Economics, Ethics and Green Consumerism: December 2001
Economics, Ethics and Green Consumerism: December 2001
Economics, Ethics and Green Consumerism: December 2001
net/publication/279719539
CITATIONS READS
5 481
1 author:
Jouni Paavola
University of Leeds
126 PUBLICATIONS 6,045 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
All content following this page was uploaded by Jouni Paavola on 27 April 2016.
This article examines green consumerism or the making of consumer choices at least
partly on the basis of environmental concerns. It has two different goals. First, the article
aims to clarify the promises and pitfalls of green consumerism as a way of transforming our
current consumption patterns towards a more sustainable direction. Second, the article seeks
to demonstrate that an economic approach is useful for understanding social and environmen-
Green consumerism is an interesting and important object of analysis for several reasons.
First, consumer choices have a significant effect on the environment and, therefore, also a
(see e.g. Elgin, 1993) are becoming fashionable and the belief in their ability to improve envi-
ronmental outcomes is increasingly widely shared. Finally, attention in both scholarship and
international policy arenas is moving toward consumption. It is increasingly felt that the po-
or is already largely exhausted (see e.g. Cogoy, 1999; Crocker and Linden, 1998; Georg,
1999; Jackson and Marks, 1999; OECD, 1997a, 1997b, 1998; Røpke, 1999).
Economics is not by any means an obvious candidate for other social scientists to gain
deeper understanding of consumer behaviour. After all, economic theorising in its usual form
is based on narrow and counterfactual assumptions concerning human behaviour, which ren-
der consumption as an object of analysis devoid of symbolic and social dimensions. In es-
sence, the traditional economic approach has viewed consumption as a string of rational
choices that individuals make to maximise their personal welfare without regard to the con-
sequences of their choices for other humans and non-humans and without regard to the choic-
2
es made by others and their consequences. Even economists themselves have sometimes con-
sidered the theory of consumer choice as an area of research, which has not developed essen-
Yet some relatively recent developments in economics promise to make it more amena-
ble and fruitful for the kinds of inquiries into consumption that interest other social scientists.
These developments include the recent revival of the interest in the study of interdependent
consumer choices, originally pioneered by Thorstein Veblen at the turn of the 20th century
(see e.g. Corneo and Jeanne 1997; Frank 1985, 1991; Veblen 1899). Another area of research
in the interstices of economics and philosophy has made space for non-welfarist behavioural
motivations and examined their implications for economic analysis (see e.g. Sen 1977, 1979;
Anderson 1993, Kavka, 1991, 1993). Finally, the ever more popular game theory provides a
In essence, as I will seek to demonstrate below, at its best economics enables us to ana-
lyse consumer choices as choices of agents that have plural values and act on socially con-
structed identities and knowledge. Often their choices are interdependent, that is, moves in
games for distinction in a context in which different agents have internalised different rules
for distinction. Some agents may thus seek to display their wealth in the Veblenian (1899)
fashion, while others may seek brownie points in their subcultures by resorting to green con-
sumerism or lifestyles, for example. The paper also demonstrates that we can infer policy and
other lessons from analysing consumption games that are characterised by plural motivations.
These lessons indicate, inter alia, that green consumerism may need to be supplemented with
In what follows, the first section describes the usual understanding in economics of con-
sumption as a series of independent and welfare-seeking consumer choices, and the limited
role green consumerism can play in this model. The second section demonstrates how this
3
standard model can be expanded to accommodate plural values and a broader notion of green
consumerism. The third section examines the significance of the interdependence of consum-
er choices in a game-theoretic framework, and the fourth section works out the implications
of value pluralism for interdependent consumer choices. The fifth section examines in greater
detail the implications of green consumerism when value pluralism prevails. The conclusions
will summarise and elaborate upon the arguments of the previous sections.
The model of rational choice (see e.g. Hargreaves Heap et al., 1992) is a useful starting
point for understanding how economics has traditionally approached consumption and how it
understands green consumerism. The rational choice model has it that consumers are interest-
ed exclusively in their own utility or welfare and that they rank choice alternatives according
to how choosing them would enhance their welfare. The model also assumes that consumers
have limitless cognitive capabilities so that they can obtain perfect knowledge about the
choice alternatives they face and that they make choices that do maximise their welfare. Fi-
nally, consumers are not understood to have any control over what alternatives are available
for them: market forces generate the menu of choice alternatives they face.
Three different views of items of consumption and their relation to the utility or welfare
of the choosing agent coexist in economics. The first view that is embodied in the standard
microeconomic approach assumes that the items of consumption somehow directly translate
into enhanced utility or welfare: this “naïve” view collapses consumption into acquisition.
