Arne Naess - Ecology, Community and Lifestyle - Outline of An Ecosophy (1989) PDF
Arne Naess - Ecology, Community and Lifestyle - Outline of An Ecosophy (1989) PDF
Arne Naess - Ecology, Community and Lifestyle - Outline of An Ecosophy (1989) PDF
Ecology, community
and lifestyle
OUTLINE OF AN ECOSOPHY
ARNE NAESS
Council for Environmental Studies
University of Oslo
I CAMBRIDGE
UNIVERSITY PRESS
PUBLISHED BY THE PRESS SYNDICATE OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE
The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 2RU, UK
40 West 20th Street, New York, NY 10011-4211, USA
10 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, VIC 3166, Australia
Ruiz de Alarcon 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain
Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town 8001, South Africa
http://www.cambridge.org
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
David Rothenberg
Department of Philosophy
Boston University
September 1987
Introduction
previous autumn - that is what I thought the old man said. Later I came
to doubt it. A misunderstanding on my part. The porridge was served
cold, and if any tiny piece was left over on my plate he would eat it. In
the evenings he would talk incidentally about mountains, about
reindeer, hunting, and other occupations in the highest regions. But
mostly he would play the violin. It was part of the local culture to mark
the rhythm with the feet, and he would not give up trying to make me
capable of joining him in this. But how difficult! The old man's rhythms
seemed more complex than anything I had ever heard!
Enough details! The effect of this week established my conviction of
an inner relation between mountains and mountain people, a certain
greatness, cleanness, a concentration upon what is essential, a
self-sufficiency; and consequently a disregard of luxury, of complicated
means of all kinds. From the outside the mountain way of life would
seem Spartan, rough, andrigid,but the playing of the violin and the
obvious fondness for all things above the timberline, living or 'dead',
certainly witnessed arich,sensual attachment to life, a deep pleasure in
what can be experienced with wide open eyes and mind.
These reflections instilled within me the idea of modesty - modesty in
man's relationships with mountains in particular and the natural world
in general. As I see it, modesty is of little value if it is not a natural
consequence of much deeper feelings, a consequence of a way of
understanding ourselves as part of nature in a wide sense of the term.
This way is such that the smaller we come to feel ourselves compared to
the mountain, the nearer we come to participating in its greatness. I do
not know why this is so.3
We need to compare ourselves with the mountain - this is not meant to
be a grand metaphor for a possible humanity, like Nietzsche's Uber-
mensch ('six thousand feet above men and time!'), but an actual, living
mountain: a model of a nature in which we can fully exist only with
fabulous awe. The possibility of modesty is the most human of characteris-
tics. But why is the link between people and nature so central?
Naess would, in time, try to discover 'why this is so' by elaborating a
philosophy that leads from the immediate self into the vast world of
nature. It is this which is presented in this book. The intention is to
encourage readers to find ways to develop and articulate basic, common
intuitions of the absolute value of nature which resonate with their own
backgrounds and approaches.
The recognition of the problem and its subsequent study using
philosophical methods is called ecophilosophy. More precisely, it is the
utilisation of basic concepts from the science of ecology - such as
complexity, diversity, and symbiosis - to clarify the place of our species
within nature through the process of working out a total view.
4 Introduction: Ecosophy T—from intuition to system
find their way into ethical categories are complexity, diversity, and
symbiosis. These concepts underlie the reasoning toward values through-
out the entire work, and are given relational definitions in chapter 7.
I don't want to say too much about how Naess derives a notion of
Tightness from these terms, but let it suffice to say that he does not uphold
a norm of 'life', as this smacks of the danger of 'cult of life' that is a root to
certain fascistic philosophies. Perhaps it is too little connected to the
individual, or to the fact that one should be prepared, through an
ecosophy, to make one's own decisions about the world, and this is then
built upon norms with a more dynamic and directional quality than what
we get by simply upholding 'life!'
How do we make the link from ethical principles to decisions? With the
notion of gestalt understanding comes the possibility of gestalt switch. At
first one sees the world one way, but with an increasing awareness of
formerly hidden relations, another understanding suddenly comes to
light and we make an instantaneous shift. All of a sudden things become
clear - a kind of a-ha! experience, the moment of insight. Another way of
describing the purpose of Ecology, Communityy and Lifestyle is as an
effort to bring about this moment of ecological gestalt switch - conver-
sion, if you will. Many methods are useful.
Many people who had read the book in its five successive Norwegian
editions through the 1970s were consulted to find out what parts were
important to them, how they found it useful. There was a tremendous
diversity of responses, as there are many motivations for the particular
gestalt switch needed to reach an understanding of the abyss between our
species and the Earth. One of Naess's aims is to reveal as many possible
motivations as possible.
(b) Self-realisation
One thing common to all these motivations (ways of reaching the
switching point) is that they all connect the individual to the principles of
interconnectedness in nature. Naess's key concept in this is 'Self-realisa-
tion', used throughout the book in various guises. Keeping with his belief
in the power of To formulations, Arne stubbornly refuses to pin down this
term to a rigid definition:
People are frustrated that I can write an entire book upon an intuition
that is 'nowhere defined or explained'. It is tantalising for our culture,
this seeming lack of explanation. . . But if you hear a phrase like'all life
is fundamentally one!' you must be open to tasting this, before asking
immediately 'what does this mean?' Being more precise does not
necessarily create something that is more inspiring.12
Clarification of terms in translation 9
(c) Derivation
The process of motion in thought is for Arne synonymous with
derivation. And here he precisises in the direction of logical derivation,
i.e. from 'Self-realisation!' and 'Self-realisation for all beings!' we can
trace a system of syllogisms to derive ecological norms for 'Diversity!' and
'Complexity!' This does not refer to historical derivation, i.e. 'Where
have these concepts come from in time?' or derivations of purpose, i.e.
'Why are these concepts useful for me?' (even though both these ques-
tions could be addressed within Ecosophy T). It is purely logical deriva-
tion which is meant.
Naess wishes to show how we can justify all actions and beliefs by
connecting them back to those most fundamental for us, beginning with
Self-realisation. It is rigid and pure logic he uses, yet the core statements
are still basically intuitive and elusive.
How is the world existent in a gestalt perspective? Why do we make use
of the relational field? Baruch Spinoza, one of Naess's sources of inspira-
tion, had a response to these questions that might well be echoed today:
I do not know how the parts are interconnected, and how each part
accords with the whole; for to know this it would be necessary to know
the whole of nature and all of its parts . . .. By the connection of the
parts, then, I mean nothing else than that the laws, or nature, of one part
adapt themselves to the laws, or nature, of another part in such a way as
to produce the least possible opposition.15
This provides a clue on how to embrace more gestalt relations. Look for
things that flow together without opposition. From these can meaningful
wholes be discovered. (This involves a breaking down of some of the
unnatural oppositions we have come to accept as parts of our culture.)
So we concentrate on finding within each discovered relation a mirror
of the larger structure. In this way our total views are hinted at with every
single thing we complete. We should not believe that more information
will make this clearer. What is needed is a re-orientation in thinking to
appreciate what can be learned from specific and simple things through
recognising their defining relations with other things. And this accom-
panies the process of learning to feel as one with them.
(d) Identification
The process of motion through experience manifests itself
through identification, identifisering in Norwegian. This is also an active
term: it could be thought of as 'identiting'. We discover that parts of
nature are parts of ourselves. We cannot exist separate from them. If we
Clarification of terms in translation 11
interaction. We tend to lose friends if we act that way too long. The same
could happen with nature.
(f) Depth
Wittgenstein noted that ordinary thinking is like swimming on
the surface - so much easier than diving into the depths18. The framing
metaphor is equally applicable to approaches to ecological conflicts.
It is the work of the philosopher to go deeply into problems and
situations which may at first seem simple or obvious, digging out the roots
to reveal structures and connections that will then be as visible as the
problem first seemed to be easy. This is why a philosophical ecology is a
deep ecology. Naess first introduced this term in the early 1970s, and since
then, as a To term, it has, not surprisingly, been taken to mean many
things (precisised in many different directions): from an ecology with a
wider perspective (like 'human ecology') to a form of radical protest that
seeks to undermine the deepest roots of 'the system' at once.
What Naess originally intended was simply stated (in Naess (1973) and
chapter 1). Depth only applies to the distance one looks in search of the
roots of the problem, refusing to ignore troubling evidence that may
reveal untold vastness of the danger. One should never limit the bounds
of the problem just to make an easier solution acceptable. This will not
touch the core. One should think not only of our species but of the life of
the Earth itself. The planet is more than us, more fundamental and basic
than our own single species in isolation.
The word 'shallow' as used to name approaches and solutions which do
not take such a wide perspective has an unfortunate defamatory ring.
Words like 'narrow' and 'limited' may be no better. Yet some argue that
all we can work for in the practical world is for solutions that would be
classified under these categories. In one sense the magnitude of any truly
deep change would be so vast that perhaps all we can work at is a
succession of short-term, limited solutions. But we should not lose sight
of the bond between our immediate beliefs and any distant goals. These
specific solutions should be linked to our underlying intuition and the
understandings derived from this intuition.
Some examples should clarify how specific situations could be
approached with a deep ecological perspective.
(1) A storm causes a blowdown of trees over a favoured hiking trail in
the forests surrounding Oslo. An anthropocentric solution would be to
clear away all the trees to make the forest look 'cleaner' and 'neater'. A
deeper solution: clear away only what is needed from the trail itself,
Clarification of terms in translation 13
recognising that the removal of too many trees might endanger habitats
for other species which were improved by the blowdown.
(2) A forest fire burns in a popular national park, putting visiting
tourists in danger. Should the rangers put it out or let it burn? Fires are a
natural part of the healthy existence of a forest. They are thus sometimes
necessary. Conditions would have to be carefully considered before the
fire is tampered with.
(3) Before building a hydropower project it is customary to estimate the
useful life of the dam and lake. How long before it will become filled with
silt and be unusable? A suitable lifetime according to the industry might
be 30 years. The deeper opinion would be that such a solution to our
energy needs is largely irrelevant. It may be useful in this limited period,
but it is no substitute for longer-term thinking and planning.
(4) In planning an irrigation project in an excessively dry area, one
should see it as a process to help the soil and the land itself, not only to
improve productivity for man. It is the health of the soil that is at stake;
man can only make use of this with due respect for the Earth19.
(5) Aurlandsdalen is one of the most beautiful river valleys leading
from the high plateau of the Hardangervidda to the Sognefjord in western
Norway. The watershed has been developed for hydropower as part of a
larger scheme, but most of the workings have been built underground,
and the cables have not been placed through the valley. So the canyon
itself still appears relatively untouched. Satisfying enough for some - but
those who remember the rushing falls of earlier days find their gestalt
understanding of the valley is disturbed. The amount of water is now
merely a trickle, a shadow of its former strength. The dignity of the
waterfall is impaired.
