25 .... Proclus: Ill Tim. I. .~06. 31-.'\0.... , .. (Porphyry: Ill Tim. fr ... I) reports
that 'after Amclius Porphyry. bdic:ving that he was in agreement with
Plotinus. applies the term "Demiurge" to the superldc:stial soul. and the
term "l.iving Creature in ltsdf" to its intellect to which it reverts. as though
the paradigm of the Demiurge were to be located in this intellect' (J.IETQ o&
TOV 'AJ.IEAlOV 6 nopqn)ptOc; oi6J.IEVOc; T<!> nl..roTtV(J> auvQ.OElV, n'w J.IEV 11/UXJiV TJiV
imEpK60J.UOV llltOKai..Ei 011J.UOUpy6v, TOV o& voiiv aim;c;, npoc; ov E7tEOTpa7tTat,
TO (lUTO~<!>ov, we; dval TO ltapaOElYJ.I!l TOU OTJJ.IlOUpyoii KQTcl TOUTOV TOV voiiv ).
W'ith some hesitation Plotinus: Emz. Ill. 9 I 131 I. 1-37 concludes that the
Demiurge is a phast: of Soul.
2SH. Proclus: Ill Tim. I. :\.22. 1-7 (Porphyry: In Tim. fr ... 2).
MACROimiS
264./bid. I, 14, 14-16. The texts being interpreted hy Macrobius arc Virgil:
Aeneid. VI, '72-1 ff. and Homer: Iliad. H, 19.
26'i. Sec Porphyry: Hlst. Pbilos. fr. 16 (Cyril: Contra Julian. \'111 (PG 76.
9168)) as cited inn. 2S3. Plminus generally proceeds without distinguishing
the world soul and the hypostasis of Soul, although in a few passages he
develops a systematic distinction. For the Iauer see Emz. 111, S /SO/ 3. 22-111. S
/SO/ -1. L IV. 3 1271 2, S-l-"i9; IV. 3 1271 4.. 14-21; IV. 4 1281 32, H-11; IV. lJ 181
-t, IS-18. The importance of such texts is emphasized by Blumenthal: soul.
World-Soul. and Individual Soul in Plotinus'. pp. S"i-63. and Heileman-
Elgersma: op. cit.. pp. ;\2-88. Given more ext:lnt evidence the Porphyrian
position might turn out to he equally complex.
26(!. Mac:robius: In Somn. Scip. I. I"'. II.
267./bid. II. 10. 9.
MACROilll IS
268. Ibid. l, 14, 8. For intellect as the highest phase of Soul see Porphyry:
In Tim. fr. 70 (Produs: lt1 Tim. II, 247, IR-23) where the Egyptians are said
to have used the letters X and 0 as symbols of this principle, indicating by the
former 'its dyadic procession' (Ji 5uo&t5itc; np6o5oc; atrriic;) and by the latter
'its monadic life and its intellectual circular reversion' (Ji llOVO&t5Jic; ~roft Kai Ji
Kata KliKA.ov vo&pov &motpoqn\). Cf. ibid. fr. 75 (Produs: In Tim. 11. 306,
l-2S); fr. 76 (Proclus: In Tim. II, 309, 7-23). The same doctrine occurs in
Plot in us: Enn. IV. 8 /6 I R. 13-16. etc.
269. For the reconciliation of Macrobius' Neoplatonism with the Stoicism
of Cicero seep. S'iS ff.
2:o. At J\bnohius: In Smnn. Scif1. I. I'"'. 12-1 'i the celestial sphere is :tgain
tlescrihed as possessing an intellect.
:-.!EO I' LA TO:'~! ISM
2 7 1. Ibid. I. 11. 16-IH. For the celestial sphere and planets as ensouh:d bc-
in~s sec Porphyry: De Ahsti11. II. 37. 3 where he refers to the fixed stars and
planet~ as ,isibh: gods compostd of hody ;md soul' (&K TE ljiUXfi~ Kai
CJWjlaTO~ OVTE~ 6patoi 8Eoi). Other Porphyrian texts expound more complex
theories which arc consistent with Macrobius' view: sec /11 Tim. fr. <;2
(Produs: In Tim. I. 422. l.f-423. 7) where each heavenly body possesses a
particular 'intellect' (vou~) having a definite relation - the simultaneous
sameness and otherness obtaining between intelligible whole and parts- to
uninrsal lntcllc<:t; and ihitl. fr. 7 9 (Produs: In Tim. Ill. 6-l. H6c;, 7) where
the different courses of the heavenly bodies result from the wars in which
their 'intclh:ns' (VOE<;)- in accordance with their mode of partidp:uion in
being, life, :md intellect - revert upon the prior principles. Porphyry ;tgrecs
with Macrobius in speaking of intellects rather than souls since it is the in-
tellectual phase of Soul which is their source. For the Plotinian equivalent to
this doctrine sec Enn. II. 9 I 3 3/ 16. 9-1 I. etc.
MACRO BillS
Dionysus =
sun ( as vouc; 1 )
1
Jupiter Minerva
1
man
279. See Plotinus: Emz. V, 3/49/12. 39-'i2; V, 'i /32 17, 16-3'i: V, 5/32/
H. '7-13; V, 6/24/4, 14-20; VI, 7/38/16, 22-35; etc.
280. See Orac. Cbald. fr. 3 (Psellus: Comm. (PG 122, ll44A)); fr. 6
(Simplicius: In De Cael. II. I, ~~7'i. 19-21); fr. 10 (Psellus: Cnmm. (PG 122,
114'iA)); fr. _H (Produs: In Tim. I, 420, 13-16); l'tc.
281. Porphyry: DeAbstin. Ill. II, 3.
282. Porphyry: De Simul. fr. 2, z 1-3. Porphyry gols on 10 say that this
light 'is ln\'isible to sensation en<:umhercd hr mortal life' (ciqmvou~ TE
TUYXclVOVTO<; aio9l'JOEI ltEpi 9VTJTOV j3iov clOXOA(!) ). hut hy this he prohahly
means simply that it is invisihk when not diffused through :1ir. In fact. thl'
MACROBiliS
Pscllus: Expos. (PG 122. ll52A) 'And they postulate :m archk sun dcri\'cd
from the solar source and an arch angelic sun. and a sour<:c of sensation' (c:paai
lit Kai CtPXIKOV i;A.tov Ct1t0 tiic; ~AIUKiic; 1t11Yiic; Kai cipxayyEAIKOV, Kai 1tl1YiJV
aia9itaEroc; ) where their doctrine is summarized. Using :1 certain latitude of
interpretation. Porphyry might also have found inspiration In the writings of
his teacher. Sec Plotinus: Enn. IV. 3 f2if II. H-21 where 'thc highcr sun (6
EKEi fiA.toc;) is linked to 'the sun of this realm' (o1hoc; 6 fiA.toc; ) hy Soul. For
similar elahoratiuns in Martian us Capella see pp. 618-620 and n. 72.
291. Sec Porphyry: In Parm. Ill, 13-30.
292. There is. however. no extant Porphyrian text which testifies to this
reading of the Cbaldaean Ol'tlcles.
293. Macrubius: Saturn. I. 17. 1-1,23. 22.
MACROIUUS <;61
302. Ibid. I. 19. ""-9. This interpretation is contained in the same passage
which described Mer<:ury"s visual representation.
303. IIJ/d. I. 22, 2-6. Of course, this interpretation of Pan does not exclude
a metaphysical role also.
304. For the nature of this distinction between the two levels see pp.
S'iR-560. The ancient systems of philosophical monotheism differ from one
another in the following ways: (i) Varro: Antiqultates Rerum Divinarum. All
divinities reduced to one substance, that substance being material: the 'spirit'
(1tVEUJ.Ia). See pp. 822-825. (ii) Macrobius ( = various Porphyrian works). All
divinities reduced to one substance, that substance being a) intelligible: the
'solar intellect' <ftA.taKoc; vouc;) and b) sensible: the sun. (iii) Porphyry: De
Cultu Simulacrorum. All divinities reduced to one substance, that substance
being ambivalently immaterial and material: the 'generative power' ('YOVIJ.IOc;
&UvaJ.Itc;). See pp. '55H-560. It is the fact that there are striking similarities bet-
ween these systems which enables details from one to be transposed into
another, as in the example mentioned inn. 295.
50'5. It may he useful to present a diagrammatical t;tlmlation of the inter-
1\lACROIJil :s
Minerva
+--~---------J1---------~~
Mercury
Dionysus
a) the sun (as voiic;)
Pan 1
Apollo
....,.. Jupiter
~ 1';. Plot in us: Enn. II. ~ /';2 I 9. 6-9 'In the Timaeus the creating god
hc:swws the: origin of Soul, the gods moving in the: heaven the: dread and
nen.ssary affections - anger. desire. pleasure and pain - and that other
phase of soul in which !hose: affections arise' (fv t Ttllaiq> eeoc; ll&V 6
non'taac; ttiv apxtiv tftc; wuxftc; BiBromv, oi l)t q>Ep6J.1EVOI 9Eoi tel BEIVcl Kai
avayKaia 1tQ9Tl, 9UJ.lOUc; Kai &7tt9UJ.llQc; Kai i!oovac; Kai AU1tac; au, Kai \j/UXftc;
c'iUo dooc;, aq>'ou tci na9ftllata tauti ). Cf. ibid. II, 3 /52/10, 1-3; II, 3/52/
II, 1-13 .
.~ 16. Ibid. II,~ 1521 ~. 21-2';; II, 3 /;2/ -4, 1-~; IV, 4 /28/-42. 1-29. AI iiJid.
Ill. '; /SO/ 6. 7-13 he makes the hask distinction hetwc:en gods and demons
thl ahsence or presence of affections' (na9nJ. The heavenly hodic:s arc for
Plminus the visihle gods.
31 '7. Ibid. 111, 4 /I';/ 6. 2 1-2'; 'We must realize that there is nO! only an in-
telligihle world in our souls hut also a distrihution of phases like that in the
world soul. The Iauer is distrihuted 10 the sphere of fixed stars and the
planets according to its diffc:rem facuhks' (XPli yap oiea9m Kai K60J.lOV dva1
f.v t(l wuxu till<i>V llli J.lOVOV vont6v, ana Kai wuxiic; ti;c; KOOJ.lOU OJ.lOEIBii
Bt6.9Emv VEVEJ.lllllEVllc; OUV KCtKEiVllc; Eic; t tiJv a1tA.avi; Kai tcic; 1tAQV(I)J.lEVac;
Kara Buv<illEtc; &taq>opouc;)
~IH. lbicl. \'1,; f.J.,H/ 6. 1-2. At ibid. Ill. f /!';/ f, '"'-lf Plotinus states that
the faculties of sensation and growth are 'prc:sem and not presem (n<ipeattv
... ou 7tapov) the world soul. In other words they arc presem in inchoate
form.
MACROBHJS
329. See pp. 564-565. It is the presence of this last feature which suggests
that Macrobius follows Porphyry rather than Plotinus.
330. Macrobius: In Sumn. Scip. II, 2, I. Cf. Ibid. I, 6, 4. Macrobius' discus-
sion of the numbers and ratios in the world soul should be compared with
corresponding passages in Calcidius' Commentarius in Timaeum. See pp.
475-478. The similarities between Macrobius and Calcidius are perhaps main-
ly to be explained on the basis of both authors' dependence upon Porphyry.
Sec nn. 334 and _'\37.
MACROB!liS
noting the view of the Platonists that (i) the distance from the
earth to the sun is twice that of the earth to the moon, (ii) the
distance from the earth to Venus is twice that of the earth to the
sun, (iii) the distance from the earth to Mercury is four times
that of the earth to Venus, (iv) the distance from the earth to
Mars is nine times that of the earth to Mercury, (v) the distance
from the earth to Jupiter is eight times that of the earth to Mars,
(vi) the distance from the earth to Saturn is twenty-seven times
that of the earth to Jupiter;336 and concludes by citing Por-
phyry's opinion that 'these intervals in the world's body which
are filled with sesquitertians, sesquialters, superoctaves,
semitones, and a lemma imitate the fabric of its soul' (ad im-
aginem contextionis animae haec esse in corpore mundi inter-
val/a, quae epitritis, bemioliis, epogdois, bemitoniisque com-
plentur et limmate).337 These interpretations of the solidity of
the numbers and the ratios between them therefore place the
discussion squarely in the context of late ancient Platonism.
340. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. l, II, 10-12 alii tero- nam Ires esse inter
eos senterrliarum ditersitates ante slgntwimus - in duas quidem el ips!
partes slcut primi faciunt, sec/ mm istlem terminis dil'idtml mundum. bi
enim ccwlum quod anA.avi)c:; spluwru I'Ocitatur partem unam. septem tero
spbaeras quae tagae toccmtur et quod inter illas ac terram est terramque
ipsam altertmz partem esse zoluertmt. secundum bos ergo. quorum sectae
amicior est ratio. animae beatae ab omni nn'uscumque amtagione ,or-
ports libertle cae/um posside1/l, qtme tero appetentimn corporis et huius
quam in ferris tilmn 1'0Ctl111l1S ab ilia specula ti/lissima et perpetua /uce
MACR081l IS 'i7:\
(ii) 'The sequence of the descent itself. by which the soul slips
down from heaven to the infernal regions of this life, can be
described as follows. The Milky Way encircles the zodiac, its
own circle obliquely crossing the circle of the latter, so that it
intersects it where the two tropical signs of Capricorn and
Cancer are located. The physicists called these points the por-
tals of the sun because the sun's progress is checked at the
solstices on either side where it retraces its course to that part of
the belt whose limits it never crosses. The souls are believed to
pass through these portals when going from heaven to earth and
again from earth to heaven. For this reason, one is called the
portal of men and the other the portal of gods: that of men be-
ing Cancer, since through it takes place the descent to the infer-
nal regions; that of gods being Capricorn, since through it souls
return to the abode of their rightful immortality and to the com-
munity of the gods. This is also what Homer in his divine
wisdom signifies by his description of the cave at Ithaca.
Pythagoras also holds that the empire of Pluto begins with the
Milky Way and extends downwards, because the souls which
fall away from it seem already to have withdrawn from the
higher realm. He says that milk is offered as the first nourish-
ment to newborn children because their first motion when slip-
ping into earthly bodies begins from the Milky Way. This is why
Scipio was told, when the Milky Way was shown to him that
blessed souls "proceed hence and return hither" '.541
(iii) 'As long as the souls which are on the downward path re-
main in Cancer, since in that position they have not yet left the
Milky Way, they are still in the company of the gods. But when
they arrive at Leo in their descent, they enter upon the first
stages of their future condition. Since the beginnings of birth
and certain primary elements of human nature are found in Leo,
and Aquarius is in opposition to Leo hy setting just as it is rising.
the festival of the dead is celehrarcd when the sun is in Aquarius:
that is the sign which contains what is contrary or hostile to
human life. From this point where the zodiac and the Milky
Way intersect, then, the descending soul is protracted from the
sphere which alone is the divine form into a cone by emanation;
and just as a line is derived from a point and passes from the in-
divisible into length, so the soul turns into a dyad which is the
first protraction from its point which is a monad. This is the
substance which Plato in the Timaeus called both indivisible
and divisible when he was speaking about the construction of
the world soul. For souls whether of the world or of individual
men will be found now unacquainted with division if they are
thinking of the divine nature's simplicity, but now also suscepti-
-~i2. /bit/. I. 12. '1-6 ergo descensume cum eulhuc in Cancro stmt,
cjtumictm illic positae necdum lacteum reliquertmt, adlmc in 11Wm!ro sunt
deorum. cum tero ad Leonem labendo pert'etterint, illic condicirmis
jilfurae mtspicantur exordium. et quia in Leone sunt rudimenftl nascendi
et quaedam bumanae n11turae tirocinia, Aquarius autem adtersus Leoni
est et il/o oriente mo.\' occitlit, ideo cum sol Aquarium tenet. McmiiJus
futrentatur, utf)()/e in signo quod buman11e tilae contrarium te/ cultersum
j(ratur. illinc ergo id est a confinio quo se zrJdit~cus lacteusque nmtingunt,
anima descent/ens atereti. quae solttforma ditina est, in comon defluendo
prruludtur. sicut a fJtmcto nasdtur linea et in lrmgum ex inditiduo pro-
cedi!: i!Jique a puncto suo, qtwtl est mrmas, t'ellit i11 t~}'ttdem. quae est
prima protractio. et baec est essentia quam illtlil'iduam eandemque
tlitiduam Plttlo in Timaeo cum de mundmwe animae fttbriat loqueretur
e.\pressil. tmimtle enim, sicut mwuli. i/11 et bominis uniu.~. modo tlitisirmis
reperientur ignartte. si tlitinae naturm simplicilas 'O!(iletur, modo
capaces. cum ilia per mtmdi. baec per lmminis memb,-a di{{tmdiltt1'.
S76 :'IIEOPLATONISM
truth is not evident to all men on earth all men have opinions,
since the failure of memory is the beginning of opinion. Those
who have drunk less of forgetfulness have more grasp of the
truth because they easily recall what they have previously
known above. This is why the equivalent of the Latin word for
reading among the Greeks is one which means knowledge
regained, since when we are learning the truth we recognize
those things which we naturally knew before the influx of mat-
ter intoxicated our souls as they approached their bodies.
Moreover, this is the matter which is imprinted with Forms and
produced the whole body of the world which we perceive
everywhere. Its highest and purest part by which divine things
are sustained or generated is called nectar and believed to be the
drink of the gods, whereas the lower and more turbid part is
believed to be the drink of souls and was called the river Lethe
by the ancients. The Orphics interpret Bacchus himself as signi-
fying the vouc; UAlK6c; since he is generated from that indivisible
principle but is himself divided into separate parts. In their
religious rituals this god is depicted as being torn apart by the
angry Titans, buried in separate places, but rising again single
and whole, since that vouc; which we have stated to be Intellect,
by offering its indivisible substance to be divided and by return-
ing again from its dividedness to the indivisible, both discharges
its worldly function and does not forsake its hidden nature' ..~15
343. Ibid. I, 12, 7-12 anima ergo cum tmbitur ad corpus, in bac prima
sui protlucti(me slltestrem tumu/tum id est ili..nv it~{luentem siiJi incipit ex-
periri. et boc est quod Plato notmit in Phaed(me animam in corpus trabi
nota ebrietate trepidantem. tolens twttl111 potum materia/is allmionis in-
tel/egi, quo tlelibuta et gral'tlla deducitur. arcani lmius indicium est et
Crater Uberi patris il/e sidereus in regione quae inter Cancrum est et
Leonem /ocatus, ebrietatem illic primum tlescensuris animis etenire silta
inj7ue1lfe sign~ficans, unde et comes ebrietatis ob/il'io 11/ic animis incipit
lam /atenter obrepere. tu1m sf an/mae memoriam rerum dil'inarum,
qtwrum in caelo erant consdae, ad corpora usque deferrettl. nulla irtter
lmmines foret de ditinitate dissensio: sed oblitionem quidem omnes
MACROBIUS
(v) 'The soul which has sunk down under this first weight
from the zodiac and the Milky Way as far as the spheres lying
beneath, not only acquires the aforementioned envelope of a
luminous body as it passes through each sphere but produces
the individual motions which it will later exercise. In the sphere
of Saturn the soul obtains reasoning and understanding which
they call A.oytcHtK6v and 9eroprrnK6v; in Jupiter's sphere the
power to act called npaKttKOV; in the sphere of Mars the
boldness of spirit named 9UJ.1tK6v; in the sun's sphere the
substance of sensation and imagination which they call
aia9TJnK6v and cpavtaattKOV; the motion of desire called
E7tt9UJ.1TJ'ttKOV in the sphere of Venus; the ability to express and
interpret thoughts called EPJ.1TJVEUttK6v in Mercury's sphere; and
it exercises the q>UttK6v or the function of producing and in-
creasing bodies on entering the sphere of the moon. This last
faculty is in us and all earthly things the first just as it is the fur-
thest removed from the divine, since our body is the first
substance of the animal just as it is the last remnant of the
:\"iS. Ibid. I. 12. J'7 -1 H nee te mmeat quod de anima. quam esse inmlm-
talem dicimus. mortem totiens nomitutmus. et enim sua morte anima non
extinguitur sed ad tempus nbruitur. nee tempora/i demersione beneficium
pet1Jetuit,llis eximltur, cum rur.ms e corpore. ubi meruerit nmtagitme
l'itiorum pen it us eli mala purgari, ad perennis titm! lucem restituta in in-
tegrum retertatur. plene ut arbitror de ti/(1 et mnrte animae definitio li-
quet, quam de (U~)'Iis pbilosophiae dmtritw et sapient/a Cicemnis e/icuil.
.'H6. For these categories seep. 530.
3-17. Ibid. l, I I. I I (text i). See Numenius: fr. 4 7 (Philoponus: In de Anlm.
I pr. 9. 35-39); Plotinus: Enn. l. 7 I 54 I:\. 7-8: I. 8 /51 114. 32-33: IV. 1 I 21 I
:\-4: VI. 4 I 22 I 14. 17-21; Porphyry: De Abstin. I, .H. 1-4; De Regr. Anim. fr.
II I 3. 41 13-17; fr. II /5, 41 28-32.
580 NEOPLATONISM
348. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I, 12, 6 (text iii). See Numenius: fr. 39
(Proclus: In Tim. II, 153, 17-25); Plotinus: Enn. I. I /53/8, 9-18; IV, I /21/
8-22; IV, 2 /4/ 2, 1-55; IV, 3 /27/ 19. 27-.H; IV, 9 /8/ 2, 24-28; VI, 2 /43/ 5,
I-VI, 2/H/6, 20; VI, 2/43/11, 9-12; VI, 9/9/1. 17-i:'; Porphyry: DeAbstin.
I. 30, 6-7. All the Numenian and Plotinian passages agree in (i) not
distinguishing universal and particular souls regarding the question of unity,
(ii) considering simplicity and multiplicity as correlative aspects of both
universal and particular souls. See nn. 211 and 3fl3.
349. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I, 12, 6 (text iii). See Plotinus: Enn. I, 6/1 I
6, 13-16 'wholly of the divine' (<'>All tou 9&iou); II, 9 I 33 I 17, 21 'souls being
divine' (IVUXai 9&i:a! ouam); IV, 2 I 4 I I, 4-7 'of the divine kind' (tile; 9&iac;
~toipac;); IV, 7 /38/10, 1-2 'akin to the more divine nature' (tij 9&\0tEp~ q>ua&l
auyy&Vl\c;), etc. The divinity of human souls is also implied in Numenius: fr.
31 (Produs: De Antr. Nymph. 23, 23, 18-23); fr. 35 (Produs: In Remp. II,
129. 13-21) where the portal of Capricorn is described as their route to the
gods. On the relationship between Numenius and Porphyry here see pp.
516-518.
350. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I, 4, I. This blessedness of human souls is
suggested at Plotinus: Enn. I, 4 I 46 I 3. 23-1, 4 146 14, 8; I, 5 I 36 /7, 20-24;
VI, 9 19 I II, 1-51. See Numenius: fr. 35 (Proclus: In Remp. II, 131. 9-14)
'happy souls' (ai &uoai~tov&c;); Porphyry: De Regr. Anim. fr. 1115, 41" 31-32
'they are held in blessedness' (beatae ... teneantur); ibid. fr. II /5, 41 34-35
'blessedness' ife/lcitas).
351. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. l, IL 3-5. See Numenius: fr. 42
(lamblichus: De Anim. in Stobaeus: Flori/. I, 458); Plotinus: Eml. I. I /53/ 8,
1-6; Ill, 8130/6, 21-26; IV. 3/27/18. 1-24; IV, 4 /28/ I. 1-16; IV, 6/41/3.
10-16; V, 3 /49/3. 1-45; V, 3 /19/ 9. l-2fl; VI, 7/3815. 2'-30; Porphyry: De
Abslin. I, 28, 3; I, 30, 6; I, 48, I; Ad Gaur. 12, 50, 10-15; De Reg,. Anim. fr.
10, 37" 11-21; Sent. 40, 50, 16-21; In Tim. fr. 18 (Proclus: b1 Tim. l, 156,
26-31 ). The Plotinian passages actually postulate a more complex doctrine in
which intellect is (i) the human soul's highest phase, and (ii) transnnds that
soul's highest phase. See nn. 204, 218 and 308.
352. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I. II. II (text i). Cf. ibid. I. 14. 4 and I. 21,
34. Sec Numenius: fr. 32 (Porphyry: De Anlr. Nympb. 28, 28. 13); fr. 35
(Prod us: In Remp. II. 129, 2 1-26 ); Plotinus: Enn. IV, 3 1271 12, -l-5; IV. 3 /271
MACROBilTS ';HI
12. 26-.~0; IV,~ /2'7/1';. 1--4: IV.~ /27/17, 1-2: IV.~ /2"1/18. 1~-1';: IV. -fi2RI
';, I 1-1 ~;Porphyry: De Antr. 1\)mpb. 29. 28. 16-21.
~5~- Sec pp. ~ 13-318 and ~85-387.
354. See nn. 347-352.
355.Seepp. 315-318.
~56. On the importance of Numenius as a source of Macrobius' doctrine of
the human soul see pp. 516-5 IR.
357. Macrobius: In Smnn. Scip. I. 21. .~4. Cf. ibid. I. 9, I; I. 9 ..-\. Macrobius
belic\'es that the human soul can undergo a serit:s of incarnations and can
transmigrate into animals. See ibid. I. 9. 5-6. This follows the traditional
Platonic doctrine and runs counter to Porphyry who denied transmigration
into animals. See pp. 490-492. The question is discussed by Flamant: op. cit.,
pp. 620-622 and 624 .
.~58. Macrobius: In Sonm. Scip. I. 4, I. Cf. ibid. I. 9. 3 .
.H9. IIJid. I, 9, ~-
~60. Sec n. ~53.
iH2 NE<lPLATONISM
.:\61. The Neoplatonic doctrine of descent and ascent of the human soul
takes \'arious forms. It represents (i a) the entering into the body at birth and
(i b) the departure from the body at death; and (ii a) the concern for the body
during life and (ii b) the detachment from the body during life. For (i a) see
Plotinus: Emz. lll, 2 147 I 15, 21-29; III, 2 147 I I5, 47-62; IV, .3 127 112,
1-12; IV, 816 I 5. 16-33; Porphyry: Sent. 8, 3. 6-8, 4, 2; for(i b) see Plotinus:
Enn. Ill, 2 147 I 15, 21-29; III, 2 147 I 15, 47 -62; IV, 3 I 27 I 12, 1-12; IV, 8 I 6
I c;, 16-33; Porphyry: Sent. 8, 3. 6-8. 4, 2; 9, 4. 3-6; for(ii a) see Plotinus: Enn.
I. 8 I 5 I I l.:\, 1-1. 8 I 5 I I 14, 54; III. 2 I 47 I 8, 9-16; IV, 8 I 6 I 5. 16-33; Por-
phyry: Sent. 7, 3. 4-5; 8. 3. 6-8. 4. 2; 9. 4, 3-6; for (ii b) see Plotinus: Enn. I, 8
I'; I I 1.:\, 1-I, 8 I'; I I 14, 54; III, 2 I 4718, 9-16; IV, 816 I 5. 16-33; Porphyry:
Sent. 7. 3. 4-5; 8, 3. 6-8, 4, 2. Plotinus contends that the soul has a further
phase accompanying (i a) and (ii a) in which it simultaneously remains on the
higher level. See Plotinus: Enn. I, 4 146 I 9. 10-1, 4 I 46 I 10, 6; II, 9 I 33 12,
4-10; III, 4 I 15 I 3. 21-27; IV, 3 I 27112. 1-12; IV, 3 I 27 I 30, 7-16; IV, 816 I
4. 25-35; IV, 8 I 6 I 8. 1-23 (where the author stresses the novelty of his view);
V, I I 10 I 12. 1- 10; VI. 4 I 22 I 14, 17-22. The Plotinian doctrine is discussed
by J. M. Rist: 'Integration and the Undescended Soul in Plotinus', American
jounzal of Philology 88 ( 1967), pp. 410-422 and C. Steel: The Changing Self
A Study on tbe Soul in Later Neoplatmzism: lamblicbus, Dmnascius, and
Prise/anus (Brussel, 1978), pp. 34-38. Whether Porphyry also believed in the
further phase accompanying (i a) and (ii a) is not absolutely clear from the
available testimony. Here, we must perhaps contrast De Abstitl. I, 30, 6; Sent.
32. 30. 1-5 with De Abstin. I, 39. 1-1, 40, 2. For differing interpretations of
Porphyry's position see Smith: op. cit., pp. 25-26, 41 and C. Steel: 'Por-
phyrius' Reactie tegen het Amoralisme van de Gnostici', Tljdscbrift mor
Fllosofie 37 (1975). pp. 211-22i. At all events. Macrobius' reference to the
fact that the soul seems never to have left the heaven which it possessed in a
relation and in its thoughts' indicates first. that he is aware of the existence of
(i a) and (i b) and (ii a) and (ii b) since he refers to the soul's transcendence
cogitation/bus; and secondly, that he belie\'es in the existence of the further
phase accompanying (i a) and (ii a) since he states that the soul nee: deseruisse
umquam that transcendence.
MACROBJliS
the human soul must be prefaced with some remarks about his
handling of the transition from transcendence to immanence.
This latter aspect of the soul, which enters into the picture
because of its relation to the temporal process. is described as
follows: the souls in their transcendent state experience a 'lqog-
i.os for rhe hooy' (deside1ium corporis, appetentia corporis).~6l.
~~<;.ause~!hef1! to_ 'flow dO'Y.!lJ.rorn _tht;.I:t~aven' (manare de
caelo),363 this descent taking place at the tropical sign of
Cancer: the so-called 'portal of men' (porta hominum)YH or
more precisely at the point where Cancer is replaced by Leo.
The descent of the soul is, of course, complemented by its as-
cent: h~re_tlu:.soul in its immanent state 'is freed from the sweet
ent~ap~oLthe..de.sir~-~a-q~--~ll9.~h~.f..,ga..~~ic)ris; (citpiditatum
dulces insidias reliquasque omnes exuitwpassiones)365 so that
.'\62. M;u.:rohius: In Sonm. Sclp. I. 9. 10. Cf. Ibid. I. II. II (text i); I, 12. 16
(text v). See Plotinus: Enn. IV, .~ /17/ 1.3. 17-20 'They go forth neither willing
nor tompelled. hut with a naturallc:ap, as in the desire for sexual intercourse'
(iacn 0& olin: EKOUOat OUt& 7ti:J.1<j)9eiaat ... aAJ..'w<; tO 7t11MV Katil (jliJO!V, fjrrpo~
y<i)..lrov q>ucnKac; rrpo9u)..liac; ): Porphyry: Sent. 29. 19. 9-10 'becoming subject
to the allure of corporeal form' (rra9atVOJ..lEV11 rrpo<; to d.So<;). Sec also Por-
phyry: De Antr. Nymph. 1S. 16, 17-19, 20, 20 where honey is interpreted as
symbolizing the plc:asure associated with the descent.