The second, more realistic view has it that the items of consumption have characteristics that
are useful for consumers (see Lancaster, 1966). This approach is able to treat the act of con-
sumption as distinct from the act of buying, but it still usually incorporates a narrow and
problematic notion of consumption as an isolated and individual activity. Finally, the third
4
view is that the items of consumption such as steak, wine and candles generate utility only
indirectly after being transformed into final goods such as candlelight dinners by household
production (see Becker, 1976; Stigler and Becker, 1977). This view would enable a rich and
acting on plural motivations. This is not usually the case. Quite the contrary, scholars in this
mentally centred on the agents’ welfare (see e.g. Stigler and Becker, 1977).
More broadly, all traditional economic theories assume the consumers to be motivated by
the improvement of their personal utility or welfare only. These traditional theories also usu-
ally fail to make a distinction between utility and welfare and assume that whatever values
inform agents’ preferences, the choices made on the basis of these preferences must improve
the choosing agent’s welfare. Early economic theory indeed warranted this close association
of utility and welfare. It provided a strong link between the utility, welfare, and preferences
of agents by associating utility with pleasure or usefulness: agents simply preferred things
that made them happier and better off (see Georgescu-Roegen, 1968; Sen, 1991). However,
in the early 20th century utility was redefined as the satisfaction of an agent’s preferences,
whatever they are (see e.g. Broome, 1991; for the original argument, see Hicks and Allen,
1934). This redefinition left utility without substantial content and severed its connection to
Therefore, there is no reason why agents’ choices should improve their welfare when the
broad notion of utility is accepted: agents may deliberately choose to forward some other
goals than their personal welfare. For example, these kinds of motivations are likely to ex-
plain at least some agents’ engagement in green consumerism. This article cannot adopt the
broad notion of utility as the satisfaction of preferences, because it aims at understanding the
implications of different ethical values for preferences and choice, and thus needs to be able
5
to distinguish between them. In what follows, utility will be understood in the classic sense as
a pleasure or usefulness that is closely connected with a narrow understanding of the agents’
welfare. To put it differently, the agents of the standard model can be thought to be informed
Although the rational choice model understands that the consumers choose between al-
ternatives so as to maximise their welfare within the constraints of their budgets, this does not
necessarily render the agents short-sighted hedonists. In the contemporary scholarship, agents
are usually understood to seek to maximise their utility or welfare over their whole life spans
(see e.g. Deaton and Muellbauer, 1980). Sometimes this may entail postponing consumption;
when saving for a home before buying one, for example. At other times, it may be best to in-
cur debt and save in the future to buy a home. While utility or welfare maximisation over
agents’ life span provides a richer view of consumption than a view that does not consider
agents as forward-looking planners, it also overestimates their actual capabilities and down-
The standard model has also another noteworthy feature: no effects are seen to prevail
between one agent’s consumption and another agent’s welfare. These kinds of inter-personal
effects are called consumption or positional externalities (see e.g. Frank, 1985, 1991; Hirsch,
We all know that relatives, neighbours, and peers do care about each other’s consumption:
they may feel better or worse off depending on whether they do or do not have the items of
consumption possessed by others, for example. We start with the assumption of independ-
ence, because independent consumer choices form the necessary first step in understanding
No matter what the preferences of self- and welfare-centred consumers are, the alterna-
tives they face, and the budgets within which they operate, they are always better off by ex-
6
hausting their budgets, either by consuming now or in the future. Moreover, it is best for
them to spend their budgets on baskets of items of consumption that maximise their welfare –
no matter what are their effects on other humans and non-humans. This does not mean that
the consumers of the standard model of rational consumer choice could not engage in green
choices. For example, consumers may well choose environmentally benign non-material ser-
vices, such as going to an art exhibition or theatre, if they think doing so would improve their
welfare more than material consumption. Consumers can also choose environmentally friend-
ly products, such as organically grown produce or vegetarian meals over ordinary ones if they
To put it differently, the rational choice model assumes that all agents revealing envi-
quality. It also understands that the seeking of these welfare gains exhausts motivations for
valuation of the environment is based on this idea: rational consumers are thought to be will-
ing to pay at least the value of changes in environmental quality to secure these changes for
themselves. This line of reasoning suggests that the value of environmental quality or its
change could be determined by measuring the consumers’ willingness to pay for it.
haviour and support environmental protection only because of the expected welfare gains are
iour such as green consumerism as self-interested welfare maximisation, because the im-
number of choices. For example, forgoing the use of a personal car often imposes significant
burdens on those who commit themselves to cycling or the use of public transport only. It is
7
similarly with dutiful recycling and composting of household and garden wastes. Finally, the
choice of more pricey environmentally friendly products may increase expenditure more than
it can compensate for by any additional welfare benefits. Economists usually explain these
apparent contradictions away by claiming that agents obtain some sort of psychological satis-
faction from what they do. However, this does not do justice to all consumer choices: indi-
viduals do sometimes consider that certain goals are more important than their own welfare.