It is difficult to come up with convincing examples of deep ecological
solutions, because the terms in ecosophy T are so removed from the
language planners are accustomed to working with. As Naess might put it
(see chapter 3), the middle section of this system pyramid is hollow - no
one has taken the time to elaborate the connection between the basic
principles of an ecosophy and the specifics of a singular real-world
situation. And this is a shame, because, if there is to be any test of the
worth of ecophilosophy, this is it. So here is an area where much work can
be done!
And in this application of ecosophy it is hoped that some form of
optimism can be maintained despite the amount of negative information
that bombards us daily. The root of philosophy is in wonder, and this joy
in wonder cannot be lost even in a time when conditions appear so grim.
14 Introduction: Ecosophy T-from intuition to system
ways. But some of these understandings will not be what you had in mind!
In this section we review the way environmental philosophies have been
categorised, and try to clear up some basic misconceptions concerning the
interpretation of the concept of deep ecology. A common problem is that
the distinction between the movement and the philosophy is not realised.
Philosophising can be an inspiration and a source of support for the
movement, but no one is claiming that it can replace practical action of
different sorts.
A useful chart which shows a structure analogous to the shallow/deep
outline is found in O'Riordan. 23 He contrasts the approaches of ecological
and technological environmentalism, or ecocentrism vs. technocentrism.
The sub-divisions which O'Riordan employs to elaborate are important
as they illustrate the very fluidity of the original terms (see the table).
The basic distinction is accurate, but the separation of deep ecology
from self-reliance technologies illustrates a common misreading - nar-
rowing deep ecology away from the practical concerns with people and
the community, as if it were merely a discussion of animal or species
rights. The points listed under O'Riordan's deep ecology column should
be seen as the basis of a conception of the world which is meant to underlie
the specific work of developing more appropriate technology and man-
agement, not as something more radical or extreme.
The whole designation 'ecocentrism' is closer to an equivalent for what
Naess means by 'deep ecology': centring on the ecosphere. Compare
O'Riordan's statement 'ecological laws dictate human morality' with
Naess' more searching, feeling, and listening way of seeking guidelines in
nature:
There is a kind of deep yes to nature which is central to my philosophy.
What do we say yes to? Very difficult tofindout - there is a deep
unconditionally, but at the same time there is a kind of regret, sorrow,
or displeasure . . .Nature is not brutal, but from a human point of view,
we do see brutality - as we see yellow in the sun; as we see these
fantastically blue mountains outside this window.24
And O'Riordan's next sentence says that a part of deep ecology is
'biorights: the rights of unique landscapes to remain untouched'. A
response according to Naess might be: not 'unique', not 'rights', but
thinking of the landscape first, before human needs, and then devising
technologies, and management, that stem from a rootedness in place and
nature.
One should be able to see a range of possible optimisms in deep ecology
if it is to have any use as a constructive concept - it cannot be considered
merely a particularly extreme or pessimistic position along a linear scale.
16 Introduction: Ecosophy T-from intuition to system
En vironmentalism
But Milbrath clearly has an insight into the usefulness of the distinction
'deep ecology' when he calls it both radical and conservative. This hints at
the potential strength of a green politics which will be introduced in
chapter 6, which should dispel the idea that deep ecology is something
wholly non-political.
So much so that some rather conservative lobbies in Washington are
quite worried about the movement:
There is also a trend towards a new revolutionary stream in the
environmental movement referred to as 'deep ecology'. . . This
powerful faction is not merely content with striving for environmental
protection, [but] is seeking to cultivate a liberal, almost counter-culture
view of the world . . . .Today's environmentalist is not merely seeking a
clean and safe environment, but is striving for some vague political goal,
designed to come about by stopping energy production as we know it.27
[italics mine]
A far cry from Milbrath's opinion about irrelevance! So some organisa-
tions seem afraid of the possibly revolutionary nature of deep ecology.
That those who strongly disagree with the tenets of deep ecology are
concerned is not a bad thing. But worry and fear are the wrong reactions.
Tremendous effort should be spent on communicating with those who
disagree - from both sides. Any agenda within deep ecology should not
shun the task of communicating with the opponent, in action, writing, or
speaking, as Gandhi emphasised over and over again (see chapter 6).
With this in mind there can be a danger of over-rhapsodising the
benefits of a new understanding of nature, especially if you are not
prepared to provide this understanding, but only cry of the need for it:
Deep ecology is emerging as a way of developing a new balance and
harmony between individuals, communities, and all of nature. It can
potentially satisfy our deepest yearnings: faith and trust in our most
basic intuitions, courage to take direct action, joyous confidence to
dance with the sensual harmonies discovered through sport, playful
intercourse with the rhythms of our own bodies, the rhythms of flowing
water, and the overall processes of life on Earth.28
One should be wary of placing too much expectation upon deep ecology.
Though the imagery here draws us in, it can be dangerous if no one is
taking the time to move beyond these To formulations: many potential
supporters might be turned off by them. There can be a danger in flowery
rhetorics. This is why Naess avoids a heavily rhetorical style.
But he still encourages those with conflicting opinions and means of
communication to continue in their different ways, while he maintains the
maxim: 'simple in means, rich in ends'.
Where do we place deep ecology? 19
the environment are available.32 There are various trends and poles in
such a discussion that are blurred in reality. Is Man a part of nature?
Defined by nature? Or are we free to construct nature ourselves, or enter
it through various phenomenological approaches which can involve both
the observer 'constructing his reality' and 'things presenting themselves'?
Something in this last dual approach is close to what Naess advocates.
The sections in the book that suggest this (also perhaps the most difficult)
are those in chapter 2 that deal with the gestalt perspective and in
particular the concept of concrete contents - that all the qualities we sense
in things somehow lie in the identity of the things themselves.
The advantage of the concrete contents approach for environmentalism
is to demonstrate that the feelings of oneness which we can learn to feel
in/with nature actually exist in nature, and are as real as any quantifiable
environment that can be subject to cost-benefit analysis.
But as to how we can reorient ourselves, Naess points us toward
participatory understanding:
I'm not much interested in ethics or morals. I'm interested in how we
experience the world . . . If deep ecology is deep it must relate to our
fundamental beliefs, not just to ethics. Ethics follow from how we
experience the world. If you articulate your experience then it can be a
philosophy or a religion.33
But just how should we experience the world? And then how should we
articulate it? Are there examples of the expanded perspective? What
would it look, feel, taste, smell, or sound like? How do we know if we are
approaching it?
These questions remain. This book suggests a way to proceed. It
springs from intuitions, and it will end with them. But they will be yours,
no longer only the author's. The system begins and ends with the
immediate.
David Rothenberg
Oslo
16.9.86
Notes
1. Arne Naess, 'How my philosophy seemed to develop,' Philosophers on their
Own Work, Vol. 10 (New York: Peter Lang, 1982), p. 270.
2. See chapter 7 for Naess's views on the process of growing up and the expansion
of the self.
3. Arne Naess, 'Modesty and the conquest of mountains', in Michael Tobias,
zd., The Mountain Spirit (New York: Overlook Press, 1979), pp. 13-16.
4. A.R. Ammons, 'Essay on poetics', Selected Longer Poems (New York:
W.W.Norton, 1980), p. 50.
Notes 21
5. See I. Gullvag, 'Depth of intention', Inquiry 26,1973, p. 33, for a good overview
of Naess's work in semantics. Also see Naess's own introduction for the general
public, Communication and Argument (Os\o\ Universitetsforlaget, 1966).
6. From 'Is it painful to think? A discussion with Arne Naess', in Peter Reed and
David Rothenberg, ed., Wisdom and the Open Air (University of Oslo: Council
for Environmental Studies, 1987).
7. In the Norwegian articulation of Naess's notion of normative systems, the verb
presisere is a central term - the active, verb form of precision, leading to the
process of precisation. We have unfortunately had to translate this to the rather
awkward English verb 'to precisise.'
8. Seethe works of WolgangKohler(Gesta//Psyc/io/ogv and The Place of Values in
a World of Fact), Kurt Lewin (Topological Psychology) for an idea of the
theoretical work in gestalt perception study. More recently, Paul Goodman
and Frederick Perls (Gestalt Therapy) have applied the original ideas in their
practical work.
9. See Arne Naess, 'Reflections about total views', Philosophy and
PhenomenologicalResearch, 25,1964,16-29.
10. See Arthur Lovejoy, 'Nature as aesthetic norm', Modern Language Notes, 42,
1927,445-51, and Jens Allwood, 'Language, beliefs, and concepts' in Natural
Resources in a Cultural Perspective, Swedish Research Council, 1979.
11. In Norwegian it is common to use the word 'nature' as an object; a thing to enjoy
or experience. We say 'se pa den vakre naturen!' - 'look at the beautiful nature!'
This usage is not common in English, but it could be.
12. From'Is it painful to think?'6
13. Fyodor Dostoyevsky, The Brothers Karamazov (New York: Random House,
1950), p. 363.
14. From'Is it painful to think?'6
15. From letter xxxii, The Correspondence of Spinoza, ed. A. Wolf (New York:
Russell and Russell, 1966), p. 209.
16. Dostoyevsky13, pp. 382-3.
17. See, for example J. Baird Callicott, 'Intrinsic value, quantum theory and
environmental ethics', Environmental Ethics 7, No. 3,1985,257-76.
18. Attributed.
19. Deeply ecological thinking in practical land use policy planning can be found in
the work of Malin Falkemark, a Swedish hydrologist. See, for example, Malin
Falkenmark and Gunnar Lind, Waterfor a Starving World (Boulder, Col.:
Westview Press, 1976).
20. From a debate between Naess and A. J. Ayer, 'The glass is on the table: an
empiricist vs. a total view', in Fons Elders, ed., Reflexive Water: the Basic
Concerns of Mankind (London: Souvenir Press, 1974), p. 59.
21. Ibid, p. 58.
22. Personal correspondence, August 1986.
23. T. O'Riordan, Environmentalism (London: Pion 1981), p. 376.
24. From'Is it painful to think?'6
25. Robert Cameron Mitchell, 'How soft, deep, or left? Present constituencies in the
environmental movement for certain world views', Natural Resources Journal,
20,1980,348-9.
26. Lester Milbrath, Environmentalists: Vanguard for a New Society (Albany: State
University of New York Press), 1984,pp. 25-6.
27. T.M. Peckinpaugh, 'The specter of environmentalism: the threat of
environmental groups,' (Washington, DC: Republican Study Committee,
1982), p. 3.
22 Introduction: Ecosophy T-from intuition to system
28. Bill Devall and George Sessions, Deep Ecology: Living as if Nature Mattered
(Salt Lake City: Peregrine Smith Books, 1985), p. 7.