36.3. Macrohius: In Somn. Scip. I. 9. I. See ~umenius: fr. 30 (Porphyry: De
:lntr. Nymph. 10. 12, Il-lS); fr . .31 (Porphyry: DeAntr. ,'1/ympb. 28, 28. 1-.~):
fr ..~S (Proclus: In Remp. ll. 129. 26-1.30, 1): fr. _3"7 (Proclus: In Tim. I...,..,_
15-1 <; ); fr. 18 (lamhlichus: De Anim. in Stohaeus: Flori/. I. 380) 'descent into
becoming' (ei~ ytvecnv Kanvat, K<i9o.So~). Sec Porphyry: De Antr. I 'f. I 6.
2-3:19.18. 2.326:AdGaur. 16. S6, 28-S7. 15: DeSimul. fr. S . .,.I 1-8"2: De
Regr. Anlm. fr. I I. w 4-"7; fr. 11/4, 41 12-23: 111 Tim. fr. 16 (Proclus: 111
Tim. I. 147, 6-24): fr. 18 (Proclus: 111 Tim. I. IS6, 26-.31): fr. 22 (Produs: In
Tim. I. 16<;, 16-23) .
.~64. Macrohius: In Scmm. Scip. I. 12. l (tc:xt iii; I. 11. <;(text iii): I. 12. 8
(lc:xt iv). Sec Numenius: fr. 3 I (Porphyry: De A11tr. Nymph. 21. 22. 2 24. 24.
:\); fr. 52 (Porphyry: De Anlr. Nymph. 2H. 26. 26-18, 28. 6): fr. 5S (Produs:
In R'mfJ. II. 128. 26-130. 14 ). This doctrine has no c:xact parallel in Plotinu!>.
3M. Macrobius: In Somn ..kip. I. 13. 6. Cf. ibid. I. 8, 8 and I. 9, 5. Sec:
Plotinus: Emz. I. 2 I 19 I r;, 5-19 'The soul maybe collects itself in a kind of
i84 NEOPI.ATONISM
place away from body, becoming quite impassive to it ... It will certainly
have no desire of the base: none of food and drink for the relief of the body,
none of sex' (ano f.l~V 51) arof.latoc; raroc; f.l~v Kai toic; olov t6nmc; auvciyouaav
taun'Jv, ncivtroc; f.lftV ana6roc; npoc; auto fxouaav ... S7tl6Uf.l{av ot; 5n f.ltV
l.lTJli&voc; lj)QUAOU, liijA.ov' aitrov 5~ Kai 7tOtcl>v npoc; clV&OIV OUK autit f~&l' oulit
tcl>v alj)pOlilairov lit ); Porphyry: Sent. 32, 32, 11-J4 'He is involved in the
pleasures or pains of the senses with eagerness and a sympathetic inclination.
From this condition he must especially be purified' (npoanaaxrov lit taic; tcl>v
aia6TJI.llitrov l'Jliovaic; ii AU7talc; aov 7tp09Uf.li~;t Kai &7tlV&UO&l OUJ.17ta9&i. cllj)'ftc; liit
f.lciAlOta lim9ta&roc; autov npoat\K&l Ka9aip&lV ). See also Porphyry: De
Abstin. I, 30, 1; I. 30, 6: II, 45, 4; De Regr. Anim. fr. 11/2, 41 1-3.
366. Macrobius: In Scmm. Scip. I, 9, 3. See Numenius: fr. 31 (Porphyry: De
Antr. N_ympb. 22, 22,14- 23,23); fr. 35 (Proclus: In Hemp. II, 129. -l-8); fr. 37
(Proclus: In Tim. I, 77, 6-9); fr. 60 (Porphyry: De Antr. Nymph. 6, 8, 13-15)
'ascent 10 the gods' (⁣ 6&ooc; clVlEVal, civolioc;, avay&a9m). See Porphyry: De
Regr. Anim. fr. 1111, 40 14-16: fr. I 1/4 . .J I 2225: fr. I 1/5, 41 28-32;
Sent. 29. 19.14- 20,6; In Tim. fr. 10 (Produs: In Tim. I, i7, 6-9): fr. 16
(Proclus: In Tim. 1, 147. 6-24 ).
."167. Macrohius: In Somn. Scip. I. 12, 2 (text ii). Sec Numenius: fr. 31 (Por-
phyry: De Antr. N_ymph. 21. 22,2 - 24. 24.3): fr. 32 (Porphyry: De Antr.
Nympb. 28, 26.26- 28,6); fr. 35 (Prod us: In Remp. II, 128.26 1.'\0,14 ). This
doctrine has no exact parallel in Plot in us.
368. See pp. 3 13-318 and 385-387 .
.~69. See nn. 362-.~67.
370. On the importance of Numenius and Porphyry among Macrobius'
sources (and the relationship between Numenius and Porphyry) see pp.
516-522.
MACROBJllS
;PI. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. l, II, II (text i); I, 12, 13 (text v). Sec
Plotinus: Enn. IV. 3/27/ 1';, 4-7 'wei~ht' (j}apuvat~); Porphyry: Sent. 29, IH.
14 'the heavy spirit' (to j}apu nv&ulla ); 29. 19. 16 'grows heavy' (j}ap&ia6at).
372. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. l, 12,7 (text iv). See Numenius: fr. 33 (Por-
phyry: De Anlr. Nympb . .H. 32. 13-21 ); Plotinus: t:mz. I, H /';II 4, 14-22; I, 8
/51114, 17-50; Porphyry: DeAbslin. I. 30. 4; II. 43. 3; Ill. 27. ';;Sent. 37. 4S.
1-9: In Tim. fr. 13 (Prm:lus: In Tim. I. IIi. 5-8). For the accumulation of mat-
ter by the disembodied soul explicitly see Porphyry: De Abstin. 11. 38. 2-4.
3..., 3. Macrohius: In Srmm. Scip. I. I I. 12 (text i). Cf. /IJ/d. l, 12. 13 (text v).
See Plotinus: Emz. Ill. 6 /26/ ;, 22-29 'spirit' (1tV&UilU); Porphyry: Sent. 29,
18. 6-..., 'The spirit which it has collected from the spheres accompanies it' (to
nv&ulla auvo1-1apt&i, o EK t<i>V aq>atp<i>v auv&M~aro); In Tim. fr. 80 (Prudus:
In Tim. Ill. 2.-\4. 18-26) 'The vehicle and the irrational soul ... they are com-
pounds derived from the he:tvenly spheres which the soul has collected in its
descent' (tOUt& OXiJilato~ Kai tfi~ aA.6you 11/Ulfi~ ... q>upciJ.tata 5 &iva! taUta
EK t<i>v oupaviwv aq>atp<i>v Kai Kanouaav aura auA.My&lV ri)v 11/UXiJV ). For a
fuller documentation of this question seep. 592 ff .
.F ... Macrohius: In Sonm. Scip. I. 12. 8 (text iv). Descending souls are
descrihed as growin~-t wet hy Numenius: fr. 30 (Porphyry: De Antr. Nympb.
SH6 NEOPI.ATONISM
10. 12. 12-2';); Porphyry: DeA1ltr. Nymph. II, 14, 1-12, 14. 24; Sem. 29, IH,
lf-19. 4; In Tim. fr. 13 (Proclus: In Tim. I, I 16, 27-1 Jl. I H).
:\7';. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I, 12, '; (text iii). See Numenius: fr. 39
(Proclus: In Tim. II. I S3. 17-25) 'Some say that the soul is a number. produc-
ing it from the monad as the undivided substance and the indefinite dyad as
the divided ... Aristander's and Numenius' followers and many other com-
mentators subscribe to this view' (oi IJEV apt91J(>V autilV Ein6vn:~ EK IJOV<i6o~
7tOlOUOlV, W~ QIJEpiatOU, Kai til~ ciopiatOU 6u<i6o~, W~ IJEptatil~ ... KOi til~
1-1E:v npottpa~ Eiai 6o~il~ oi 7tEpi 'Apiatav6pov Kai Nou1Jl\vtov Kai ciHm
7tAEiCJtOI tli>V E~TIY'ltWV ),
376. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I. 12, 5 (text iii). See Numenius: fr. 39
(Produs: In Tim. II, 153, 17-25) 'Others say that the soul is a geometrical
substanle composed of the point and the line. the former being the undivid-
ed substance ;md the latter the divided ... Severus subscribes to this view' (oi
6'w~ YEWIJEtplKtlV im6ataatv ouaav EK CJTIIJE!OU Kai 6taatciOEW~. toG IJEV
ciiJEpoii~. til~ 6& IJEptatil~ ... til~ 6& 6wttpa~ U:uilpo~ ). Since this doctrine
parallels Macrobius in providing a geometrical interpretation of the soul, and
is apparently contrasted with the Numenian position described in the
previous note, it might be argued that Macrobius is following a source other
than Numenius in repeating it. Thus, Beutler: 'Numenios', col. 676-677;
Elferink: op. cit., p. H ff. Two points may be made against this thesis: (i) The
parallel between Macrobius' and Severus' theories is not really that close.
since: the former speaks of the: protraltion of a sphere into a cone: and the lat-
ter of the protraction of a point into a line; (ii) It is a mistake to place
disproportionate emphasis upon a small piece of evidence when the over-
whelming tenor of Macrobius' account of the soul's descent is Numc:nian. See
de: Ley: op. cit., pp. 2'"'-';0; Flamant: op. cit., pp. 5 11-513.
37 .... Macrobius: In Sonm. Scip. I. 12. 9 (text iv). Cf. ibid. I. 10. 10 and I.
12. 10-11 (text iv). Descending souls are said to grow forgetful by Plotinus:
MACROBiliS
Enn. IV, 3/27/1 ';, 4-7; IV, 31271 26, S0-5';; IV, 4 /28/ ';, 22-26: Porphyry: De
Abstin. I. 28, 2: De Regr. Anim. fr. 11/1. 39 19-22; De Simul. fr. 5. 7
10-8 I.
378. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I, II, I. Cf. ibid. l, 12. 17 (text vi). See
Plotinus: Enn. l, 8 /'; 1/ 13. 2 1-2'; And its death is. while still immersed in the
body, to sink down in matter and be filled With it' (Kai 6 9avato<; autfj Kai l:tt
EV t<!) OCilllatt J3eJ3an:ttOI!EV1J EV UAlJ EOti KataMvm Kai 7tATj09ijvat autfi<; ');
Porphyry: In Tim. fr. 13 (Proclus: In Tim. I. 117. 5-8) 'And it is immersed in
the inundations of matter, which is the other death of intelkctuaJ souls' fKai
J3an:ti~Etal tote; tile; UATJ<; PEUI!QOI, Kai aA.Ao<; OUtO<; ljiUXWV ni>v VOEp<i>v
9avatoc; ). However. neither passage refers to the death of the disembodied
soul explicitly.
379. Macrobius: In Srmm. Scip. I. II, 12 (text i). There seems to be no
parallel in any extant Greek source to the statement that the crossing of seven
spheres is equivaknt 10 seven 'deaths' of the soul. Howevt'r. il is clt"arly a
consistent development of the norion expressed at Plotinus: Enn. I. 6 II/ S,
:'d-39 that the soul's involvement with maHer is a 'multipk death' (n:oA.uc; 6
8avatoc; ). The doctrine that the soul undergot"s seven 'deaths' as it crosses
the spheres Is juxtaposed with further interpretations of death as (i) freeing
the soul from the body by contemplation, (ii) freeing the body from the soul
hy physical annihilation. Sec Henry: op. cit .. pp. 163-182.
380. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. l, II, 12 (text i ). See Plotinus: Etm. I, 8 I 5 I
I 14, 113: I, 8 I 5 I I 14, 44-50; III, 5 I 50/7, 19; Ill, 5 I 50/9, 45-';7; Ill. 6/
26 I 14, 4-18; Porphyry: De Abstiu. Ill, 27, 35; Sent. 37. 4';, 1-9: 40. 51,
-~12.
381. See nn . .P2, 5!4-.'\"'6.
'588 NEOPLATONISM
382. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I, 14, 4. Cf. ibid. I. 10, 10. See Plotinus:
Enn. II, 9 /33/7. 911: III, 6/26/ '5, 19-22; Porphyry: De Abstin. I. 33. 2; I. 34,
4: Ad Marc. 33. 36, ll-16; Sent. 7, 3. 4-'5: 8, 3. 6-8. 4, 2.
383. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I. 12. 6 (text iii). See Numenius: fr. 39
(Proclus: In Tim. II. 1'53. 17-25): Plotinus: I:.'nn. I. I /53/8, 9-18: IV. I /211
8-22; IV, 2 /4/2, 1-55: IV, 3 /27/ 19. 27-34: IV, 9 /HI 2, 24-28; Porphyry: Ad
G(mr. l.~. 53, 3-6; 13. 53. II. All the Numenian and Plotinian passages agree
in (i) not distinguishing universal and particular souls regarding the question
of multiplicity, (ii) considering simplicity and multiplicity as wrrelative
aspects of both universal and particular souls. See nn. 211 and 348.
384. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. l, 10, 9 and I, 10, 17. This interpretation of
the underworld is suggested at Plotinus: l:.'nn. I. I /53/ 12. 24-39: IV. 3 /27/
26, 50-56; IV. 3 /27/ 27. 7-23. See Porphyry: De Regr. Anim. fr. 5, 7 II
-8 I.
385. Macrohius: In Somn. !kip. I. 10, 10-11. These interpretations cannot
he paralleled exactly in Greek Ncoplatonic writers, although this may simply
he because so much material is now lost. For the possibility that Macrobius is
dependent upon an earlier Latin commentator see pp. 515-516.
386.1bid. l, 10, 12 ff. Sec n. 385.
387. Ibid. l, 12,9 (text iv). See Plotinus: l:.'nn. II, 2/14 I 3. 1-6; Ill, 8/30 I
7, 3-4: IV. 7 12 /8, 1-10; IV, 8/6/8, 1-3: V, 3 /49/9, 28-32: V, S I 321 I,
1-2: VI, 2 /43/1, 1-5: Porphyry: Ad Gaur. 4. 40, 11-19. The Plotinian inter-
pretation of 'opinion' (56E,a) (i) contrasts it with the higher faculty of
knowledge and the lower faculty of sensation and (ii) applies it to judgments
which are true and to those which are false.
388. Macrobius: In .Somn. Scip. I. 12. 6 (text iii). See Numcnius: fr. 52
MACROBilJS SH9
(Cakidius: In Tim. 29"", 299, IH-300, 3); Plotinus: l:.'nn. IV. 2 1412, 155; IV,-~
12"'13. 1-29: IV, 3127/19. 27-.H: IV, 3127/20, I-IV, 3/27/23.47: IV. 9/H/ 3.
10-29; Porphyry: Ad Gaur. 1.~. S.~. 7-27: Sent. 31. 43. 11-16.
389. See pp. 315-318 and 380-384.
,WO. Sl'l' nn. 301HHl and .~H":'-3HH.
391. Sc:enn.3HS-3H6.
W2. Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I. 21, 34 .
.W.~. The statements elsewhere that the: human soul lan achine eternal
bliss must be: interpreted in accordance with the sense adopted here. Sec ibid.
I. J. I ami I. 12. I"' (text vi). According to the first sense ofimm;menl'e, the
perpetuity of the: soul's bliss would require a final escape from transmigra-
tion. but according 10 the second sense. this postulate is not necessary. The
question is discussed by Flamant: op. cit.. pp. 624-627.
394. See nn. 3S3 and .~60.
WS.Seen.361.
396. Sec n. 361.
-;l)O ;\IEOPLATOi'\IS~1
(iii) Cancer and Capricorn are the two tropics of the sun -
the points of the summer and winter solstices respectively -
and therefore called 'the gates of the sun' (itA.iou nuA.at).:\99
(iv) There are correspondences between the signs of the
zodiac and the planets according to their various distances from
the earth. Thus,
a) proceeding from Cancer to Capricorn: Leo is the house of
the sun. Virgo that of Mercury, Libra that of Venus, Scorpio that
of Mars, Sagittarius that of Jupiter, and Capricorn that of Saturn;
b) proceeding from Capricorn to Cancer: Aquarius is the
house of Saturn, Pisces that of Jupiter, Aries that of Mars, Taurus
that of Venus, Gemini that of Mercury, and Cancer that of the
moon.-ioo
(v) Two constellations in the heaven also have an
eschatological function: that of Cancer in the north, and that of
Capricorn in the south.
(vi) Disembodied human souls are congregated along the
Milky Way -which is bounded at its two ends by Cancer and
Capricorn- and called 'the people of dreams' (cSihwc; oveiprov).
(vii) Human souls descend and ascend through Cancer and
Capricorn respectively ..JOI
.~99. Thcst ideas occur in ;all three Numenian fragments and arc bastd
upon the exegesis of two Hor.-=ric texts (Odyss. XIII. 109-112 and XXIV.
12-15). For a detailed comparison between Numcnius' doctrine and the
material presented hy M;tcrohius sec l.eemans: up. cit .. pp. 14"'- I <;2.
100. This doctrine appears only in the senmd fragmenl. Its soun:e is
astrological.
HI I. These ideas occur in all three Numenian fragments and are based
again upon the two Homcrk texts. :'llumenius' doctrine also comains variou~
notions derived from Plato (Rep. X. 614b-621d)- (i) The location of judges
for the disembodied souls between heaven (the sphere of fixed stars) and the
underworld (the seven planetary spheres). and (ii) The disembodkd souls'
journey of twelve days from the center (through earth. w;lter. air. ;and the
seven pl;anetary spheres) 10 the sphere of fixed stars - which arc not
repeated hy Macrohius.
NEOPLATONISM
-HH. I, rod us: In Tim. Ill, 23'1. 26-30 (Porphyry: In Tim. fr. 80) 'And Por-
phyry's disciplc:s think that they are following the Omcles when they say that
the soul in its descent collects a vehicle by taking 'a portion of aether, "of
sun, of moon. and of what is borne on air" ' (Kai 5oKoliatv fn&a9at toi~
l..oyim~ t.v tij Ka965q> TftV ljiUXftV Atyouat aui..Uy&lV auto Aaj.1j3avouatv ai9pTJ~
llEPO~ 'T)&I..iou t 0ATJVQiTJ~ t Kai oaaa I T)tpt auvvnxovtat').
Hl5. The doctrine em he: reconstruned from twelve texts:
(i)DeAbslin. I. :\1. 3--t.
(ii) /hid. II. 3R. 2-11. 39. 2.
(iii) /hid. II. -t6, I.
(iv)DeAutr. Nympb. II. li. 5-11.
(\')Ibid. 1-i. 16. 11-1.~.
(vi)AdGttur. II. ~9. lf-21.
(Vii) Ibid. 6, 4.2, 'i-1 'i.
(viii)DeRegr. Anim. fr. 2. 28'.~-29'"
(ix) /hid. fr. ~. :\2 23-25.
(x)//Jid. fr. "'. _~:; 1:\-li.
(xi) Sent. 29. 1"'. 11-20.6.
(xii) In Tim. fr. HO (Proclus: In Tim. Ill. 2.'\L IH-30). These passages will he
identified hy their numhers in the: dislussion below.
NI:OPLATONISM
Martianus Capella
8. 1 INTRODUCTION
I. For the text sec Martianus Capella, edidit }. WU/is (Leipzig 19tH).
There is an English translation of A. Dick's earlier edition (Leipzig 192';) in
\li'. H. Stahl, R. Johnson. and E. L. Burge: Martian us Capella and tbe Sezen
Uberal Arts II: Tbe Mt~rriage of Pbilnlogy ami Merczu:.J' (~ew York. 19'7i).
Thc::re is an Italian translation and running commentary on part of the trc::atise
in 1.. Lenaz: Mt~rtiani CClpellae De Nuptiis Philologiae et Mercurii Liber
Sccundus. lntroduzi(me, trClduzione e commento (Padova. 19'7i ). For
general introductions see P. Wessner: 'Martianus Capella'. Pau~}'S Realen-
(l'clopiitlie tier klassischen Altertumsll'issenscbaft l.f (Stuttgart. 19~0), col.
2003-.20 16; M. Cappuyns: 'Capella (Martianus)'. Dictimmaire tl'bistoire et de
geograpbie ecc.:tesiastiques I I (Paris. 1919). pp. H~';-R4R; W. H. Stahl. R.
Johnson, and E. L. Burge: Martian us Capella mul tbe Sezen Liberal Arts I:
The Quadrizium of Martimms Capella. l.c1tin Tmtlitions in the.'
.Hatbematical Sciences 50 B.C. to A.D. 1.250. zl'ith a Stutly of the Allegm:.1
and the Verhtll Disciplines (New York/London, 1971 ); F. Le Moine: Mar-
timws Capella, A l.iterm:.J' Re-F.za/uation (Munchen, 19'7 2); L. l.c:naz: 'Mar-
ziano Capella', Cultura e sc:twla 44 (1972). pp. i0-i9: and J. Willis: ~tar
tianus Capella und die mittclalterlichc: Schulhildung'. Altertum 19 ( 19"' 3 ). pp.
16i . 1'7 .j.
';9i
'ilJH NEOPLATONISM
2. The intluente of Martianus Capdla upon the Middle Ages has been in-
\'lstigated in the following works of modern slholarship: (i) Gen1..ral studies
of his intluence. M. Manitius: Geschicbte der lateinischen Litem fur des Mit-
telalters 1-111 (Miinchen. 1911-19:\1). indins: \'\1essner: op. cit .. col.
.W 12-20 1_-\; Cappuyns: op. cit .. pp. H-H-H-i' (containing a useful classifica-
tion of the kinds of influence); C. Leonardi: 'Nota introdutti\'a per un'in-
dagine sulla fortuna di Marziano Capella ncl Medioe\'o'. Hollellitw dell'
lstituto Storico Italiano peril Medio Eto e Architin ,"trfuratoricmo 67 ( 19'i'i).
pp. 26'i-2HH; Stahl. Johnson. :tnd Burge: ofJ. cit. I. pp. 'i'i-' I: and Willis: op.
cit .. pp I '1-1"" -t. (ii) Studies of :\lartianus' influence based upon the diffusion
of m:tnuscripts. C. I.eon:1rdi: I ~..-odid di :\l:1rziano Capella I', Aetum .H
(19'ilJ), pp. H;\--tl-19: 'I codid di Marziano Capella Jl', ibid. :\-1 (1960). pp.
1-99 and i ll-'i2L ). Prcaux: 'Les manuscrits prindpaux du De Nuptlis
Pbilologiae et Mercurii de Martianus Capella', Lettres latines du moyen clge
et de Ia Renaissance. recueil cditc par G. Cambier. C. Deroux et ). Prcaux
(Bruxdks, ll)""'H ), pp. ""6-128. (iii) Sllldics of his influence based upon the
production of tommentaries by mediae\'al writers. E. Narducd: 'lntorno ad
un comento incdiw di Remigio d'Auxerrc al Satyrinm di Marziano Capdl:1',
llullettino tli bibliogmfia e di storia delle scienze matematicbe e fish-be I 'i
(I HH2), pp. 'iO'i-'iHO: ). Willis: Marlianus Capella tmd bis Early Commen-
tatms. Diss. (London, llJ'i 2 ); :tnd C. Lutz: Martianus Capella, Catalogus
Translationum et Commentariorum: Medietal and Renaissance Latin
1'rtmslations ami Cmnmentaries ll. l'dited by P. 0. Kristdler and F. E. Cranz
(Washington. DC. 19""'1) pp. ;\6''-381. (i\') General studies of the influence of
books 1-11. <i. Nuchdmans: 'l>hilologia l't son mariagl' a\'cc Menurc jusqu'ii Ia
fin du XIll sicdc'. /.atom us 16 ( 19'ii ). pp. Hi- Hl7. Proceeding in
MARTIANl!S CAPELLA
fl';tris. 1888). pp. 277296; F.. Jc:;umc:au: 'l.c: Prologus in Eptatbeunm c.k
Thkrry de Chartres', Medkteta/Studies 16 (19S.f). pp. 171-17S). thc:rc: is a
cornmc:ntary hy Rc:rnard Silvc:stris on Book I ( sc:c: F.. jc:aunc:au: Note: sur
l'l'colt: de: Chartrc:s, Studi medietali, tc:rza sc:rit: S ( 196-!), pp. HSS-86-!),john
of Salishury's Meta/ogicon c:mploys the: allt:gory and cc:rtain passagc:s in the:
latcr hooks (sc:c H. Lkhc:schi.itz: Meclictetal llunumism in tbe l.ife and
lr'riNngsofjobu ofSalisbm:l'(l.ondon. 19';0). pp. 8-i-HS: R. Klih;tnsky: 'The
Rock of Parmc:nidc:s. Mc:diac:val Vkws on the Origin of Dialt:ctil"'. Medimta/
and Reuaissance Studies I ( 19-!l-19-!~). pp. 178-186). and Godfrey of St.
\'ictor i~ intluctKcd hy the allegory. William of Conches also dcdarc:s that hl
was the: author of a commentary (sec P. Oronkc: Fabu/a. t:xplort~tions into
tbe f!ses r~(Mytb in Mediel'ttll'/atonism (.'1-fitte//tlteiniscbe Stutlien und Texte
II )(l.cidcn/Ki)ln. 19"'-t). pp. 161-IH_-\).
602 NEOJ>LATONISM
II. See ibid. I. 92 ir~terpres. There was a traditional Greek etymology: 'Ep-
llTJ~ = tpJ.1TJV&U&lV
1.2. Martianus" description of Philology has already been presented in con
junltion with that of Mercury in n. 9.
I;. See ibid. I, 7.
li. See ibid. I, 2; i11cu/ta. Of course, 'Psyche' ('1/UJ(Tt ) corresponds to soul
in Greek.
NEOPI.ATONISM
15. For this theme see pp. 99- t 00 (Cicero), t 79-180 (Seneca). 380-382 (the
Asclepius). 482-483 (Calcidius), etc.
16. The influence of Apuleius over Martianus has been detected in three
areas: (i) linguistic style. (ii) the allegorical marriage itself (cf. the episode of
Cupid and Psyche in Apuleius' Metamorphoses). and (iii) philosophical doc-
trine. For (i) see C. Weyman: Stud/en zu Apuleius und seine11 Nachahmern
(Sitztmgsbericbte tier Bayerlscbe11 Akademie tier Wissenscbaften 1893. 2)
(Miinchen, 1893). pp. 374-375: C. Morelli: 'Quaestiones in Martianum
Capell am', Studt italian/ dl filologla clt~ssica 17 ( t 909), pp. 2 56-260; and
Wessner: op. cit .. pp . .2006-2007. For (iii) sec my remarks in nn. HI. 90. etc.
li. The doctrines of the Cba/daean Oracles have heen examinl'll. as far ;1s
the fragmentary remains allow. in the following works: \V. Kroll: De
Oraculis Cba/tlaicis (Breslau. IR9l; repr. Hildesheim, 1962); H. Lewy:
Cba/daea11 Omc/es and 7'/Jeurgy. Mysticism, /Hagle ami Platonism ill tbe
l.ater Roman Empire (Recherches d'arcbeologie. de philologie et d'histoire
1;\) (Cairo. 19'Hl)- wgether wilh a review: E. R. Dodds: 'New I.ight on the
Cha/daecm Om des. Hmtard Tbeo/ogica/ Retieu 5i ( 1961 ), pp. 263-27 3
-: ami t des Places: Orachs Clmldaiqms. te.\'11! tfta/J/1 et trmluit (Paris,
l'r I). In :1 paper included in I he corrccled reprinl of LLwy's hook (Paris.
llJ~H ), P. H:1do1 has summarized the results of tht: modern scholarship on
lhcse oracles, nolin~ lhl' ~reat uncertainties whkh remain in many anas
( Rilan e1 perspeltives sur les Oracles Chaldaiques'. pp. 703-7 20). For discus-
sion of lheir influence upon varius hiler writers, both Greek and Latin. the
608 :'llf:OI'LATONISM
408. 14-15; Damascius: Dubit. et Su/ut. I, 315, 22; 11, 152. 23: Lydus: De
Mens. IV, 53. 110, 9; etc. On the later Neop1atonic testimonies seen. 22.
25. Orac. Cbald. fr. 5 I (Prod us: In Remp. 11, 201, 14-16). Cf. Omc. Cbald.
fr. 96 (Psellus: Comm. (PG 122. 1141C)) .
.26. Orac. Cha/d. fr. 5.2 (Psellus: Comm. (PG 122, I 136A)). Cf. Orac.
Cbald. fr. 32 (Produs: In Tim. I. i.ZO, 1:\-16); fr. 35 (Damascius: Dublt. et
Solut. II. 135. 3-6); and fr. 50 (Damascius: Dubit. et So/ut. 11. 164. 19) .
.27. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. 11, .20.2. Cf. ibid. II, 185 'unknown father'
(ignotus pater ) and ibid. IX, 922 'inconceivable creator' (incogitabilis ef-
figientia). Cf. Omc. Chald. fr. I (Damascius: Dubit. et Solut. I, 154, 1626)
'that intelligible ... subsists beyond intellect' (to vontov EKEivo ... v6ou f~w
(mlip;(El); Porphyry: De Abstin. Ill, II, 3: In Pamz. II, 431 and X. 11-29 .
.28. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. II, .ZO:\. Cf. Orac. Cba/cl. fr. I (Damascius:
Dubit. et Sol. 1, 154. 16-26) 'flame of intellect ... eye of the soul' (v6ou cpA.6~
... OJJJJQ 11/UXfi<;); fr. 49 (Prod us: In 1'im. Ill, li. 31 0) 'flower of intelle<.'l'
(v6ou iiv6o<;); and Porphyry: In Pann. II, 14-2"'.
MARTIAN US CAPELI.A 611
29. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. II, .202. Cf. ibid. IX, 910 'supermundane
intdlcct' (extramtmdcma intellegentia). Cf. Urac. Cbaltl. fr. 18 (Produs: In
oat. 'ii. 2'i) 'the supermundane paternal depth' (6 imtpKOOI.lOc; natptKoc;
pueoc;): fr. 3 (Psellus: Comm. (PG 122 II44A)) 'The father has removed
himself' (6 natftp ilpnaaa&v ~aut6v); fr. 5 (Produs: In Tim. II, 57, 30-58, 2)
'the fire beyond' (nup E7tEK&tva); Porphyry: In Parm. IX, 1-3 'Others say that
it has removed itself from all things derived from it' (oi lit apnciaat autov EK
ncivnov nov autou &in6vt&c;): and Sent. 10, 4, 9-10 'the beyond' (to
E7tEK&\VQ).
30. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. II, 206. Cf. Porphyry: In Pann. XII, 22-25
'The One which is heyond substance and being is neither being nor substance
nor activity' (to EV TO E7tEK&IVQ ouaiac; Kai Ovmc; Bv llEV OUK ~anv oulit ouaia
ouM tv&py&ta) and Sent. 26. I 'i. 9-13 'the non-being which is prior to being'
(to imtp to ov llTt Ov).
31. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. II. 202. Cf. Orac. Chald. fr. 'i (Proclus: In
Tim. II, 'i7, 30-'i8 . .2) 'the craftsman of the fier-y world' (6 K60ilOU texvitnc;
nupiou). Cf. Prod us: In Tim. II, 57, 9-12 'They divide all things into the fiery,
the aetherial. and the material' (Tii ncivta litatp&ia9at &lc; Ell7tUptov aletptov
uA.aiov). Cf. Produs: In Tim. II, 58. 6-9; In Crat. 76, 2-3: Damascius: Dubit.
el Solut. II, 88, 18-24: and Psellus: Expos. (PG 122, 1149C-11 'i2A).
52. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. IX, 910. Cf. Urac. Chald. fr. 3 (Psellus:
Comm. (PG 122. 11HA)) 'He did not include his own fire in his intellectual
powl'r' (ouli 'tv ~fj liuvcill&l VOEP~ KA&iaac; ilitov nup): fr. 5 (Prod us: In Tim. II.
'i~ ..~O-'i8. 2) 'the fire beyond' (nup E7tEK&tva); fr. 6 (Simplicius: In De Caelu
II. I, 37'i, 19-.21) 'the primal fire'(nup nprotov); and fr. 36 (Proclus: In Crat.
';8, 14-1 'i) 'the implacable fire' (tlll&iAIKtov nup) .
.H. ~lartianus Capl'lht: /)t NufJt. II. .206. Cf. Omc. Om/d. fr. :r:" (Proclus:
lu Parm. HOO . .20-1-101. .:; ) intcllec!llal thoughts whkh pluck the abundant
llowlr of fire from thl' paternal sourle (~vvotat vo&pai 7tfi'Yiic; 7tatptKf(c; ano,
rrouA.G lip&7tTOilEVat nupoc; av9oc;) ;md fr. I :\0 (l'roclus: In Tim. Ill. .266.
I'J-2:\) 'The soul plucks the soul-sustaining flower of the fiery fruits whkh
lbnnd' (IVUXTt Kanovtwv/Cil7tUpiwv l)p7t&tat Kapnrov IVUXOtpOIJIOV av9oc;).
:\.f. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. II, 204. Cf. Orac. Chald. fr. 18 (Proclus:
612 NEOPLATONISM
-t9. For the multiplicity of intellect in the Clm/daemr Omc/es sec Omc.
Chait/. fr. I (Damascius: Dubit. et So/ut. I. I S4. 16-26) where the power
derived from the father is 'tl:tshin~ot with intellectual divisions' (VOf:paic;
cnptintouaa tOJ,1aimv) and fr. 37 (Proclus: In Ptlnll. 800, 20-80 I, S) where
lhl Forms emanating from the father were divided into other intellectual
Forms having been separated br intellectual fire' (EJ.1Epia9T]aav voep<jl nupi
J.101pl]9&iaat/eic; ciA.A.ac; voepti:c;). For the same doctrine in Neoplatonism sec
Porphyry: SePII. 22, 13. 13-16 'Thc intcllcctual substance has simihtrity bet-
ween whole and parts. so that the beings exist both in the particular and in
the l'omplcte intcllect. But in the universal intclkct en:n particular things cx-
ist universally. in the particular intellect even universal things particularly' (tl
VOEpa ouaia OJ.10lOJ.1EPt'lc; tanv, ci>c; Kai tv t<\Jj.!EptK<\J v<j> dvat tO. ovta Kai F.v
HlJ 7tQVti:J,Ei(!)' ai..A'f.v J.1t':V t<\J Ka90AOU KOi tQ J.lEptKQ Ka90AIKWc;, EV Of: t<\J
J.lEptK<jl Kai tQ Ka96A.ou J.1EptKWc;).
SO. Martianus Capclla: De Nupt. II, 203. The reference to a multiplicity of
intellects has madc this passage one of the pieces of e\'idencc adduced by sup-
pontrs of the thcsis that Marli:mus is influenced by the Neoplatonist
lamblichus. SeeR. Turcan: 'Martianus Capella et Jamblique', Rerue des etudes
Ia tines :\6 ( 1958) pp. 235-254. It is testified that lamblichus wrote a commen-
tary upon the Cha/daean Oracles in at least twenty-eight books (Damascius:
616 NEOPI.ATONISM
Dub it. et Solut. l, 86, S-6 and I, 154. 13-14) and therefore possible that Mar-
tian us found his oracular texts embedded in this treatise. However, the argu-
ment (Turcan: op. cit.. p. 253) that the occurrence of the term intellectualis
in the present passage shows lamblichean influence is inconclusive. since the
corresponding Greek word voEp6c; is used extensively in the writings of Por-
phyry (see Porphyrii Sententiae ad 11llelligibilla Ducentes, edidlt E.
Lamberz (Stuttgart. 1975). index verborum s. v.). It is simpler to postulate the
influence of Porphyry whose philosophy was widely known in the Latin
West and is mentioned explicitly by Firmicus Matcrnus, Macrobius.
Augustine, and others. See Courcelle: op. cit., pp. 217-219 and n. 74. A fur-
ther passage where some scholars have appealed to the influence of
lamblichus will be discussed inn. 124.
<;I. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. I. 92. Willis mist:1kcnly reads lmnos.
52. Sec pp. 609-610.
S3. Sec pp. <;3<;-538.
54. Sec Porphyry: In Tim. fr. 20 (Proclus: In Tim. I. 159. 25-27) 'the in-
tellect of the moon ... the intellect of the sun' (vouc; I:EA11V1aK6c; ... HA.laKoc;
vouc;). At iiJid. fr. 52 (Proclus: In Tim. I. 422, 5-26) Porphyry states regarding
the planetary intellects that 'in them the part is a whole, for all things which
are in the whole universally arc in each individual particul:uly, owing to the
unification of intclligibile Forms' (v KEivmc; to J.LEpoc; oA.ov ati' mi.vta yap
MARTIANlJS CAPELLA 61""
tanv tv CKQOTQ> J.lEPIK<i:Jc; oaa tcj> 6/..Q> navtEI..<i:Jc; 6u'.t tijv fvwmv t<i:JV VOllTWV
Ei6<i:Jv) thereby applying to planetary intellects the principle discussed in n.
19. At ibid. fr. 79 (Proclus: In Tim. III, 64, 8-65, 7) a more complex schema
relating each of the planets to 'being' (ouaia). 'life' (~wi)). and 'intellect'
(vouc;) is expounded.
55. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. VII, 731.
56. Seen. 49.
57. See Nicomachus ofGerasa at Ps.-lamblichus: 11Jeol. tlrithm. 5, f. Iff.
The innuence of Nicomachus (directly or indirectly) upon this part of De
Nuptiis has been summarized by Stahl: M"rtianus Cape/let tt1UI tbe Sete!l
Ubeml Arts I. pp. -18-49.
SR. See pp. 535-538.
';9. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. VI, 567. At ibid. VI. 5"' I she is characteriz-
td as 'the nower of fire' (ignisflos).
60. See pp. 609-610.
61. See pp. 535-538.
62. For the interpretation of At hcne in :"1/eoplatonism see Porphyry: De An-
tr. Nymph. 31. 30. 11-33. 32. -:-r. In the Porphyrian system Athene seems to
618 NEOPlATONISM
'alone having plucked abundantly the flower of intellect from the father's powt'r
and ahlt tu percei\'c the paternal intellect' (nol..u yap ll6voc; EK rrarpoc;
uhf]c;/cSpEijiQjlEVoc; v6ou iiv9oc; E;(EI TO voEiv 1tUTptKOV VOUV). Here. there arc the
Mriking parallels With Marti:mus' address to the sun: 1tUTpoc; ai..Kf]c; = 1is patris.
narpoyevtc; =prima pmpago. jlovoc; =so/us. etc. Smh similarities of expression
lend further support to the thesi~ that the intdlecti\e sun of Marrianus is
tquivalcm 10 the Aion of the Cba/dcwtm Orades. On the doctrine of Aion in late
:mtiquity sec A.~J. fcstugiere: L(l nlt.ilaticm d'Het7nes Tristtufgiste IV: Le Dieu in-
cmmu et Ia (;noS' (Paris, 19'H ). pp. I '52-199.
76. Sec n. 7_-\.
-n. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. II. 191-192.
7H. This reduction of polytheism to monotheism is implied in Numcnius:
fr. S-4 (Macrohius: Saturn. I. 17. 6S) where Apollo's name cStl..qHoc; is held to
signify the unity of tht' divint' realm. It presumably also un<krlit's tht' inter-
pretations in Numcnius: fr. '57 (l.ydus: De Mens. IV. HO. I ~2. 11-1 S). etc. of
Ht'rmts. Htphacstus. and Nt'mt'sis. Howevt'r. thert' is no cvidcnct' 10 suggest
th:u this reduction of polytheism to monotheism postulates a prim:try roll'
for the sun.
79. Sc:c n. - ~-
80. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. ll. 126. The writer actually altrihutes
MARTIANUS CAPELLA 621
these characteristics to Mercury and Philology, but this fact does not
diminish the validity of the present conclusion.
81. See pp. 609-610.
82. See pp. 535-538.
83. Seen. 54.
84. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. 1.92.
85. Seep. 615 ff.
86. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. VI, 574. Since ibid. I. 27-28 associates the
nine Muses with the sphere of fixed stars, the:: seven planets, and the earth. we
must understand Athene as representing a universal intellect which embraces
a plurality of planetary intellects. This helps to confirm the conclusion of nn.
5f and 83. On the Muses as interpreted by the present author sec J. Preaux:
622 NEOPLATONISM
H9. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. I, 61-1. The: logical function of Forms (;ts
genera and species) is discussed at ibid. IV. 3h-34S.
90. Sc:e Plotinus: Emz. V, I /10/1'1, 11'1-22; VI. c; /23/4. 20-2';; Marius \'il"
tori nus: Adz. Arium I. 60. I. 131: and Damasdus: Dubit. et Solut. I. .:\0 I.
2H-;'102, I.
91. See pp. 290-292.
92. See ch. 4, nn. 286 and 302.
9:t M:lrlianus Capella: De Nupt. VII. 7;'13. Thl production of Forms from
the: monad (equivalent to Jupiter) is also described at ibid. VII. 7 .~I.
NEOPLATONISM
99. Sec). Sczncc: La surtitcmce des diell.\' allfiques. Essai sur /e 1'(1/1! de Ia
traditirm mytbologique dans l'bumanisme et dans /'art de Ia Renaissance
(London, 1940), pp. 3540.
100. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. VIII, 812.
I 0 I. Ibid. II, 169170.
IO.l.lbid. II, 171180.
I 03. Ibid. II, 181. This appc:uancc in the anthropomorphic mode docs
not, given Martianus' way of writing, preclude the goddess' simultaneous
manifestation as a planet.
IIH.Ibid. II, 182193.
105.1bid. II, 194-195.
616 :'IIEOP!.ATONISM
in the first, second, fourth, and ninth regions. liB If one inter-
prets the conciliar gods as comprising the traditional list and
allows for the alternative names of single divinities. then the
repetition in the whole scheme is further increased. Secondly,
the gods are classified according to their abodes in sixteen
regions of the heaven, clearly suggesting that they are
distributed through the four cardinal points of the compass. An
examination of similar discussions in Cicero,lllJ Pliny's
Natura/is Historia, 12o and Servius 121 indicates that the
Etruscans had arrived at a division of the heaven into sixteen
regions by multiplying the compass points. Thirdly, the ar-
rangement of the gods seems to imply a hierarchy: thus, Jupiter
and the conciliar gods appear in the first, second, and third
regions, while the lower ranking gods are mentioned in the fif-
teenth and sixteenth regions.l22 However, since there also
seems to be a hierarchical arrangement within each group of
four regions. the whole scheme is already more complex than a
simple descending sequence from beginning to end. Naturally, a
passage so abundant in religious lore has attracted the attention
of modern interpreters. Among those, S. Weinstock has provid-
ed the most convincing explanation by comparing the reference
to similar doctrines expressed elsewhere in De Nuptiis and in
other Latin writers. He therefore suggests that the sixteen
regions of the heavens are numbered in sequence from north to
east, to south, to west, and back to north in a spiral descent
IIH. For somc suggestions why thcsc gods arc rcpcatcd scc G. Dumczil:
'Remarques sur les trois premieres regiones caeli de Martian us Capella'.
Hom mages it M. Niederman II (Col/ectionl.atomus 2.l,) (Rruxcllcs. 19')6). pp.
102-107.
Ill). Ci<:cro: DeDitin. II, 8789.
120. Plin}': Nat. Hist. ll. 143.
121. Scrvius: b1 Aeueid. VIII, 427.
122. for some suggestions regarding the principles of hierarchy in the first
three regions sec Dumczil: op. cit .. pp. I 02-107.
MARTIANLJS CAPELLA 62l)
125. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. II. 150. In order to make the structure of
this spiritual hierarchy clearer, the attributes of each rank will be lisred in the
same sequence. This sequence will be: first, the region inhabited; secondly,
their nature- divided into a) substance, b) impassivity or passivity, c) moral
status. and d) function; thirdly, their hierarchical position- divided into e)
their ruler and f) their collective name; and fourthly, the spirits included in
the class.
126. Ibid. II, 150.
I 2'7. Ibid. II, I 50.
128. This characteristic is determined by extrapolation from Ibid. II, 155.
These 'extrapolated' characteristics - which can be deduced from Mar-
tianus' logical and symmetrical scheme- will be noted in parentheses().
129. Ibid. II. 150.
I :\0. Ibid. II. 150.
131. !IJid. II. 150.
132. By extrapolation from Ibid. II. 151 ff.
I :H. Porphrrr: !:'pist. ad A neb. 2-3 and De Regr. Anim. fr. 4. 32" 25.
I.H. Set pp. 551-1-560, 610-61-i. and nn. 31-jj.
135. See pp. 551-1-560. 610-6J.j. and n. 42.
MARTIANUS CAPF.LI.A 6~1
kind is that which is wicked and injurious to souls' (nap'o[c; 6 .SaiJ.LOOV tptxwc;
Kai yap &ivai cpaot tO J.LtV 9Eirov lialJ.LOVOOV yevoc;, tO lit Kata OXEatV, 0 IJ.EplKai
oUJ.17tATJpoiim IJIUX,al SatJ.Loviac; tuxouaat A.iji;Eroc;, to .Sf: noVTipov ciAA.o Kai
A.uJ.LaVnKov t&v IJIUX,WV). That Martianus agrees with Porphyry and disagrees
with the Cbaldaea11 Oracles on this point is a piece of evidence in favor of
the thesis that Martianus read the Iauer embedded in the former's commen-
tary.
16';. Porphyry: De Philos. ()rae. p. 147 'And the god Sarapis is identical
with Pluto, being for this reason chietly the ruler of the demons' (o autoc; lit
tc:i> nA.oUt(I)Vl 6 8E6c;, Kai O!Ct toiito J.LQAlota lialJ.LOV(I)V apxrov).
166. Porphyry: De Simul. fr. 10, 19" 13-20" 6 'They addressed Isis as the
power of the "heavenly earth" and of the terrestrial one ... Dionysus ...
Osiris .... (t~c; <'it oupaviac; yiic; Kai lie; x.Soviac; titV OUVQIJ.lV 'lmv rrpooEinov
... .1t6vuooc; ... "Omptc;).
167. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. II, 160.
161-1. By extr;1polation from ibid. II, 154.
169. By extrapolation from ibid. II, 150 and II, 167.
170. By extrapolation from ibid. II, 155 and II, 167.
1"'1./hid.ll, 162-163.
MARTIANliS CAPELLA
190. Orac. Cha/d. fr. 88 (Psellus: Cmnm. (PG I 22. I 1)7 A)); fr. 90 (Pscllus:
Comm. (PG 122. 11408)); fr. 161 (Psellus: Comm. (PG 122, 114 lA)); and fr.
162 (Psellus: Comm. (PG 122, I 1458)).
191. Porphyry: DeAbstin. ll, .:\8. 1-40, 4; DeRegr. Anim. fr. s..u 28-.H
I; and In Tim. fr. 10 (Proclus: In Tim. I, 77. 6-24).
192. Porphyry: De Antr. Nymph. 10, 12. 121.'\; 1), 14, 2529; and De
Simu/. fr. 7. 11 11-1.3.
I 9.3. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. ll, I 56 and II, 165-166.
194. See pp. 615-622.
195. See pp. 535-542.
I tJ6. l.enaz: op. cit., pp. 81-82 dues nul setm to have n<>lkcd this distinc-
tion.
6:\H NEOPI.ATONISM
2 I I. /IJifl. I. 9 :L Cf. ibid. II, I 09 'mortal limbs (mort ales art us).
212. Ibid. II. I 09. Cf. ibid. II. l.ci2.
21.~. IIJid. 11. 120. Philolo~y seems tu achine '<kification' (apotbeosis) at
ibid. II. 206.
2 14. See above.
215. Martianus Capella: De Nupt: I. 22. At ibid. I. 93 and II, 126
Philology's learning is said to surpass that of Mercury.
216. /fJid. II. lB. Cf. ibid. I. 21. 'She forces the gods to obey her com
mands' (deos urgens in iussa coactos). It is predicted that Philolo~y will
herself assign causes to the planetary motions at iiJid. II, II H.
21..,. Ibid. II. 120.
MARTIANl!S CAPELLA 6-11
not easily be paralleled in other religious rituals of the period which are
known. He therefore suggests that Martianus himself invented a symbol for
the Neoplatunic notion of approaching God through the abandonment of all
dist:ursive knowledge.
224. See pp. 62.2-623. That this correspondence is intended is suggested by
the allusions to the presenn: of the four elements in both the sphere and the
egg. those elemt:nts being understood as Forms in the case of the sphere and
;1s physical substances in that of the egg. Cf. Porphyry: De Simu/. fr. 10. 18"
1619 'They say that this god brings forth from his mouth an egg. from which
is born the god whom they call Phtha and the Greeks Hephaestus. They inter-
pret the egg as the cosmos' (tov ot 8Eov toiitov EK toO at6j.lato<; npoiEa8ai
!pUOlV WOV, e; OU yEVVci08UI 8EOV OV autoi npoaayopEUOUOI cJ)8ci, Ol OE
"EAA.nvEc; "H!paaatov EPilllVEuoumv ot tov o>ov tov K6aj.IOV). Since Porphyry
et1uates the Egyptian god Kneph described here with the Demiurge of
Platonism. the bringing forth of the egg must represent the instantiation of
the elemental Forms.
2.2'5. Plotinus: Enn. Ill, '5 /'50/7. 9-1 '5.
2.26. Porphyry: Sent. j7. 4'i, '5-9. Cf. DeAbstin. Ill, 2-:', .v;.
22:. Plotinus: Enn. Ill. 5 /'iO/ 7. 1-IIl, '5 /50/9, '57; Porphyry: De Abstitl.
MARTIANliS CAPELLA
doctrine that the human soul has a dual nature with an account
of the method by which it may be elevated to the higher state.
for just as Philology can attain divinity partly by an intellective
process and partly by the performance of a purificatory ritual,
so does Porphyry explain the elevation of the human soul as
taking place both by means of philosophy and by means of
'theurgy' (tbeurgia). According to Porphyry's teaching, intellec-
tive activity elevates the human soul by specifically perfecting
its higher part - this process leading to God himself,HH -
whereas theurgic activity elevates the human soul by specifical-
1y perfecting the lower - this process leading to the empyrian
rcalml!'> -, the two kinds of activity however being not
necessarily pursued in conjunction with one another.2.:\0
Ill. 2"'.-! and Sent. :\7. 4S, S-9. Th~ passage which provides the exegetical
basis for this theory is Plato: Symp. 20:\h ff. It is p~rhaps no accident that the
latter also d~picts a marriage.
228. Porphyry: DeRegr. Anim. fr. 2, 2s 10-13 and fr. 7, 3s 26-29.
229./bid. fr. 2. 28 3-10; fr. 3. 31 H-32 I; and fr. -1. 32 23-21.
2:Hl. Ibid. fr. 7, 3S 13-1 S. For a r~c~nt discussion of Porphyry's attitude
to theurgy see A. Smith: Porphyry's Place in tbe Neoplatonic Tradition. A
Slue~}' 111 Post-Plotinian Neoplatonism (The Hague, 1974), pp. 128-141.
2:\ I. Martian us Capella: De Nupt. II, I.H.
2.U. Ibid. II, 134.
233.1/Jid.ll.l-f."'.
2:\-1. Ibid. 11. 1-f 3- llf.
NEOPI.ATONJSM
25<;. /IJid. II. li<;. The palanquin is also mentioned at iiJid. II. 169 and II,
200.
B6. Sec Len;lz: op. cit., pp. 15-li who quotes lierodian and Dio Cassius as
his evidence.
257. See Courcelle: op. cit .. pp. 215-216. On the doctrine of the human
soul's 'vehicle' (~XTU.La) sec pp. 490-492 and <;79 ff.
25R. Of course. ~lartianus might vaguely have intended both.
MARTIANUS CAPELLA
23CJ. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. I, 7. Dick and Willis were mistaken in re-
jc:cting the testimony of the best manuscripts and re:tding ente/ecbill here and
~~~ ibid. ll, 213. Sec n. 242.
2-tO. Ibid. I, 7.
HI. Ibid. I, 23.
242. At Cicero: Tusc. Disp. I, 22 the term vliEA.tXEta is used to signify the
world soul equivalent to aether in a doctrine combining Platonic.
Aristotelian. and Stoic ideas. As J. Pepin: Tbeo/ogie cosmique et tbeologie
clmJtienne (Ambroise, Exam. I, I, 1-4) (Paris. 1964). pp. 206-216 has
demonstrated, this term is probably not a confusion of the standard
Aristotelian technical term for soul - the vtEI..tXEta of De Anim. ll, I,
i 12a27. etc. - but a genuine element in the cosmological doctrine of the ear-
ly Aristotle. That Martianus has in mind the same doctrine as Cicero is in-
dicated by De Nupt. ll, 213 where Aristotle is depicted as pursuing Endelichia
'through the heights of heaven' (percaeli ... culmina).
243. Seepp. 618-620.
244. See pp. 640-643.
NEOPI.ATONISM
Boethius
9.1 INTRODUCTION
Evans: 'More geometrico. The Place of the Axiomatic Method in the Twelfth-
Century Commentaries on Boethius' Opuscula sacra. Archive intema-
timzale d'histoire des sciences 27 (1977), pp. 207-221; and S. Gersh:
Platonism, Neoplatonism, Aristotelianism. A Twelfth-Century Metaphysical
System and its Sources', Renaissance and Renewal in the Twelfth Century,
edited by R. L. Benson and G. Constable (Cambridge,MA, 1982), pp. 512-534.
3E. C. Jourdain: 'Des commentaires inedits de Guillaume de Conches ct de
:-.Jkolas Triveth sur Ia Consolation de Ia Phi/osophie de Boece', Notices et e."C-
tmits des manuscrlts de Ia Blbliotbeque Imperiale 20 (1862), pp. 40-82-
contains extract from the commentary of William of Conches-; A. Wilmart:
Reg lat. "'2 (f. I 10126): Commentaire de Ia Consoltltion de Boece', A,lalec
Ia Reginensia 9 (Stud/ e Testi 59) (Citta del Vaticano, 1933), pp. 259-262; E.
T. Silk: Saeculi Noni Auctoris in Boetii Consolationem Philosophiae Com-
melltarius (Roma. 1935)- contains text of a twelfth-century commentary
mist:tkenly attributed by the editor to Eriugena -; ). Hatinguais: 'En marge
d'un pocme de Bocce. L'interpretation allegorique du mythe d'Orphee par
Guillaume de Conches'. Cm1gres de Tours et de Poitiers 1953. Actes du Ve
Cong,i!s de /'Association G. Bude (Paris, 1954 ), pp. 2R'i-2R9; N. M. Haring:
Four Commentaries on the De Consolatione Pbilosophiae in MS.
Heiligenkreuz 130', MedlaetJa/ Studies 31 (1969). pp. 287-316; and E.
Jcauneau: 'Un commentaire inedit sur le chant 0 qui perpetua de Boece', Lec:-
lio Pbilosophorum. Recberc:hes sur /'Ecole de Chartres (Amsterdam, 1973),
pp. 311-3.~ I. Other brief surveys of Boethius' influence in the Middle Ages
can he found in some of the general studies of his thought listed inn. 13 .
.?.. Boethius: In Delnterpr. ed. II. 2 ..~. 79. 180, 17.
3. See for example Elias: In Categ. pr. 123.7-11.
NEOPLATONISM
-i. Sec Bocthius: De Consol. Philos. IV. pr. 2. I ff. (to Plato: Gurg. -i66 a ff.
on the respective powers of the good and tht> wicked); ibid. I. pr. 2. 13-1-i (to
Plato: MenoR I c ff. on karning as recollection); ibid. I. pr. 4, 18-21 (to Plato:
Rep. V. 47:k-d on the need for philosopher-kings); ibid. Ill, pr. 9. 99-10 I (to
Plato: Tim. 27b on the need to pray for divine assistance); ibid. Ill, pr. 12.
II 0-112 (to Plato: Tim. 29b on language and reality); and ibid. V. pr. 6, 31 ff.
(to Plato: Tim. 37d on the perpetuity of the cosmos). On the passages in this
work influenced by Plato see P. Courccllc: Lllte Latin W'rile1s and their
Greek Sources, translated by H. E. Wedeck (Cambridge. MA, 1969), pp.
296-297 and J. Gruber: Kommentar zu Boetbius De consolatione
philosophiae (Texte und Kommentare 9) (Berlin/New York. 1978), p. 36.
5. In the passages mentioned above Philosophy refers to 'our Plato' (Plato
noster), to 'Plato's decree' (Pia tone stmciente). and so on.
6. See Boethius: De Crmsol. Pbilos. III. pr. 8, 23 together with lamblichus:
Protr. H. 47. 13 (to Aristotle: Protr. on theeyesoflynceus); ibid. V. pr. I, 35
ff. (10 Ariswtle: Pbys. II. 4. 195b 31 ff. on the relation between causation and
chance); and ibid. V, pr. 6. 18-22 (10 Aristotle: De Caelo II, I, 2R3b26-3I on
the world's eternity). On the passages in this work influenced by Aristotlt: see
Courcclle: La Consolation de Philosophic dans Ia traditimz litteraire.
..tnttfnJdents et posttfrittf de H()ike, pp . .25-.26 and 1.2-i-125; :md Gruber: op.
cit., pp. 36-37.
7. At De Trill. pr. 31-32 Boethius asks the addressee: 'You should however
examine whether the seeds of argument from Saint Augustine's works have
horne any fruit in my writing' (Vobis tamen etiam illud inspiciendum est.
llll ex beati Augustin/ saiptis semiml rationum aliquos in nos l'enientia
fructus e.xtulerint).
BOETHillS
13. At this point it may be useful to list the general studies of Boethius' life
and thought during the last century. H. F. Stewart: Boethius. An Essay (Edin-
burgh. 1891 ); T. Venuti de Domenicis: Boezio I. Studio storico-filosofico, II.
De Consolatirme Philosophille (Grouaferrata, 1911-1912); M. Cappuyns:
'Bohe'. Dictiomwire ct'histoire et de geogmphie ecclesiastiques 9 ( 1937).
pp. 3-iH-.'180; M. Galdi: Saggi Boeziani (Pisa, 1938); H. M. Barrell: Boethius.
Some Asp(cts of bis Times ami Work (Cambridge. 1940); E. Rapisarda: La
aisi spiritua/e di Boezio (Firenze, 1947); G. Vann: The Wisdom of Boethius
(Oxford, 19'i2); H. Liebeschiitz: 'Boethius and the Legacy of Antiquity', The
Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medier,al Pbi/osophy, edited by
A. H. Armstrong (Cambridge. 1967). pp. 538-'i'i'i: C. Leonardi, L. Minio-
Paluello, lJ. Pizzani, e. P. Cournlle: 'Boezio', Dizionario biografico degli
italiani II (Roma, 1969). pp. 142-16'i; L. Oberrello: Severino Boezio 1-11
(Genov;t, 1974); F. <lastaldelli: Boezio (Roma, 1974); A. Crocco: Jntrodu-
zione a Boezio, secunda edizione (Napoli, 1975); and H. Chadwick:
Boetbius. Tbe Consolations of Music, Logic, Theology and Philosophy (Ox-
ford. 198 I). For general studies of the theological tractates see K. Bruder:
'Die philosophischen Elememe in den Opuscula sacra des Boethius. Ein
Beitrag zur Quellengcschichte der Philosophic der Scholastik'. Forschungen
zur Geschichte der Philosophie und der Piidagogik 312 (Leipzig, 1928): H.).
Brosch: Der Seinsbegriff bel Boetbius. mil besonderer Beriicksicbligung tier
Beziebtmg ron Sosein und Dasein (lnnsbruck, 1931); V. Schurr: Die
Triniliitslehre des Boethius im Lichte tier skythischen Kontroversen (Pader-
horn. 193'i): Schrimpf: op. cit .. pp. 1-36: I. Cramer-Riigenberg: Die
Substcmzmetaphysik des Boethius in den Opuscula sacra, Diss. (Koln, 1967);
M. Elsasser: Das Person-l'erstiincl1zis des Boethius, Diss (Wiirzburg, 197 3);
and B. Maioli: Teo ria de/l'essere e clell'esisten lee classificazione delle scienze
in .H. S. Boezio. lfna cle/ucidazicme (Siena, I 9 7 8). I' or general studies of De
Crmsolulione Pbilosophiae see F. Klingner: De Boetbii Consolatione
BOETH!l'S
St. Again the term 'intelligible' is employed for the objects rather than for
the subject of investigation. See the detailed discussion below.
S'i. To complete the symmetry of the scheme we would have 10 say that
the terms (i) intellectible and (iii) natural are also defined as signifying a) ob-
jects of investigation and b) subjects of investigation. However. it is obvious
that neither God nor n:uural bodies cngage in discursive reasoning since the
former is above it and the latter below.
662 NEOPLATONISM
the noetic to that intermediate between the noetic and the sensi-
bleY> Moreover, when he continues that 'they are therefore as
much subjects of intelligence as they are its objects, and they are
more blessed in the purity of intelligence the more they join
themselves to the intellectihles' - by which he means that the
object a) of division (ii) has now become a subject h) of division
(ii) in addition but can return to its original status - he is
repeating the further Neoplatonic doctrine that the human soul
acquires a duality of consciousness as it descends from the
noetic sphere hut can lose this once again as it reascends
thither5 .. Finally, the words 'the second substance- that ofthe
intelligibles - is rightly located in the middle, because it is
responsible both for the animating and to some extent the
vivification of bodies and for the investigation and knowledge
of intellectibles' repeat the idea that the object a) of division (ii)
also represents the subject b) capable of investigating the objects
a) of division (i).
The second fundamental question which this description of
the three branches of theoretical philosophy raises is that con-
cerning its relation to the similar tripartite analysis in the second
chapter of De Trinitate. ss Since the latter has been much more
formas cum materia, quae a corporibus actu separari non possunt, quae
corpora in motu stmt ut cum terra deorsum ignis sursum fertur, habetque
motum fonna materiae conitmcta). mathemcltlca, sine motu lnabstracta
(IJaec enim fonnas corpon1m speculatur sine materia ac per hoc sit1e motu,
quae formae cum In materia sint, ab his separari non possunt), theologlcll,
sine motu abstracta atque separabUis (nam dei substantia et materia et
motu caret)). For the interpretation of the many ambiguous formulae see
bdow.