Moreover, references to “satisfaction” do not improve our understanding what actually moti-
The existence of non-welfarist motivations such as doing good for the environment for
its own sake should be taken seriously. Our own intuitions tell us that our choices are not al-
ways determined by deliberations to improve our own lot. There is also evidence of non-
welfarist motivations and behaviour from surveys that aim at establishing the monetary value
mental protection, while still refusing to offer willingness to pay estimates (see e.g. Jorgensen
et al., 1999; Spash and Hanley, 1995). A number of philosophical and theoretical objections
have also been presented against exclusively welfare-based explanations of and prescriptions
for human behaviour and choices (see e.g. Foster, 1997; Sagoff, 1988; Sen, 1995; Vatn and
Bromley, 1995). Finally, contemporary research on ethics and economics provides a sound
The next section incorporates plural values into the standard model of rational choice and
The extension of rational choice model to accommodate plural values requires a redefini-
tion of what is understood with rationality. The usual view in economics of rationality as
deliberated, intentional action (see e.g. Elster, 1983; Simon, 1978). As agents may well be
thought to base their deliberations and intentions on values other than self-centred welfarism,
I emphasise the formal plurality of values in addition to their substantial plurality. Two
self- and welfare-centred consumers may appreciate taking a bus instead of a car quite differ-
ently and hold different views also with respect to consuming vegetarian meals. Still, their
assessments are based on what they consider as best enhancing their welfare. However, other
kind of values may lead agents to choose in ways that do not improve or may reduce their
welfare (see e.g. Sen, 1977). For example, social welfarists could make personal sacrifices for
the common good, however they understand it. Other-centred welfarists could in turn choose
so as to maximise the welfare of other humans or non-humans, even at the expense of their
own welfare. Similarly, non-utilitarian consequentialists would make personal welfare sacri-
fices to realise the consequences they consider to be intrinsically valuable. Finally, agents
need not attach value to the consequences of their choices at all: they could rather attach it to
acting in a particular way. For example, a rule-following Kantian consumer would not seri-
ously consider certain alternatives because she thinks choosing them would simply be wrong.
Instead of following rules, agents may also consider certain choices virtuous.
cal ethical foundations. The preferences of a self-interested welfarist depicted in the standard
model of rational choice cannot induce her to choose in ways that decrease her welfare. How-
tialism and deontology could do so. Ethical premises capable of inducing welfare-reducing
behaviour do not influence behaviour towards the environment only: they influence many
choices and especially the institutional ones. For example, the attitudes expressed towards the
freedom of private enterprise or freedom from government interference imply that these free-
9
doms are often felt to be intrinsically rather than instrumentally valuable. They may thus be
When values are plural, an agent may hold different values that could all inform her choic-
es in a choice situation (see e.g. Kavka, 1991, 1993). It can be thought that agents deliberate
and choose between values when their values are in conflict and would call for different
choices. Anderson (1993) argues that we make these choices in order to pursue an ideal per-
son we want to be. When values are plural, different agents may also choose on the basis of
different values in the same choice situation, and arrive at either similar or different choices
(Anderson, 1993). That is, the choice of an alternative, say a vegetarian diet, may be based on
different ethical premises. Some may choose vegetarianism to improve their own welfare,
while others may base their choice to consideration for animal welfare. Still others may
choose to become vegetarians simply because they consider it a virtuous thing to do. Agents
do choose to engage in green consumerism or to adopt a green lifestyle in a similar way be-
The incorporation of value pluralism into the model of rational choice is relatively
straightforward at a general level. In the standard model, an agent’s preferences can be under-
stood as that ranking of choice alternatives that maximises her welfare (see e.g. Sen, 1973).