29. Warwick Fox, 'Approaching deep ecology: a response to Richard Sylvan's
critique of deep ecology', Hobart: University of Tasmania Environmental
Studies Occasional Paper 20,1986.
30. Richard Sylvan, 'A critique of deep ecology', Canberra, Australian National
University Discussion Papers in Environmental Philosophy, no. 12,1985.
31. Fox(1986), p. 85.
32. David Pepper, The Roots of Modern Environmentalism (London: Croom Helm,
1984), p. 124.
33. QuotedinFox(1986),p.46.
1
The environmental crisis and the
deep ecological movement
is given priority without asking if life is experienced as good. But the taste
is the proof of the pudding, and more and more people in the so-called
affluent societies are finding that its flavour isn't worth the stress. 'I am
rich' as an experience is largely, but not entirely, independent of the
conventional prerequisites for the good life. High life quality - yes; high
standard of living - tja. *
The politicians and energy experts speak of exponentially increasing
energy needs as though they were human needs, and not simply demands
on the market. The material standard of living and the quality of life are
for all intents and purposes thought to be one and the same. This results
in demand for exponential material expansion. It is important to realise
that percentage growth is exponential and that a yearly growth of 1% or
2% introduces increasing social and technical changes in the course of
each year in addition to enormous accumulated changes.
The deep-seated roots of the production and consumption ideology can
be traced in all existing industrial states, but perhaps most clearly in the
rich Western countries. A great deal of available mental energy within
economic life is used to create new so-called needs and entice new
customers to increase their material consumption. If it were not,
economic crisis and unemployment would soon be upon us, or so it is said.
The dissatisfaction and restlessness due to the artificial tempo and the
artificial 'modern' life are conventionally entered on the balance sheet
without the batting of an eyelid. A change in the ideology of production
and consumption is not possible without considerable change in the
economic machinery. At present, the machine seems to require and to
produce a distorted attitude to life. Within such a well-oiled system, a
revision of value standards in favour of all-round experiential values, life
quality rather than standard of living, must sound like a dangerous
proposition.
We have 'progressed' to the point where the objectives of the good life
must be considered threatening; we are intricately implicated in a system
which guarantees short-term well-being in a small part of the world
through destructive increases in material affluence. The privileges are
regionally reserved because a similar increase of affluence in Africa, Asia
or South America is not intended and would hasten the advent of an
environmental Armageddon.
The authors who describe environmental problems and agitate for their
solutions refer often to certain exponential curves, those which aptly
illustrate the crisis situation. Authors who wish to placate an uneasy
movement, and a deep, but less influential, movement, compete for our
attention. I shall make an effort to characterise the two.
absolute sense, but basic among the views that supporters have in
common.
cannot so far point to enduring victories. But the tripartition blue, red,
and green is manifest in the political life of many countries. Green
technology, green economics, green population policy, green community
life and green peace movements are all pillars of support for the richness
and diversity of life.
Some supporters minimise the inherent value or effectiveness of green
lifestyles, while others announce that we cannot but start with ourselves,
changing our lives. It seems, however, that we must acknowledge that the
frontier is long and that supporters mayfindtheir place somewhere along
the front - among the political activists, the social reformers or among
those 'hating' politics and appearance before the public.
The last chapter returns to fundamentals and is more narrowly coloured
by my own variant of ecosophy, Ecosophy T. Here historical evidence is
gathered to support the view of a nature with value in itself, and
suggestions are put forth as to how to shape a world-view in harmony with
a true respect for nature. Finally the most basic norms and hypotheses of
Ecosophy T are tied together in a systematic sketch, followed by a short
commentary on the prospects for the future of the deep ecological
movement.
From ecology to ecosophy
(a) Ecology
Biology is central in today's world: three fields of biological
research infringe upon the future of Homo sapiens in a dramatic way
which concerns us all - biological warfare, genetic engineering, and
ecology. Thesefieldscry out for evaluative thinking: what do we want and
36 From ecology to ecosophy
how can it be realised? Is the 'we' invoked here a collective with unitary
basic value, or is it a constellation doomed to unquenchable strife
occasioned by irrevocable interests in continual opposition?
The expression 'ecology' is infused with many meanings. Here, it will
mean the interdisciplinary scientific study of the living conditions of
organisms in interaction with each other and with the surroundings,
organic as well as inorganic. For these surroundings the terms 'milieu' and
'environment' will be used nearly interchangeably.
The preceding formulation is not especially informative. A great deal
depends on one's attitude to the study of one particular animal species -
Homo sapiens. Do all possible studies of humankind's relations with all
possible kinds of surroundings belong to ecology? Hardly.
In the following, the aspect of the science of ecology that is most
important is the fact that it is concerned first of all with relationships
between entities as an essential component of what these entities are in
themselves. These include both internal and external relations. Example:
when a bird eats a mosquito, it gets in an external relation to that
mosquito, but eating is an internal relation to its environment. (The
mosquito is initially outside the bird, but both are within the environ-
ment.) This approach can have application in many fields of inquiry -
hence the growing influence of the subject of ecology outside its original
biological domain.
Table 2.1
Concentrating
on relations
All-inclusive to nature
2 Normative evaluation
(a) Objective science cannot provide principles for action
If the term 'objectivity' is meant to imply certainty, intersubjec-
tivity, and stability, scientific texts gain in objectivity when evaluations
used as premises are explicitly formulated.
Values are linked together: one thing is good for another which in turn
is good for a third thing. A detailed investigation of the evaluations in a
given ecological or other scientific investigation will never uncover the
values at the end of this process. At the end of the scientific process lie
ultimate assumptions of a philosophical kind. For all other values, it is
relevant to ask: is it correct that it is good for what it is said to be good for?
In what does the good consist in the instance investigated? For example,
many people contend that greater productivity is valuable because it
increases the general level of material affluence. This is in turn a rhetori-
cally popular value widely considered beneficial to well-being. A critique
of the first two values would pose questions like 'Does greater productiv-
ity widen or narrow the gap between rich and poor within a country, or
the gap between rich countries and poor countries?', 'Is a high standard
of material affluence conducive to happiness?', 'What effects do yearly
increases in affluence have upon aspiration levels?', 'Are people being
encouraged to believe in a constantly receding pie in the sky?' These
questions can be approached empirically and probable answers can be
Normative evaluation 41
pieces of the game are two classes of sentences, the descriptive and the
prescriptive. In extremely simplified form, they may be arranged in a
diagram which shows lines of logical derivation between the statements.
Of the two kinds of statements, thefirstare called norms - prescriptions
or inducements to think or act in certain ways. They will be written with
an exclamation point, e.g. 'No exploitation!' or 'Be honest!' or 'Don't
pollute!'. To justify, explain, and relate such beliefs or pronouncements
to one another, a network of supporting non-normative statements is
required. These will be written without an exclamation point, and will be
called hypotheses. The name for this second class of statements is not
choosen primarily to suggest uncertainty, but rather a certain tentative-
ness or revisability.
Throughout this book lists of norms will be presented by letters as N l ,
N2, N 3 , . . . and hypotheses as HI, H2, H 3 , . . . . Diagrams are presented
that illustrate the logical derivations within normative systems.
It has been objected that the term 'norm' and the sign of exclamation
make the norm-sentences seem absolutistic and rigid. Actually the func-
tion of the general norms is that of tentative guidelines. Wise decisions -
the aim of normative thinking - are absolute in the sense of being either
carried out or sabotaged. In ecosophy, unlike academic philosophy,
decisions and actions count more than generalities.
A total view can be systematised in many ways. There is no one
definitive way of tracing lines of derivation. It is to some degree arbitrary
which norms are chosen as basic, ultimate or most fundamental in the
sense of not being logically derivable from any others. And even if the
verbal expressions of the norms and hypotheses are arranged in a definite,
authorised way, there is still room for differences in interpretation.
There are serious considerations which favour a certain vagueness and
ambiguity in the outlining of normative systems. Instead of tentatively
rejecting one of the norms or hypotheses in favour of a completely
different one, it is often better to introduce alternative interpretations of
the initial or 'point of departure' wording. The initial vague and ambigu-
ous sentence expressing the hypothesis or norm may then be tentatively
given more precise meanings, resulting in new formulations called pre-
cisations. The concept of precisation is one of the central concepts of an
empirical theory of system communications (Naess, 1966). Roughly, a
sentence Sx is more precise than another, So, if and only if the latter, So,
permits (in ordinary or technical talk) all interpretations of the former,
whereas the former, S1, does not admit all interpretations of the latter, So.
In short, the set of 'plausible' interpretations of the more precise sentence
is a genuine subset of that of the less precise.
Normative evaluation 43
presentation (Soule, 1985) I follow in the main, puts forth four norms as
the simply worded basis of conservation biology: (1) 'Diversity of
organisms is good.' (2) 'Ecological complexity is good.' (3) 'Evolution is
good.' (4) 'Biotic diversity has intrinsic value.'
Including these norms in Ecosophy T, I prefer them written as nouns
with an exclamation point, e.g. 'Diversity of organisms!' The derivation
of the first two norms within Ecosophy T needs no comment. As to
'Evolution!', this norm inserts a long-range perspective characteristic of
the deep ecological movement: 'Long term viability of whole systems!'.
What goes on today is a destruction of the conditions necessary for
continued evolution, including speciation, through future millions of
years.
Continued evolution is indispensable for the long-range maintenance
of diversity and richness of life forms (cf. point (2) of the Platform,
chapter 1). This indispensability gets into Ecosophy T in the form of a
hypothesis. From point 2 and this hypothesis we derive the third norm of
conservation biology. The fourth norm, 'biotic diversity!' is a special case
of 'life form diversity!' if we use the broad sense of 'life' used in point (1)
of the platform. The conservation biologist has, of course, ecosystems,
habitats, and communities strongly in mind.
The normative character of conservation biology results in recommen-
dations and decisions which can be made as hastily as our current political
structures require. These have for instance influenced the political deci-
sion in Western New Guinea (Irian Jaya) to establish a series of national
parks. Recommendations were made before biologists had made the
usual scientific investigations concerning loss of species etc. if logging
were to continue. Political constraints made such investigations impossi-
ble, but the normative character of conservation biology allowed the
scientists to have a say in the deciding process.
The gravity of the situation is eminently clear from some of the well
confirmed 'hypotheses' of conservation biology. Species are a significant
part of one another's environment, therefore the tendency towards
non-natural (anthropogenic) communities threatens their structure, func-
tion, and stability. The extinction of one species of a community may
eventually result in the extinction of hundreds of others. Therefore the
saving of one may result in saving hundreds. But time is running out!