<;lJ. Among the most important discussions in modern scholarship see).
~larictan: Problimze de Ia clllssificlltitm des sciences d'A,Istote il sctlnt-
11mmas (Valais. 190 I), pp. 63-76; Bruder: op. cit .. pp. 3-10; K. Kremer: Der
Metaphysikbegriff In det1 Aristoteles-Kommentllrell der Ammonius-Scbule
(Reitriige zur Geschichte der Pbi/osopbie und Tbeologie des Mittelalters
:Wil) (Munster, 1961), pp. 17-26;). A. Weishcipl: 'Classification of the
Scknces in Medieval Thought'. Medlet'al Studies 27 ( 1965 ). pp. 54-90; P.
Mc:rlan: From Platonism to Neoplatrmlsm, Third Edition (The Hague, 1968),
pp. !7-84; R. Mcinerny: 'Boethius and St. Thomas Aquinas'. Ritista dl
filo.mfiu neoscolastica 66 (1974). pp. 219-245; and Obertdlo: Se!'erino
Boezio 1, pp. 573-588.
60. Thus, the first part is concerned with both God and the human soul
(onc: part rel:ues to several objects), the human soul is studied in both the first
and second parts (one object relates to several parts). and so on.
66i ~EOPI.ATONISM
9.21 THEOLOGY
6<;. In the past. scholars have tended to paraphrase given Bocthian works
rather than synthesize the teachings which they contain. perhaps on the
a~sumption that there is no underlying philosophical consistency. Howc,er.
as a good example of the synthetic approach one might mention M. Baltes ar-
tkk: '(lott, Welt. Mensch in der Conso/atio pbllosopbiae des Boethius',
l'igilie~e Chrlstianae :H ( 1980), pp. 313-340.
66. i.e. in describing God from the viewpoint of our perception.
6'7. i.e. in describing Gud from thl" viewpoint of his l"Xistence.
6R. i.e. in describing God without specific reference to what he creates.
69. i.e. in desuibing God's transcendence in a general way.
-:>o. i.e. in describing God's transcendence in its specific modes.
NEOPI.ATONISM
11) atemporality
9) incorporeality
1) unified plurality
h) causal't
(I) defined as causar'2
a) form
~)mind
y) providence
2) having attributes of causality""3
a) omnipotence
~)activity
y)beneficence
B) volition
E) bestowal of being
~) bestowal of motion
11) bestowal of similarity
The presentation of Boethius' theological position in the form
of a synthesis has the advantage of demonstrating its overall
coherence, although we would be ill-advised to ignore totally
the different contexts in which the various constituent elements
originally appear. Our discussion will therefore begin by ex-
amining the separate contributions of the school writings, the
relevant theological tractates, and De Conso/atione
Philosopbiae to the evolution of the system as a whole.
79. = ii hI !3./bid. 1, 3. ' I'H6. Cf. ibid. 1, 3. 7. 19-20 where the study
of wisdom is defined as 'the study of divinity and the kinship with that pure
mind' (Situlium dil'initatis et purae mentis illi11s amicitia). By interpreting
wisdom a~ the illuminator of tht human intdktt in tht dau~e intervening
between these two quotations. Boethius shows that the mind with which that
wisdom is identified is the divine one and not the human.
HO. = ii;t29. Boethius:/n/sag. ed./1.1,10. 160.23-161.2.
HI. = i c. Bocthius: Conlm Eutycb. et ,Vest. I. 13-1 c;,
H.!. = ii :1 I a. /IJitl. ;\. 99-100.
H.~- = ii a.! E. Ibid. .!. 2-t-l'i. Cf. ibid. 6. 13-IL
BOETHIUS
99. = i a. Boethius: /J(' Ctm.wl. PIJi/(}S. \', pr. ~. 6-H. Cf. i/Jid. IV, pr. 6.
126-12"".
I 00. = i h. fiJi d. Ill, m. 9 . .23-H. This is the first of a number of passages in
this section taken from the important poem 0 qui perpetua. The poem
represents a summary of Plato's Timaeus and as such has attracted the atten-
tion of numerous commentators from mediaeval times onwards. The impor-
tance attached to 0 qui perpetua by its author is underlined by its central
position in the work as a whole.
101. = i c./bid. V. pr. 5. 'i0-53.
102. = ii a I a. Ibid. Ill, pr. 10, -i9-'i 1. At Ibid. V, pr. 6, 38-40 God is
declared to be prior to created things not in quantity of time but in simplicity
of nature.
103. = ii a JJ}.Ibid. Ill, pr. 10. 2'i-2"'. Cf. ibid. Ill. pr. 10. 'i7-58.
UOETHILIS
104. = ii a 2 a./bid. Ill, pr. 12, l'i-24. The argumem is repeated several
times in different language.
IO'i. = ii a 2 p.Jbid. Ill, pr. 9. 101-102. Cf. Ibid. Ill, m. 8, l'i; Ill, pr. 10,
23-25; and Ill, pr. 11,22-23 ('good' (bonus)); ibid. Ill. pr. 9. 91-93 ('the true
good' (t,erum bonum)); and ibid. Ill, m. 9, 23 ('the source of goodness' lfcms
boni)).
106. = ii a 2li.Jbid. Ill, m. 9, 7-8.
107. = ii a 2 &. Ibid. Ill, m. 9, 2-3. Cf. ibid. III, pr. 12, 102-108 'For such is
the form of the divine substance that it neilher extends to the external nor
receives anything external into itself. But as Parmenides says of it "On all
sides it is like the bulk of a well-rounded sphere", it rotates the moving
sphere of things while it preserves itself immobile' (E'a est enim ditintle for-
ma substantiae ut neque In exte1'1Ul dilabatur nee in se e:~:tenlUm aliquid
ipm suscipiat. sed, sicut de ea Pt1rme11ides ait: 7tciv-ro9&v &UKUKA.ou OqJaipTJc;
tvaA.iyKIOV {)yKqJ, rerum orbem mo/Jilem rot~lt, dum se immobilem ipsa nm-
sertat).
108. = ii a 2 fl./bid. V, pr. 6, 'i-11. Cf. Ibid. V, pr. 6, 25-31. At ibid. V, pr.
6, 35-38 a contrast is established: 'For it is one thing to enjoy an endless life.
which Plato attributes to the world. and another to embrace the entire
presence of an interminable life simultaneously, which is dearly the
NE< >PLATONISM
characu:ristic of the divine mind' (Aiiud est enim per intermi1labilem duci
titam, quod mtmdo Pifllo tribuit, a/iud intermbrabi/ls titcte totam pariter
cmnplexum esse praese111iam, quod dlti11ae mentis proprium esse
manifestum est). Cf. Ibid. V. pr. 6, 57-'59.
109. = ii a 2 1. JIJid. Ill. pr. 10, 142-144. Cf. Ibid. Ill, pr. 9, 41-49; Ill, pr.
10, 106-1 15: III. pr. I 0, 119-125; and Ill. pr. 10, 134-14 2.
I HI. = ii b I a. Ibid. V, pr. 4, 89-91. Cf. ibid. Ill, m, 9, 5-6 and Ill, pr. 10,
2('formofthegood'(bonifomra)):ibid. lll,pr.l2. 102-104('formofthe
divine suhstance' (ditoinqe forma substa11tiae)); and ibid. IV, pr. 6, '56-'58
('form of things to he accomplished' (gerendarumforma rerum)).
Ill.= ii hIp. Ibid. IV, pr. 6, 90-92. Cf. ibid. Ill, m. 9, 7-9: IV, pr. 6,
22-25; IV, pr. 6, 73-78: etc.
112. = ii b I y. Ibid. IV, pr. 6, 32-33. The theme of God's providence and
its relation to human free will is developed at length from this point onwards.
113. = ii b 2 a. Ibid. Ill, pr. 12.74-78. cr. ibid. IV. pr. 2, 121-123.
BOETHiliS
ble, IIH semi-intelligible, 119 supreme, 120 unity, Ill goodness, Ill
omnipotent, 123 beneficent, 124 bestowing being, 12'; motion, 126
EOpaiCJJV Kai J}&jlaiCJJV yiVOVtal). Cf. ibid. 29, 19, 7-8; 31, 22, 10-13; 33. 37.
14-15; and 35. 39, 19-21.
127. The One is described as the source of similarity at Plotinus: Emz. I. :
/S-4/ I. 11-19 'The Good must not look or aspire 10 another, hut stay quiet be-
ing the source or cause of natural activities and making other things like the
<iood' (O&i to ciya6ov 1.1~ npoc; ciA.Ao I}A.tnov l.lllO'tqntll&Vov ciHou tv ~alix.C!l
ouaav 1tl1Y~V Kai cipx_~v tv&py&IWV Kata cpl.imv ouaav Kai tO. ciA.A.a tiya6o&tOii
nmoiiaav ). Cf. ibid. IV, S /29/7. 17-20and V, 6/24/ S. 12-IS: Porphyry: In
Pann. III, 32-IV, 4; etc.
128. It should be stressed that the departures 10 be illuslr:ued below arc
from the sbaret/teaching of Plotinus and Porphyry. Thus. some will he con-
sistent with Porphyry bul not with Plotinus, while olhers will be consislenl
with ndthcr Porphyry nor Plotinus.
129. Bocthius' intellectibile is of course equivalent 10 the intelligible
(VOfltov) of the Ncoplatonk tradition. Sec Plotinus: Enn. V. S /32/ 6. 19-20
where <iod is 'beyond the imclligiblc' (tntK&tva toii VOfltOii) and /hit/. I. I
/'i3/ H. 9-11 where he is 'horne upon the intelligible' (tnox.olill&vov tfj VOfltU
IPUCJ&l).
UO. Porphyry: Ad Gaur. 12, SO. 21-22.
NEOPLATONISM
I:\ I. Porphyry: De Regr. Anim. fr. 10. ji 12-1 .'\. Of courst', that God is
intelligible implies that he is accessible to intellect for Plotinus, Porphyry,
;and Roethius.
132. Porphyry: In Parm. II, li- P.
13.~. Porphyry: se,t. 26, 1'5. 1-H. At ibid. 2'5. 1'5. 1-.f God is accessible 'to
non-intellection abo\'e intellection' (avol]aic;r KpEittovt voJ1aeroc;). On the in-
tl'llecti\'e approach to God in Porphyry and later Neoplatonism see]. M. Rist:
'Mysticism and Transcendence in Later Neoplatonism', Hermes 92 ( 1964),
pp. 213-22'5.
13-f. See Plotinus: Enn. VI, 7 /.:.HI 3'5. 1-'5 where the soul dismisst's intellec-
tion in order to see God e,en though it is by means of intellect that it has the
vision' (KaitOl vouc; YEV6J.lEVoc; atitl] 9eropei). Cf. Ibid. VI. 9/9/:\. 11-27.
135. On God as intelligible in Augustine see De Ord. II. 3. 8 (CCSL 29,
III-112);11,8,25(CCSL29,121);11,11,30(CCSL29,124);.'io///.I,I,2(Pl.
32. 869-870); I, 6, 13-8. 15 (PL .U, 876-877); De Mus. VI, 12, .'\6 (PL 32,
1183); De Mor. Ecc/. Cath. I, 12,20 (PL 32. 1320); and De Vera Relig. 55,
I U (CCSL 32. 259-260). For the significance of Augustinian parallels seep.
70'i.
BOETHil'S
1~6. Plotinus: Enn. I, 7/'i:f/1, 19.20; II, '11121 16, 2'i; III. 9/1;\/9, I; V. 4
!"'fl. 910: VI.: /.~R/'10, 262'7; and VI. K/39/19, 12-19.
I ~7. Compare the treatment by Calcidius discussed on pp. 440-442.
I :H~. Plotinus: Etm. V.; /~2/6, 'i-6.
lW.IIJitf. III, K/~0/10. 2K-;H.
140. IIJid. VI. 8/_>,9/ 11. 'H~.
680 NEOPI.ATONISM
l'il. Ibid. XII. 29-35. Cf. ibid. XII, 23-24 and XII, 26-27. Cf. also Por-
phyry: Sent. 26, I 5. 7-1 ;\.
I 'i2. Ibid. XI, 1-XIl. 35.
I 5.'\. /hid. XI. 'i-10.
154./bid. XII, 22-29.
155. Ibid. XI, 33-XII, 3. On Porphyry's transformations of being, ex-
istcnn:. and essence seeP. liadot: Porpbyre et Victorim1s, passim; 'L'ctrc et
l'etant dans le ncoplatonisme'. Etudes neoplatonicietmes, (Neuch:itel. 1973).
pp. 27-41 and 'Dieu commc acte d'ctrc dans lc: neoplatonismc. Apropos des
theories d'E. Gilson sur Ia metaphysique de I'Exode', Dier1 et /'etre. EYegeses
d Ex ode J, li et de Coran 20, 11-24, presentees par P. Vignaux (Paris. 1978).
pp. 57-63.
BOETHil~S
16l. Plotinus: t:nn. I, 6/1/6, 251, 6/1/7, 30. Cf. ibid. V, S /32/8, H-13
and V, 9/5/2, 1-9.
162. See ibid. I, 6/1/9,32-43: V, 5/32/12, 9-40; V, 8/31/8, 1-12; V, R
/31113, 11-12; etc.
16.'\. Ibid. VI, 71.'\H/ .U . .26-30. On heauty in Plotinus s~~ A. H. Armstrong:
Beauty and the Discovery of Divinity in the Thought of Plotinus'.
1\epbtt/aion. Studies in Greek Phi/mopby ami its Continuation offered to C.
.f. de Vogel, edited hy J. Mansfeld and 1.. M. de Rijk (Assen. 1975). pp.
155-163.
164. On God as heauty in Augustine sec Soli/. I. 15.27 (PL 32. 883-8H4):
De Mus. VI, J'7, 56 (PL 32 I 191 ); De Quant. Anim. 35. 79 (PL 32, I 0"'9); De
Vera Rllig. I 1. .2 I (CCSL 3.2, .200-.20 1): Conf IV, 16 (CSEL 3 3/1. HS-H8): and
Cit. Dei X, 16 (CCSI. 47, 21i9291 ). The last passage quotes Plotinus.
686 :'>IEOPLATONISM
that there are no more than three principles, he stresses that the
terms 'One' and 'Good' indicate different aspects of the first
hypostasis rather than a first and second hypostasis.l65
Elsewhere, he approaches the same question from another
viewpoint by arguing that the unity and the goodness derived
from the first principle by other things are identical, since all
things come into existence endowed with simultaneous tenden-
cies to both unity and goodness. 166 In all such passages, Plotinus
is careful to stress that God's plurality is strictly one of at-
tributes.
In the case of the second hypostasis or Intellect, we find a
plurality in a more genuine sense. although even here the unity
of the hypostasis makes the nature of its inherent plurality dif-
ficult to grasp. In some texts Plotinus speaks of Intellect as (i) a
plurality of constitutents whose nature is not further
specified. H' In most of these the writer stresses that 'each part
is the whole and in every respect all. Yet they are not confused
but still distinct' (oA.ov tE yap ottv ~Kaotov Kai nav-raxu ndv'
Kai OU OlJ"(KEXUtat, aA.A.a au xropic;). 168 Other passages refer to
Intellect as (ii a) a plurality of partial intellects.l69 The whole
and partial intellects interrelate in that 'the whole is all the par-
tials together in actuality but each of them separately in poten-
tiality, while the partials are what they are in actuality but the
whole in potentiality' (EvEpyEiQ ovtt ta nO.vta iiJ.la, ouv<iJ.lEl of:
EKaotov xropic;, toile; o'aO EVEpyEiQ J.lEV 0 ElOl, OUV<iJ.lEl OE tO
oA.ov).l7o In further texts Plotinus speaks of Intellect as (ii b) a
178. Plotinus: 1:'1111. V, 6 /}AI I. 21-2-i. Cf. ibid. Ill, 9 /1.~/ I. 12- H. On the:
One and Intellect as unified pluralities in Plotinus sec: R. Arnou: 'La separa-
tion par simple alteritt' dans Ia Tri11ite plotinienne'. Gregorimwm 2 ( 1930),
pp. IHI-193; A. H. Armstrong: "Eternity, life: and Movement in Plotinus' Ac-
counts of Nouc;'. Le Neoplatrmisme. pp. 67-76; J. M. Rist: "The: Prohlc:m of
Otherness in the: Enneads', ibid. pp. "'7-88; and A. Smith: 'Potentiality and
the: Problem of Plurality in the: lntc:lligibk World'. Neoplatonism and Early
Cb1isticm 7'/mugbt. Essays in lltmour of A. II. Armstmng, l'tlitc:d hy II. J.
Blumenthal and R. A. Markus (London, 1981 ). pp. 99-107.
179. Seep. 682 ff.
I HO. Sec: however nn. 167. 171. and 177. On God as unified plurality in
Augustine: sc:e the: following examples: (i) God as a unity of his attributes at De
Trin. V, H, 9-\'. 10. II (CCSL 50, 215-218}; VI, 3. 5-VI, -4, 6 (CCSI. 50,
233-235): VI. 6. 8-VI, 9. 10 (CCSL 50, 236-240); VI. 10, 12 (CCSL 50,
24 2-24 3 ); and VIII, I, 2-VIII. 3. 5 (CCSL 50, 269-27 4 ); (li) God as a unity con-
mining Forms or numbers at Soli/. I, 8, 15 (Pl. 32, 877); De Mus. VI. 4. 7 (PL
32 1166-1167); De Lib. Arb. II. II, .'\0-.~2 (CCSL 29, 258-259); De Dit.
Quaest. 46, 2 (CCSI. -l4A. 7 1-73); and De Trin. IV, I. 3 (CCSL 50. 162-163.)
BOETHil!S
185. See Plotinus: Enn. VI. 7 /38/17, 17-18; VI, 7 /38/ 28, 28-29; and VI, 7
/38132.9-10.
186. As we have argued above.
187. See Hierodes: In Aur. (.(lrm. I, 10, 2-21 and 20, 87. 19-89. 14.
188. See pp. 548-551.
I H9. This is the interpretation of I. Hadot: Le pmbli!me du mfoplatonisme
a/e.wuulrh1. 1/illmc/es et Simplicius (Paris, 1978), pp. 93-94 and 113-116
which supersedes all earlier views.
190. Sec p. 5.~0 ff. On God as form in Augustine see De Lib. Arb. II, 16,
44-17. 46 (CCSL 29, 267-268); De Vera Relig. 3. 3 (CCSL 32. 188-190); II. 21
(CCSJ. 32. 200-201); 18,35-36 (CCSL 32. 208-9); 31,58 (CCSL 32, 225-226);
-~6. 66 (CCSL 32. 230-231 ); and H. H 1-44, 82 (CCSL 32. 241 ).
BOETIHIIS 691
should be beyond Intellect' (Ei ouv vouc;, O't'l 1tOAUc; EO't'l, Kai TO
voeiv auto oiov 7tapEJ.17tEa6v, Kiiv t~ auwu 1), 7tA:n9uEt, cSEi to
7tUVHI a1tA.ouv Kai 7tpw-rov a1tavnov tmiKEwa vou Eivat).l9t 'If
there is a multiplicity, there must be a unity prior to the
multiplicity. And if there is a plurality in the intellective, there
must be no intellection in the non-plural. The latter is the first
principle' (Ei cipa 1toA.A.a -ri an, cSei 7tpo twv 1toA.A.rov fv Eivat. Ei
ouv -reT> voouvn 7tA.t;eoc;, 5Ei E.v -reT> lllt 7tA.iJ9Et to voEiv J.Lil Etvat. ,;v
8f: 'tOU'tO TO 7tpW'tOV).192
However, despite the fact that God lies beyond and is the
cause of Intellect proper, the former can be regarded as intellec-
tual in a special sense. In the first place, since it is the cause of
Intelkct, 'whatever is present in Intellect is present in a far
higher mode in that One' (oiov yap to tv veT>, 1toA.A.axu J.LEi(,ov ii
totoutov to f.v ~vi EKEivq>)193; and secondly, since ignorance re-
quires a relation to something external, 'that which is alone
neither knows nor has anything of which to be ignorant' (to <Sf:
J.LOVOV OU'tE ytyvcboKEl, OU'tE 't'l EXEl 0 ayvoEi).191 Furthermore,
this special variety of intellection- which he now calls 'quasi-
intellect' (oiov vouc;) t9S or 'super-intellection (\mEpv6nmc;) t96
- can be characterized more precisely as an activity without a
determinate subject. Thus, the highest can be considered 'not as
something having intellection hut rather as intellection' (ou yap
Kat a TOV VOOUVTU ... a:\A.a J.LciAAOV KU'ta 'tltV VOT\01V),19' or alter-
natively as 'like an awakening which is not of something being
198. Ibid. VI, 8 /39/ 16, 3 1-32. On the notion of intellect in Plot in us sec R.
Arnou: 'L'acte de !'intelligence en tam qu'elle n'est pas intelligence. Quelque
considerations sur Ia nature de !'intelligence selon Plot in', Mekmges ].
Marechalll (Paris, 1950), pp. 249-262;). Pepin: 'Elements pour unc histoire
de Ia relation entre l'intelligcncc ct l'intclligiblc chez Platon ct dans lc
neoplatonisme', Ret'lle pbilosopbique R 1 ( 1956). pp. 39-64; and A. H. Arm-
strong: 'Thc B;u:kground of thc Donrinc "That thl lntclligihlcs art: not Out-
sidl' the lntdkct'' , l.es sources de Plotin (Frmdation Hardt. Enlretiens sur
/'Ani/quite c/assique <;) (Vandocuvres-Gcnevc, 1960), pp. 393-42<;.
199. Sec Boethius: In /sag. ed. I. I. 3. 7. 15-16; De Cm1sol. Pbi/os. Ill, m,
9. 7-9: IV. pr. 6. 22-25: IV. pr. 6, 73-78; etc. Bocthius follows the Latin
Ncoplatonil' tradition in rendering vouc; as mens.
200. On this question sec also the discussion ofheing on pp. 679-684.
201. Porphrry: In p,,,.,,, XIII, 20-2:-\. Cf. Sent. 25. IS, l-2; In Tim. fr. 51
(Proclus: In Tim. l, 394, R-9). On Porphyry's transformation of the notion of
IJOETHillS
intellect see P. Hadot: 'Etre, vie, pensee chez Plotin et a\ant Plotin'. l.es
sources de Ploti11 (Fondation Hardt, Entretiens sur I'Antiquite c/assique 5)
(Vandoeuvres-Geneve, 1960) pp. 105-141; 'La metaphysique de Porphyre'.
Porpb_)'re (Fonda lion Hardt, Elllretiens sur f"A11tiquite c/assique 121
(Vandoeuvres-Geneve. 1966). pp. 125-163; and Porpbyre et Victorinus,
passim.
202. Porphyry: In Pann. V. 8-9.
205. Porphyry: Sent. 10, 4. 7.
20-l. Porphyry: In Pann. V. 10-11. Cf. ibid. V. 15-15; V. 25-2-l; and V.
2/i-29.
205./hid. Vl,8-lO.Cf.ibid. VJ.I0-12andXIV.I-4.
206. Ibid. IX. 3-5.
207./hid. IX, 3. Cf. DeRegr. Anim. fr. 7, 35" 27-29; fr. R. 36" 15-37" S;
and fr. 9. 37" 7-9.
NEOPLATONISM
20H. Porphyry: In Parm. XIV. 7-R. Cf. ibid. XIII, 1-9 and XIII, 34-XIV, 4.
209. Ibid. XIV. 10-26.
210. On God as mind in Augustine see Contra Acad. Ill. 19, 42 (CCSL 29,
60): De Ord. II, 5. 16 (CCSL 29. 115-116); II, 9. 26 (CCSL 29, 12 1-122); De
Dit. Quaest. 46, 2 (CCSL 44, 71-7 3 ). It seems that from a relatively early date
in his career Augustine replaced the Neoplatonic intellectuslintellegentia
with the more Scriptural sapietllia. See Soli/. I, 1, 2-3 (PL 32, 869-871); De
Quant. Anim. 3L 77 (PL 32. 1077-1078): De Mor. Eccl. Catb. I, 7, II (Pl. 32.
1.-\15 ): De Doctr. Christ. I. R. 8 (CCSL 32. II) and innumerable later passages.
2 I I. See Plot in us: Enn. V, 3 /-t9/ 12, 2H-31. Plotinus seems to have
transferred such a function from the first principle to the Logos, a hypostasis
which takes over many of Soul's functions in certain late treatises. See ibid.
Ill, 3 /48/ I, 1-2, 15: Ill, 3 /4H/ 4. 6-13; Ill, 3 /-18/ 5, li -20; and VI, 8 /39/ 17.
1-9.
HOETHIUS 695
212. Proclus: /em. Then/. 106, 5-7. Cf. ibid. 104, 31. 31 ff.; 108, 1-24:
IIH, 20-.U: 124. 19-26; and 176, Iff.
213. Prod us: De Prmid. et Fa to 7, 10-12. Cf. Prod us: Theol. Plat. I, 69
ff.: De Decem Dubit. I, 2 ff.; etc. On Proclus' doctrine here see W. Beier-
waites: Pnmoia und Freiheit in der Philosoph it: des Proklos'. Freiburger
/.eitscbrift fiir Pbllosnphie tmd Tbeologie 24 ( 1977) pp. HHII I.
2 1-l. On God as providence in Augustine see De Ord. I, I. I, (CCSl29, 89):
II. I, II (CCSl 29, 113): II, 5. 15 (CCSI. 29. 115 ); De Mus. VI, II, 30-33 (Pl.
.U. 11"'9-IIHI); VI, 17,56 (Pl. 32. 1191): De Lib. Arb. I. 6, 14 (CCSI. 29.
219); II. 17.45 (CCSl29, 267-268): II, 19, 5,'\ (CCSI. 29. 272): DeMor. Eccl.
Catb. I. 7, 12 (Pl 32. 1315-1316): De Vera Rellg. 25, 46 (CCSl 32. 216): De
Doctr. Christ. I, 35. 39 (CCSL 32, 28-29); etc.
696 :'IIEOPI.ATONISM
.ZI 5. Plminus: Enn. VI. 7 I !I'd! .fO. 22-2-i. Cf. ibicl. VI. 7 /38/ 17. 9-1 I. The
same doctrine Ol"Curs at Porphyry: In Parm. I. .U-11. 2 and XII. 23-25.
216. Plotinus: Enn. V. -f 17 I 2, 28-;\ I. Cf. iiJicl. IV, c; /29/ 7, I !t-23 and V, I
I 10/ 3. 6-12. On the two kinds of activity in Plotinus sec C. Rutten: 'La doc-
trine des deux actcs dans Ia philosophic de Plot in', Rerzw pbllosophique Rl
(1956)pp. 100-106.
217. Plotinus: Emr. V. c; /32/ !1. 21-2i: VI, H !WI"" . .f6-i.f: VI, H /39/ 13.
5-7: and VI. H /39/ 16, 2-l-26.
218./bid. \',6/2-l/6, 1-8.
219. lbicl. VI. H /39/ 20, 9-1 I. The same doctrinl' occurs at Porphyry: In
Parm. XIII. 9-13 and XIV, 21-2!1.
BOETHiliS
ibid. 8 ( 1933), pp. 41-51; 'Necessity in Bocthius and the Neoplatonists', ibid.
I 0 ( 1935 ), pp. 39.-\-404; Galdi: op. cit., pp. 131-148; Courcelle: late Latin
Writers cmd their Greek Sources, pp ..-\01-307; C. J. de Vogel: 'Amor quo
caelum regitt~r', Vimrittm I ( 1963). pp. 2-Yt; W. Theiler: 'Antike und
christlkher Riickkehr zu Gott'. Mttlltts, Festschrift Tbeodor Klauser
(Munster. 1964 ). pp. 352-361; Courcclle: La Consolation de Philosophic
dans fa tradition littemire. Antecedents et posterite de Boece, pp. 163-168,
20.-\ ff.; Scheible: op. cit., pp. 101-112; Obertcllo: op. dt .. pp. 508-521;
Gruber: op. cit., pp. 277-290. 355 ff.; Chadwick: op. cit., pp. 20 and 129;
and C. J. de Vogel: 'Am or quo coelum regitur. Qud amour et que I dicu?', A ttl
del Congresso btterne~zionale di Studi Boeziani (Pavie~, 5-8 ottobre 1980), a
cura di L. Obcrtello (Roma. 1981). pp. 193-200. We cannot enter here into
the question whether Boethius acquired his knowledge of Proclus through an
intermediary like Ammonius Hermciou or some other Alexandrian commen-
tator. The extremely inconclusive results of the scholarship on this question
are reviewed by Obertello: op. cit .. pp. 540-544.
2-15. The most striking parallel is between Produs: Itt Tim. l, 378, 18 roc;
yap it aya90&l5i)c; aip&cnc; tauti;c; yiyv&TQl Kapn6c;, OUTroc; it J.lOX9TJpci tauti;c;
7tOlVll and Boethius: De Consol. Philos. IV, pr. 3, 36 Siwt igitur probis pro-
bitas ipsa fit praemium, ita improbis nequitia ipsa suppllc:ium est. This
was discovered by W. Theiler: Porpbyrios tmd Augustitt (Halle, 1933). p. 31.
There is a slightly looser parallel between Produs: In Pc1nn. 1056. 11-13 d
J.LEV EOTI 7tp6vota, 7tQVTQ 6p9ci>c; f~El Tel 5vta' Ei eSt llll EOT17tp6vota, OU5V f~El
Kal..cl>c; and Bocthius: De Cottsol. Pbi/os. I, pr. 4, I 05-106 Si quidem deus, in-
quit, est, unde malt1? Bona tero unde. si 11011 est? On this passage see Chad-
wick: op. c:it., p. 129.
2-f6. For example. the termporisma at Bocthius: De Consol. Phi/os. III, pr.
10. 92 and the phrase in Timaei cosmopoeia at De Aritbm. ll. 46, 149. 22.
both of which seem Prodinc. Sec Courcelle: La Consolation de Philosophic
dans le1 traditionlitteraire. A11tecedeuts et posterite de Boece. p. 167.
2'1"'. For example. the quotations of Parmenidcs: fr. 8. 43 navto9&v
EUKUKA.ou mpaipn.; tval..iyKlOV 5yKq> at Boethius: De Consol. Pbilos. Ill, pr.
12. 106 ;md of Orac. Clmld. fr. 9H avcSpoc; St'J l&pou 5tj.la~ ai9tpec;
oiKo56J.LTJOav at Boethius: De Consol. Philos. IV, pr. 6. 145 are dose to
similar ones in Proclus. See Courcclk: late Ltllin Writers m1d their Greek
Sources, pp. 30.-\-3<H.
BOETHil 'S
2iH. The most important of these liter:1ry forms is the hymn 10 the divinity
which is represented by \'arious examples in Produs works and by Boethius:
/Je Omso/. Phifos. Ill. m. 9. A feature of both writers' hymns is a penchtmt
for triadil' structure in whil'h :mdent literary procedures are adapted to thc-
rt:quirements of Neoplatonic metaphysics. On this question see Klingner: op.
cit .. p. ;\H ff. and Theilt:r: 'Ant ike und christliche Riickkehr zu Gott', pp.