When the motivational basis of human behaviour is broadened, it simply means that an
agent’s preferences do not reflect exclusively her personal welfare anymore: they reflect her
moral convictions, whatever they are. A consumer that is rational in the wider sense thus
rational choice gives green consumerism more depth. The consumers of the expanded model
are sometimes willing and capable to make choices, which do not improve or may reduce
their welfare. Many of these choices are not dramatic or extraordinary in any way. For exam-
10
ple, consumers sometimes choose environmentally friendly products, which are costlier than
ordinary products. Their choices may not bring about such welfare improvements as would
compensate for their diminished ability to spend on other items of consumption and to obtain
welfare gains promised by them. Still, consumers could make these welfare-reducing choices
deliberately, to realise their non-welfarist values. Green consumerism would thus be more
potent when values are plural. Consumers would choose in an environmentally sounder way
more frequently under value pluralism than when everybody minds only about his or her own
welfare. Some consumers would also diminish their ability to consume as the result of the
However, green consumerism still remains problematic strategy for reducing the envi-
provements at the cost of those, who most care about them. Yet there is no conclusive justifi-
cation for this allocation of costs. The agents engaging in green consumerism because of non-
welfarist reasons do not necessarily obtain welfare improvements in return for the costs they
incur. Moreover, the most concerned agents quite likely are not the ones who are most re-
sponsible for the degradation of environmental quality, so leaving them to finance environ-
mental improvements for all would relieve responsible parties from liability and violate the
“polluter pays” principle. Secondly, although agents may engage in green consumerism be-
cause of non-welfarist reasons, their behaviour may confer welfare benefits on both non-
welfarist and welfare-centred agents. There is again no conclusive reason why agents should
not pay or make other sacrifices for the benefits they obtain. Thirdly, green consumerism re-
quires widely shared environmental concerns to have an impact on the environmental out-
comes. Fourthly, public policies could reduce the environmental impacts of consumption at a
lower cost than individual consumer choices. Fifthly, an exclusive reliance on green consum-
11
erism to reduce the environmental impacts of consumption would not allow agents to agree
collectively that they do not wish to repeatedly confront certain moral dilemmas.
On the other hand, when value pluralism is accepted and honoured, the ability of some
agents to realise their values (for example by taking individual responsibility for the envi-
ronment instead of being made responsible by a government policy intervention) may have
intrinsic value for them. Yet values often conflict in real societies. One groups’ ability to take
personal responsibility may leave other groups into positions in which they do not wish to be.
For example, if choices over the mode of transport used for going to work remain the indi-
viduals’ prerogative, some agents may well start cycling or to work in/from home in accord-
ance with their preferences. However, this may coerce those whose budgets or other con-
straints do not enable them to choose according to their preferences. For example, working
increasingly from home or cycling to work does not expand the range of choices for those,
for whom public transport is the only alternative for a car. As Isaiah Berlin said, “freedom for
The next section will examine the implications of interdependence of consumer choices.
When one consumer’s choices or welfare are affected by how others choose, consumer
choices are said to be interdependent. The departure from the standard consumer theory by
recognising the interdependence of consumer choices adds realism to economic analysis, be-
cause a number of our consumption decisions are actually affected by how others choose.
The interdependence of some choices also influences choices that are not. For example, Rob-
ert Frank (1985) has argued that people spend more on items of interdependent consumption
such as cars and houses and save on items that are not readily observable by others, such as
food. This kind of behaviour is not by any means irrational from the individuals’ viewpoint,
12
because one’s relative position in certain areas of life may have important consequences. For
example, even if one has good education, it may not be enough for success if others have
even better one. One’s looks, appearance, and dressing also often serve as proxies of skills
and prowess. Poor relative performance in any of them may eliminate opportunities and
prove costly. Yet from the society’s viewpoint, competition for relative position may result in
Consumer choices can be interdependent in different ways. Competition for relative posi-
tion or merit goods was already mentioned (see Hirsch, 1995). Many of us also want to be
fashionable: we sometimes choose a good because others do so and it adds to the value of the
good for us. Witness, for example, how the use of personal palm-held organisers spreads in
certain walks of life just like the use of mobile phones did earlier. This is called a bandwagon
effect in economics (Leibenstein, 1950). Others called “snobs” in the economic parlance de-
liberately choose differently from others: the fact that others choose a good diminishes its
value for them. For yet others, the most important dimension of goods such as Swiss wrist
watches or Italian sports cars is their price, which communicates to others their ability to con-
sume and hence status. This is the Veblen effect (see Bagwell and Bernheim, 1996; Leiben-
stein, 1950), named after Thorstein Veblen who presented a theory of consumption as a be-
haviour primarily concerned with establishing one’s status (see Veblen, 1899).