Another hypothesis: a species has a greater chance of survival in a
larger natural area or nature reserve. Examples of reasons for this:
sudden considerable growth 'outbursts' of the population of one species
can destroy other species. They 'are most probable in small sites that lack
Different descriptions of nature 47
We are sure that the rose itself does not possess colour, but light waves
reflected from it generate photochemical reactions in the visual cells of
our eyes, and specific impulses are passed on through the visual nerves
to the brain. The sensation of colour is only then coordinated with the
physiological activity . . .
This 'coordination' is about the most inexplicable thing in Rensch's
philosophy.
Let us look at the matter in a historical light: During the seventeenth
century, the following distinction became generally accepted among
scientists.
(1) Primary, geometric-mechanic qualities - size, shape, movement.
They were considered to be part of the physical bodies as such, 'in the
objects themselves'.
(2) Secondary qualities - colour, warmth, taste, etc. These were
considered to be mere names for the sensations and feelings experienced
as an (unexplained) effect of physical and physiological processes in the
outer, physical world.
Descartes and Galileo established this distinction while Newton lent it
his authoritative approval in his Optics.
(3) The term tertiary qualities comprises the perceptually complex
qualities, such as the quality of strength expressed by powerful orchestral
chords associated with the visual impressions of an attacking bull, and
qualities such as sorrowful, beautiful, threatening, pathetic. Qualities
like open and closed referring to landscapes can be interpreted as tertiary.
They all have a more or less emphatic complex gestalt character (see later
in this chapter).
With regard to the distinction between (1) and (2), one can say that the
primary qualities were considered objective, independent of every sub-
ject which beholds them, while the secondary qualities were considered
non-objective, dependent upon the constitution of the subject, particu-
larly its sensory apparatus. Furthermore, the primary were considered in
reality to be 'out there', in the object, while the secondary only appeared
to be out there and in reality were within consciousness. They were
thought to be somehow 'projected' into nature: the wild, flowering
meadow was in reality in one's head. Remarkable indeed! Out there were
merely colourless atoms, until the idea of atoms disappeared in our own
century into abstract mathematical structures.
An example taken from the great mechanist Thomas Hobbes illus-
trates how the differences in the shape of a body's smallest parts were
thought to cause differences in the experiencing of taste qualities. He
Qualities: do they exist in nature? 53
* Some of the paragraphs of this section are quotes from Naess (1985a).
Gestalts and gestalt thinking 57
or organism. But what are the actual contents of the relational field?
Within such afield,any concrete content can only be related one-to-one to
an indivisible structure, a constellation of factors. Concrete contents and
abstract structures make up reality as it is in fact. It is misleading to call it
real only as felt by a subject.
Concrete contents have a one-to-one correlation with constellations -
there is an isomorphism between the concrete and the abstract. When we
say that the sea is now grey, the water of the sea is only one part of the
constellation. Nevertheless it is somehow the dominant part. We would
not say that the air between the sea and us is grey, or that we are grey. The
sea has thousands of individual colour hues as inherent properties, but not
as an isolated thing. One must take the colour of the heavens, the colour
of the plankton, the waves, and the senses of observers into consideration.
The colours of the sea are part of innumerable gestalts.
The ontology I wish to defend is such that the primary properties (in a
narrow sense) are entia rationis characteristic of abstract structures, but
not contents of reality. The geometry of the world is not in the world.
The both-and answer as elaborated here emphatically rejects the
theory of projection. There is no such process as the projection of sense
qualities. The theory is a clever invention which makes it possible to retain
the notion of things in themselves retaining their separate identity in spite
of the bewildering diversity of secondary and tertiary qualities. But the
price of this conservation of the Galilean ontology is desparately high:
there is no evidence whatsoever of a process of projection.
movements - Allegro, Adagio and Allegro. Many people know only the
second movement. This is a genuine whole in itself, and the experience of
each tone will be decisively influenced by the whole movement. But
normally the experience will be different if people get to know the whole
sonata. The movements are subordinate wholes, subordinate gestalts as
part of musical reality. Within the movement there may be sets of tones
forming contrasting wholes. We have therefore a complex realm of
gestalts, in a vast hierarchy. We can then speak of lower- and higher-order
gestalts. This terminology is more useful than speaking about wholes and
holism, because it induces people to think more strenuously about the
relations between wholes and parts. It facilitates the emancipation from
strong atomistic or mechanistic trends in analytical thought.
Historically, gestalt research began in the psychology of perception,
not in ontology and conceptions of reality. Very well-known are the
ambiguous visual gestalts that cause oscillating perceptions of pictures;
you see one face, then seconds later a different face, and you soon learn
to switch back and forth.
Entering a room, there may be a spontaneous experience of it as a
whole, even with a strong, definite negative or positive colour. Within the
roo'm, the experience of a subordinate whole - an arrangement of chairs
around afireplace- may change the experience of the room decisively, for
instance from a definite kind of negative, to a definite kind of positive
gestalt. So, within the hierarchy of gestalts, influences may go in any
direction. Up or down the hierarchy or horizontally within one level.
The gestalt of a complex piece of music is subordinate to the experience
of that piece in a particular situation. The piece may be played in the open
or in a beautiful or an ugly building. If we have a particular companion,
our relation to the companion in that situation influences the experience
of the music. No part of the experience stands entirely alone.
In the same way the gestalt of a flower - with all its parts coming
together - is influenced by a higher order gestalt which includes the
surroundings. If a 30 cm tallfloweringplant is found together with a 5 cm
tall one with proportionately large flowers, the former may be experi-
enced as small and the latter as big, because of the gestalts formed
through experiencing the two species and knowledge of the average size
of the two species.
The most well-known slogan of gestalt psychology has been 'the whole
is more than the sum of its parts'. It is a good slogan against mechanical
models, but it does not allude to the infusion of the character of the whole
into each single part. It neglects what might be called the hologrammatic
part, a conception of a part for instance of a piece of music as much more
than a fragment getting its meaning from the whole as if the whole could
Gestalts and gestalt thinking 59
exist apart. Whole and part are internally related. General gestalt think-
ing and ontology cannot accept the slogan, but neither would 'the whole
is in the parts' do. This sentence is instructive in so far as it suggests that
you cannot have the whole as something or something that can be shown
except through subordinate wholes.
By 'fragments' we mean something most easily understood as part of a
larger gestalt. A grain of sand might most spontaneously signify a beach.
But of course such an 'atom' may be inspected and it will be experienced
as of a definite shape and with definite patterns of colours and light - a
microcosm which supplies us with endless opportunities for discovery.
Then even something so tiny can have a gestalt character. Everything in
nature, as nature, has this ability or potency.
Auditory and visual gestalts are connected into gestalts of higher
orders. Three hills or mountains silhouette the sky, e.g. the lowest on the
left, the next lowest in the middle and the highest on the right, in such a
way that we get a bowed, rising line which immediately gives rise to a
similar gestalt as the introductory, first three crescendos in Beethoven's
Sonate Pathetique (see figure 2.1).
Etc.
50 From ecology to ecosophy
These symbol and gestalt relations are significant because they concern
the social cost of centralisation, urbanisation, greater efficiency, and
increased mobility. It is easier to take these relations into account in the
initial phase of an ecologically responsible policy than in a policy of
sustained material growth. For the former, the local community is the
natural starting point for political deliberation.
The rising degree of meaninglessness felt by people who have 'done
well for themselves' is partially due to such an indifference to symbols.
People who have succeeded according to the usual criteria tend to regard
everything as a means. In this situation, I believe that therapy to a great
extent should be milieu therapy and nature therapy, and that correct
milieux have uncharted resources for a meaningful and good life. The
concept of nature relevant here implies that nature is not something to be
used only as a means for this or any other end, it is something independent
which requires our unconditional attention. Ecological psychology and
psychiatry take this seriously.
To 'only look at' nature is extremely peculiar behaviour. Experiencing
of an environment happens by doing something in it, by living in it,
meditating and acting. The very concepts of 'nature' and 'environment/
milieu' cannot be delimited in an ecosophical fashion without reference to
interactions between elements of which we partake. Spinoza conceives of
knowledge as cognitive acts of understanding/love.
Gestalt formation crosses boundaries between what is conventionally
classed as thinking as separated from emotion. The tertiary qualities tend
to be separaed from the gestalts and referred to as merely subjective
emotions. The overcoming of this prejudice has profound consequences
for environmentalism.
Within life and society, new and unpredictable considerations arise and
clash constantly. The situations to be judged are incessantly shifting. Our
hypotheses on the effects of our actions and policies, be they public or
private, will be more or less mistaken. Norm collisions are inevitable.
Absolute consistency through time is illusory: you change, things change.
Should we consistently recommend an immediate stop to the polluting
production of 'useless' articles, or should we consistently first establish
new jobs in the vicinity for the workers to be affected by the ceasing of
production? Perhaps neither? But we need general guidelines!
Our opinions as to what is or ought to be done are highly dependent
upon our hypotheses as to how the world is organised. Applied to
ecological relationships, this implies that our norms are dependent upon
our beliefs regarding the interdependency relations within the biosphere.
A set of norms can be arranged in pyramidal form, or more precisely,
in the form of a frustum of a pyramid with a broad base and a narrow top.
The non-derived norms are placed at the top (see figure 3.1). Though this
is a useful conceptual device, it can be problematic if one analogises to
structures or organisation or implementation: remember the pyramid is
only for purpose of logical derivationl The upper norms are not to be
considered as ethically superseding. We make use of the pyramidal
systematisation, but only with our revised conceptual determination of
the key terms of attitude and priority. (This must be understood fully, so
as to avoid misunderstandings of the type that Fritjof Capra (The Turning
Point, 1982) might criticise - if the image of a 'tree of norms' with the top
level of norms as the trunk or stem seems more appropriate, then by all
means use it.)
Each norm has its particular position. The top norms may concern
liberty, equality and fraternity, love for one's neighbour, or the search for
truth. All other norms and evaluations within the field to be systematised
are then conceived as derived norms in relation to the fundamental ones.
The derivation may be called logical. Other uses of the term 'derivation',
such as historical or generative derivation (seeking origins) are to be
avoided here.
When a value is accented as a means in a given systematisation, this
does not imply that it lacks intrinsic value, but merely that any such
prospective intrinsic value does not appear in the systematisation. To
illustrate: from 'Choose that which lasts longest!' and 'Honesty lasts
longest!' follows (with tolerable logic) 'Be honest!' But the derivation as
such does not contradict the intrinsic value of honesty.
A norm which is valid only as a means to the fulfilment of another more
Total systems; pyramidal system models 75
Figure 3.1
\\
\\
11 \\
1 \
78 Fact and value; basic norms
p. 213). The limitation of what we are doing when asserting our hypoth-
eses and announcing our norms does not reduce our right and our
obligation to assert and to announce.