_'\;2-.~61.
219. Boethius: De Consol. Pbifos. II. m. H. The respe-ctive doctrines are
discu~sed by dl Vogel: 'Am or quo caefum regitur'. pp. 2-.H.
2;0. !fJid. Ill. m. l). See the discussions of Klingner: op. cit .. p. 3H ff. and
Courcclk: /.a Consolation de Philosophic clans Itt traditiml litteraire .
.lnten!clellts et posterite de Boece. pp. 163-164 and I 17.
25 I Ibid. IV, pr. 6. The respective doctrines are discussed by Patch: 'Fate
in Boethius and the Neoplatonists'. pp. 62-72 and Courcellc: Late Latin
\l"rilers mul their Greek Sources, pp. 302 30L
252. !fJid. V. pr. -i. See the discussion of Obertello: Seterino Boezio I. p.
; 1.~ ff.
.!55. On the first question sec H. D. Saffrcy ct L. G. Wt:stcrink: Proc/us.
Thc.'ologie platonicicnne. Li1re /, texte etah/i et traduit par fl. D. S. et L. G.
II". (Paris. 196H), pp. l\'lxxxix: on the second, W. Beicrwaltcs: Pmklos,
Grwulziige seiner Metaphysik, 2. Autlage (Frankfurt, a. M. 1979). pp. 50-60;
onrhc third. E. R. Dodds: Procfus, The Elements of Theology. A Re1ised Te:~:t
uitb Translation, lntroductitm ami Commentm)'. Second Edition (Oxford,
iO-t NEOI'I.ATONISM
1963 ), p. 2"57 ff.: and on the fourth, S. Gersh: From lamb/ichus to Eriugena.
An lnl'estigation of the Prehistory and Et,olution of tbe Pseudo-Dionysian
Tradition (Studien zur Problemgescbicbte det an liken und mittela/terlichen
Phi/osopbie 8) (leiden. 19i 8 ), pp. IH-1 "5 I.
25-i. Seen. 246. The term n6ptOIJ.a could equally have been derived from
Hierodes: In Aur. Cann. 23. 96. 14 or from various mathematical writers;
the terms KOOIJ.Oltmia I KOOIJ.OltOt6<; from Aristotle: Metaph. A. 4. 98"5al9;
Actius: Plm:. I. 25, 3. 321a9 and h9; and ps.-lamblichus: Tbeol. Arithm. 43,
5 ..... 2 I.
2"55. Sec n. 247. Boethius could also ha\'t." found the quot:ltion from
Parmenidcs in Plato: Sopb. 2-t'!e - sec 1-1. Diels und W. Kranz: Die
Fragmente tier Vorsokratiker. Griechisch unci Deutsch ton H. D.,
herausgegeben von W. K., 12. Aufage, I (l>uhlin/Ziirich. 1966), pp. 2.H-23i
-and the Cb,llclae'm Oracle presumably in Porphyry's commentary.
2"i6. Seen. 248. The similarity of literary form betwen Bocthius: De Con-
sol. Pbi/os. Ill. m. 9 and \'arious hymns of Prod us can easily be explained on
the assumption that both arc following the ancient classical as opposed 10 the
more modern Christian forms.
2"57. Sec n. 249. The doctrine of cosmic love could e4ually have been
derin:d from Plato's reminiscences of Empedoclt:s at Gorg "508a :md Tim.
32c or from a Stoic or eclectic reworking of his theory. Similar ideas also oc-
cur in Philo and the Hermetic Asclepius.
2';8. See n. 2SO. Although Boethius' God and Produs' Demiurge have
many similarities in their respective modes of causality. the latter can all he
explained in terms of their <:ommon dependem:e upon Plato's Ti,weus and
the accepted traditions of its exegesis. Thus. nothing definite can he conclud-
ed from the references 10 God's la,k of envy. the presence of the paradigm in
his mind. and so on.
BOETHHIS 70S
their results;ZS9 and even the arguments about (i) the presence of
several parallel textsZ6o and the agreement of doctrine concern-
ing c) the relation of providence and fate are not totally con-
clusive,26t In short, we may admit that the references to post-
Porphyrian Neoplatonists in Boethius' logical writings indicate
some use of these late ancient sources on this topic, and that the
textual and doctrinal agreements with Proclus in De Conso/a-
tione Philosophiae suggest that its author had some knowledge
of the later Neoplatonists' theology. However, it is clearly a
mistake to emphasize these doctrinal affiliations in preference
to the more obvious one with the Plotinian and Porphyrian
traditions.
259. See n. 252. The doctrine of the levels of human cognition could
equally have been derived from Aristotle: De Anim. Ill, .3. 427b7-26,
although the more systematic presentation may reflect the traditions of later
<:ommentary. Such Aristotelian hierarchies are frequent enough in l'lotinus
and Porphyry.
260. Seen. 215. The two Procline texts ;tre extremely short and have tht
character of maxims. They could presumably have reappeared in any stt of
glosses stemming from the Athenian or Alexandrian :'lleoplatonic schools
which Boethius might have found attached w one of the ':lassie philosophical
texts.
261. Seen. 251. This is the only point at which a connection between Pro
clus and Boethius is virtually established. The present author has therefore
accepted the Procline character of Boethius' doctrine of providence. See pp.
69-i-695.
706 NEOPI.ATONISM
262. This influence h:1s been ably documented b}' P. Henry: Plotln et /'Oc-
cident. Firmicus Matenzus, Marius Victorinus, saint Augustin et ,uacrobe
(Lou\"ain, 19.:\4) and Courcc:llt': Lllte Latin Wrif(rs ami their Greek Sources,
pp. 26--i7, 71-78. 165-196, 208-223, 238-251, and 295-318. Interestingly,
Hc:nry did not notice the reference to Plotinus at Boethius: De Dhis. (PL 64,
~F5D-8768).
263. The Latin text has already been given inn. 7. For various viewpoints
on the influence of Augustine over Boethius see G. Boissic:r: 'Le christianisme
de Boece'. journal des Savants ( 1889), pp. 449-462; R. Carton: 'Le chris-
tianisme et l'augustinisme de Boece'. Melanges augusllniens (Paris, 19 31 ),
pp. 243-329; E. T. Silk: 'Boethius' Consolatio Phi/osophiae as a Sequel to
Augustine's Dialogues and So/lloquia', Harvard Theological Rer,iew 32
( 1939). pp. 19-W: Courcelle: La Consolation de Philosophic: dans Ia tradi-
tion littemire. Antecedents et posterite de Boece, pp. 168-176: Obertello:
Seterbw Boezio I. pp. 270-275: and Chadwick: op. cit .. pp. 249-250. The
debate has often been focused mistakenly on the search for parallel texts
rather than underlying structures of thought.
26-i. E\"idc:ncc indicating the \"alidity of these hypotheses can be found by
HOETHil 'S 707
9.12 PSYCHOLOGY
l'X;unining the:: Augustinian parallels already assc::mhlc::d in nn. 13;, 160, 16L
I HO. 1l)O, 210, 2 H. 221. 227. and 23.3.
26S. For the classification sec pp. 658-664.
2(l6. Boethius: Contra Eut)'Ch. et Nest. 2, 24-28; 6, 70-74; and De Como/.
Philos. Ill, m. 9. 18-21 (soul and God): Boethius: In/sag. ed. If. I. 10, 160.
23-161. 2 and De Cmzso/. Philos. Ill, pr. 11. 31-34 (soul and body).
26~. Bucthius: De Consul. Pbilos. \'. pr. 2. 16-lO.
NH>PI.ATONIS~I
Do;. Bocthius: De Omso/. Pbi/os. V, pr. -1. "'1-1.20 and V, pr. 1, 12-lfl.
n6. Boethius: lnlsttg. ed. I, I. 10, .2-l, 18-.2'5, I; I, 10 . .21. 6-8; .2, 12. IOH .
.~fl; and In /sag. ed. 1/, I, I. 13 7. 8-16. At In lsttg. ed. I. I, 3, 8, 1.~-16 and In
l.~ttg. etl. II. l, 10. 160, :\-10 i11tel/ectus is employed in tht same sense.
r-. Boethius: De Consol. Pbilos. V. pr. 4. 7'5-1.20.
2-H. /hid. II, pr. 'i. "'2-7H.
2-'J. Ibid. Ill, pr. 10. HH-90.
710 NEOPLATONISM
280. Ibid. Ill, pr. 9. 10-13. Cf. ibid. Ill, pr. 9, 45-49. For the analogous at-
tribute of God see pp. 666-675.
281. Ibid. ll, pr. 5. 70-72. Cf. ibid. IV, pr. 3. 25-28. For the analogous at-
tribute of God see pp. 666-675.
282. Boethius: Crmtra E'utycb. et Nest. 2, 23-28. Cf. ibid. 6, 6682. For the
analogous attribute of God see pp. 666-675.
283. Boethius: De Crmsol. Philos. If. pr. 4, 91-97. Cf. ibid. If. pr. 7. 79-85
and IV. pr, 4. 20-.2'5. The analogous attribute of God is atemporality- see
pp. 666-67'5- yet clearly the human soul has a temporal activity.
284. Boethius: /n /sag. ed. I. I, 10, 29, 22-30, 4. Cf. In De Interpr. ed. /1,
6, 13, 459, 2-3. Forrhe analogous anribute of God see pp. 666-675.
285. Boethius: De Crmso/. Phi/os. Ill. pr. 9, 80-86. Cf. ibid. If. pr. 4,
.,. 2- I 0 I. etc.
BOETHilrs 711
2H(l, /hid. IV. pr. 6. 6~- .. H. Cf. iiJid. \'. pr. 2, 11-2"'.
2H". See pp. 579-582 and 587-589 for a discussion of the same question in
:\lacrohius.
1HH. Sec hclow.
2HlJ. l'seful commentaries on this hymn are pro\'ided hy Sthl'ihlc: op. cit ..
pp. I 01-112 :tnd Gruhcr: op. cit .. pp . .2-:'7-290 who summarize a quantity of
carlic:r scholarship. My remarks hclow arc indehted to this scholarship.
although they will lay less emphasis upon the doctrinal paralll'ls with Pro-
clu~.
N EOPLATON ISM
299. Omc. Cba/d. fr. 18. This paternal depth corresponds to the 'twice
ht:yund' (Ol~ EnEKEtva) or Demiurgic intellect of ibid. fr. 169 .
.~00. For the Porphyrian interpretation of the Cbe~ldaean Oracles see p.
608 :md ch. 8, n. 18.
50 I. Boethius: De Como/. Pbilos. Ill. m. 9. 18-ll .
.~02. Sc:e Pl:uo: Tim. 41 d .
.~0:~. Sc:c ibid. -i te 'having mounted them as if in a chariot' (EI-If3tf3aaa~ <i>~
Et; OXTII.lU) .
.~!H. Sc:e ibid. -l2d.
50'i. Sec: Porphyry: Sent. 2.~. 14, 1--i, etc .
.\06. For the: doctrine in the Che~/d(leml Oracles, Porphyry. and Martianus
Capella seep. 629 ff .
.~o-. Sc:e Porphyry: De ReRr. Anim. fr. 2. z,. 2:~-2f, c:tc .
.~08. Syncsius: Hymn. l, 377; 595. The dependence of Synesius'
71..f NEOPLATONISM
psychology upon Porphyry has been noted on p. 635 and ch. 8, n. 178.
309. Seep. 71 I ff.
310. Bocthius: ln/s(lg ed. I, I. 3. 9. 2-6.
311: Bocthius: De Cmtso/. Philos. IV. pr. 4, 149-154: V. pr. 2. 20-27: and
V. m. 3. H-10.
312./bitl. IV. pr. I, 24-31: IV. pr. 2. 38-42; and IV, pr. 2, 113-119.
31."1. Bocthius: DeArithm. I, I. 9, 28-10. I; De Crmso/. Ph/los. Ill, pr. 2.
2-5;11l,m.II.I-16:1V,m.l, l-30;etc.
314. See Macrobius' doctrine examined on pp. 571-595.
HOETHiliS 71';
this manhood is described using language normally applied to God - see nn.
98 and II 0: this equation being possible because the divine form is a unity in
plurality of the kind described earlier in this chapter .
.HH. Boethius: In lst~g. ed. I. I. 10, 24. 1~-2<;, II.
.~19. Boethius: De Consol. Pbilos. V, pr. 1. 92-120. This passa~-:e also ap-
plies a further important epistemological principle: that it is the subject
rather than the object which determines the n;lture of a perception. Cf. Ibid.
V, pr. -i, "12-7!.
BOETHiliS ""17
.UO. Ibid. V, m . .f. 35-40. The mentis !!igor strictly corresponds to the
third faculty described in the passages wnsidered earlier - it is responsible
for the collection and division of concepts associated with discursive reason
- although it is probably intended as loosely equivalent to the third and
fourth faculties combined. Cf. ibid. V, pr. 'i, 1-10.
3 21. See the discussion in my article 'Realism, Dictiot~a rJ' of tbe Middle
Ages 6 (New York, forthcoming) .
.U.2. This system operates in terms of an immanent Form. a paradigmatic
Form. and the Demiurge and is described in p:tssages such as Bocthius: De
Aritbm. I. I. 10. 10-28 and De Como/. Philos. lll, m. 9. 5-9.
3.23. See Bocthius: In /sag. ed. I. I. 10 . .26. 15-25; De Triu. I, .25-30 and 2.
-lltR.
"71H NEO PLAT< >:-.I ISM
32-i. This system operates in terms of the material, formal, tlnal and effi-
cient causes and is described in texts such as Boethius: In /sag. ed. II, 2, 3.
17L 14- Hi; In Cic. Top. V, ll.fiD-1146A; and De Top. Diff ll. 1188A-H.
32i. See Boethius: hllsag. ed. II. I. 10. 161. 14-162, 3: Contra Eutych. et
Nest. 2 ..P-i2; 3. 29-i7; and t. 106-109.
326. Sec my discussion of Syrianus and Produs in From lmnblichus to
Eriugena. An flwestigation of the Prehistory am/ ENJiutirm of tbe Pseudo-
Dionysian Tradition. p. 86 ff.
327. llniversals of manufactured objects, ethically negative things. and
composite objects do not correspond to transcendent absolutes .
.UH. Transcendent absolutes of cthicallr positive things do not correspond
to transcendent Forms.
329. Sc:c: p. 647 ff.
Excursus D
Marius Victorious'
Commentarius in Ciceronis Rhetoricam
..,.,9
720 NEOPLATONISM
2. P. H:u.lot: ,Uarius Victol'inus. Rechel'cbes sur Stl 1ie et S'S oeu,.,es (Paris.
)l)i(),pp. -.~101 .
.~. Tht:rt' art: also discussions of thl' tln c:llt:gorit:s and of tht: syllogism
which :tre ofsornt: intt:rt:sl. St:t: Hadot: o{J. cit .. pp. 92-99.
MAR ILlS VICTORINliS
4. Marius Victorinus: In Cic. Rhet. l, 21 '), 23-39 Haec ratio est, ut diffici/is
sit naturae definilio; etenim aput sapientes cnntenlio est, quid prius sit,
deus an natura. Si natura prior est, ergo deus natus est: atqui deus twsci
non potuit. Rursus, si deus prior est. nata est natura: quod si nasci potu it
natura, incipit non esse natura. ltaque naturae difficilis de/initio est. 'Dif-
fici/is' inquit; alioquin ostendit posse definiri. Denique sapientes quidam
sic definlere naturam: natura est ignis artifex quadam zia vadens in res
sensiblles procreandas; etenim manifestum est mmria principe igne
generarl. Plato autem sic defitzivit: natura est del volrmtas. Et inter ceteras
IJaec magis probanda definitio; nam si deus et natura ita sutzt, ut ex IJis
alterum prius non sit (necesse est autem ex primo nasci, quod secundum
est, deinde si quod nascitur nee deus est nee natura), recte naturam del dix-
it esse voluntatem: deus enim semper roluerit et relit necesse est. Ita
quoniam nasci natura tzon potuit, si dei voluntas est. ut deus nasci non
fmtuit, nee natura. 11/ud autem scire debemus, naturam illud esse quod
mundum, ultra mundum naturf:ltll mm esse. sed deum: toluntatem cmtem
dei. qua mundus est. eandem esse twturam. The text is in C. Halm: Rbetores
Latini minores, ex codicibus ma..Yimam partem primum adiJibitis, emetr-
dclbat C. H. (Leipzig. 186.'\l.
5. This comprises the first and last sections of the prcscm passage.
6. Victorinus will later repeat this doctrine with much further elaboration
in his Trinitarian writings. Cf. Adt. Ar. I. 49, 39-40 where the Om: 'is
through an ineffable power and in a pure manner all things which truly are'
722 NF.OPLA TONISM
(inenarrabili potentia pure exsistens omnia quae vere sunt) and ibid. l, 49,
13-14 where it is 'before all existence, before all existentiality, and absolutely
before all inferiors' (ante omnem exsistentiam, ante omnem exslsten-
tialitatem et maxime ante omnia infer/ora).
i. This comprises the middle section of the present passage.
H. Hadot: op. cit .. pp. HH-91 demonstrates this syncretism by comparing
two passages: Seneca: Nat. Quaest. II. 15. 23 where 'nature' (natura) is
equated with 'providence' (pror,identia) and ps.-Piutarch: De Fato 9, 572 f
where 'providence' (np6vma) is equated with 'God's will' (9EOU ... ~oUA.llal<;).
To the Latin parallel to this syncretism which Hadot adduces from Calcidius:
In Tim. IH. 1!:13. 6-10 should be added those at Asclep. B. 305, 12-15 and
Firmicus Matern us: Math. V, pr. 3. See my discussions on pp. 345-348 and
7:\0.
9. Marius Vktorinus: In Cic. Rhet. I. 211. 25-30 VOv Graeci substantiae et
uccldenti genus ponrmt, sed mm bene; pars enim omnis generi suo simi/is
esse debet. Substantia porro res est, quae a/ils rebus subest capax acciden-
MARILIS VI\.TORINUS
timn qua/ita tum: deinde accidens est id, quod in substantiam cadit. Quare,
qucmiam illud superius ov utrumque esse non potest, non recte substantiae
et accidenti genus factum est.
Ill. Ibid. I. 22H. 29-34 Aristoteles 'opposita' genus posuit, 'ccmtrarium.
dispamtum. ad aliquld' sub oppositis. Cotllrarium porro Aristote/es sic
definitit: 'suiJ eodem genere species multum inter se dit,ersae ', hac ratione,
ut cmmia ad unum il/ud genus referantur. quod supra omnes res principtlle
Gmeci pcmrmt. id est ov. quod Latini 'ens t'ocant, id est, quod esse possit.
I I. See Hadot: op. cit. pp. 9'i-98 and Porph_vre et Victoritrus I (Paris.
1968). pp. 249-2'i3.
724 NE<>Pl.ATONISM
12. Marius Victorious: In Cic. Rhet. I. 155. 28 - 156 . .j Virtus est animi
habitus, in naturae modum rationi cmzsentaneus, et ideo in naturae
modum; duobus enim constamus, anima et corpore. Animll inmortalis est.
Si imnortalis est, a ditinis descendit: si a divinis descendit. perfecta est. Sed
acies quamtis perfectae an/mae qurulam corporis crasso tegmine inretitur
et drcumftmditur. et ita fit, ut quandam oblivionem sui capiat. Cum vero
studio m: disCJjJlina teluti detegi coeperit atque nudari. tunc in naturae
suae modum animi baiJitus rerertitur atque ret,ocatur. Hanc virtutem
Plato dicit nunc arte fieri, nunc cum hominihus nasci. maze exenitatione
cmifici, nunc a deo dari.
13. Ibid. I. 160. 15-li lft supra diximus. Clitmt philosopbi e dtwbus
hominem ccmstare, anima et corpore. An imam tero esse petfectam, sed in-
pediri crassituditze corporis, quo minus se talem exserat, qua/is est per
twturam. Ergo mundo conslituto emnt homines nimis inpedlti corpore, et
in quilms tis animae obruta atque oppressa esset. Tunc necessaria rapto
MARJliS VICTORINliS
c. 'The soul is like wine. Just as wine either retains or loses its
strength depending upon the vessel in which it is kept. so does
the soul preserve its nature if it meets with a good and chaste
hody but loses it if the opposite is the case. Thus, when the mor-
tal race wandered in stupidity and ignorance of all things. a cer-
tain great man appeared. His soul preserved its nature and he
perceived that all men had something divine within themselves,
that this was oppressed and ruined by the vices of the body. but
that it could produce the greatest benefits for mankind if it
could be brought out' .14
Three remarks are required in connection with passage 3 a.
First. the wording of Cicero's definition which has been inter-
polated here from a later passage of De lnventione is slightly
changed. I'; Secondly and more importantly, the argument as a
whole shows that the original notion that virtue is conformity
to nature in the sense of an immanent logos is transformed by
Victorinus into the notion that virtue is conformity to nature in-
terpreted as the transcendent status of the soul.t6 Third, the
reference to Plato can be identified as a loose paraphrase of cer-
titelumt et malls moribus, uppresso an/mae bono, circa res omnes tlrilms
corporis abutebantur. Sed quia natura nun aequaliter se per omnes ju11dil.
alicJucmdo tmus extitit, qui se bene inte/legeret et qui t1ideret esse in
lmmi11ibus animam il/am divbzam, qut~e /)(lberel in se mu/tt1s utililt~les, si
tamen posset ab aliquo e /atebris quibusdam elici atque proferri.
I -i. Ibid. I. I 61. I 2-20 Anima ita est ut vin um. Nmn, quemadmudum
tinum pro vase, in quo est habitmn, aut retinet aut amittit vio/enliam,
{Jmimle a11ima, si optimum et c:astmn corpus offemleril. serrat 11atumm.
sin alias, telut amittlt. Ita ergo c:um mortale genus bruttlm atque insc:ium
rerum omnium tagaretur. extitit quitltU11 tir 111t1gnus. in quo anima suam
retineret1taturam et qui i1zte/legeret omnes homines habere in se quiddam
clitinum. sed id titio corporis opprimi clique deperire: quod si fuisset
elicitum. maximas incle c:ommoditates hrmzinibus posse contingere.
I'\. Cf. Cicero: De lnv. H. I S9.
I 6. This is noted by Hadot: Marius Vic:torinus. Rec:herc:bes sur sa tie et sm1
oetwres, p. 82 who comments on the fusion of Stoicism with Platonism.
726 NEOPLATONISM
these elements are in space, that is to say the void. Yet the
elements themselves are also spaces, as fire is the place of the
stars, air that of birds, water that of swimming creatures, and
earth that of walking creatures or all which are generated in
it' .22
These last two passages of Victorinus' Commentarius are
largely self-explanatory.
22. Ibid. I, 222, 35-40 Ac primo secundum Lucreti ceterorumque sen ten-
limn inane totum locus est, quod lnmle patet rebus oc:cupaturque ab
ehmentis. igni, aere, aqua, terra. Ergo baec e/ementa in loco sunt, id est, in
immi. Sed rursus ipsa elementtl loci sutlt, ut Ignis sideribus locus est, tier
mibus. aqua natantibus, terra gradient/bus tel lis omnibus, quae in
eadem nascuntur.
Excursus E
Firmicus Maternus'
Matbesis
4. See Hadot: op. cit., col. 38'; and Ziegler: op. ciT., col. 94 7.
5. For the critical text of the Mathesis see lu/ii Finnic/ Matern/ Matheseos
Libri VIII ediderunt G. Kroll et F. Skutscb,Jasciculusprior(Stuttgart, 1897) .
. . ediderunt G. Kroll et F. Skutscb in operis societatem assumpto K. Ziegler,
fasciculus alter (Stuttgart, 1913 ).
6. Firmicus Maternus: Math. l, ';, 7 summusdeus.
7 .Ibid. V, pr. 3 'God, whoever thou art' (quiwmque es deus).
8.1bid. l, 5, 78; VII, 1, 2.
9. Ibid. Vll, l, 2 substantia.
I 0. Ibid. I, 7, II maiestas.
II. Ibid. Ill, pr. 2; IV,!, 3: VII, 1, 2 'creator' (fabricator); V, pr. 3 'ruler'
(gubernator); I. 5, 12; VIII, I, I 'author' (auctor); etc.
12. Ibid. I, 5, 6; I, 7, II; Ill, !, ? 'the provident divinity' (prot,idum
numen). Cf. ibid. I, 5. 7-8.
13.1bid. Ill, 1. 9; VII, I. 2.
14.1bid. I. 6. 2;V, pr. 3.
15.1bid. I. 5, 7; V, pr. 3; VI!, I, 2.
16. Ibid. Ill, pr. 2; IV, I, 2-3.
17. Ibid. I, 5, 7. The translation is perhaps uncertain here.
18.1bid. V, pr. 3. See pp. 731-7.'\5.
19.1bid. V. pr. 3. See pp. 73i-'.'\5.
FIRMJCUS MATERNlJS 731
20. Ibid. l, 5, 10-11 mens dirina. Cf. ibid. V, pr. 3. The same principle is
apparent I)' described as caeleslis mens at ibid. Ill, pr. 2; as dirJ/nus animus at
ibid. I, 5. 9 cf. ibid. l, 5, II; and as animus caelestis at ibid. I. 5. I 0.
2 I. In contrast to the divine spirit which is so distinguished. Cf. n. 34.
22. Ibid. I, 5. 10; I, 5. 12.
25. /hid. l, ;, 11 maiestas; ibid. I, 6, 4 vis.
2~. Ibid. I, 5. 10 'motion ... mobilit)'' (agitatio ... mobilltas).
25. /hid. I. 5. 10.
26. Ibid. I. 5. 12.
2"'./bid. I. 5. 9; IV, I. 5.
2H. Ibid. I, 'i, II.
29. Ibid. I, 5. 9; IV. I. 3 .
.~0. Ibid. I. 5. 10.
51./bid. I, 5. 12; I, 6, 4 .
.\2./hid. I. 'i. 10. See pp. 734-7.~'5.
5.'\. /hid. IV. I 1 spiritus dirinae mentis; ibid. IV. I. 6: V, pr. 3 inspiralio.
phasis upon the relation between the macrocosm: God and the
microcosm: manY! This is no doubt justifiable on the traditional
grounds that there is an analogy between the further relations of
God to the world's body and the soul to the human one.W
However, the specifically astrological orientation of the writer
makes it inevitable that the relation between the macrocosm
and the microcosm should be mediated by a third term: the
heavenly bodies.-w Thus, the heavenly bodies are described as
being sustained by the divine mind, 41 having a fiery constitu-
tion,-tz endowed with their own sense and the divine wisdom;H
and as performing the transfer of mind or soul to and the recep-
tion of spirit from terrestrial bodies-i-t and the production of in-
dividual characteristics in the lower realm. -1<; Similarly, the sun
is invoked as subject to the divine mind,-16 the source of all
celestial fire, -17 the mind of the universe;-18 and as agent of
distributing mind or soul among living creatures and of permit-
ting their reascent to the higher sphere.4<J
Firmicus Maternus' anthropological doctrine is founded on
3H. Sec Ibid. I. i. 12 the human soul 'corresponds 10 its crc:uor and its
origin' (mu-tori suo originique ... respondeat).
39. On the importance of this doctrine in Cicero and the Hermetic
Asclepius sec pp. 99 ff.. 119 ff., 380-384.
40. Sec: Firmicus M:ucrnus: Matb. Ill. pr. -~'the five planets and the sun and
moon sustain man like some smaller univc:rsc' (bominem quasi minorem
qu(tulam mundum stel/ae quinque. Sol etiam et Luna ... sustentant).
t I./bid. I, i. II; V, pr. 3.
42. /lJid. I. 'i. I I.
4 3. Ibid. I, .:; , 7 pmpl'ius sensus ditinaque pmdentitt.
44. Ibid. I. 'i. II. Here the term employed is animus. Traditionally. this
could indicate hoth mind and soul. Cf. n. 49.
45. Ibid. I, 'i, 6.
-!6. fiJi d. \'. pr . .:; .
-i~.lbid. I. 10, 1-t.
-iH.Ibid. l, 10. 1-f mensmmuli.
-t9. JfJid. V, pr. 5. Here the term employed is anima. It is unclear whether
a distinction is intended with animus. Cf. n ..W.
FIRMIU:s MATERNl'S 7.H
61. See Boll: op. cit .. col. 2367-2369 and 237 3. This scholar compares Fir-
micus Maternus: Math. I, I. 3-4 and Cicero: De Nat. Deor. l, 1-4; Firmicus
Maternus: Math. l, 4, I, ff. with Cicero: Tusc. Disp. I. 57 ff.; Firmicus Mater-
nus: Math. l, 5. II and Cicero: De Nat. Deor. ll. 39-40.
62. Firmicus Maternus: Math. Ill, I, I; IV. pr. 5.
63./bid. V, pr. 4. Cf. Asclep. l, 296.4-8, etc.
64. FirmicusMaternus:Math. l,4,4.Cf.Asclep. 19.318. 12-17;41,353.1
-355, 4 and my discussion on pp. 338-340.
65. Firmicus Maternus: Math. VII. I. 2-3. Cf. Asclep. 1. 297.6-9. etc.
66. Firmicus Matcrnus: Math. V, pr. 3. Cf. Asclep. 20.321. 9-11; 21,321,
I H-19 and my discussion inch. 5. n. 161.
FIRMIClJS MATERNliS 735
c,-. Firm it: us M;tternus: .'rltllb. V. pr. :\. C. f. Asclep. H. 50S. 12-1 <; and my
dist.:ussion on pp. :\~ S-.:HH.
hH. Firmicus Maternus: Matb. IV, I, I; IV, I, 6; V, pr. :\; etc. For the
paralld texts in the Asclepius see pp. 361-363.
(,9. Firmicus Maternus: Math. I, 5, 6-7. Cf. Asclep. 19, 319. 1-5 and my
dbl:Ussion on pp ..'\S5-:\'H.
-o. Firmit.:us !\laternus: Jfatb. VIII, I, 3. Cf. Asclep. 6 ..~02, S-19 and my
dbcussion on pp. :\HO-:\H2.
-I. Firmicus Maternus: Matb. I, 7. 18. l'irmicus seems to have in mind the
dourine expounded in Plminus: Enn. II, 3 /52/.
-2. Firmicus ~faternus: MatiJ. I. 7. 19-2 I. The account of Plotinus final il-
NEOPLATONISM
Favonius Eulogius'
Disputatio de Somnio Scipionis
I. For the attribution of this lommentary to Fa von ius Eulogius. and for the
identification of the latter as Augustine's pupil see R. E. \'an Weddingen:
/:amnii Eulogii Oisputatio de Somnio Sdpionis. Edltirm et traductf(m de R.
E. l'an \V. (Collection Latomus 27) (Bruxdles. 19S7), pp. 510; M. Sicherl:
'Fanmius Eulogius'. Reallexlkmz fiir Ant/k( und Christentum 7 ( 1969). col.
65(>-6-!0; and L. Starpa: Fmonii Eulogii Disputatio de Somnio Sdpionis.
l:'dizimze critica, traduzimze e note a cura di L.S. ( Padova, 197 4 ). pp. xi-xii.