Different strands of research in economics explain and treat the interdependence of con-
sumer choices differently. For Becker (1976), for example, consumer choices are interde-
pendent simply because an agent’s welfare depends on the income, wealth, welfare, or the
choices of other agents. That is, consumer choices are interdependent because agents have
sometimes “nosy” preferences (see Sen, 1970). However, this approach is unable to treat con-
consumption: there is nothing outside an individual that explains her having nosy preferences
13
in the first place. The approach makes it difficult to justify public policies to alleviate prob-
lems that result from interdependent consumption, because it dresses interdependent con-
sumption in the garb of consumer sovereignty: consumers do truly prefer what they choose
when they are interdependent with others and would suffer a loss of welfare if they are denied
Other economists in turn understand that the interdependency of consumer choices results
from the characteristics of certain consumer goods. For example, goods that satisfy our pref-
goods (Frank, 1985). Other goods such cars and dwellings may convey signals about our sta-
tus and wealth and thereby affect the choices or welfare of others. Goods that have this sig-
nalling capacity are called positional goods (Frank, 1985; Hirsch, 1995). Still, as Dugger
(1985) has argued, a good does not by itself communicate anything about the status of its
owner, if it is not signified in the society as a positional good. The bottom line is that con-
Some contemporary economists (see e.g. Corneo and Jeanne, 1997) consider that posi-
tional goods do not contribute to the welfare of their consumers. This amounts to a problem-
atic understanding according to which there are altogether superfluous goods that only serve
to make distinctions and other goods that serve “genuine needs” intimately related to the
agents’ welfare. The familiar concepts of “necessities” and “luxuries” reflect this understand-
ing. Yet it is difficult if not impossible to separate the symbolic use of goods from their mun-
dane use for satisfying needs. Therefore, the desire to distinguish oneself should be under-
stood to enter into all consumption choices, including those that primarily seek to satisfy
“needs,” whatever is meant by them. As a result, we spend more on all items of consumption
than would be necessary to obtain their basic services, in order to obtain more of the charac-
Paying a premium for the symbolic functions of consumer goods does not alone raise en-
vironmental concerns: it amounts to taxing oneself and cutting back one’s ability to material
consumption. After all, adverse environmental impacts are usually directly related to the
quantity of material consumption. However, the situation is different if consumption for sta-
tus causes more adverse environmental impacts than ordinary consumption. This is true of
many positional goods, such as cars and dwellings. Competition for status also influences the
life span of many goods, such as garments, furniture, household appliances, and vehicles.
sumers maximise the public display of their possessions or expenditure (see Veblen, 1899).
Interdependent consumer choices can be analysed as games in which self- and welfare-
centred agents seek to distinguish themselves. The agents are understood to make their choic-
es aware of the alternatives faced by others but without being able to communicate or collab-
orate with them (Kreps, 1990). The competition for status and distinction follows the logic of
the Prisoners’ Dilemma game, which is exemplified below in Table 1. If consumer A chooses
to distinguish herself when consumer B does not, she earns a high pay-off 4 in comparison to
the low pay-off 1 of B, and vice versa. If both try to distinguish themselves at the same time,
they fail to do so and earn a relatively low pay-off 2. Had both decided not to distinguish
themselves, they would have earned payoff 3 and the maximum joint outcome in the game
(see Kreps, 1990; Schelling, 1978, 216-17). This outcome would also have been the most de-
sirable one from the environmental viewpoint, given our assumption that consumption for
TABLE 1: Payoffs in the Consumption Game among Self- and Welfare-Centred Agents
15
Signals (A = 4, B = 1) (A = 2, B = 2)
The game’s expected outcome is the one in which both A and B try to distinguish them-
selves, because it is the best choice for both of them individually, whatever the other does.
However, it is the game’s worst outcome in welfare and environmental terms. The self- and
welfare-centred consumers of the standard rational choice model are not able to avoid this
outcome within the constraints of the usual two-person one-shot Prisoners’ Dilemma. The
same applies to a multi-person Prisoners’ Dilemma game that better characterises status-
seeking in real societies (see Schelling, 1978). The consumers can avoid status competition in
an endlessly repeated game (see Axelrod, 1984). However, in this game the players can dis-
cipline those who do not conform with the jointly best strategy by their choices: this amounts
to rudimentary communication and collective action which was ruled out from the two-
to choosing green consumerism and lifestyles in societies where competition for status is rife.
In the standard model of independent rational choice, individuals informed by self- and wel-
fare-centred values could choose in an environmentally friendly way if it improved their wel-
fare. When we recognise the interdependence of consumer choices, the very same choice by
the same agent may have significant adverse consequences to her. One may face high costs or
forgo important opportunities if one attains a poor relative performance in important areas of
that are related to the environment. This also means that there may be a number of agents
16
who would view environmentally benign behaviours welfare-improving for themselves, but
who are discouraged from acting according to their preferences. For these agents, public poli-
cies requiring changes in consumption or lifestyles and eliminating the sanctions of competi-
In this section, the analysis was based on assuming welfarist values that only give a nar-
row scope for green consumerism and other environmentally benign behaviours. The next
section examines the implications of value pluralism for interdependent rational choice.