The quotation is useful in making it clear that the work with the
'unfolding' of a view of 'the totality of all that is' is itself a part, a
subordinate gestalt, of that very totality. We are when active in unfolding
our views creative in shaping and creating 'what there is' at any moment.
Table 3.1
Goal Norm
W - well-being
G - glow (passion, fervour)
Pb - bodily pains
Pm - mental pains
Basic norms associated with the three listed possible goals can be
formulated:
(1) Choose that alternative for action which gives most pleasure!
('hedonism')
Immediately, questions crop up. Most for whom? Most for myself? For
Norway? For developed and developing countries? For every living
being? For our generation? In the long run? Immediately? -Any kind of
pleasure?
What if an alternative gives most pleasure, but also some pain? How
can the pain be introduced into the calculation? The most romantic
response: the attainment of maximal pleasure can be consummated most
advantageously by seeking death immediately thereafter. Pessimists -
Schopenhauer and others - prefer negatively phrased norms which speak
of pain rather than pleasure, e.g. 'choose that alternative which gives least
pain!'
Every answer to the above questions gives rise to yet other questions:
how do we find out what gives most pleasure? What is the appropriate
methodology? And, what if an alternative which entails little effort will in
all likelihood provide a certain moderate pleasure, while another prom-
ises greater and more intensive pleasure, but entails difficult times and a
low chance of real success?
Pleasure (or pain) as an obvious and isolatable experience seems to be
confined to strictly limited physiological and spiritual functions. A pin-
prick on the leg, a swallow of cold water in the heat. A pin-prick near the
eye, however, often causes anxiety, even panic if one sees the needle
approach. We experience a negatively laden total situation, perhaps of
some few seconds duration. The pain is next to nothing, but the situation
is unpleasant.
Technocracy and hedonistic philosophy may be said to have certain
characteristics which make them good bedfellows. For example, in
certain medical circles, it is maintained that our endeavours to eliminate
pain have gone too far. The elimination of pain by means of technical aids
is an implicit norm which the technology of our cultures seeks to fulfil. But
this may destroy good health, thereby bringing about suffering (in a wide
sense) which is worse than a given dose of pain.
(2) What about happiness, well-being, and, as an extreme, joy a la
hilaritas in Spinoza's terminology. These expressions relate, as under-
stood here, to enduring total situations. Gestalt thinking necessarily leads
from the pleasure norm to such a happiness norm. Well-being as opposed
to, for instance, depression concerns wholes.
The search for ultimate goals 83
To - self-realisation
Tj - ego-realisation
T2 - self-realisation (with lower case s)
Self-realisation as top norm 85
* Norwegian proverb.
86 Fact and value; basic norms
It is elaborated as follows:
In 1975 a poll was undertaken which indicated that three out of four
Norwegians believed the standard of living in Norway was too high.
'More than 80% of those questioned expressed the opinion that further
growth in production, income and consumption will mean more
materialism, more unnecessary goods, more stress and danger to health,
at places of work, more pollution and more inhuman cities.' (Dammann,
1979, p. xiv.) In 1975 the concept of quality of life was largely unknown,
but the answers illustrated the need of such a concept.
The Future in Our Hands is actively associating consciousness and
lifestyle change with direct action. Attempts at a change in lifestyle
cannot wait for the implementation of policies which render such change
more or less required. The demand for 'a new system' first is misguided
and can lead to passivity. The same applies to personal lifestyle change
first, and consequent isolation from political action. These two changes
must proceed simultaneously. Changes have to be from the inside and
from the outside, all in one.
Debate as to the importance of a change in 'consciousness' is clouded
over by the failure to differentiate between change and that strategy which
is best suited to bring about such change. There can be complete concor-
dance with regard to the urgency of change, while attempts at direct
change, by moral harping, for example, may be considered ineffective. In
the following, change in consciousness is taken seriously, although the
direct approach, i.e. appeals, information, humanitarian action and
education, is not assumed to be the sole or most effective method. The
change must essentially be interpreted as a 'dependent variable'. Perhaps
changes in certain variables which subsequently influence consciousness
are the most effective, e.g. a direct change in economic policies. But the
political will to change can only be developed among the people and
90 Ecosophy, technology, and lifestyle
Stated briefly, it does not follow from the norm 'the system must be
changed!' that 'consciousness need not be changed!' and the hypothesis
'the system changes everything' does not lead to 'consciousness changes
nothing'.
The change of consciousness referred to consists of a transition to a
more egalitarian attitude to life and the unfolding of life on Earth. This
transition opens the doors to a richer and more satisfying life for the
species Homo sapiens, but not by focusing on Homo sapiens. This attitude
arises through a truer picture of our existence.
Table 4.1
Alpha Beta
Food build down trade in food, try to restore the old system
drop cash crop practices; that the food is grown within
build down agribusiness the horizon - local autarchy;
also local preservation and
storage; collectivise ground
that can be used for food
Clothes build down international try to restore patterns of local
textile business handicraft: symbiosis with
food production
Shelter build down housing business; try to restore local building
transfer more work to homes patterns with local materials;
to help dissolve centre- collectivise ground that can be
periphery distinction used for housing
Medical care rural clinics, control of drugs positive health care: participa-
tion, less separation between
healthy and ill
Transportation/ less centralised, two-way try to restore patterns of
communication patterns, collective means of walking, talking, bicycling,
transport more car-free areas, cable TV,
local media
Energy better distribution of centres solar/wind/wave/biogas net-
for large-scale energy works
production
Defence democratised armies, better local defence patterns, non-
distribution of commanding violent groups
positions
Comprehension maximum transparency small-size units compre-
through citizen participation hensible by anybody
and reporting
increases to the European level within thirty years, living conditions will
degenerate ten or more times faster than the present rate.
B1 B2 B3 B4 B5 B6
D12 D10
An economic policy system fragment 109
Such a proposition is clearly untenable. But it does point to the fact that
all human actions are goal-directed and work within a hierarchy of goals
which correspond to a hierarchy of gestalts. If one does not work with
goals one does not work with human actions. Model thinking is thinking
in terms of models. If one is not concerned with the goals, such models are
useless.
The aim of the diagram is to provide an easily perceivable skeleton
fragment of a complex system. Vagueness in formulation goes together
with the fact that the goals suggest broad guidelines for policy goals rather
than precise directives.
The decisive weakness of this fragment from an ecosophical standpoint
is the fact that a vast number of hypotheses are required to logically derive
the norms D7-D12 from the 'fundamentals' B1-B6. None of the required
hypotheses appear in the fragment.
An example: from 'Much leisure time in the future!' (B5) is derived
'High investment!' (D9). But in Ecosophy T 'voluntary simplicity' is
taken to be necessary to achieve much leisure time. High investment is
incompatible with voluntary simplicity. The derivation of D9 is only
possible with 'High consumption in the future!' (B3) as a basic norm.
From B3 follows D8, 'Rapid economic growth!', etc. With such anti-
ecosophical norms, the comparatively attractive 'leisure time' norm gets
absorbed into a total economic system which is decidedly un-ecosophical.
In short, the postulated relation of derivation between a norm of more
leisure time and a norm of more investment presupposes hypotheses
about how leisure time is to be increased. The fragment is one-sided and
reveals according to ecosophy the gigantic illusion that modern industrial
society guarantees leisure time.
A second weakness of our system fragment is that the basic norms are
not placed deeply enough: the justification of leisure time and norms of
distribution are already beyond the reaches of current economic science.
A kind of philosophical welfare theory seems to be assumed. Without
such, the choice of basic norms B1-B6 must be considered highly
arbitrary. Why should a wise household need high consumption as a basic
norm?
Norms can be divided up between those which function as rules and
those which function as guidelines. Economics as a social science is by
nature coloured by guidelines: one cannot by pure deduction come to the
solutions as they are generally given. The estimations of economists will
therefore only be one set of economic opinions. A set of norms together
with a series of evaluations will therefore lay the ground for results.
Economic tradition since the 1890s has put systematic weight on the
110 Economics within ecosophy
However, goods stands for the value of all goods and services which are
used as production factors. Holte says: 'in the production of milk,
production factors include among the other things hay, labour costs,
services from the cows, services from the workers, protection of the cows
against the weather, etc' (Holte, 1975).
Independently of the ecological movement, economists have in recent
years introduced a vigorous critique of economic growth and 'national
goal setting' as an indicator of welfare growth in the industrial countries.
But the key word 'economic growth' has continued to have great impor-
tance in politics, in spite of the growing evidence that it has negative
influence on contemporary quality of life in the rich industrial nations. As
to future generations their life conditions are heavily threatened.
It is a grave error within the ecological movement to fail to utilise
economists' own criticism of the economic growth propaganda. Every
day, every week of the year newspapers and television programmes
continue to mention economic growth as measured by GNP as if it were a
decisive ingredient of a successful economic policy. People engaged in the
ecological movement rarely protest at this. I suspect that if, in private and
public discussion, we had systematically inserted some of the economists'
own critique we would no longer have economic growth as a kind of
'superstar' in our overdeveloped industrial society. This is one of the
worst instances of our neglect of economics!
But what we can collect of data in this way is very limited. The person
can, of course, be observed on the market but for instance it is very
difficult to observe his choice between A and B when choice A is 'living in
the city' and choice B is 'living in the countryside'. And if there are five
hundred goods on the market his choices will not of course cover all five
hundred. So it is necessary to introduce a notion of 'conjectured' choice,
or hypothesised choice, about how A would act, not in a real situation S
but in a constructed situation. We can ask in an interview: 'If you were to
choose between A and B what would you choose?'
This is how satisfaction is introduced, simply as another term from what
is chosen among relative choices, in definite real-life situations or in
conjectured situations.
We must also look into another case. If you think of getting hold of one
kind of good A, and more and more of it, the rate of satisfaction of each
unit of this would generally diminish after a point. If you have then six
units, one may ask what satisfaction the addition of a seventh unit would
give you. This is called the marginal utility of the good A when a person
NN already has some acceptable number of such units.
Now another notion, namely profile of goods and services. You have,
for instance, questions of where to have your home, where to have your
place of work, and to what extent you will need free nature in the
neighbourhood of where you live, and more generally what kind of
society you prefer. Then the choice between A and B would imply choice
of economic policies, even choice of ways of democracy. The choices of
individual things will then depend on one's choice of profiles. The term
'profile' is used because you then have to compare a tremendous number
of goods and services, put into the various classes of such things. This
leads to other important notions, namely individual welfare, interna-
tional, global welfare, and then something very important for environ-
mentalists: the welfare of any living being which can be said to experience
satisfaction or have preferences.
Most of the welfare theories so far have thought of human beings
exclusively, whereas if you use the theories of classic utilitarianism
(Bentham, Mill), then utility is related to every living being capable of
experiencing satisfaction or dissatisfaction. Individual human welfare is
then only one, rather narrow, application of welfare theory. The equa-
tions of welfare can be related to any kind of social unit and also of course
the ecologically important extremes of local community and the bios-
pheric whole.