2. Fanmius Eulogius: Disp. de S(mm. Scip. 2, 1-2. I shall quote the text of
Sctrpa's edition in all passages except that cited on pp. 743-74-i.
:~.Ibid. .25. 1-3.
-1. Ibid. S. 2-:\.
'i. Ibid. S. 6.
6.1hid.I2,S.
- /hid . ..... 12.
738 NEOPLATONISM
B./bid. 19.4-7.
9. Ibid. 19, 4.
to. This is correctly surmised by Sicherl: op. cit .. col. 638-639 who
postulates Varro and a lost Neoplatonic commentary on Virgil's Aeneid as the
sources for all Favonius' philosophical material. On the controversial ques-
tion regarding the identity of the lost Neoplatonic Virgilian commentary see
my discussion in connection wilh Macrobius on pp. S I 5-'i 16. As Sicherl: op.
cit., col. 637 also remarks, there is unfortunately no e\idence to show either
the priority or posteriority of Favonius' work to the Commelllarius in Som-
nium Scipimzis of Macrobius.
I I. Cicero: De Rep. VI. I .2. Cf. Favonius Eulogius: Disp. de Somn. Scip. I .
.2.
I 2. Cicero: De Rep. VI, 18-19. Cf. Favonius F.ulogius: Disp. de Somn. Scip.
21. 1-.~.
13. On p. 745.
FA VONilJS EUl.OGiliS 7:\9
.~!. For the: doctrine: of the: monad's stable motion see pp. :\59-360.
Vi. For the: doctrine of the monad as male and female: sc:e ch. 'i. n. 161.
5CJ. The:: argument is c:tymological: lmw = tmi + lol'i.
:\-. Fa von ius Eulogius: /Jisp. de Srmm. ScifJ. 6. 1-.~. Cf. Ibid. 'i. --1 .
.~H. The meaning of the phrase creare mm taleat id quod ipse sit is am
higuous. The probable meaning is that thrc:e, when added to another odd
number. cannot produce a further odd number .
.~9. The meaning of the phrase mtmdus ah bo numero nomen accepit is
742 NEOPLATONISM
unclear. Van Weddingen: op. cit.. p. 19 suggests that mut~dus is a mistake for
terra which is 'etymologically' connected with trias. Scarpa: op. cit., p. 52
suggests that mundus is to be understood as the adjective meaning 'ordered'
or 'beautiful' which is also applicable to the triad.
40. Favonius Eulogius: Disp. deSomn. Scip. 7, 1-4. Cf. ibid. 'i. 4.
4 I . Ibid. 5. 2.
42. This interpretation of soul's unity parallels that regarding God's. On
this question see pp. 7 39-7 40.
43. Favonius Eulogius: Disp. deSomn. Scip. 5, 2.
44./bid. 19,4-7.
FA VON IllS ElllOGJl 'S '743
t;;. It i~ likdy that these arc understood as equi\'alcnts for one another.
t6. Thl Virgilian passage cited here is Aeneid VI. -i.-~9.
t ~. For the notion that the tlowin~ of the Styx corresponds to the descent
of ~oul. See pp. SH9-S9S.
tH. For the notion that souls scattered through the cosmos are mounted in
vthides see pp. SH9-S9S.
t9. The meanin~ of the sentence mana/que ... consert.enl is unclear. Ap-
parently the su~gestion is that the planetary spheres have ill-defined orbits
until they are infused with the appropriate portion of soul.
NEOPI.ATONISM
iO. Favonius Eulogius: Disp. de Sumn. Scip. 19. -4-6. The passage has given
rise to numerous emendations by modern scholar~. and my version does not
agree precisely with either van Weddingen or Scarpa. With the former, I
transpose the phrase hinc dicitur TCTiyaia to the only place where it makes
sense, and leave Styx to stand before posita a<.-cording to the manusnipt -
Scarpa's objections against both on contextual grounds have no validity.
However. with the latter, I read dissipat as being a simpler conjecture in the
fan of the obvious corruption than the: Dis est proposed hy certain earlier
editors - although Scarpa~ ohjntion to the latter on contextual grounds
ag:tin has little weight.
i I. The boundary of the: transcendent realm is indicated by the words sub
pedilms summi pcllris. since: the: God n:fern:d 10 would have a transcendent
or metaphysical status.
il. The individual souls inhabiting these sphc:rc:s are indicated by the
words singu/is .. . nmcta titentia. They will he those of the: sphc:rc:s
themselves and of earthly hc:ings bet\vc:c:n incarnations.
FAVONIUS Elii.O<ill'S
'i5. It should be emphasized that neither this triad of terms nor anything
ds<: in the Dlsputatlo de Somnio Scipionis indicates a Christian affiliation on
the author's part. On this question see Sicherl: 'Favonius Eulogius', col. 659.
'it. See pp. 51 0 and 515-516.
'i'i. The reference to soul as 7rl1Yaia. On the connection between the no-
tions of soul and source which is very characteristic of the Cbaldaean
Oracles see H. lewy: Cbaldaean Oracles and Tbeurgy. Mysticism. ,\.lagic
and Platonism in tbe Later Roman Empire (Recbercbes d'arcbeologie, de
fJbilo/ogie el d 'bistoire 15) (Cairo, 1956). Nouvelle edition par M. T:1rdieu
I Paris. 19"H). pp. H-t-HS :md 1:-18-89. For Porphyry's use of the Cbaldaean
( Jrac/es sec: ch. H. n. I H.
Excursus G
Servius'
Commentarii in Virgilii Carmina
747
NEOPI.ATONISM
'5. Sec K. Barwick: 'Zur Scrviusfrage', Philologus 70 ( 191 I), pp. 106-145.
That this second ancient commentary was that of Aelius Donatus was argued
by E. K. Rand: 'Is Donatus' Commentary on Virgil Lost?'. Classical Quarterly
10 (1916). pp. 15H-16i. His view was supported by N. Marinone: E/io
Donato. Macrobio e Serl'io commentatori di Vergilio (Vercelli. 1946), pp.
-45--jH and 77 but rejected by A.H. Travis: 'Donatus and the Scholia Daniells:
A Stylistic Comparison', Hartard Studies in Classical Philology 53 ( 1942),
pp. I '57-169.
6. See A. F. Swcker: A Possible New Source for Sertius Dmzielis on Aeneid
Ill v. Studies in Bibliography 4 ( 195 1-1952), pp. 129131.
7. Some examples of the influence of the Sen ian commentaries on
mediaeval thought have been noted by P. Courcelle: 'lntcrpn!tations neo-
pl:uonisantes du livre VI de I' Em!ide ', Recherches sur Ia tradition platoni-
cienne (Fondation Hardt, Entretiens sur I'Antiquite classique 3)
(V:mdoeuvn:s-Genhc, 19'55). pp. 9'5136 and 'Les Peres de I'Eglise devant les
enfers virgiliens'. Arcbites d'bistoire doctrinale et littemire du moyen dge
22 ( 19'5'5). pp. '5'-l.
H. For some obsenations on this philosophical material see E.G. Sihler:
'Serviana', American .founwl of Philology 31 (1910), pp. J,2.f; E. 0.
Wallace: Tbe Notes on Philosopby in the Commentary of Sertius on tbe
Eclogues. the Georgics. and tbe Aeneid of Vergil (New York, 193R) - a
valuable inventory of material although weaker as criticism -; 1.. F.
1-lackemann: Servius and bis Sources in the Commentary on the Georgics
SERVJUS 749
( :'l:ew York. 1940), p. I'; ff.; and P. Courcelle: Late Latiu Writers tmd their
Greek Sources. translated by H.E. Wedcck (Cambridgc.MA. 1969). pp. 16.
2l)-) 1. ~0-41 and 46.
lJ. Servius: In Aeneid. l, .'\88; VI. 724; VI, 726; b1 Georg. IV, 219; IV, 221.
I shall quote the commentary on Aeneid l-V from E. K. Rand, etc.: Ser-
l'immrum in Vergilli Carmbza Commentariorum edilio Harrardiana 11-IJI
(l.ancaster,PA and Oxford, 1946 and 196';); the commentaries on Aeneid VI-
XII, on the t'c:/ogues. and on the Genrgics from Thilo: op. cit. Passages cited
:1~ 'Scnius' will be those occurring in both the Servius Daniclis and the
\'ulgate Senius, while those cited as 'Servius Danielis' will be those occurring
in that version alone.
I 0. Sen ius: In Aeneid. VI, 726; VI, 727.
II. Ibid. VI. 727; VI, 747.
1.2. Ibid. VI. '24.
I;\. 1/Jid. l, 388; VI. 724; VI. 726; VI. 72""'; In Bucol. 3, 60: In Georg. IV,
221.
I-t. Sen ius: In Georg. IV, 226.
I 'i. Servius: lt1 Aeneid. VI. 72,..: VI, 726; VI. 727.
16.1bid. VI, 727.
P. lfJid. VI, 7 2 .. ; VI, 726: VI, 7 28; 111 Georg. IV. 219.
I H. Senius: In Aeneid. VI. 7-!7.
19. Sen ius: 111 Bucol. 2, 31. Cf. 111 Aeneid. VI. 7 24.
20. St:r\'ius: lt1 Georg. I. 'i .
.21. Senius: 111 Bucol. 'i, 66; In Georg. I. ';.
22. Senius: In Aeneid. I. 17: Senius Danielis: In Ae11eid. 11. 296: Scnius:
In Aeneid. IV, 20 I; In Georg. 11, 3.25.
750 NEOPI.A TON ISM
numbers,23 to the Ideas after which all visible things are pattern-
ed,24 and to matter.zs Among observations which the commen-
tator makes on psychological questions are some which require
a more detailed analysis.
Servius observes that, although the whole of Virgil contains
scientific material, Aeneid VI is especially rich in this respect.26
In fact, this text contains so much of the profoundest teachings
of the philosophers, theologians, and Egyptians that many of
these have written commentaries devoted to it alone. Precisely
what kind of philosophy is contained there is explained by the
note on the poet's words: 'meanwhile Aeneas sees .... ' Here,
Servius comments that throughout this passage the doctrine
m:pi wux.ii~ which Plato had expounded in his Phaedo and
Varro in his Antiquitates Rerum Divinarum functions as an
underlying theme.r The Platonic theory of the soul identified
18. Senius: In Aeneid. VI. 724. Cf. ibid. VI, 71-t; VI. 7W.
29. Ibid. VI, 724. Servius contrasts this and the next two attributes with
the corresponding ones in the case of body.
W. Ibid. VI. 724.
31.1bid. VI, 724. Cf. ibid. VI, 714 .
.H./bid. VI, 724. Cf. ibid. VI, 733.
H. Ibid. VI. 7 32.
3i. Ibid. VI. 7 24. The commentator quotes an analogy with a light source
which is undiminished yet obscured by an object placed beside it.
35. See the discussion of Macrobius on pp. 579-582 .
.~6. Sc:r\'ius: In Aeneid. VI, I 27.
-~~.Ibid. VI,l27;Vl,439.
7'JEOPL.ATONISM
38. Ibid. VI, 4 39; VI. 7 14: XI. 51. The last two passages differ slightly
regarding the qualities which the descending soul is said to acquire from the
seven planetary circles:
Saturn torpor humor
Jupiter regni desiderium bonorum desiderium
Mars iracundia sanguis
the sun spiritus
Venus libido cup/dilates
Mercury lucri cupiditas ingenium
the moon corpus
ibid. VI. 714 ibid. XI. 5 I.
It is ob\'ious that there \\<ere a number of variants upon this theme in the com-
mentator's source or sources. Seep. 589 ff.
39.1bid. VI. 705. Cf. ibid. VI, .264; VI. 703.
40. Sec pp. 488-490 .
.j I. See pp. 582-587.
-il. See pp. 7'!.2-745.
i:\. Servius: In Aeneid. V, 81; Senius Danielis: In Aeneid. V. 81. Cf. Ser-
vius: In Aeneid. VIII. 564.
44. Senius: In Aeneid. IX. 182. Here, Senius cites Plotinus' view that
SERVIllS 75.~
souls entering human bodies are accompanied by genii which will be respon-
~ibh: for their better moral conduct. For Plotinus, the genius is a reduplica-
tion of the soul, as shown in n. 46.
15. Ibid. VI, 134. Cf. ibid. IV, 654; VI, 650. Here, the commentator states
that souls which have returned to the gods retain certain images which in-
habit the underworld. This is revealed by the mythological accounts of Her-
cules. Liher, and Castor and Pollux. At Ibid. VI, 7.W he adds that the souls
which have departed from the body are not themselves punished but only
"the remains of that union which existed between soul and body' (illius con-
itmctirmis re/iquiae, quae fuit inter animam et corpus). These remnants
prtsumably correspond lO the image described above. For Plotinus and Por
phyry, this image is a reduplication of the soul. as shown inn. 46.
>~6. Plot in us' teaching is that the genius corresponds to the phase of the in-
dividual soul immediately above the one which is active. See Emz. Ill, 4 /I 5/
.1o. 1-r. Servius' employment of this doctrine is discussed by P. Henry: Plotin
et I'Occitlent. Firmicus Matenms, Marius Victor/nus. saint Augustin et
.lfacmbe (Louvain. 1934). pp. 19'1-196. Plotinus also holds that the image
l"llrresponds to a phase of the individual soul which it projects towards body
and which undergoes punishment for sins. See Enn. I. I /53/ 12, 1-39; VI, 4
122! 16. 1-iR (the first passage using the illustration of Hercules' shade). Cf.
Porphyry: Sent. 29, 17. II ff. Servius' relation to this tradition is discussed by
J PC:pin: 'Heracles et son reOet dans le neoplatonisme', Le Neoplatonisme
fCul/nque lnternellional du Centre National de Ia Rechetcbe Scienlifique,
Royaumont CJ-13juitz /969)(Paris, 1971). pp. 167-192 .
~. Servius: In Aeneid. VI. 44R. Cf. ibid. Ill, 6R; Ill, 140; VI. 603.
-IH. J1Jid. VI, 741.
NEOPLATONISM
water, air. and fire to reach the point v.here new bodies are
assigned to them. -t9 Elsewhere the souls return to bodies is said
to result perhaps from their need to revert to the place of pro-
creation, perhaps from the capacity to do so consequent upon
their immortality, and perhaps from their desire for bodies
whose pains have been forgotten. <;O Finally, after leaving their
present mortal bodies human souls may become free of
transmigration either because they need not return to bodies for
a considerable length of time'i I, or because they need not return
to bodies at all. 'il Although some of its details cannot be parallel-
ed exactly in other late ancient writers, this theory is generally
in line with Calcidius', 'i~ Macrobius', 'i4 and their Greek sources'
views on the subject.
The doctrine of the soul which Servius finds especially in
Aeneid VI is obviously put together from commonplaces in
Platonic philosophical literature. These are perhaps drawn in
the first instance from much earlier Latin writers among whom
Varro is explicitly cited on this topic, 'i'i Cicero in conjunction
with closely related issues, 56 and Apuleius in the context of one
9. Fulgentius: Mitol. I. 15, 26, 18-20 'Hermes in his book "Opimandra" .. .'
(llermes in Opimandrae libro ... ).
10./bid. III. 9. 74. 11-14.
II. Fulgentius: Expos. Virg. Cont. 85. 21-86, I.
12. Fulgentius: Mitol. III. 7. 71. 19-22.
15. /hid. III, 9. 7-i, 9-10 'Orpheus in his "Theogony" .. .' (Orfeus in
teogonia ... ).
14. /hid. III, 9. 75, 4-7: III, 10, 79. 7-11: and Expos. Virg. Cont. 85. 20-21.
I 5. /hid. 85, 21.
16. Fulgentius: Mitol. I, pr. I 5. I.
1-. /hid. II. -4, 43. 14-1 'i 'Plato in his ethical writings (Plato in
11/0I'U/i/J/IS ... ).
I H. Fulgentius: E:~:pos. Virg. Cont. 8'i. 21.
I<J. Ibid. 88,2-5.
20. IIJid. 90, H-1 'i.
2 I . fiJi d. 86, I.
22. Compare ibid. 88, 3-'i voiic; civ6promvoc; 6e6c;' OUtoc; t.av ciya66c;, eeoc;
Eu E:pya~6~Evoc;. id est: sensus bominis deus est; is si bonus est, deus est pro-
{Jitius with Corp. Herm. XII, 1-2. 174, 7-16 outoc; M 6 vouc; t.v ~f;v civ6pronOtc;
0E6c; tan ... Kai yap 6 ciya6oc; l)ai~wv ... 6 yap vouc; '1/UXWV t.anv EUEPYEtllc;
<i vOpronwv.
760 NEOPLATONISM
23. Fulgentius: Milo/. l, pr. 4 . .f-7 'But let his "Republic" indicate what
Cicero achieved' ( Verum res publica tldeat quid Cicero egerit).
24. Fulgentius: Expos. Virg. Cont. 102,2-4.
25. Fulgentius: Expos. Serm. Antiqu. 11, 115, 8-10 'Varro in his book on
mystery rites .. .' (Varro in mlstagogorum /ibro ... ).
26. Ibid. 14, 116, 3-4.
27. Fulgentius: Milo/. Ill, 6, 66, 19 ff. Apuleius in his book "Metamor-
phoses" .. .' (Apuleius in libris metamorfoseotl). Cf. ibid. III, 6. 68, 21-22;
Ill, 6, 69,28-70,2: Expos. Serm. Antiqu. 17, 116,21-117, 4; etc.
28. Ibid. 16, I 16, 18-20 Tertullian in the book which he wrote about fate
... ( Tertul/ianus in /ibro quem de Jato scripsil ... )
29. Ibid. 4, 112, 11-13 'Labeo who explained this in fifteen books .. .'
(Labeoqui ... quindecim toluminibusexplallat'il ... )
30. Ibid. 4<;, 12.~. 4-'> 'felix Capdla in his book "On the Marriage of Mer-
cury and Philolo~y" ... (Feli.Y Capella in /ibro de nuptiis .Hercurii et
Pbilologiae ... ).
.31. Thus, Fulgentius usually memions the name of the work in which each
writer expressed the view described. See above nn. 23. 25, 27 etc. This con-
trasts clearly with the mostly quite imprecise references to Greek writers.
FliLGENTilTS 761
HI H ff. Since the S!Oics were the main practitioners of the philosophical ra-
tionalization of myth. it is among the Platonists who were actively interested
in SlOicism that this method recurs .
.-\7. For Porphyry and the Swics sec pp. 558-560.
;\H. Fulgcntius: Mftol. I. 2, I H, 7-9. The translation of the Greek vouc; hy the
Latin se11sus is characteristic of the Hermetic Asclepius in its extant form. See
ch.5,n.U .
.'\9. Sec p. 561 (interpretation of Dionysius).
HI. Sec pp. 620-621 (interpretation of Mlrcury).
-ll. Fulgentius: Milo/. II, 6, 46. 8-9.
FULGENTJllS 76;\
.:\. The doctrine of this work has been studied (with emphasis upon the
Thcophrastean material) hy E. Barbotin: La theorie aristotelicienne de
/'Intellect d 'apres Tbeophmste (louvain, 1954) and (with emphasis upon the
Neoplatonic clements) by C. Steel: The Changing Self A Study on the Soul in
Later Neuplatonism: lamblichus. Damascius and Priscianus (Brussel,
1978).
4. I quote the full latin text of the Solutiones' preface at the point where
the sources arc listed: E:r Platunico enim Timaeo Faedoneque et Faedro et
Politia. et aliis comenietllibus disputallonibus assumptct atque confecta
sunt, et m:tionibus Aristotelis de Physica et de Caeli generalione et corrup-
lione et MET0EQPQN, similiter quoque et ex his quae sunt de Somno et
somniis, et ex bis quae quasi in dialogis scripta sunt de Pbilosophia et de
Mundis. Tbeofrastus item plurimas occasiones sennone dignas praestetit
his quae quesita sunt ex Naturali bistoria et Natumli au,litu, et ex his quae
dicit de Somno et somniis, Morsibusque slmu/ tzocivis. et de Ventis. et de
Modis et moribus et babitationibus: Hippocrates quoque ad hoc perveniens
de Aere /ocis aquis. l!si quoque stmms ulillbus quae sunt ex Strabonis
Geograpbia. Latini quoque. e:r Ge~ii sco/is, e.wmp/aribus P/atonicorum
dogmatum. e~dbuc etiam ex commento Gemini Posidonii de MET0QPQN,
et Pto/omaei Geograpbie~ de k/imalibus, et se quid utile nobis ex
Astranominis apparuil. Marcianique Periegesi. et MET0EQPQN Arriani,
Didymoque de Aristotele, et ipsius scriptore dogmatum, et Dorothei
Ne~turalirmr Aristotelis commento. Aesli11wtus est autem et Tbeodotus nobis
oportunas occasiones /argiri ex co/lectione Ammonii sco/arum, et Por-
pbyrius ex Commi:rtis quaestionibus. /amblicbusque de Anima scribens, et
Ale:wmder. et Tbemislius, qui ea quae sum Aristote/is narmrrt. Plot/nus
quoque magmts, et Proclus in omnibus defererrtes singulos libros com-
ponens. et maxi me de Tribus sermonibus per quos apud P/atonem mrime~e
immortale ostenditur. This text is reproduced in the form edited by A.
Wilmart: 'lcs rcponscs de Priscicn lc philosophe sous le nom de saint
Augustin'. Rerme bemfdicline 49 ( 1937), pp. 4-5 after the two Carolingian
manuscripts.
'i. That Didymoque de Aristotele. et ipsius scripture dogmatmn is a
reference to the famous doxographcr Arius Didymus is argued by H. Diels:
PRISCIANLJS l YDl'S 769
been copied at least twice during the ninth century and five
times during the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries. JO However,
its influence on actual philosophical writing cannot be clearly
demonstrated prior to the Salernitan Quaestiones Physica/es of
ca. 1200 and the encyclopaedic activity of Vincent of
Beauvais.ll
Priscianus' So/utiones as preserved contain treatments of the
following topics disposed in separate chapters: (i) the soul, (ii)
sleep, (iii) dreams, (iv) the seasons, (v) medicine, (vi) the tides,
(vii) rain. snow, etc., (viii) the adaptability of animals, (ix)
poisonous reptiles, (x) the winds. Since the first chapter is the
only one which includes any developed philosophical argu-
ment, the remainder of this discussion will be devoted to ex-
amining its content. As a matter of convenience, the analysis
will be divided under the following headings: (1 a) the
arguments regarding the nature of the soul, (1 b) the assump-
tions regarding the nature of the soul, (2) miscellaneous doc-
trines about causality and the intelligibles.
(1 a) Priscianus' arguments regarding the nature of the soul.
In a series of arguments which seem to reflect the doctrines
of Proclus in particular, Priscianus demonstrates that the human
soul is a self-subsistent substance and that it is incorporeal, sim-
ple, and indestructible. It is a 'self-subsistent substance' (essen-
ria ll se ipsa subsistens) because it is receptive of contraries like
Esposito that the translation is too barbarous for Eriugena and that it is
nowhere cited in the latter's Periphysenn; nor those of d' Alverny that the
translation contains peculiarly Eriugenian expressions and that one passage is
retlccted in the latter's E."<positiones in lerarchiam Caelestem arc really com-
pelling. Thus, the precise question of authorship and dating should be left
open.
10. The \'arious manuscripts arc listed by Schmitt: op. cit .. pp. H t-82.
II. On the intlucncc of the Solutiones see also B. Lawn: The Salenritan
Questions. An Introduction to the History ofMedieral and Renaissance Pro-
blem Literature(Oxford, l963).passim.
PRISCIANl 'S 1. Yl>l'S 7"7(
12. Priscianus: Solut. I. B. 23-44, J.l. Cf. ibid. I. 48 ..u-.:H. For the no-
tion of the "self-constituted substance' (au8un6atatoc; ouaia) sec Proclus:
Flem. 7/Jeo/. 40, -42. H ff. The Proclinc: doctrine is examined in S. Gersh:
A'intsis Akinetos. A Stud) of Spiritual Motion in t!Je P/Jilosopb.J' of Proclus
tl.ciden. ltJ~:\). pp. 7-9and 12H-13S.
1:\.J>risdanus:So/ut. 1.44. 1.'\-14: I.-46.1-2: 1.46.6-7: I.-48.29.
I i. I!Jitl. l. 44. I 5-28. This is clearly one of the :trguments which Pris-
lianu~ has dr:twn (sec n. -4) from the Quaestiones Commixtae of Porphyry.
The latter's teaching on this question has already been examined in the light
ol it~ influence on Calcidius in (.'hapter 6.n. 26-i.
I<;, l'riscianus: Solut. I. ojl. j 1-15. 12.
16./bicl. I. .f.!. 12-.f6, 19.
1-. Ibid. l, 46, 19-29.
lH.IIJid. I. -17, 2; I. -48. 9.
19. !hid. 1. -i7. 2-2-f. Plot in us is explicitly cited as an authority at this point
l 'ce n. -1 ). Possibly Priscianus is recollening the argument atl:'nn. IV. 7 /2/ II.
NEOPLATONIS.M
14-17 that a principle: which confers life must be immortal since it cannot ad-
mit life's contrary.
20. Priscianus: Solut. I. 4 7. 2i-4R. 9.
21. Ibid. I, 48, 10-49, 36. These three argumems for the immortality of
the soul clearly correspond to Produs' Tres sennmzes, per quos apud
P/atonem animae immortale ostendilur mentioned in Priscianus' preface
(see n. 4 ). On this monograph which is partially preserved in the Arabic tradi-
tion see L. G. Westerink: 'Proclus on Plato's Three Proofs of Immortality',
Zetesis, Album Amicorum aangebode11 aan /:.'. de Slr.Jcker (Antwerpen,
1973). pp. 296-306.
22. Priscianus: Solut. I. 46. 12 ad se ipsmn cmwersa. Cf. Proclus: E/em.
Tbeo/. 42. 44. II everything self-constituted reverts to itsc:lf (nCiv to
au9u1t6cnatov 1tp0<; eaut6 EOtiV e1tlOtpE1ttiK6V).
23. Priscianus: So/ut. I. 48, 21 eandem enim essen/lam babens et opera-
lio1lem. Cf. Proclus: In Tim. II. 293. 18 where primary hc:ing 'does not have
ils activity distinct from its substance' (ou5t yap ID.A.T)v EX.Et tiJv tvtpyEtav
~tapa tl')v ouoiav).
24. Priscianus: Solut. I. lB . .Z.Z tota in totam se ijJsam i1lfrtms. Cf. Pro
clus: Elem. TIJeo/. 47, i6. 31 where the self-lonstituted 'will revert to itself as
a whole' (oA.ov auto atpaq>tlOEtal1tPO<; eauto ).
2i. Priscianus: Solut. I, 4 3. l:~; I. B. 2i; etc. a se ipsa subsistens. Cf. Pro-
d us: 1:"/em. Tbeol. 189, 164. 22-2." 'the: soul is self-constituted and the cause
of its own existence' (tlljiUX,l') apa UU9U1t60tat0<; KUi EUUtl')V U(j)lOtT)OlV).
PRISCIANlJS LYDllS
.'\'i. Ibid. I. 4". 18-2-t. This argument occurs in almost identical terms in
Proclus: Elem. Tbeol. 7. 8, I -28. Priscianus' causate corresponds to Prod us'
napciyov /napaKnK6v. and his causatitw1l to the Greek napay6~Evov.
;\6. Priscianus: Solut. I. 49. 4-S. This thesis is stated in almost identical
language at Proclus: E/em. Then/. 18. 20. 3-20. Priscianus' ipsum primo esse
quod parlicipantibus infert equals Proclus' auto np<i>TW~ tcni TOUTO, OU
~Etaoiowm toi~ XOPTJYOU~tvot~ .
.'\.,. Priscianus: So/ut. I. 'i2. I 0- I I .
.'\H. Depending upon the extent 10 which Produs' elahorately hierarchical
interpretation of the higher realm is assumed.
59. Priscianus: Solut. l. 49. 24: I. i9. 26.
-W.Ibid. 1. -l9. 2'i.
-t I. Ibid. I . 'i2. I 0- I I.
-il.. Ibid. 1. 4 S. 14.
PRISCIANllS l.YDUS
. 1 .~. !11id. I. ';2. 16-18. At this point the Porphyrian doctrine. whi<:h is also
repelled at ibid. I. ';0, 2'; ff.. comes hack into the picture. Seen. 14.
Note on Priscianus Grammaticus
...,..,..,
Conclusion
779
CONCLUSION
'i. The middle of the twelfth century is a useful terminus in that beyond
this point the intellc~o:IUal milieu is totally transformed by the influx of Greek
and Arabic m:uerial.
MEDIAEVAL PLATONISM 781
quotations except one (which is derived through the Academical come from
the part translated by Cicero, and Augustine expressly cites this latin transla-
tion at Cil'. Dei XIII, 16 (CCSL 48, 396-398), it seems that all his information
;lhout Plato's cosmology is drawn from Cicero. These passages are listed and
discussed by Hagen dahl: op. cit. I, pp. 131-138; II, pp. 53 5-540.
21. Augustine: Conf Ill, 4 (CSEL 33/1, 48-50). The writer here cites
Cicero's Hortensius as the crucial influence.
22. Ibid. Ill, 7 (CSEL 33/1, 53-56); IV, 15 (CSEL 33/1, 83-85); \', 10 (CSEl
.~.~11. I 0')-108); etc. Augustine himself associates lhis interpretation of God's
nawre with Manichaeism rather than Cicero. However. Testard: op. cit .. pp.
I<J-6H and 116-118 argues convincingly that he must also have seen its con-
nection with Cicero's eclectic Stoic and Platonic theology.
2.~. Augustine: Conf V. 10 (CSEl 33/1, 105-1 08). The writer here men-
tions the Academic/ about whom he would have read in Cicero.
2"1. This theme is developed especially in Augustine: De Lib. Arb. I and
rt:prcs<.ms the Stoic teaching of Cicero's De Republica and De Legibus. On
Au~ustine's Stoicism which is derived through Cicero, the doxographies, and
l'lotinus !>cc G. Verbeke: L 'evolution de Ia doctrine du pneuma du stoicisme
ti s. ..tugusti11. t.'tude philosopbique (Paris/lou vain, 194') ): R. M. Bushman:
~t. Augustine's Metaphysics and Stoic Doctrine', Neu Scholasticism 26
( 1952), pp. 2H3-305; G. Verbeke: 'Augustin et le stoicisme. Recherches
augustiniennes I ( 19')8). pp. 67-89; M. Sicherl: 'Piatonismus und Stoizismus
in lien Friihschriften August ins', Acta Pbi/ologictl Aenipontana 2 ( 1967), pp.
6 :\-65; C. Baguette: 'line periode stoicienne dans revolution de Ia pensee de
~aint Augustin .. Ret' lie des etudes augustiniennes 16 ( 1970). pp. i 7-77; R. J.
O'Connell: 'De Libero Arbitrio 1: Stoicism Revisited', Augustitzitm Studies I
1~ 9 "'0); pp. 49-69; and M. Spanneut: 'le stokisme de saint Augustin', Forma
htturi: Stud/ in on ore diM. Pellegrino (Torino, 197';), pp. 896-914.