The two-person consumption game introduced in the previous section also enables us to
analyse the implications of non-welfarist environmental concerns and value pluralism for in-
terdependent consumer choices. It also helps us to draw some conclusions concerning green
Since we do need two consumers for their choices to be interdependent, there are two dif-
ferent kinds of situations to analyse. First, both consumers may have non-welfarist environ-
mental concerns. Second, one consumer may have these non-welfarist environmental con-
cerns while the other consumer is informed by self- and welfare centred values that are usual-
ly assumed in economic analysis. I will first address the situation where both consumers
share non-welfarist environmental concerns and will then move on to discuss the situation
A few modifications are needed to the consumption game introduced in the previous sec-
tion before analysing a consumption game between two consumers that have non-welfarist
concerns for the environment. First, as these two consumers are not motivated by their per-
sonal gain when making their choices, the term “pay-off” is not really satisfactory to describe
the desirability of choice alternatives. It would be better to talk about index values that reflect
17
the desirability of an outcome from the viewpoint of a player, given her motivations. Second,
the non-welfarist consumers assess and rank the choice alternatives differently than the wel-
When consumers A and B have non-welfarist concerns for the environment, the best out-
come for both is the one in which neither of them distinguishes themselves. The second-best
outcome for both is not distinguish themselves when the other player does so. The third-best
outcome for A and B is to distinguish themselves when the other does not. The second and
third outcomes are equal in environmental terms, but for a rational agent an outcome brought
about when she acted according to her moral convictions must be preferable to a similar out-
come which was brought about when she did not so act. The worst outcome for both A and B
is the one in which they both try to distinguish themselves. The desirability index values of
different outcomes are depicted below in table 2 by integers 4, 3, 2, and 1, listed in order
Signals (A = 2, B = 3) (A = 1, B = 1)
Table 2 indicates that consumers who have non-welfarist concerns for the environment
are able to avoid competitive consumption for status and its environmentally adverse conse-
quences in a two-person, one-shot consumption game. Committed agents are able to do solely
on the basis of their individual deliberated consumer choices, without government assistance
or intervention. The result indicates the possible potency of green consumerism to change
18
aggregate outcomes and partly explains the increasingly widely shared confidence in differ-
However, the table 2 presents a rather typical analysis in game theory that understands
another set of values to dissolve the relationship of interdependence. Therefore, the above
described one-shot two-person game does not shed adequate light on the potentially problem-
atic consequences of a game for distinction on non-welfarist merits among green consumers.
This game is described below in table 3 with the pay-offs of the standard consumption game
presented in table 1. The index values indicate that this game is likely to lead to undesirably
stoic conduct among competing green consumers, a phenomenon that finds empirical support
from the behaviour of environmentalists: some of them drift towards more extreme positions
Signals (A = 4, B = 1) (A = 2, B = 2)
and practically important and is replicated in game-theoretic analyses of many other interde-
pendency situations as well. It is also important to recognise that a new set of values may
simply institute undesirable competition towards another direction. Yet these analyses do not
characterise well the interdependency dilemmas faced in actual societies. After all, they do
19
consist of numerous consumers who have both formally and substantially different values.
Therefore, I will next examine a two-person game in which values are plural and which goes
one step further towards a more realistic understanding of the actual social dilemma posed by
Values are plural in the formal sense when consumer A is informed by self- and welfare-
centred values and consumer B would because of her values protect the environment or be-
have in an environmentally benign way even at the expense of her personal welfare. Table 3
describes a game between these two consumers that have different values. Consumer A’s
pay-offs can be obtained from Table 1 and consumer B’s ranking of alternatives is available
in Table 2. The pay-offs and the desirability index values are indicated below in table 4 by
Signals (A = 4, B = 3) (A = 2, B = 1)
Table 4 indicates that in this game the right column’s outcomes would never be chosen,
because they are inferior for both agents. The game’s worst outcome in welfare and environ-
mental terms could thus be avoided on the basis of deliberated individual consumer choices
even when value pluralism prevails. However, if the self- and welfare-centred consumer A
always seeks to distinguish herself, as she is thought to do under the usual assumptions, she
would bring about of the two remaining alternatives the environmentally more undesirable
20
one. On the other hand, a good question is whether the green consumer would “qualify” as a
participant in competition for status for consumer A. That is, she might not be able to suc-
cessfully distinguish herself from the green consumer by choosing goods that have signalling
consumer A could well reassess her valuation of outcomes to reflect their contribution to her
welfare as an isolated consumer. This could mean that consumer A would also choose not to
To conclude, the analysis of the implications of value pluralism for interdependent con-
sumer choices indicates that the existence of consumers who are committed to non-welfarist
environmental goals could dampen the competition for status by consumer choices. That is,
green consumerism could also influence the choices of those consumers who act on self- and
welfare-centred values, by giving incentives for them to make their choices as isolated indi-
viduals rather than as participants in status competition. Of course, the degree to which this
could actually happen depends on the relative numbers of welfarist and non-welfarist con-
sumers and how the welfarist consumers respond to the non-welfarist ones. The ordinary two-
person, one-shot consumption game does not shed light on these issues.