The last notion of relevance is welfare optimum. Clearly if you have a
hundred people there will be different kinds of increase of satisfaction,
118 Economics within ecosophy
market research. The term 'deep' here is used because the interview
should take place in the natural milieu of the person being interviewed,
and take at least several hours and proceed in a relaxed and natural
manner, hoping to reach ultimate value priorities and outlooks on life.
One needs say on average at least half a day's work before any useful
information can come out. This may be a very costly affair, but results so
far indicate that the real norms, and real satisfactions people experience,
are different from what researchers have supposed. The money is well
spent. We discover great differences between conventional views as to
what people want, and what they really want.
In Ecosophy T it is of basic importance to realise that the minorities,
that is to say groups with very different normative systems from the
majority, are helped to retain those conditions for life which they think
are essential without destruction by majority voting and prioritising. On
the whole, the democratic ideal of the majority is undermined quite a bit
by life-quality research. People are diverse! Too many decisions are made
on the basis of majorities which tend to coerce the minorities in their most
vital interests.
Concluding, it should be clear that, whatever the usefulness of welfare
theory and the kind of empirical data obtained from its conceptualisation,
it remains superficial, and it hinders the necessary move from the
descriptive to the normative point of view. As soon as normative impact
is acknowledged, the theoretical tools should be changed from welfare
terminology to the terminology of normative systems, defining level of
welfare as the level of agreement of actual life with a life in harmony with
one's norms and values.
9 Shadow-pricing nature
In cost-benefit analyses and in many other investigations,
economists handle prices found by observing markets. The value of
certain goods and services which are not exchanged on markets is
estimated in other ways - they get their 'shadow prices'. So why not
consider pieces of free nature, for instance, the value of not developing a
certain river? If it should and could be done, conservation projects might
be said to create vast monetary values and thus be economically on a par
with industrial production.
There is not much data on the question, but I guess social scientists, and
among them economists, are on the whole less favourable in their
attitudes towards environmentalism than natural scientists, humanists,
and medical scientists. There are, of course, exceptions. And among
124 Economics within ecosophy
- the disutility is greater than the utility measured in money. The same
conclusion may turn up in every other environmental conflict. People are
more willing to protect than politicians believe.
But, says the concerned environmentalist, what if the quantitative
treatment in serious cases goes in disfavour of free nature? The
economists think they have convincing answers to that. Their conclusions
should never be taken as the only basis for a decision. The report of their
studies should be delivered to the decision makers as only one set of
relevant material, and the weakness of the methodology and the limited
relevance of the conclusions should of course be made plain. Environ-
mentalists tend, they conclude, to misconceive both methodology and
conclusions.
Some environmentalists I suspect will answer that the quantitative
nature of the conclusions will impress decision makers, and rarely will
they have time to study the methodology. They will be glad to give up
'subjective' and 'intuitive' evaluations in favour of 'objective data'. Their
responsibility will be lighter. In the long run a question of principle should
be faced as the most important: the surveys conducted in March and April
1985 are explicitly used in decision making on the highest levels, support-
ing the view that we may interfere with free nature without limitation so
long as people of the present generation indicate little interest in protec-
tion. The ethical and philosophical problem is evaded. And this would be
fatal.
To all this the economist may answer that it is based on the premise that
politicians are already used to 'quantifying everything'. A mother asks for
a sign 'Children at play' to be placed in her street, and gets the answer 'It
would cost too much if everybody in your situation were offered such a
sign. The price is $1000.' The mother says: 'Shame on you! Putting a
price-tag on my son!' As it is now, disutility of an intervention is measured
by a listing of interests interfered with. Examples: fishing, regional
economy, pollution, cultural heritage. With no weighting it is tempting to
count each alike. If careful weighting, and thus quantifiability, is intro-
duced it may support protection of nature. In one study (Wenstrup, 1985)
the economist author finds that a sample of people attached weights
which, if plotted from 10 to 100, give the following results arranged from
100 and down: protection of nature 100, agriculture 90, friluftsliv 70,
protection of cultural heritage 60, . . . . The big pressure groups which
seem strongly to influence decisions are in rich democratic welfare states
very unlikely to arrive at a favourable ranking.
With increasing awareness of the tremendous exciting and awe-inspir-
ing past, reaching back 3500 million years, the conviction strengthens that
Shadow-pricing nature 127
10 Summary
(1) The debate in economics in the 80s has not yet in all serious-
ness taken into account the ecosophically valuable contribution of
economists like Georgescu-Roegen, Fritz Schumacher and Kenneth
Boulding.
(2) Environmentalists contribute to a change in this situation by
acquaintance with the work of some of these green economic classics.
Summary 129
(3) This implies also, however, acquaintance with the kind of economic
doctrines they (sometimes rather rhetorically) criticise, perhaps even an
acquaintance with the quasi-philosophical welfare theory.
(4) Humans' gross interference in nature mirrors our economic
activity. Protection of what is left of free nature depends largely on the
way humans are willing and able to change their ways of production and
consumption - and the ideologies justifying the present economic misuse
of the planet.
(5) The development of the Western science of economics has stressed
value-neutrality and quantitative relations, but its insights into the com-
plicated web of contemporary existing economic factors are of importance
in any environmental conflict. In many questions, like that of the relation
between GNP and economic progress, some economists hold critical
views useful to environmentalists, who cannot avoid partiality in discus-
sions of an economic character.
(6) Because so many major destructive projects carried out by state or
private capital have been judged and found profitable by some hired
economists, it is natural that the profession is looked upon with suspicion
by environmentalists. But there is a growing treasure of economic
literature which supports environmentalists' views.
Ecopolitics within ecosophy
nature, by nature, and for nature, do not make themselves felt in political
life. This is a great obstacle for those politicians who try hard to satisfy to
some extent the needs of people engaged in conservation of the planet.
On the other hand there are plenty of jobs in environmentalism which do
not require any political participation beyond mere voting and similar
tasks.
realities, and there is a hope that this will lead to a greater interest in green
politics in the near future.
Figure 6.1
green
blue
Figure 6.2
Figure 6.3
green
, red
-*• blue
Figure 6.4
red
• green
blue
Checklist of ecopolitical issues 135
areas of major parts of political platforms which would have to look quite
different if the deep ecological movement became influential. We begin
with a checklist of the basic areas of ecopolitical interest, and expand
them in several directions.
Questions: What is the proposed politics of x in regard to subject yl
x - a person, an institution, a nation, a group
y - any of the subjects listed below
(1 A) Politics of pollution of human environment
(a) short vs. long term perspective
(b) local vs. regional vs. national vs. global perspective
(c) class aspect: local vs. regional vs. national vs. global perspec-
tive
(IB) Politics of pollution of the habitats of other life forms
(a) short vs. long term perspective
(b) local vs. regional vs. national vs. global perspective
(c) discrimination: favoured vs. unfavoured life forms
(d) politics related to specific species, ecosystems, landscapes
(2A) Politics of resources for humans
(a) short vs. long term perspective
(b) local vs. regional vs. national vs. global perspective
(c) class aspect: local vs. regional vs. national vs. global perspec-
tive
(2B) Politics of resources for non-human life forms
(a) short vs. long term perspective
(b) local vs. regional vs. national vs. global perspective
(c) discrimination: favoured vs. unfavoured life forms
(d) politics related to specific species, ecosystems, landscapes
(3A) Politics of population of humans
(a) short vs. long term perspective; stabilisation or reduction?
(b) local vs. regional vs. national vs. global perspecive
(c) class aspect: local vs. regional vs. national vs. global perspec-
tive
(3B) Politics of population of non-humans
(a) short vs. long term perspective
(b) local vs. regional vs. national vs. global perspective
(c) discrimination: favoured vs. unfavoured life forms
(d) politics related to specific species, ecosystems, landscapes
(b) Resources
Politically, resources in a narrow context are now a main issue.
But the experts appointed by governments of the rich countries have
nevertheless not realised that there are ethical problems attached to the
industrial countries' consumption in relation to developing countries,
future generations, all living beings, and what is left of free nature. There
is not a sufficient distinction between usable and nonusable resources as
Georgescu-Roegen (1971) and others have tried to point out. Neglecting
wide contexts, governments can continue resource waste and use profes-
sional resource optimists to powder their conclusions.
Neither the ideals of private economic profitability (USA) nor those of
volume of production (Soviet Union) have had implications unfriendly to
resource waste. A close relation between political growth ideology and pro-
ducers' interests makes a green resource policy extraordinarily difficult.
140 Ecopolitics within ecosophy
(c) Population
In the beginning of this century, the terms 'empty' and 'desolate'
were frequently used to refer to land without human settlement. If the
land seemed to be capable of development it seemed to cry for humans,
longing only for exploitation by humans. With the human population
doubling again and again, and with increasing alteration per capita,
explorers, tourists, and naturalists use a considerably different terminol-
ogy now at the end of the century. The term 'free nature' is used about
land with no settlements or major signs of present human activity.
Because of the steadily shrinking areas of free nature, human attitude
towards their own imprints is radically changing. Until recently, it was
generally assumed that people born and raised in cities would not develop
love of free nature. That has turned out wrong. Free nature is seen by
them no longer as empty nature, but as full of life and other marvels.
Earlier in this century there was also vivid interest in how many people
the Earth can support - its carrying capacity. In an excellent textbook this
is said to be like asking how many cigarettes you can smoke before you get
cancer (Miller, 1975, p. 107). The question of optimum population is now
found more relevant, but unhappily the general term is used in a narrow
way, referring to only one species, Homo sapiens, and the mature human
need of a superbly rich planet is ignored.
According to Richard A. Watson and Philip M. Smith (Watson, 1970)
a United Nations study poses the following question: 'Given the present
world-wide industrial and agricultural capacity, technological develop-
ment, and resource exploitation, how many people could be supported on
earth today with the standard of living of the average American? The
answer is just 500 million.' The authors think that 500 million would not
result in a uniform, stagnant world and refer to the seventeenth century.
Agreed, but the question raised refers only to humans. How about other
living beings? If their life quality is not to be lowered through human
dominance, for instance agriculture, are not 500 million too many? Or:
Strengthening the local and the global 141
are cultural diversity, development of the sciences and arts, and of course
basic needs of humans not served by, let us say, 100 million? A question-
naire in Norway suggests that there is a minority who think 100 million are
enough. (Naess, 1985d). But many more do not really answer, but brush
the question away as 'academic', 'Utopian'. They immediately think of the
difficulties of reduction in a humane way.