78-J CONCLUSION
deny that the world itself is endowed with a soul,25 and the
belief in immanent seminal reasons.26 Other Latin writers are
generally used only as sources of philosophical information. For
example, Seneca's De Superstitione provides some material
critical of the Roman civil theology ,27 Gellius' Noctes Atticae an
anecdote about a Stoic philosopher,zs Apuleius' De Deo
Socratis an account of the pagan demons' mediating role bet-
ween God and man,29 the same author's De Mundo some notes
on the causes of physical catastrophes,3o and the Latin Asclepius
a discussion of the theurgic animation of statues. 31 All this in-
dicates that the reading of Augustine in the Latin Platonic
writers of late antiquity is extensive, their role as sources of in-
formation climaxing in De Civitate Dei and their role as in-
25. The notion recurs in at least eight of Augustine's works. For a complete
list of references sec V.). Bourke: 'St. Augustine and the Cosmic Soul', Gior-
nale di metafisica 9 ( 1954), pp. 4 31-440. It is, of course, both Ciceronian
and Plotinian.
26. This theme is developed especially in Augustine: De Trin. III (CCSL 50,
127 ff.) and De Gen. ad Lilt. (CSEL 28/1 ), and reflects the Stoic teaching of
Cicero's De Natura Deorum, etc. Seen. 25.
27. The list of Senecan and Augustinian references can be found in Hagen-
dahl: op. cit. I. pp. 245-249. In addition, one Epistula of Seneca is quoted by
Augustine. See also J. Oroz Reta: 'Seneca y San Agustin. (lntluencia o coin-
cidenzia?', Augustin us 10 ( 1965), pp. 295-325.
28. Augustine: Cit. Dei IX, 4 (CCSI. 47, 25 l-25.:H cf. Gellius: Noel. Attic.
XIX I, 1-21.
29. The list of Apuleian and Augustinian references can be found in Hagen-
dahl: op. cit. l, pp. 17-28. In addition, the Apologitl and Metamorphoses of
Apuleius are quoted by Augustine. See also C. Moreschini: 'La polemica di
Agostino l"ontro Ia demonologia di Apuleio', Ann ali della Scuole Normale de
Pisa, Classe di lett ere e filosofitl 2 ( 197 2), pp. 583-596.
30. Augustine: Cit. Dei IV. 2 (CCSI. 47. 99-1 00) cf. Apuleius: De Mundo
3-f.
31. The list of Hermetic and Augustinian references can be found in Hagen-
dahl: op. cit. l, pp. 29-33. Textual parallels indicate that Augustine consulted
the latin \"ersion of this \Vork.
MEDIAE\' AL PLATONISM 7fl5
-i9. Isidore: De Nat. Rer. 26. 2, etc. For the Gregorian influence over this
aspect of Isidore's thinking see Fontaine: op. cit. II, p. S41 ff.
SO. Sc=c= nn. 4S, 48, and 49.
S I. For a useful introduction, see the works cited by G. Schrimpf:
'Gdc=hrsamkeit und Philosophic im Bildungswesen des 9. und 10.
Jahrhunderts. Ein Literaturbericht fiir die Jahre 1960 bis 197S '. Zeitschrift fiir
pbilnsnphische Forschtmg 31 ( 1977) pp. 123137.
i.!. See W. S. Howell: The Rhetoric of Alcuin attd Cht~rlemagne. A
Translation with a11 /1llroductio11, the Latin Text and Notes (Princeton,NJ,
191 I). p. 22 ff.
S3. The philosophical material in this manuscript, which can be associated
with Akuin's pupil Candidus, has been discussed by C. lneichen-Eder:
'Thtologisches und philosophisches Lehrmaterial aus dem Alcuin-Kreise'.
D('lltsches Archit fiir Erforschung des Mittelalters 34 (1978). pp. 192-201
and .f. Marenbon: From the Circle of Alcuin to the School of Auxerre. Logic,
Thenlo!{J' and Philosophy in tbe Early Middle Ages (Cambridge, 1981 ), pp.
;;.;~ .
. ';-f. Sc=e 1.. Wallach: Diplomatic Studies in Latin and Greek Documents
}rom !be Camli11gian Age (lthaca.NY. 1977), p. 71 ff.
SS See lneichc:n-Eder: op. cit., pp. 196-199 and Marenbon: op. cit .. p. S7.
CONCLlTSJON
(H. Alcuin: Disp. de Vera Philos. (PL to I, 853A-854A (where the work ap-
Pl':lrs as :1 prolo~ue to his De Grammatica)). Since the smdies of this text hy
F. Brunhiilzl: 'Ocr Rildungsauftrag der Hofschule', Kml der Grosse.
l.d>ensuerk wul Ne~cb/ehen II: Das geistige Leben. herausgegeben von W.
llraunfl'ls (Dusseldorf. 1965). pp. 2H---ll and P. Courcelle: La Consolation dc
Philosophic dtms Ia tradition litteraire, Antecedents et postirite de Boece
fl'arb. 1967) pp. :\3-ii we know that it is p:1cked with allusions to Boethius'
Oe Consolatimte Pbilosophitte.
<>5 Akuin: De Rhet. et de Virt. 44--47. The m;uerial on the pagan virtues is
drawn largdy from Ciccro 's De bll'l.!lltione (which is one of the major
sources for the whole hook). See Bowell: op. cit .. pp. 29 ff.. 69 ff. and S.
,\liihl: <JuaJriga \'irtutum. Die Ktudilwllugelldn in der Cielstesgescbicbteder
1\aru/ingazeit (Beibefte zum Arcbit .fiir Kulltu:~escbicbte 9) (Kiiln/Wien.
I>C.<)), p. H.~ IT.
(,(, Thnc transformations of perspec.:ti\'e ha\'c been s!Udied by G. Mathon:
l.es formes ct Ia signification de Ia pedagogic des arts libcraux au milieu du
IXl sil:ck. L'enscignemcnt palatin dc Jean Scot Erigene', Arts libemu.\ et
/JI>ilusopbit au mo)en tlge ( Actes t/u /Ve Congres International de
1'hilosofJbie Mtlditltc;le. 2- mnlt-.! septemiJre 196 ..) (MontrC::ti/Paris. 1969).
Pp. ,-.c,..and G. Schrimpf: Das Werk des .Joburmes Scottus Eriuge1w im
790 CONCLUSION
tion that these studies are ultimately directed towards the better
comprehension of Scripture remains intact.
It is within the area of the actual elaboration of philosophical
doctrine that we see the clearest evolution during the Carol-
ingian period. Although Alcuin and his contemporaries had ac-
cess to most of the Latin Platonic writers of late antiquity, it re-
mains true that their interpretation of those writers is entirely
within the perspectives established by the Latin Fathers,
Cassiodorus. and Isidore. However, in the cases of Eriugena and
other later Carolingian scholars there is a greater readiness to
approach the Latin Platonists on their own terms. A few ex-
amples will perhaps illustrate this.
(i) Johannes Scottus Eriugena
Among the various Latin Platonic writers Eriugena67 reveals a
marked preference for the later ones. A passage from Cicero's
Tusculanae Disputationes dealing with the Stoic theory of the
emotions is utilized three times in his Expositiones in lerar-
chiam Coelestem;6R a passage from Macrobius describing the
Greek exegetical principle of the 'purpose' (oK07t6c;) is the basis
of another section in the same work.69 From Martianus
"'II. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. VI, 609 at Eriugena: Peripb. III. 719A. On
the Carolingian glosses on Martianus Capella sec pp. 798-80 I .
.., I. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. VIII, 859 at Eriugena: Peripb. Ill, 720 B.
.., 2. Boethius: De Aritbm. I, I, 7, 21 ff. at Eriugena: Peripb. I. 498B-C (ex-
plidtly dting De Aritbmetit:u); ibid. l, 5038-C; and ibid. Ill, 655 A (citing his
IJe Matbesis lihri). On the Carolingian glosses on Bocthius sec pp. 802-80-i .
..., .'\ Boethius: Contra Eu~)cb. el Nest. 6, 7 3-82 at Eriugena: Peripb. V, 877
B (explidtl)' citing this work as secundus /iber de Trinitate).
CONCLLISJON
bodies in different ways. and yet remains in its natural and un-
changing state; for these reasons it is always in motion and
always at rest. Similarly the body, that is the universe of visible
things, is partly at rest in eternal stability as earth, partly in mo-
tion with eternal velocity as the aetherial region, partly neither
at rest nor in motion with velocity as water, and partly in mo-
tion with velocity but not the maximum velocity as air. And this
argument of the greatest of philosophers is not wholly to be
despised, I believe, because it seems perceptive and in accor-
dance with the nature of things'. 74 Eriugena has derived this
discussion without doubt from Calcidius' Commentarius in
Timaeum, since its final section does not correspond to
anything in the Ciceronian translation of the dialogue.7S It is
also clear that Eriugena is using Calcidius' commentary rather
than his translation alone, since the latter breaks off before the
discussion corresponding to the last part of the Pe1iphyseon's
account.- 6
Plato is also explicirly cited in support of Augustine's account
of rhc nature of matter. 'With this Plato agrees in his Timaeus,
lkdaring in similar terms that formless matter is a receptivity to
forms.-- The source of this quotation is in all likelihood
catcidius' translation of the Timaeus, since the most relevant
section of Plato's text was not translated in the Ciceronian ver-
sion.-H
A third discussion quoting Plato through the intermediary of
the Latin Platonists of late antiquity concerns the motion of the
79. Eriugena: Periph. Ill. 698A Plmzetae tero quae circa eum l'(J/vtmtur
mutant co/ores secundum qualitates spatiorum in quibus discurrunt,
lorem dico et Martem. Venerem et Mercurium, quae semper circulos suos
circa so/em pe,.agunt sicut Plato in Timeo edocet, atque ideo dum supra
so/em sunt claros ostendunt tJultus, dum tJero infra rubeos.
80. That Eriugena is advocating a heliocentric theory of planetary motion
is the opinion of the majority of modern scholars. However. for a dissenting
view see E. von Erhardt-Siebold and R. von Erhardt: The Astronomy of
.fobmmes Scott1s Erigena (Baltimore. MD. 19-40) and Cosmology in tbe An-
notationes in Mardanum. More Ligbt ott Erigena 's Ast1"mwmy (Baltimore,
MD. 1940.) These authors' translation of the passage quoted is totally dif-
ferent.
81. Calcidius: In Tim. 110, 157.6-21.
82. Martianus Capella: De Nupt. VIII. 857. The same theory is expressed in
a less distinct form by Macrobius: In Srmm. Scip. I. 19. 5-6. For excellent
discussion of these passages see W. H. Stahl: Roman Science. Origins,
Derelopment. and Influence to tbe Later Middle Ages (Madison, WI. 1962),
pp. 148-149, 158-160, 183-184.
MEDIAEVAL PLATONISM 79'i
H.~. Eriugt:na: Peripb. Ill, 7320 De Platone sileo, ne l'idear sectam i/lius
sequi. qui diffinil ange/os esse animalia rationabilia immortalia. The
S:lmt: dt:finition is utilized at ibid. IV, 762C-763A.
H-~. Calcidius: In Tim. 13'i. 17'i, 16-18.
H'\. Eriugena: Peripb. I, 476C-D Principia cae/um ac terram camposque
licfuemes I lucentemque glob urn /unae titaniaque astra I spiritus intus alit.
1{(,. M:tcrohius: In Srmm. Scip. I, 14, 14.
H~ Sl'rvius: In Aeneid. VI, 721-726. The same passage of Servius also
reters to the Greeks' description of the totality of God and the world as 'the
All' (to nciv): a notion which Eriugena translates into the Christian context at
Peripb. I, 4698. Cf. however Macrobius: In Somn. Scip. I. 17, 'i.
":'l)(l CONCl.L'SlON
H8. Eriugena: Peripb. Ill. 712 8-C Dum enim caliditas umiditati et
frigid/las ariditali natura/i quodcmt coitu miscentur, omnia quae in terra
et marl nasnmtur procreationem accipitmt. quod etiam poeta intelligebat
clicens: 'Tunc fuller omnlpotens foecwulis lmbrihus aetber I coniugis in
gremium late clescendit'. Patrem siquiclem ignemn qua/itatem, qtwe est
caliditas. foecwulos te1o imbres aquaticam, qtwe est frigid lias, appellat!/1.
crmiugis tero gremium fertilitatem umiditatis, quae est qualitas aeris pro-
pria, et arlditalis, quae est terrm qtwlitatit.la proprietas, tocando unius
L'eluti uxoris nominafiune terram cum sibi proximiuri et corpolentiori aere
significal'it.
H9. Servius: In Georg. II. 325. The same verse is interpreted in less detail at
Augustine: Cit. Dei IV. 10 (CCSl. 4"'. 106-108).
90. For the tl'Xt Sl'C C. l.ambot: LiiJer de Anima ad Oclonem
Be/lcJI'acensem. te.Yte inedit pub/ie par C. L (Analecta Mediaetalia
MEDIAEVAl. PLATONISM
101. Set: Eriugena: In Mart ..~. -i (M), 6, 20 (C); Remigius: In Mart. 6. 20; 7,
2.
102. Remigius: I" Mart. 2i. 1-i; 2i, 14. There art: valuable t'omments in C.
E. Lutz: 'Remigius Ideas on the Classification of the Seven Liberal Arts',
Traditio ll. ( 19'i6), pp. 6'i-86 and 'Remigius' Ideas on the Origin of the Seven
Liberal Arts'. Mediaetalia et Humanlstica I 0 ( 19i6), pp. 3219.
103.SeeEriugena:b1Mar/. i.14;6.20;7.li;9,12(C).
10-i.Remigius:lnMar/.7,16; 19.11.
IO'i.SeeEriugena:ln,'t-far/. 7,10;7,13: 13.2:\(C).
MEDIAEVAl. PLATONISM HOI
106. Eriugena: hz Mart. 32.6 (M); 32.7 (C); Remigius: In Mart. 32.7 ff. See
<i. Schrimpf: 'Idee II A 2', Historiscbes Wiirterbucb der Pbilosopbie 4.
herausgegeben von). Ritter und K. Grunder (Basel, 1976), p. 68.
w-. Eriugena: /11 Mart. 7, 10 (M): " 10 (C); Remigius: In Mart. r, 10. G.
Mathon: 'jean Scot Erigi:ne. Chalddius et le probli:me de l':ime universelle',
pp. 561-57'; demonstrates Eriugena's extensive knowledge of Cakidius on
the basis of these glosses.
I OH. Eriugena: /11 Mart. 15. 2-4; 15. i-IH (;l-1); U. I (C); Remigius: hi Mart .
.. . II; 13. I: 13. 6. On the exposition of Platonism in M and the apparent
niticism of it by Prudent ius of Troyes see H. liebeschiitz: western Christian
Thought from Boethius to Anselm'. Tbc Cambridge History of /.a fer Grcek
and Ear~l' /Hedietal Philosophy. Edited by A. H. Armstrong (Cambridge.
ll)(,-). pp. 'P6-i78 and 'The Place of the Marti;mus G'lossae in the Develop-
llll'nt of Eriugena's Thought'. The Mind of Eriugena. edited by J. J. O'Meara
and 1.. Bieler pp. 49-'iH. On the Macrobian reference in C see Silvestre: op.
cit, pp. 172-17-f.
109. Eriugen;t: /11 Mart. 27, 'i-8: 32. i (.1-1): 31. 12; 34. 5 (C}, Remigius: In
.1/art. 21. II; 26. -t. On the report of Varro's cosmology in M and the :tp-
parlnt criticism of Prudentius of Troyes sec lieheschiitz: 'Western Christian
802 CONCLUSION
Thought from Boethius to Anselm', pp. 576-578 and "The Place of the Mar-
tianus Glossae in the Development of Erlugena's Thought', pp. 49-58.
II 0. There are two main traditions of glossing Boethius" works in the Mid-
dle Ages: one associated with the Opuscula Sacra and one with De Crmsokl-
tione Phi/osophiae. The first tradition is represented by an early commentary
probably from the hand of Remigius of Auxerre (see E. K. Rand: johannes
Scottus (Quel/erz und Ullfersuchungen zur lateinischen Phi/olugie des ,.,fit-
telalters 1/2) (Miinchen, 1906) together with M. Cappuyns: 'Le plus ancien
commentaire des Opuscula Sacra et son origine', Recherches de theologie
ancienne et medietale 3 (19.:H). pp. 237-332 and E. K. Rand: 'The Supposed
Commentary of John the Scot on the Opuscula St1cra of Boethius'. Retue
mfoscolastique de philosophie 36 (1934) (Hommage a M. de Wulj). pp.
67-77). and by an important group of twt:lfth-century works. The second
tradition includes a number of commentaries from the "Anonymous of St.
Gall" in the ninth century onwards: see the titles listed in nn. 112, 114, and
116 for extra<.ts from these texts.
I II. Boethius: De Consol. Phi/os. Ill, m. 9. 1."1-1 5 Tu triplicis mediam
naturtle c:zmcta moventem I conec:tens animllm per consoru1 membrtl
resoltis. I Quae cum secltl duos motum glomeratil in orbes ... for discus-
sion of the mediaeval commentaries on this work see P. Courct:lle: La Con-
solation de Philosophic dans Ia tradition /itteraire. Antecedents et puster/te
de Boece (Paris. 1967). pp. 239-299: F. Troncarelli: 'Per una ricerc:a sui com-
menti altomedicvali at De Consolatione di Boezio , ,.,fiscel/ttnea in memoria
di G. Cencetti (Torino, 19"7."1), pp. 363-380: and). Beaumoll!: 'The Latin
MEDIAEVAL PLATONISM
122. For example. Calcidius has more importance than in the Carolingian
period, while Martianus Capella is somewhat less significant.
123. See T. Gregory: Anima Mundi. La filosofia di Guglielmo di Conches
e Ia smola di Chartres (Firenze, 1955). p. 123 ff. and 184-185; Platonismo
mediezale. Studi e ricerche, p. 136 for some useful illustrations.
12-i. On the influence of these works on Anselm of Canterbury and
William of Conches see K.-D. Nothdurft: Studien zum Einfluss Senecas auf
die Philosophie zmd Theologie des zu6/ften jahrhunderts (Leiden/~oln,
1963). p. 161 ff. and 182 ff.
125. On the influence of Apuleius over john of Salisbury set D. D.
McGarry, The Metalogicon ofjohn of Salisbury. A Twe/fth-Cellfury Defense
of the Verbal cmd Logical Arts of the Trivium, trmzslated with an Introduc-
tion and Notes by D. D. MeG. (Berkeley/Los Angeles. 1955), p. xxiii and
passim.
126. See R. B. Woolsey: 'Bernard Silvester and the Hermetic Asclepius',
Traditio 6 ( 19-iH), pp. 340-34-i and B. Stock: ll1ytb and Science in the Tue/ftb
Century. A Study of Bernard Siltester (Princeton.NJ, 1972). pp. 101-103.
150 ff.. etc.
127. This was clearly because their less metaphysical tendency was ob-
vious to twelfth-century thinkers.
MEDIAEVAL PLATONISM 807
Varro
X.ll INTRODUCTION
809
810 APPENDIX
2. Cicero: Acad. 3.
3. Ibid. 4-8.
4. Ibid. 7. Cf. Plato: Tim. 47b.
5. Cicero: Acad. 9-14.
VARRO 811
14. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 4 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VI, 3 (CCSL 47, 168-169)).
The numbering of the fragments will follow the edition of B. Cardauns.
15. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 6 (Augustine: Civ. Dei. VI, 12 (CCSL 47, 184)) and fr.
7 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VI, 5 (CCSL 47, 170-172)). The scholarship on this
question has been discussed and evaluated by G. Lieberg: 'Die theologia
tripertita in Forschung und Bezeugung', Aufstieg und Niedergang der
romischen Welt: Festschrift]. Vogt I, 4, herausgegeben von H. Temporini
(Berlin, 1973), pp. 63-115. Among more important treatments are]. Oroz de
Ia Consolaci6n: 'lntroducci6n a una theologia agustino-varroniana, vista
desde Ia Ciudad de Dios', La Cuidad de Dios, Numero Extraordinario 1
(studios sobre la Ciudad de Dios) (El Escorial, 1954), pp. 459-473; P.
Boyance: 'Sur Ia theologie de Varron', Revue des etudes anciennes 57 (1955),
pp. 57-85; B. Cardauns: Varros Logistoricus uber die Gotterverehrung (Curio
de cultu deorum). Ausgabe und Erkliirung der Fragmente (Wiirzburg, 1960),
pp. 53-67; ]. Pepin: Mythe et Allegorie. Les origines grecques et les contesta-
tions judeo-chretiennes (Paris, 1958), Nouvelle edition (Paris 1976), pp.
276-392; H. Hagendahl: Augustine and the Latin Classics, with a Contribu-
tion on Varro by B. Cardauns (Goteborg, 1967), pp. 589-666; T. Orlandi:
'Sallustio e Varrone in Agostino, De Civitate Dei I-VII', La parola del passato
23 (1968), pp. 19-44; and G. Barra: Lafigura e l'opera di Terenzio Varrone
Reatino net De Civitate Dei di Agostino (Napoli, 1969).
16. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 7 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VI, 5 (CCSL 47, 170-172)).
814 APPENDIX
17. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 8 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VI, 5 (CCSL 47, 170-172)).
18. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 9 (Augustine: Civ. Dei. VI, 5 (CCSL 47, 170-172)).
19. Varro:Antiqu. fr. 18 (Augustine: Civ. Dei. IV, 31 (CCSL47, 125-126)).
Varro's attitude here has been compared with that of Q. Mucius Scaevola, a
pontijex maximus of the early first century B.C. Augustine: Civ. Dei IV, 27
(CCSL 47, 120-122) reports that Scaevola made a slightly different use of the
tripartite scheme by rejecting the theologies of both the poets and the
philosophers in favor of that of the state. We shall see that Varro's interpreta-
tion is much more complex than this. On the whole question see Boyance:
op. cit., pp. 63-66; Pepin: op. cit., pp. 280-283; and Cardauns: Varros
Logistoricus ii.berdie Gotterverehrung, p. 53 ff.
20. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 12 (Augustine: Civ. Dei IV, 31 (CCSL 47, 125-126)).
VARRO 815
were too base to guide the people and those of the philosophers
too obscure - these two theologies moreover disagreeing with
one another - there are nevertheless many elements which
civil theology can adopt from both sources.
A study of the remaining fragments of Antiquitates I indicates
that Varro 's aim is to investigate the civil theology in terms of its
origin in either myth or natural science, although these two ap-
proaches are clearly not viewed by him as having equal value.
The relation of civil to mythical theology is described in several
fragments, one of which laments the fact that the people were
often more inclined to follow the poets than the philosophers,
with the result that the gods were endowed with sex and paren-
tage.zz The mythical basis of much civil theology is also shown
by the belief that certain heroes of history were transformed in-
to gods, to be eventually worshipped in specific countries -
like Amphiaraus at Thebes - or throughout the world - like
Castor and Pollux.23 Varro contends that such doctrines are
false, although even a mistaken belief in divine parentage could
have a positive social value in encouraging aspiration towards
noble conduct,24 and so it is to natural theology that we should
turn in preference. A number of fragments therefore describe
the relation of civil to natural theology, the most important il-
lustration of this being the location of Jupiter's temple in the
Capitol as an indication of his status as the supreme cosmic prin-
Thus, Dionysius' first group corresponds simply to natural theology, his se-
cond group to natural in relation to mythical theology, and his third group to
natural in relation to civil theology. On this basis a real distinction between
the three groups can be maintained, while the reference to natural theology
alone at the beginning of the text retains its obvious meaning.
22. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 19 (Augustine: Civ. Dei IV, 32 (CCSL 47, 126)).
23. Varro:Antiqu. fr. 31 (Tertullian:Adv. Nat. II, 7, 1 (CCSL 1, 51))andfr.
32 (Servius Danielis: In Aeneid. VIII, 275).
24. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 20 (Augustine: Civ. Dei III, 4 (CCSL 47, 67-68)) and
fr. 21 (Augustine: Civ. DeilY, 31 (CCSL 47, 125-126)).
VARRO 817
25. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 14 (Augustine: Civ. Dei IV, 9 (CCSL 47, 105-106)).
26. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 15 (Augustine: Civ. Dei IV, 9 (CCSL 47, 105-106))
and fr. 16 (Augustine: De Cons. Evang. I, 22, 30 (CSEL 43, 28)).
27. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 24 (Tertullian: Adv. Nat. II, 3, 1, (CCSL 1, 44)).
28. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 33a (Tertullian: Adv. Nat. II, 8, 6 (CCSL 1, 53)).
29. Tertullian: Adv. Nat. II, 9, 3 (CCSL 1, 55) and other testimonia cited by
Cardauns: M. Terentius Varro, Antiquitates rerum divinarum I, p. 63 ff.
818 APPENDIX
30. Augustine: Civ. Dei. VII, 5 (CCSL 47, 190-191)). Varro's tripartite
scheme and its applications invite comparison with certain texts of Cicero
discussing the nature of the gods. See Pepin: op. cit., pp. 300-305. Perhaps
most interesting in this connection is De Nat. Deor. II, 56-69 where the at-
tribute of divinity is applied successively to (i) the world and the heavenly
bodies (ibid. II, 59-60); (ii) things of great utility conferred upon humanity.
For example, corn is Ceres (ibid. 60); (iii) extremely powerful forces. For ex-
ample, Faith and Mind have temples devoted to them on the Capitol (ibid.
61-62); (iv) great human benefactors who have been deemed gods because of
the immortality which their souls earned. For example, Castor and Pollux
(ibid. 62); and (v) figures of poetic fiction which symbolize natural forces.
For example, the belief that Caelus was castrated by his son Saturn, then
Saturn thrown into bondage by his son Jupiter, indicates that the highest ele-
ment of aether or fire which by itself generates all things lacks that bodily
member which requires union with another to achieve procreation (ibid. 63
ff.) Category (i) clearly coincides with Varro's natural theology, whereas
categories (ii), (iii), and (iv) seem to be versions of Varro's civil theology.
However, the extensive developments in category (v) (of which only one il-
lustration has been quoted) seem to go beyond Varro, since the latter tends to
downplay the mythical theology in the Antiquitates. What seems to have oc-
curred is that Varro's theory that civil theology should be purified by increas-
ing its dependence upon natural science and decreasing its dependence upon
myth (Antiqu. fr. 11 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VI, 6 (CCSL 47, 172-174)) has led
him to apply to civil theology the physical allegory which Cicero applied to
mythical theology. The comparison between Varro and Cicero reveals two
important facts: (a) that the various methods of theology interrelate in a very
flexible manner, different authors combining different elements in accor-
dance with their respective philosophical aims; and (b) the most famous prac-
titioners of these methods in the period before Cicero were the Stoics whose
spokesman Balbus is at Cicero: De Nat. Deor. II,. 59 ff.
VARRO 819
38. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 227 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VII, 23 (CCSL 47,
203-205)). It should be noted that Varro uses the term animus for 'mind'
with anima reserved for 'soul' in the wider sense. However, in the previous
fragment animus seems to indicate 'soul' in contrast to body. The flexibility
of terminological usage parallels the Ciceronian practice. See ch. 1, n. 255.
39. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 226 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VII, 6 (CCSL 47, 191)).
40. See pp. 94-99 for the Stoics and 101-118 for Antioch us.
41. Seneca: Consol. ad Helv. 8, 3 'Believe me, this was done by him,
whoever he was, who created the universe, whether he is an omnipotent
god, or an incorporeal reason creating great works, or a divine spirit per-
vading all things both great and small with a uniform tension, or fate and the
unalterable sequence of causes dependent upon one another' (Id actum est,
mibi crede, ab illo, quisquis formator universi fuit, sive ille deus est patens
omnium, sive incorporalis ratio ingentium operum artijex, sive divinus
spiritus per omnia maxima ac minima aequali intentione diffusus, sive
fatum et immutabilis causarum inter se cobaerentium series). Two points
in this passage are worthy of note: (i) The reference to God's incorporeality.
That Platonists of this period attributed incorporeality to God is stated
VARRO 821
44. Augustine: Civ. Dei VII, 13 (CCSL 47, 196-197) ad quemfortasse ceteri
referendi sunt . . . cum hie ipse sint omnes, sive quando partes eius vel
potestates existimantur, sive cum vis animae, quam putant per cuncta dif-
fusam, ex partibus molis buius, in quas visibilis mundus iste consurgit, et
multiplici administratione naturae quasi plurium deorum nomina ac-
cepit. Cf. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 237 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VII, 11 (CCSL 47,
195-196)).
45. For Xcnocrates see Aetius: Plac. I, 7, 30 (DG 304b 17 -22) 'He calls the
watery aspect Poseidon, the generative aspect of earth Demeter. He
paraphrased earlier doctrines of Plato and passed them on to the Stoics' (-ci]v
OE OtU 'tOU uypoi3 TioaEtf>Glvu, -ci]v OE OtU 'tfi~ yfi~ <pU'tOCJ7t6pov dft~TJ'tpU. 'tUU'tU
f>e XOPTJYitau~ -cot~ 1:-cffitKot~ -cu 7tp6-cepu 1tapu -coG Tii..a-cffivo~
~E'tU7tE<ppU KEV).
824 APPENDIX
46. Servius: In Georg. I, 5 (SVF II, 1070). Cf. Servius: In Aeneid. IV, 638
(SVF II, 1070).
47. Philodemus: De Piet. 11 (SVF II, 1076 = DG 545b12-547b16). This
whole passage should be compared with Cicero's account of Chrysippus'
theology at De Nat. Dear. I, 39-41.
48. It is obvious that this passage suggests two ways in which the relation
between unity and plurality is formulated: (i) as the relation between Jupiter
and his various names, and (ii) as the relation between Jupiter and the other
gods. Both occur with equal frequency in Stoic texts. For (i) see Stobaeus:
Eclog. I, 31 (SVF II, 1062); Lydus: De Mens. IV,71,122,15-19 (SVF II, 1063);
for (ii) Plutarch: De Isid. et Osir. 40, 367c (SVF II, 1093); Servius: In Georg. I,
5 (SVF II, 1070); for (i) and (ii) Philodemus: De Piet. 11 (SVF II, 1076 = DG
545b12-547b16); Diogenes Laertius: Vit. Philos. VII, 147 (SVF II, 1021). Both
occur in Varro also. For (i) see Varro: Antiqu. fr. 237 (Augustine: Civ. Dei
VII, 11 (CCSL 47, 195-196)); for (ii) Varro: Antiqu. fr. 229 (Augustine: Civ.
Dei VII, 2 (CCSL 47, 185-186))
VARRO 825
51. See Varro's account of Antiochus' theory (which the following discus-
sion reflects in a mythological mode) at Cicero: Acad. 24-29. See pp.
101-118.
52. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 226 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VII, 6 (CCSL 47, 191)).
53. Two other fragments preserved by Tertullian give information about
VARRO 827
the Varronian cosmology. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 24 (Tertullian: Adv. Nat. II, 3,
7-11 (CCSL 1, 44-45)) states that heaven, earth, and the heavenly bodies are
gods. Furthermore, they are living creatures 'because they are moved by
themselves' (quod per semeiipsa moverentur). This argument should be
compared with Cicero: De Nat. Deor. II, 31-32 where Plato's authority is in-
voked for the equation between self-motion and divinity. Varro: Antiqu. fr.