The next section seeks to remedy the problem by examining the implications of a greater
cally than the two-person games analysed above did. However, as the multi-person games are
significantly more complex than the two person games and usually entail quite technical
analysis, this section only seeks to draw some heuristic lessons that can enrich the already
conducted analysis. In what follows, the analysis will first be conducted by assuming that all
21
consumers are informed by self- and welfare-centred values. The implications of introducing
consumers informed by non-welfarist values into the game are discussed in the end.
with lines or curves drawn against a horizontal axis that represents the number of individuals
making the choice and a vertical axis describing the magnitude of the pay-off (Schelling,
1978). For example, figure 1 below portrays an interdependence situation in which consump-
tion for status yields a higher pay-off (curve S) than ordinary consumption (curve N) no mat-
ter what others do, and in which consumption for status yields a higher pay-off when fewer
consumers choose it. This is indicated by the fact that the right end of the pay-off curve S
yields a higher pay-off than the left end. The collective outcome in welfare terms is shown by
dotted line that lies between the pay-off curves. It indicates that in welfare terms it would be
Consumption for status is the dominant choice in the multi-person game described in the
figure 1. Correspondingly, the game has an equilibrium that is represented by the left end of
the collective outcome curve: everybody engages in consumption for status to the detriment
of their private and collective welfare. Not consuming for status entails a welfare loss before
a critical number (k) of consumers choose it. The critical coalition size k is indicated by the
intersection of the curve N and the horizontal axis. When more than k consumers withstand
from consuming for status, their choices result in a positive individual pay-off. If everybody
chose to withstand from consuming for status, it would be a better outcome in terms of both
collective and individual welfare than everybody signalling. This is indicated by the fact that
the right end of the collective pay-off curve is at a higher level than its left end, and that the
right end of the curve N is at a higher level than the left end of the curve S. However, this
outcome is difficult to attain as everybody is inclined to consume for status when it is not a
welfarist agents, it is easy to indicate the implications of value pluralism in it. Signalling is an
to choose withstanding from status competition before it can become a viable strategy in wel-
fare terms. That is, the environmental vanguards engaging in green consumerism may suffer
significant welfare losses if they cannot enlist enough support. The self- and welfare-centred
consumers assumed in standard economic analysis do not voluntarily choose to the detriment
of their personal welfare. Therefore, they cannot form the critical coalition.
Quite the contrary, the consumers that hold non-welfarist concerns for the environment
are able and willing to make personal welfare sacrifices for the environment. The crucial
question is, are they numerous enough to make withstanding from status competition a pref-
erable choice also for welfarist agents. This is an important question. An outcome in which a
small minority (N<k) of non-welfarist consumers withstands from status competition while a
large majority (N>n-k) of welfarist consumers engages in it may not differ significantly from
Green consumerism may also result in elitist green sub-markets and lifestyles because of
non-welfarist status competition. In this scenario, deeply committed green consumers make
their choices at the expense of their personal welfare in order to realise their values. When
23
seeking to earn the brownie points in their own sub-culture by exhibiting non-welfarist envi-
ronmental concerns and consumer choices that are compatible with them, they continually
revise the standards of conduct that confers esteem. Over time, this leads to the widening of
the gap between the green sub-culture and the mainstream consumer culture, making it in-
environmental lifestyles and sub-markets may not be able to command enough support to
successfully transform a whole society’s levels and patterns of consumption. Broader use of
environmental alternatives could lower the cost of environmental choices, turn them poten-
tially into welfare-improving choices, and invite consumers who are informed by self- and
The analysis raises the question of whether it is wise to leave it to uncoordinated individ-
ual action to test whether a critical coalition of green consumers can be created. Collective
action could modify the alternatives and/or pay-offs so that the agents will realise collectively
the most desirable outcome. For example, one can contrast a consumer boycott of an envi-
ronmentally harmful product versus the establishment of formal institutional rules that pre-
vent offering it altogether. Being able to act morally may satisfy the informed consumer, but
it may not prevent an undesirable outcome that would be preventable by collective action.
VI. CONCLUSIONS
This article examined green consumerism and its implications for human welfare and the
environment. The analysis was based on a simple model of rational choice, which was gradu-
ally expanded in order to take into consideration that some of our choices are not informed
exclusively by our concerns for our personal welfare, and that sometimes our consumer
24
choices are interdependent with those of others. The aim was in part to demonstrate that eco-
nomics can also yield other than simplistic insights concerning consumption.