Maps with colours showing distance from nearest road are made to
make people see how little is left of the planet still free from major,
manifest human interference and domination. Extension of agriculture
into new areas has lost its function because only little of the present areas
is used directly for vital human needs. With present natural parks being
slowly ruined through excess numbers of visitors, policies are changed,
new areas must be found. But there is also an increase of respect for the
'empty' areas without any prospect for income from tourism. Politically
slogans like 'Let evolution continue!' and 'Earth first!' are increasingly
appreciated. With greater and greater requirement of space per capita in
rich industrial countries it is seen that a similar development elsewhere is
physically impossible and a total failure of conservation. The overpopula-
tion in the rich countries is manifest from a global viewpoint.
'Untouched' nature was a rather popular term in the 60s and early 70s;
with increase in knowledge both of the history of landscapes of the past
and of the ubiquitous pollution of soils, air, and oceans, the term tends
now to be used with a s<id smile. The increasing negative reaction towards
the increase of human population is not to foster any animosity towards
humans as such - on the contrary, human fulfilment seems to demand and
need free nature. 'Homocentrism' and 'anthropocentrism' which so often
have been used in a derogatory way should be qualified by an adjective,
'narrow homocentrism' etc. Gradually the prospect of protecting the
planet as a whole and for its own sake is seen as one of the greatest
challenges ever. And it certainly is a specifically human task. A deep
human need is involved, we realise a unique potentiality in revising
political decisions so as to satisfy such a need. The time is ready for
political realists to permit themselves to refer to that need.
practice it is clear that such political opinions have not stopped the
continued tendency towards bigger units. And the greater the size of the
units as a whole the less possibilities exist for individual creativity. There
is less possibility for each member of the unit to have a comprehension of
what is going on.
But again one should warn against absolutism. A worker in a big firm
with a strong central authority may have better conditions of self-determi-
nation in work than one in a small firm. 'Small' is not always 'beautiful' as
Schumacher himself clearly announced.
(b) Self-reliance
The economics of the industrial states has tended to favour any
increase in trade between nations, and the main thing here is that certain
places on the Earth can produce certain products more cheaply and one
should always then import from places where they can do things in the
cheapest way, and one should export enough to pay for this import. It is
very difficult to counteract the force of such argumentation.
The positive effects on material standard of living from international
export/import relations are obvious. Some trade has been going on for
thousands of years while enhancing cultural diversity. But social and
cultural costs may be staggering. Lifestyle and entertainment import has
led to a dependence upon international economic fluctuations, leading to
uniformity, passivity, more consumption, less creativity.
The likelihood for continued cultural diversity diminishes on a global
scale. This undermines the independence of different cultures but mostly
what it does is make it very difficult to be self-reliant, that is to have the
possibility of maximum self-activity: creating, rather than consuming.
Doing, not being done to. The basic ecosophical terms here would be
activeness, inner and outer, in reaching goals.
In some of our industrial states like Norway, we are clearly to a high
degree dependent on the resources of other countries, and one district or
community is dependent on others. What is suggested through self-
reliance is not that all kinds of such communication should cease, but that
they should be carried out only if favourable for Self-realisation, and not
done as a necessity for satisfying needs that could be satisfied locally just
as well.
Self-realisation is not against cultural communication, but it favours
intrinsic values, material and spiritual. For instance, if you make a
journey that you do not feel has any intrinsic value to a distant point in
order to get hold of a good or service, the communication has been a
minus, if it would have furthered you better to get the thing locally. On
144 Ecopolitics within ecosophy
the other hand, if you have friends or if you have something at a distant
point which you cannot furnish locally, or if the travel itself is a valuable
experience, then of course the communication is acceptable from the
point of view of Self-realisation, and therefore Ecosophy T.
Unhappily, increase of self-reliance requires individuals to be very
conscious of their values, the obstacles, and what might be done politically
to improve conditions. So it is natural that only a minority have had the
opportunity to work for a very high level of self-reliance. It is only
possible within a coherent, local, logical, and natural community.
world set levels which are completely unattainable except through profes-
sionalism. Panis et circensesl Material standard of living and professional
entertainment make the active use of one's own creative potentials seem
unnecessary. Local achievement and ability are unknown centrally in big
societies and near the local subcultures.
Without strong counter-measures the destruction of local communities
and non-industrial culture will continue.
It is also important in the ecological movement to counteract the
tendency to equate local community with local administrative unit. The
pressure from the central administration down to local administration
units is so hard that we often find, especially in northern Europe, local
administration units continuously on the verge of economic collapse. This
leads them frequently to an anti-ecological stance, even when the com-
munity whom the administration is supposed to serve has conservation as
a high priority.
have been rather passive, but what should be remembered is that the
question of the legality of the decision should always be looked into.
Another point I would like to mention is the necessity of having a very
clear, concrete, easily understandable goal for an action and that the
opponent should be told very clearly what the goal of the action is. And
the opponent is hardly ever the visible police, but usually people of high
standing in the pyramid of power. Here a couple of distinctions are
relevant: an action for instance stopping a road or work on a dam is an
action dated for a definite time and there is a precise activity limit for what
will or could happen. But the action may be part of a larger campaign, say
for instance to save a river, a large number of rivers, or a forest. The
action itself may be unsuccessful but this does not destroy the possibility
of the success of the campaign, which may contain and comprise many
actions. Its success does not depend on total success of every single
component action. A main aspect of actions is to attract the attention of
the public. The condition of success is then dependent on the tenability of
the hypothesis that, if the public only knew, the majority would be on the
right side.
Not only is the distinction between action and campaign important but
also the distinction between campaign and movement. A movement may
be for instance to protect a large landscape, making it into a national park
after years of campaigning. Such a movement may require a hundred
years before eventually reaching its goals.
One of the most important uses of the notion of campaign is to
counteract the frustrations after an unsuccessful direct action. Most
actions are unsuccessful, and perhaps have to be. It does not reduce their
importance. The campaign continues* Most campaigns are unsuccessful,
but perhaps they need not be so in the future. But certainly, in so far as
they are unsuccessful, it is important to see them as part of a movement.
As a movement, deep ecology is psychologically and culturally based on
fundamental attitudes. To stop support means to negate these attitudes-
or to find a different, better expression of them.
Experience from Scandinavia and many other places shows that the
possibility of success is highly dependent on the level of nonviolence in the
actions, campaigns, and movements. It is for instance essential to take the
initiative to contact the opponent before a demonstration or a direct
action. In the Alta demonstration in arctic Norway the powerful oppo-
nents were continually contacted for at least nine years of the campaign,
and at the direct action any opponents present were treated with coffee
and were immediately invited by the demonstrators to discuss the action
148 Ecopolitics within ecosophy
and thus avoid misunderstanding. In the Mard0la action the police were
treated with fresh mushrooms (but those who were standing near the chief
of police didn't take the risk of accepting).
It is a central norm of the Gandhian approach to 'maximise contact with
your opponent!' Nonviolent direct actions must be a part of the fight for
sound ecopolitics, but on the other hand those actions must not result in
neglect of the daily, weekly and yearly type of struggle of a far less
spectacular kind. And one must plan exactly what influence the direct
action is trying to have on the politicians. If not properly handled,
politicians may move from being moderately in favour of an anti-ecologi-
cal decision to becoming fierce defenders of that same decision.
To avoid such misunderstanding, in what follows we shall give a
systematic account of the rules for Gandhian nonviolence as interpreted
inNaess(1974).
Third-level norms:
N5 Fight antagonisms, not antagonists!
N6 Live together with those for whom you struggle and do construc-
tive work with them!
N7 Formulate the essential interests which you and your opponent
share and try to cooperate upon this basis!
N8 Do no humiliate or provoke your opponent!
N9 Acquire the best possible understanding of the factors relevant to
the nonviolent realisation of your goals!
N10 Seek unbiased description in all matters!
N i l Refrain from secrecy!
N12 Announce your case as clearly as possible, distinguishing essen-
tials from non-essentials!
N13 Seek personal contact with your opponent and be available to
him. Bring conflicting groups into personal contact!
N14 Do not judge your opponent harder than yourself!
N15 Trust your opponent as you trust yourself!
N16 Turn your opponent into a believer in and supporter of your case,
but do not use coercion!
There are also several points which should be kept in mind to encourage
the success of actions within a movement and within the larger social
sphere.
(1) Avoid proclamations like 'My movement is the most important', or
'Without first reaching the goals of my movement nothing can be done.'
(2) Resist the tendency to look for weaknesses in alternative move-
ments other than your own which have similar practical goals in mind.
(3) The 'stupidity' or 'badness' of opponents is not to be an issue.
(4) In debate, avoid technical or academic language as much as possi-
ble. Every profession has the tendency to think that the serious discussion
must proceed in its own technical jargon.
(5) Always keep in mind how the goals of your movement relate to the
ultimate values and goals of others.
lack of global and local solidarity, the lifestyle anomalies. One can
perhaps go as far as to say that pollution and resource discussions have
pushed away all the deeper aspects. The shallow movement has domi-
nated the deep.
Industrial countries can control outflow of garbage and pollutants in a
way that is economically impossible for developing countries to follow.
Industrial countries can reduce the requirements in turn for political
benevolence from the side of the developing countries, for example press
them to open their countries for certain hard technologies and immense
industrial undertakings which can ignore the environmental laws of the
rich industrial countries.
It seems powerful multinational corporations still lead the current
development. Government's and people's opinions permit them to
exploit the poor lands' cheaper resources and raw materials and labour on
the grounds of a long-lasting relationship of exploitation where the
developing countries are the losers. Their Capacities forfightingenviron-
mental degradation are different from ours. We are not all in the same
boat, but in several different boats, all of them charting a course for
catastrophe.
This is a real problem today: for people knowledgeable in the field of
ecology to decide to what degree they will let themselves become involved
only in the shallow approach, as experts or advisers in currently available
positions. Most jobs that stand open for them as advisors require that they
keep silent in public about their deeper sentiments (Naess, 1986a, 1987b).
Employers choose the questions, mostly shallow. Advisers are asked to
compare projects A and B leaving out C which goes deeper. Potential
employers choose the questions which the ecologically learned are paid to
answer. Ecologists can freely choose more essential questions but certain
opinions remain dangerous to their careers if they are published under
their names.
Experts within most institutions still are forced by constraint to take up
the shallow approach. Yet more and more within the elite in developing
countries are asking for assistance in carrying out ecological policies.
They seek to use publications like the World Conservation Strategy (1980)
and here is the hope for the future, if strong enough institutions can
enforce such policies. Its implementation would herald a transition from
exploitation to mutual aid.
certain powerful sections of society which until then did not see any limits
to human exploitation of the planet. The quantitative and sophisticated
approach made the report readable within circles of experts who never
would read the more romantic literature of the deep-ecology movement.