26 (Tertullian: Adv. Nat. II, 5, 2-7 (CCSL 1, 48)) states that divinity is to be at-
tributed first to the 'elements' (elementa) because nothing could be produced
or sustained without them, and secondly to the sun and moon, to the stars,
and to heaven itself because of their similar role. Cardauns: M. Terentius
Varro, Antiquitates rerum divinarum II, p. 150 enters into unnecessary com-
plications regarding Tertullian's use of the term elementa. Modern scholars
like Boyance: op. cit., pp. 76-77 and Pepin: op. cit., pp. 318-320 trace the
theological doctrine of these passages back to Xenocrates. Thus, Aetius: Plac.
I, 7, 30 (DG 304b10-14) reports this writer's view that the heaven, the 'fiery
stars' (toile; aatepac; 7tUpc00Etc; ) equivalent to the Olympians, and the
sublunary demons are gods.
54. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 227 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VII, 23 (CCSL 203-205)).
828 APPENDIX
65. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 205 (Macrobius: Saturn. III, 4, 8) Penates esse dix-
erunt per quos penitus spiramus, per quos habemus corpus, per quos ra-
tionem animi possidemus: esse autem medium aethera Jovem, Junonem
vero imum aera cum terra et Minervam summum aetheris cacumen: et
argumento utuntur quod Tarquinius, Demarati Corinthii filius,
Samothracicis religionibus mystice imbutus, uno templo ac sub eodem tecto
numina memorata coniunxit. The same doctrine is stated in slightly dif-
ferent wording at Servius Danielis: In Aeneid. II, 296.
832 APPENDIX
66. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 206 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VII, 28 (CCSL 47, 210-211))
in simulacris aliud signijicare caelum, aliud terram, aliud exempla rerum,
quas Plato appellat ideas; caelum Iovem, terram Iunonem, ideas Miner-
vam (vult intellegi); caelum a quo fiat aliquid, terram de qua fiat, ex-
emplum secundum quod fiat.
67. This interpretation of the Samothracian mysteries has been much
VARRO 833
whole, while the first triad signifies three moments in the con-
stitution of the human individual, these two passages are con-
cerned not only with the threefold analysis of being itself but
with a structural parallelism between macrocosm and
microcosm. 68 Many of the terms occurring in this scheme can
be adequately explained with reference to their use in the other
Varronian texts examined earlier, although certain points are
perhaps sufficiently obscure to require further clarification.
First, the term 'soul' is not explicitly mentioned in the initial
triad but only the notion of life. However, it seems reasonable
to supply it not only because it is required by the context - it is
juxtaposed with the two terms reason and body - but because
other texts identify Jupiter and soul. Varro clearly inserted the
phrase 'innermost life' in place of the term 'soul' simply because
he wished to exploit the etymology: Penates - penitus.69
Secondly, the interpretation of Minerva as the higher aether is
very characteristic of Stoic exegesis, as indicated by Diogenes
Laertius' report that this school called the cosmic God 'Athene'
'because the ruling part of the divinity extends to the aether'
(Kat a ti)v de; atetpa ouita<Jtv 'tOO TtYEJlOVtKOD UU'tOD). 70 This in-
terpretation is also common in late antiquity, since Macrobius,71
discussed in the modern literature. See especially Theiler: op. cit., pp. 18-19
and 40; Pepin: op. cit., pp. 347-351; Boyance: op. cit., pp. 77 -78; Cardauns:
Varros Logistoricus iiber die Gotterverehrung (Curio de cultu deorum), pp.
12-16 and M. Terentius Varro, Antiquitates rerum divinarum II, pp. 220-222
and 234-235.
68. See pp. 99-100 and 119.
69. Varro's use of etymology in such contexts is discussed by P. Boyance:
'Etymologie et theologie chez Varron', Revue des etudes Ia tines 53 (1975),
pp. 99-115.
70. Diogenes Laertius: Vit. Philos. VII, 147 (SVF II, 1021). Cf. Philodemus:
De Piet. 15 (SVF III, Diogenes of Babylon 33 = DG 548b 14-550b8).
71. Macrobius: Saturn. I, 17, 70 'For this goddess is said to have been
generated from the head of Jupiter, that is to say produced from the highest
part of the aether, whence the sun takes its origin' (nam ideo haec dea Iovis
834 APPENDIX
82. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 232 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VII, 8 (CCSL 47, 192-193)).
83. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 234 (Augustine: Civ, Dei VII, 8 (CCSL 47, 192-193)).
84. On the allegory of Saturn see Pepin: op. cit., p. 328 ff.
85. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 239 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VII, 13 (CCSL 47, 196-197))
and fr. 240 (Tertullian: Adv. Nat. II, 12, 18 (CCSL 1, 62)).
86. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 245 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VII, 19 (CCSL 47,
201-202)).
87. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 241 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VII, 18 (CCSL 47,
200-201)). The interpretation of the relations between Caelus, Saturn, and
Jupiter in Varro is singled out by Augustine as a clear example of the former's
inconsistency. As Augustine remarks (Civ. Dei VII, 19 (CCSL 47, 20 1-202)), if
Saturn is the son of Caelus, then he is the son of Jupiter, since Jupiter is stated
elsewhere to be equivalent to the heaven. Augustine is quite correct about
Varro's identification of Jupiter with the heaven, yet the charge of incon-
sistency misses the real point of Varro's natural theology. That is that there
are no fixed physical interpretations of any of the traditional gods, since the
latter simply represent ways of looking at the same set of natural processes.
The essence of the symbolic mentality is that it deals with approximations
VARRO 837
rather than with precise equations. Further, Varro believed that the civil
theology was a historical fact and not a methodological ideal, and he would
no doubt have admitted readily that there were inconsistencies of this kind.
When considered in its proper historical context, therefore, Varro's theology
can be defended against the polemic of Christian writers.
88. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 247 (Tertullian: Adv. Nat. II, 12, 17 (CCSL 1, 62)).
89. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 242 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VII, 19 (CCSL 47, 201-202))
andfr. 246(Augustine: Civ. DeiVII, 19(CCSL47, 201-202)).
90. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 251 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VII, 16 (CCSL 47, 199)).
91. Seep. 757 ff.
838 APPENDIX
92. The structure of Varro's thought at this point, as at many others, mir-
rors that of Cicero. See pp. 99-1 00 and 119.
93. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 226 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VII, 6 (CCSL 47, 191)). See
pp. 819-820.
94. Varro probably employed the doxographical tradition after the manner
of Antioch us rather than according to the practice of Philo of Larissa which
Cicero followed. On the relationship of such doxographical compilation to
(i) Old Academic dogmatism and (ii) New Academic skepticism see p. 63 ff.
The clearest illustration ofVarro's handling of doxography is provided by his
discussion of the various theories of the supreme good in his De Philosophia.
Fragments of this work are preserved by Augustine: Civ. Dei XIX, 1-4 (CCSL
48, 657-669)) from whom we discover that Varro employed different
variables in order to construct a classification of two hundred and eighty-
eight possible philosophical doctrines regarding the end of man. They are
'possible' in the sense that some have actually existed while some are merely
postulated theoretically. Having established this classification, Varro then
proceeds to eliminate each variable in turn until only one philosophy re-
mains, this coinciding with the Old Academy's doctrine as interpreted by An-
VARRO 839
character is fiery and that, just as fire governs all things in the
world, so does soul control all things in the human being.95
Since the fire mentioned in this passage seems equivalent to the
aether mentioned in other texts,96 soul must therefore corres-
pond to divinity in relation both to the world and to man. Thus,
in a second passage, this time preserved by Augustine, the
various levels of soul are considered, and its highest aspect is
called 'God' (deus) in the case of the world and 'personal deity'
(genius) in that of man:97 an argument which then passes into a
typically Varronian mythological interpretation of the nature of
soul.98 It is the combined doctrine presented by these texts
which explains the argument of a final passage. Here, the
fashioning of gods' anthropomorphic images is justified on the
grounds that, 99 since the relation of the divine soul to the world
is analogous to that of the human soul to its body, it is possible
to signify the thing contained in the former case by the con-
tainer in the latter. too The argument is perhaps the most striking
tiochus. Of great interest is the fact that one of the variables in this scheme is
'certain' (certum) versus 'probable' (veri simile) according to which one
might distinguish a Stoic from a New Academic position. It is easy to see that
the distinction between Varro's and Cicero's respective uses of dox-
ographical material is along precisely the same lines. The fragments of De
Philosophia can now be conveniently studied in the collection of G.
Langenberg: M. Terenti Varronis Liber de philosophia, Ausgabe und
Erkli:irungderFragmente, Diss. (Koln, 1959).
95. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 23 (Tertullian: Adv. Nat. II, 2, 14-20 (CCSL 1,
43-44)).
96. See pp. 827 and 831-835.
97. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 227 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VII, 3 (CCSL 47, 186-189)).
98. In this and all the other passages cited during this section of the discus-
sion, the Latin term animus will be translated as 'soul' (rather than as
'mind'), since the contrast is between soul and body (rather than between
mind and lower soul). Varro uses animus in both these senses as does Cicero.
Seen. 38.
99. Varro: Antiqu. fr. 225 (Augustine: Civ. Dei VII, 5 (CCSL 47, 190-191)).
100. Varro's argument clearly contains several suppressed premises: (i)
840 APPENDIX
that one can signify the contained by the container, and (ii) that what
signifies in relation to the microcosm can carry a similar significance in rela-
tion to the macrocosm. Of course, it is possible that it is Augustine who has
suppressed the premises in a careless paraphrase.
101. On Varro's influence over the scientific tradition see W. H. Stahl:
Roman Science. Origins, Development, and Influence to the Later Middle
Ages (Madison, WI, 1962), pp. 74-76.
BIBLIOGRAPHICAL NOTE (1985)
841
Bibliographies
BIBLIOGRAPHY 1
845
846 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Reid, J.S. M. Tullii Ciceronis Academica. The Text Revised and Explained
by].S.R. (London, 1885).
Reinhardt, K. Poseidonios (Miinchen, 1921).
Kosmos und Sympathie. Neue Untersuchungen iiber Poseidonios
(Miinchen, 1926).
Robin, L. Pyrrhon et le scepticisme grec (Paris, 1944).
*Ronconi, A. Cicerone, Somnium Scipionis. Introduzione e commento a
curadiA.R. (Firenze, 1961).
Ruch, M. L 'Hortensius de Ciceron. Histoire et reconstitution (Paris, 1958).
Le preambule dans les oeuvres philosophiques de Ciceron. Essai
sur Ia genese et I'art du dialogue (Paris, 1958).
Etudes ciceroniennes (Paris, 1970).
'Un exemple de syncretisme philosophique de Ciceron. Academica
posteriora 21 ',Revue des etudes latines 48 (1970), 205-228.
Saltzmann, R. Uber Ciceros Kenntnis der platonischen Schriften (Kleve,
1885).
*Sambursky, S. Physics of the Stoics (London, 1959).
Sandbach, F.H. 'evvma and 7tp6A.T]\j/tc; in the Stoic Theory of Knowledge',
Classical Quarterly 24 (1930), pp. 44-51.
*Scarpa, L. 'Sistema celeste e armonia delle sfere nel Somnium Scipionis
ciceroniano', Attie memorie dell'Accademia Patavina di Scienze, Lettere
ed Arti, Classe di scienze morali, lettere ed arti 87 (1974-1975), pp.
17-24.
Schmidt, P .L. 'Cicero: De republica: Die Forschung der letzten fiinf
Dezennien', Aufstieg und Niedergang der romischen Welt: Festschrift].
Vogt I, 4. herausgegeben von H. Temporini (Berlin, 1973), pp. 262-333.
'Zur Typologie und Literarisierung des friihchristlichen la-
teinischen Dialogs', Christian isme et formes litteraires de I'antiquite tar-
dive en occident (Fondation Hardt, Entretiens sur l'antiquite classique
23)(Vandoeuvres-Geneve, 1977), pp. 101-190 .
'Formtradition und Realitatsbezug im friihchristlichen lateinischen
Dialog', Wiirzburger ]ahrbiicher fiir die Altertumswissenschaft, N. F. 3
(1977), pp. 211-225.
'Cicero's Place in Roman Philosophy. A Study of his Prefaces',
Classical]ourna/74 (1978-1979), pp. 115-127.
Schulte, K. Orator, Untersuchungen iiber das ciceronianischen Bildungs-
Ideal(Frankfurt a.M., 1935).
Silbiger, S.F. 'Cicero Platonis aemulus', Eos 37 (1936), pp. 19-26 and
129-142.
Solignac, A. 'Doxographies et manuels dans Ia formation philosophique de
saint Augustin', Recherches augustiniennes 1 (Paris, 1958), pp. 113-148.
BIBLIOGRAPHY 853
855
856 BIBLIOGRAPHY
BIBLIOGRAPHY 2: SUPPLEMENT
BIBLIOGRAPHY 3: SUPPLEMENT
859
860 BIBLIOGRAPHY
861
862 BIBLIOGRAPHY
BIBLIOGRAPHY 4: SUPPLEMENT
Abt, A. Die Apologie des Apuleius von Madaura und die antike Zauberei.
Beitriige zur Erliiuterung der Schrift De magia (Berlin, 1963).
Fortenbaugh, W. On Stoic and Peripatetic Ethics. The Work of Arius
Didymus, edited by W.F. (New Brunswick,NJ, 1983).
Hidalgo, M.J. 'La magia y la religion en las obras de Apuleyo', Zephyrus
30-31 (1980), pp. 223-230.
Invernizzi, G. Il Didaskalikos di Albino e il medioplatonismo. Saggio di
interpretazione storico-filosofica con introduzione e commento del
Didaskalikos 1-11 (Roma, 1976).
Mahe, J.P. 'Quelques remarques sur la religion des Metamorphoses
d'Apulee et les doctrines gnostiques contemporaines', Revue des sciences
religieuses46(I972),pp. 1-19.
Michel, A. 'Sophistique et philosophic dans l'Apologie d'Apulee', Vita
Latina 77 (1980), pp. 12-21.
Pennacini, A., Donini, P.L., Alimonti, T. e Monteduro Roccavini, A.
Apuleio: letterato, filosofo, mago (Bologna, 1979).
Perkins, P. 'On the Origin of the World (C.G. II, 5). A Gnostic Physics',
Vigiliae Christianae 35 (1980), pp. 36-46.
Segura Menguia, S. Apuleyo. Apologia, Florida. Introducci6n, traduci6n
y notas de S.S.M., revidado de F. Pejenaute Rubio (Madrid, 1980).
BIBLIOGRAPHY 5
BIBLIOGRAPHY 5: SUPPLEMENT
Carozzi, P .A. 'Hoc lumine salvati tuo (Asclepius 41)', Perennitas: Studi in
onore di A. Brelich (Roma, 1980), pp. 115-138.
BIBLIOGRAPHY 6
*Baeumker, C. Das Problem der Materie in der griechischen Philosophie.
Eine historisch-kritische Untersuchung (Munster, 1890).
*Beutler, R. 'Numenios', Paulys Realencyclopi:idie der klassischen Alter-
tumswissenschaft, Suppl.-Band 7 (Stuttgart, 1940), col. 664-678.
*den Boeft,J. Calcidius on Fate. His Doctrine and Sources (Leiden, 1970).
* Calcidius on Demons (Commentarius, ch. 127-136) (Leiden,
1977).
*de C1erq, V.C. Ossius of Cordova (Washington, DC, 1954).
Courcelle, P. 'Ambroise de Milan et Calcidius', Romanitas et Chris-
tianitas: Studia /.H. Waszink oblata ... edited by W. den Boer, etc.
(Amsterdam, 1973), pp. 45-53.
*Dillon,J. The Middle Platonists. A Study of Platonism 80 B. C. to A.D. 220
(London, 1977).
*Dodds, E. R. 'The Parmenides of Plato and the Origins of the Neoplatonic
One', Classical Quarterly 22 (1928), pp. 129-143.
* 'Numenius and Ammonius', Les sources de Plotin (Fondation
Hardt, Entretiens sur l'Antiquite classique 5) (Vandoeuvres-Geneve
(1960), pp. 1-61.
Proclus, The Elements of Theology. A Revised Text with Transla-
tion, Introduction and Commentary. Second Edition (Oxford, 1963).
*Dorrie, H. 'Kontroversen urn die Seelenwanderung im kaiserzeitlichen
Platonismus', Hermes 85 (1957), pp. 414-435.
* Porphyrios' Symmikta Zetemata. Ihre Stellung in System und
Geschichte des Neuplatonismus nebst einem Kommentar zu den
Fragmenten (Miinchen, 1959).
*Festugiere, A.-J. La revelation d'Hermes Trismegiste III: Les doctrines de
l'dme (Paris, 1953).
* La revelation d'Hermes Trismegiste IV: Le Dieu inconnu et Ia
gnose (Paris, 1954).
*Gercke, A. 'Eine platonische Quelle des Neuplatonismus', Rheinisches
Museum 41 (1886), pp. 266-291.
*Gersh, S. From Iamblichus to Eriugena. An Investigation of the
Prehistory and Evolution of the Pseudo-Dionysian Tradition (Studien
zur Problemgeschichte der antiken und mittelalterlichen Philosophie 8)
(Leiden, 1978).
* Hadot, P. Porphyre et Victorinus (Paris, 1968).
*Hiller, E. 'De Adrasti Peripatetici in Platonis Timaeum commentario',
Rheinisches Museum, N. F. 26 (1871), pp. 582-589.
*Jones, R.M. 'Chalcidius and Neoplatonism', Classical Philology 13 (1918),
pp. 194-208.
871
872 BIBLIOGRAPHY
*Kissling, R.C. 'The oxruJ.a - 7tVEUIJ.<l of the Neoplatonists and the De Insom-
niis of Synesius of Cyrene', American journal of Philology 43 (1922), pp.
318-330.
*Kramer, H.J. Der Ursprung der Geistmetaphysik. Untersuchungen zur
Geschichte des Platonismus zwischen Platon und Plotin (Amsterdam,
1964).
*Krause, H. Studia neoplatonica (Leipzig, 1904).
*Leemans, E.A. Studie over den Wijsgeer Numenius van Apamea met
Uitgave der Fragmenten (Brussel, 1937).
*Lewy, H. Chaldaean Oracles and Theurgy. Mysticism, Magic and
Platonism in the Later Roman Empire (Recherches d'archeologie, de
philologie et d'histoire 13) (Cairo, 1956). Nouvelle edition par M. Tardieu
(Paris, 1978).
*Martano, G. Numenio d' Apamea. Un precursore del neoplatonismo
(Napoli, 1960).
*Martin, T. Theonis Smyrnaei Liber de Astronomia cum Sereni fragmento.
Textum primus edidit ... T.M. (Paris, 1849).
*O'Donnell,J.R. 'The Meaning of Silva in the Commentary on the Timaeus
of Plato by Chalcidius', Mediaeval Studies 7 (1945), pp. 1-20.
*O'Meara, D.J. 'Being in Numenius and Plotinus. Some Points of Com-
parison', Phronesis 21 (1976), pp. 120-129.
*Puech, H.-C. 'Numenius d'Apamee et les theologies orientales au second
siecle', Melanges]. Bidez II (Bruxelles, 19 34), pp. 745-778.
Sodano, A.R. 'Su una recente edizione critica del commento di Calcidio a!
Timeo di Platone', Giornale italiano difilologia 16 (1963) pp. 339-349.
* Steinheimer, E. Untersuchungen iiber die Que/len des Chalcidius (Aschaf-
fenburg, 1912).
*Stettner, W. Die Seelenwanderung bei Griechen und Romern (Stuttgart,
1934).
*Switalski, B.W. Des Chalcidius Kommentar zu Plato's Timaeus. Eine
historisch-kritische Untersuchung (Beitrage zur Geschichte der
Philosophie des Mittelalters 3/6) (Munster, 1902).
*Theiler, W. Die chaldaischen Orakel und die Hymnen des Synesios (Halle,
1942).
'Ammonios und Porphyrios', Porpbyre (Fondation Hardt, Entre-
tiens sur l'Antiquite classique 12) (Vandoeuvres-Geneve, 1966), pp.
84-123.
* Forschungen zum Neuplatonismus (Berlin, 1966).
'Vita/is vigor bei Calcidius', Romanitas et Christianitas. Studia
/.H. Waszink ... oblata, edited by W. den Boer, etc. (Amsterdam, 1973).
BIBLIOGRAPHY 873
BIBLIOGRAPHY 6: SUPPLEMENT
875
876 BIBLIOGRAPHY
BIBLIOGRAPHY 7: SUPPLEMENT
(Catania, 1979).
Regali, M. 'La quadripartizione delle virtu nei Commentarii di Macrobio',
AteneeRoma 25 (1980), pp. 166-172.
Scarpa, L. Commentariorum in Somnium Scipionis libri duo. Introdu-
zione, testa, traduzione e note a cura di L.S. (Padova, 1981).
Sodano, A.R. Porfirio, Introduzione agli intelligibili. Traduzione, com-
mentario e note con il testa greco, a cura di A.R. S. (Napoli, 1979).
BIBLIOGRAPHY 8
BIBLIOGRAPHY 8: SUPPLEMENT
885
886 BIBLIOGRAPHY
ziani (Pavia, 5-8 ottobre 1980) a cura di L. Obertello (Roma, 1981), pp.
141-156.
*Rist, J.M. 'Mysticism and Transcendence in Later Neoplatonism', Hermes
92 (1964), pp. 213-225.
* 'The Problem of Otherness in the Enneads', Le Neoplatonisme
(Colloque International du Centre National de Ia Recherche Scientifique,
Royaumont9-13juin 1969)(Paris, 1971), pp. 77-88.
Rodolfi, F. 'II De Arithmetica di Boezio', La scuola cattolica 8 (1894), pp.
422-428.
*Rutten, C. 'La doctrine des deux actes dans Ia philosophic de Plotin', Revue
philosophique 81 (1956), pp. 100-106.
*Saffrey, H.D. et Westerink, L.G. Proclus, Theologie platonicienne. Livre
I, texte etabli et traduit par H. D. S. et L. G. W. (Paris, 1968).
*Scheible, H. Die Gedichte in der Consolatio philosophiae des Boethius
(Heidelberg, 1972).
Schmid, W. 'Philosophisches und medizinisches in der Consolatio des
Boethius', Festschrift B. Snell (Miinchen, 1956), pp. 113-144.
'Boethius and the Claims of Philosophy', Studia Patristica 2
(Berlin, 1957), pp. 368-375.
*Schmidt-Kohl, V. Die neuplatonische Seelenlehre in der Consolatio
philosophiae des Boethius (Meisenheim am Glan, 1965).
Schrade, L. 'Die Stellung der Musik in der Philosophic des Boethius als
Grundlage der ontologischen Musikerziehung', Archiv fiir Geschichte der
Philosophie 41 (1932), pp. 368-400.
'Music in the Philosophy of Boethius', Musical Quarterly 33
(1947), pp. 188-200.
*Schrimpf, G. Die Axiomenschrift des Boethius (De hebdomadibus) als
philosophisches Lehrbuch des Mittelalters (Studien zur Problem-
Geschichte der antiken und mittelalterlichen Philosophie 2) (Leiden,
1966).
*Schurr, V. Die Trinitatslehre des Boethius im Lichte der skythischen Kon-
troversen (Paderborn, 1935).
Sciuto, F. 'II dualismo nella Consolatio di Boezio', Acta philologica 3:
Piae memoriae N.J. Herescu (Roma, 1964), pp. 361-371.
Semeria, G. 'II cristianesimo di Severino Boezio rivendicato', Studi e
documenti di storia e diritto 21 (1900), pp. 61-178.
Shiel, J. 'Boethius' Commentaries on Aristotle', Mediaeval and
RenaissanceStudies4 (1958), pp. 217-244.
'Boethius the Hellenist', History Today 14 (1964), pp. 478-486.
*Silk, E. T. 'Boethius' Consolatio Philosophiae as a Sequel to Augustine's
BIBLIOGRAPHY 895
BIBLIOGRAPHY 9: SUPPLEMENT
BIBLIOGRAPHY X: SUPPLEMENT
The following principles have been used to govern the citation of texts:
Latin Platonic works are cited according to the editions described in the
Index. These editions are mostly contained in the Bibliotheca Teubneriana,
and Collection Bude, the Oxford Classical Texts, and the Loeb Classical
Library.
Christian Latin authors are cited according to the Corpus Christianorum
Series Latina, the Corpus Scriptorum Ecclesiasticorum Latinorum, and the
Patrologia Latina, in that order of priority.
Greek Platonic works are normally cited according to the texts listed in the
bibliography of my book From Iamblichus to Eriugena (Leiden, 1978), p.
347 ff. In addition to the versions tabulated there I have used: Albinus,
Didascalicus (P. Louis (CB)); Numenius, Fragments (E. des Places (CB));
Porphyry: De Abstinentia Q. Bouffartigue and M. Patillon (CB)); De Antro
Nympharum (Arethusa Monographs); De Regressu Animae 0. Bidez: Vie de
Porphyre (Ghent, 1913)); Historia Philosophica (A. Nauck (BT)); In
Parmenidem (P. Hadot: Porphyre et Victorinus (Paris 1968)); In Timaeum
(A. R. Sodano (Napoli, 1964)); Sententiae (E. Lamberz (BT)); De Simulacris
(Bidez: op. cit.)
On certain occasions I have resorted to editions other than those described
in the Index. These occasions are noted at the appropriate points in my text.
901
INDEX OF LATIN TEXTS
Ambrose nn.250, 252;
Hexameron 613, n.40
(CSEL 32/1, Schenkl) 65 221, n.22; 267;
273
I, 1, 1-4 397
De Deo Socratis
(CB, Beaujeu)
Apuleius
Apologia I, 115 228
(CB, Vallette) 1, 116 303, n.313
1,116-3,
4 216 124 231
10 217 1, 117 272, n.180
11 220, n.21 1, 118 305, n.322
12 221, n.22; 292; 2, 120 304; 306
315,n.364 2, 121 303; 307
13 217, n.9 2, 121-122 315, n.367
15 216 2, 122 303
25 221, n.22 3, 123 303; 306
26 221, n.22 3, 124 266, n.145;
27 270; 292, 267; 272; 273;
n.263 613, n.40
29-36 216 4, 126 316, n.369
36 216; 216, n.2 4, 127 231, n.61; 301,
38 216, n.2 nn.305, 306
40-42 216 4, 128 233, n.68; 301
41 217, n.9; 221, 6, 132 309; 310,
n.22 n.344
42 236, n.78 6, 133-134 310
43 221, n.22; 309; 6, 134 231, n.61
310, n.345 7, 136 301, n.308
49-50 221, n.22 7, 137 301, n.308
55 216 8, 138 305, n.323
64 220; 221, n.22; 9, 140-141 310, n.344
266; 266, 11, 143-145 314, n.363
n.145; 267, 12, 146 301
n.I48; 270; 12, 146- 13,
272; 273; 289, 148 231, n.61
903
904 INDEX
Augustine I, 1, 10,
De Diversis Quaestionibus LXXXIII 11-13 667, n.76
(CCSL 44A, Mutzenbecher) I, 2, 12,
14-17 667
46 406; 777 I, 32, 66,
8-11 667
II, 31, 122,
25-123,3 667
Boethius II, 46, 149,
Contra Eutycben et Nestorium 22 702, n.246
(LCL, Stewart and Rand)
CENSORINUS 3 810
De Die Natali 4-8 8IO
(BT, Sallmann) 7 68; 810
9-I4 810
I, 6 390, n.IO I3 69, n.49
2, I - 3, 6 389 15-I9 75, n.76
2, 2 39I, n.13 17-I8 66, n.33
4, 1 - I 3, 6 391, n.14 17-I9 164, n.33
4, 3 390, n.11 24 101
5, I - 13, 6 389 24-29 826, n.5I
922 INDEX
XIII, 19 62
ProMurena
(CB, Boulanger)
Epistulae ad Familiares
(Shackleton-Bailey) 263 67, n.39
I, 9 68, n.46
IX, 22 68, n.45 Timaeus
(BT, Giomini)
Lucullus 1 9
(BT, Plasberg) 5 10
6 295, n.276
17 134
18 134, n.288
19-20 141 Topica
21-22 141 (SCBO, Wilkins)
30-31 142
Ill 60 26-27 132
116 74, n.75 31 132
121 60, n.11
126 828, n.55
129 74, n.75 Tusculanae Disputationes
139 68 (BT, Pohlenz)
142 74, n.75
145 135, n.291 I, 8 59; 62
I, 9-25 120
I, 18 125, n.253
Orator I, 18-22 61
(BT, Westman) I, 20 126
I, 22 109; 645,
7ff. 147 n.242
926 INDEX
I, 23 62 126
I, 26-81 120 I, 97-99 71, n.S9
I, 35-36 121 I, 103 71, n.S8
I, 36 123; 408, n.7 II, 5 79
I, 38 140, n.312 11,9 59, n.9
I, 39 68, nn.44, 46; III, 2 133; 139,
121 n.308
I, 40 125, n.253 III, 10 140, n.311
I, 40-75 121 III, 11 140, n.312
I, 42 122; 125 IV, 6 66; 67
I, 44 133, n.281 IV, 7 58
I, 45 140; 304, IV, 35 515, n.123
n.318 IV, 44 68, n.46
I, 46 140 IV, 53 133
I, 49 121 V, 7 74
I, 51 126 v, 8-11 62, n.22
I, 53-54 123 V, 32-33 60
I, 53-55 70, n.57 v, 35 71, n.60
I, 57 71, n.64 v, 36 71, n.62
I, 57ff. 734, n.61 V, 37 98
I, 57-58 149 V, 39 140, n.310
I, 58 295, n.280 v, 61-62 515, n.123
I, 59 ISO v, 68 74, n.75
I, 60 124 V, 70 130, n.274
I, 62-63 123 v, 83 60, n.11
I, 63 71, n.65
I, 64-65 123 FAVONIUS EULOGIUS
I, 65 124 Disputatio de Somnio Scipionis
I, 65-66 123, n.245 (Scarpa)
I, 66 124
I, 67 126, n.257 1, 1 500, n.31
I, 67-70 124, n.248 1, 2 938, n.11
I, 70 11 2, 1-2 737; 739, n.20
I, 70-71 123, n.243; 3, 1 739
126, n.257 4, 1-2 739
I, 71 126 5, 1-2 739
I, 72-73 128 5, 2 739; 740; 742
I, 73 126 5, 2-3 737
I, 75 127 5, 4 739; 740; 741,
I, 78-79 122 n. 37; 472,
I, 80 125, n.255; n.40
INDEX 927
lnBucolica
(Thilo and Hagen) In Georgica
(Thilo and Hagen)
2, 31 749
3,60 749 II, 336 750, n.27; 754,
5,66 510, n.95; 749; n.ss
750, n.25; 755,
n.59
8, 29 754, n.55 VARRO
8, 75 750 Antiquitates Rerum Divinarum
(Cardauns)