The standard model of rational choice and its expansion that takes into consideration non-
welfarist concerns for the environment yield a somewhat optimistic view of green consumer-
ism and its potential to transform our consumption patterns into a more sustainable direction.
the consumers to environmental values and concerns or bringing about a change of values
otherwise would be enough to change their behaviour. The models that recognise the interde-
pendence of consumer choices substantiate the promise of green consumerism perhaps even
more powerfully: we could fundamentally transform our consumer choices if only all of us
On the other hand, the models that recognise the interdependence of consumer choices al-
so equally strongly remind us of the fragility of the promise of green consumerism. To begin
with, universally shared non-welfarist values are unlikely in pluralist societies. Moreover, the
models demonstrate that it may be costly for the consumers to change their consumption pat-
terns, as long as relative performance in certain areas of consumption matters. Values would
thus need to change more broadly to bring about any environmentally benign changes in con-
sumption. The other alternative these models of interdependent consumption remind us about
is public policy, which may expand opportunity sets and alter the relative costs and benefits
Perhaps the most worrying prospect of green consumerism is its potential transformation
into an elitist alternative lifestyle, in which what are traditionally understood as welfare sacri-
fices become a sub-culture’s means for distinction. This politics of distinction would exclude
the expansion of the lifestyle and the incorporation of the bulk of consumer households into
it. After all, many of them quite equivocally deserve to consume more, not less. Therefore,
25
green consumerism might not be able deliver its environmental benefits, although it could
REFERENCES
Anderson, E. (1993) Value in Ethics and Economics, Cambridge and London: Harvard Uni-
versity Press.
Becker, G. S. (1976) The Economic Approach to Human Behavior, Chicago and London:
The University of Chicago Press.
Brown, T. C. and Gregory, R. (1999) “Why the WTA-WTP Disparity Matters,” Ecological
Economics 28(3): 323-335.
Cogoy, M. (1999) “The Consumer as a Social and Environmental Actor,” Ecological Eco-
nomics 28(3): 385-398.
Crocker, D. A. and Linden T. (eds.) (1998) The Ethics of Consumption: The Good Life, Jus-
tice, and Global Stewardship, Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield.
Deaton, A. and Muellbauer J. (1980) Economics and Consumer Behavior, Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press.
Elgin, D. (1993) Voluntary Simplicity: Toward a Way of Life That Is Outwardly Simple, In-
wardly Rich, New York: Quill.
Elster, J. (1983) Sour Grapes: Studies in the Subversion of Rationality, Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press.
Foster, J. (ed.) (1997) Valuing Nature? Economics, Ethics, and Environment, London and
New York: Routledge.
26
Frank, R. A. (1985) “The Demand for Unobservable and Other Nonpositional Goods,”
American Economic Review 75(1): 101-116.
Gowdy, J. M. (1997) “The Value of Biodiversity: Markets, Society, and Ecosystems,” Land
Economics 73(1): 25-41.
Hargreaves Heap, S., Hollis M., Lyons, B., Sudgen, R., and Weale A. (1992) The Theory of
Choice: A Critical Guide, Oxford: Blackwell.
Jackson, T. and Marks, N. (1999) “Consumption, Sustainable Welfare, and Human Needs --
with Reference to UK Expenditure Patterns between 1954 and 1994,” Ecological Economics
28(3): 421-441.
Jorgensen, B. S., Syme, G. J., Bishop, B. J. and Nancarrow, B. E. (1999) “Protest Responses
in Contingent Valuation,” Environmental and Resource Economics 14: 131-150.
Kavka, G. S. (1991) “Is Individual Choice Less Problematic than Collective Choice,” Eco-
nomics and Philosophy 7(2): 143-165.
Kreps, D. M. (1990) Game Theory and Economic Modelling, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Leibenstein, H. (1950) “Bandwagon, Snob, and Veblen Effects in the Theory of Consumers’
Demand,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 64(2): 183-207.
OECD (1997b) Sustainable Consumption and Production: Clarifying the Concepts, Paris:
OECD.
27
Sagoff, M. (1988) The Economy of the Earth: Philosophy, Law and the Environment, Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press.
Schelling, T. C. (1978) Micromotives and Macrobehavior, New York and London: Norton.
Sen, A. K. (1995) “Environmental Evaluation and Social Choice: Contingent Valuation and
the Market Analogy,” Japanese Economic Review 46(1): 23-37.
Sen, A. K. (1991) “Utility: Ideas and Terminology,” Economics and Philosophy 7(2): 277-
283.
Sen, A. K. (1973) “Behaviour and the Concept of Preference”, Economica 40(159): 241-59.
Stigler, G. J. and Becker G. S. (1977) “De Gustibus Non Est Disputandum,” American Eco-
nomic Review 67 (2): 76-90.
Veblen, T. (1899) The Theory of the Leisure Class: An Economic Study of Institutions, New
York and London: Macmillan.