What I find interesting to note is the politically unsatisfactory reaction to
the report within the deep ecology movement itself. The issue is not
without importance because every new report which is quantitatively
tinged with statistics, computer-generated printouts, and in general what
is called sophisticated technology tends to be received negatively within
the movement. This is something which weakens the impact of the
movement in the long run: in discussions with opponents with some
technical background, reference to such reports are likely to have more
impact than reference to any other kind of literature.
Among the negative comments which in my view are rather weak I
should like to mention the following.
(1) The investigation was financed by big industry. That could only
happen because the conclusions are in favour of the unecological policies
of those industries.
Historically that is incorrect. The industry supported the research
without being so clear on what sort of result would be obtained. In the
actual case, the results pointed towards a change that would adversely
affect current ways of production and choice of products within those
industries.
(2) Limits to Growth supported the maxim that we are all in the same
boat. The class differences, national and international, were ignored.
Thus it serves the overclass among the nations and within nations. People
are in different boats.
But the investigation only set out to treat global quantities. It did not
serve only the 'overclass' in doing that. Later works in the field of global
modelling modified the overly simple procedures of Limits to Growth.
This is well outlined in Donella Meadows' history of the first decade of
global modelling, Groping in the Dark (1984).
(3) The investigation does not show the exploitation of the poor by the
rich. Johan Galtung reacted as follows.
When the evils are placed at the foot of the weak they are not resisted,
not even pointed out, because the weak are too weak to do so . . . [as]
their life is a struggle to obtain very primary, essential goods. No cry of
WOLF printed out by a computer in the very centre of the Centre part
of the world can change these priorities . . . . What is almost incredible
is that it has not struck the authors that over-population, over-pollution,
and over-depletion are just those three conditions under which perhaps
Green political parties 153
the majority of the population of the world are already living, and have
been living for a long time. (Galtung, 1973)
These arguments are mentioned because again and again investigations
made within the framework of the establishment are met by similar
criticisms which are then published in such a way that makes the investiga-
tion less read among people neutral towards the deep ecological move-
ment. Being more or less neutral they can be swayed one way or the other.
We need more readers within such circles. The best thing to do so far as I
can see is to get as many people as possible to read these things and think
critically upon them. One cannot rely entirely on literature written by
explicit members of the movement. One must also consider literature by
people who take a more establishment line. Different methods of com-
munication and different types of rhetoric will reach different kinds of
people, and that is essential if the movement is to be anything but a small
partisan faction.
Looking back over the last fifteen years, I think it is justifiable to
conclude that the work of the Club of Rome has had a positive impact on
policies concerning the environment. Even in the most optimistic
technological circles there is now acknowledgement of the limits to
growth. From surveys done in several countries it would seem that in
Germany and in the UK this thought is now the opinion of the majority
and that only in the US do the majority still tend to believe there is no limit
to growth (Milbrath, 1984).
existing parties in a green direction; (2) establish a new party; (3) change
existing parties through the creation of an intermittent new party. Of
course such reasoning is most appropriate in countries which work within
a framework of a handful of competing parties, not the bipolar division of
such as the United States.
Following the first line of thought, one tries to change current politics
by establishing 'fifth columns' in existing political parties, pressing for
change in the deep ecological dimension. In Scandinavia for many years
thisfirstsolution has been favoured and as recently as 1985 a proposal for
a green party in Norway was abandoned after much discussion among
once-eager proponents.
If there is a big, clearly recognised, and established issue of an
ecological kind in a country, for instance the question of nuclear energy
plants for energy purposes, then there is a possibility of creating a party
with that as a central theme. There is the possibility of attracting the
attention of all people in the country. But if there is no such central
controversy on which the green party could focus then it is difficult to
create enough interest among the populace for a new party. And how
successful can a single-issue party be in the long run?
A difference here exists between Sweden and Norway because in
Sweden there is a tremendous debate concerning nuclear power whereas
in Norway, with its great hydropower potential, there is no central
political controversy with a marked green aspect.
In Germany there has been success with introducing a green party with
central aims relevant to the total population and the results so far seem to
confirm the conclusion that green political parties may have substantial
impact (Capra and Spretnak, 1984). But it would also confirm possibility
(3) - namely that even if the Green party explodes into competing small
groups and even if those who are against taking part in established politics
gain headway the era of the green party will have had a lasting impact. It
was certainly a good idea.
A negative aspect of a green party is that if it only gets three or four per
cent of the vote then the population gets a wrong picture of the real
importance of a green point of view and the number of people who are
really in favour of the principles behind green politics. It may be better
not to have a party than to have one that clearly cannot reach even 10 per
cent of the population.
As regards the third possibility I think that this is a way that in any case
must be continued even if a party is created. There is always a need to
have fifth columns in the other parties again and again taking up green
Green political parties 155
should from time to time send politicians letters of acclaim and support
when one thinks they have done well. Fan mail as well as hate mail is
needed.
A person active in politics should try to make it clear to the public that
they as a private person may entertain some views which are politically
unrealisable within election terms, but which nevertheless are important
for their personal political motivation. The impact of continued popula-
tion growth on conditions of life and on the ecosphere in general is into-
lerable and still increasing geometrically. Even if it is politically suicidal
to plan changes of this dimension as part of a political platform, it is irres-
ponsibility on the part of the politically active not to admit that they as
private persons entertain these green views. If these views are hidden,
the many people who do not play an active part in politics, but entertain
radical green views, feel even more powerless than they are. They get the
feeling that taking part in the struggle for power is incompatible with hav-
ing green views.
On the other hand, there is a usage of the terms 'people' and 'society'
which is dangerous in ecopolitics if it is said that society or community
should have control of the means of production. The application of these
terms is such that it is not the society or the community itself that gets
control but certain politicians or central administrative units deciding on
behalf of the community. (Using the term 'community' in these contexts
makes the slogans of socialism much more valuable.)
The Utopias of green societies point towards a kind of direct democracy
with local control of the means of production as the best way of achieving
the goals.
Because of the ambiguities of the terms it is perhaps a bit paradoxical
to say that the rather backward ecological position in Eastern Europe is
irrelevant to the socialist-capitalist question. On many points, these
states are not looked on as being truly socialistic. There was an attempt,
but it failed. Supporters of the deep ecological movement may however
find some confirmation of their anti-bureaucratic attitudes by looking at
Eastern Europe. But, at least in the Soviet Union, the problems ecologi-
cal movements have to face are not so different from our own. Boris
Komarov (1980) writes on the official hearings on the future of Lake
Baikal:
At one such meeting one old academician began to scream at us: 'But
why are we going on so about this Baikal? Pollute it if we have to. Now
we have nuclear energy, and if later we have to, we can easily make a big
pit and fill it with water, and that's that. We'll make Baikal again.' This
nonsense resounded under the vaults of the Academy of Sciences, yet
the vaults of our Temple of Science did not crumble. No one even chased
out this senile academician. The meeting went on and the attacks on us
continued. I repeat, this was a time of real arm twisting . . . (p 8-9)
11 Bureaucracy
This leads us to the basic question of bureaucracy. In capitalist
countries mixed or pure, there is a distinction between private initiative
and public initiative where public initiative involves channelling through
the bureaucracy. In ecopolitically sane societies we shall retain the term
'initiative' as a greatly positive term, but it will be personal initiative
rather than private initiative, and a maximisation of personal initiative
will be one of the norms. This means a fight against bureaucratic
dimensions which is just as hard as in capitalistic societies. Socialism here
seems to be in a weak position because when it is said that the people
should rule, very often it implies that the government should take up a
Bureaucracy 159
a greener line in politics at the moment within issue x and how could it be
realised?' rather than of the form 'What would be the deep green line of
politics within issue xT Green is dynamic and comparative, never abso-
lute or idealistic.
The term 'political voluntarism' is a term that may be helpful in this
connection - as something to be wary of. It is a term characterising
political activity in which you think that you can rapidly force a deep
change of society by sheer will power through direct action. It was used,
for instance, by Marxist criticisms of students engaged in the so-called
student revolutions of the late 1960s. Some Marxists said that universities
are peripheral institutions: Tower inside universities does not count. The
will to change society by means of student power is nonsensical. You must
have a much broader and more realistic basis of activity.' In this sense,
political voluntarism is a kind of romantic delusion.
Back to the problem of combining basic ideals of ecopolitics and
day-to-day political fights for very limited green gains! An example may
make the complicated situation clearer.
An energy problem exists in Norway and Sweden, but it is primarily the
problem of how to reduce the fantastic waste of energy. It is a problem of
how to limit the use of energy essentially to vital needs. From the green
point of view the present level of yearly consumption is more than
sufficient for any needs. Nevertheless some supporters of green policies
take part, and should take part, in discussions concerning which sources
of increased energy supply have the least detrimental consequences
socially and for life conditions in general. The situation is rather awkward:
the greens are led to promote decisions they detest. As long as we
constantly make clear that any increase of energy production is unneces-
sary and detrimental, the participation in the debate on how to increase it
with the least detrimental effect is justified and important. At the moment
policies of stabilisation or decrease of energy production should be
vigorously propagated, but politically they are dead or hibernating.
Proposals for such policies have no chance of being adopted at the
moment, and existing parties avoid them. Presently politically powerful
plans call for exponential increase of energy production until 2020,
retaining the wasteful production to the aluminum industry. A green
party, however, would have to adopt stabilisation or decrease as a
programme even if this immediately would limit the number of votes.
'Everything hangs together.' This is still a good slogan. One conse-
quence of the interrelatedness is that we all have the capacity to do
something of relevance within a framework of our own interests and
inclinations. The ecopolitical frontier is immensely long but we can only
162 Ecopolitics within ecosophy
14 Concluding remarks
(1) The green Utopias draw pictures of societies and ways of life
expressing how people in the deep ecological movement would like to see
the future. The pictures, if fairly detailed, include political institutions. In
thinking about future life conditions on the planet, questions of political
structure are unavoidable.
(2) Different from sketching Utopias, but not entirely independent of
them, we find environmental thinking focusing on how to move in the
direction of the Utopias.
(3) For the shallow or reform ecological movement, the central politi-
cal questions are significantly different from those of the deep movement.
For the former the task is essentially one of 'social engineering', modify-
ing human behaviour through laws and regulations posed by ministries
and departments of the environment - for the short-term well-being of
humans.
(4) The deep ecological movement sees the present unecological poli-
tics as necessary consequences primarily of social and economic priorities,
the ways of production and consumption, and only significant changes of
this will make the goals of the movement realisable. This implies deep
changes of political priorities, and possibly new green parties.
(5) In the early 70s ecopolitical thinking hammered out a great number
of concrete goals marking steps on the way to a green society. Looking
back fifteen years later, most of these goals are still considered to be
well-chosen and important. But no established party anywhere grabbed
the chance to incorporate the goals into its platform. The strength of the
movement to realise these goals is scarcely less than it was in the past
decade, but the inertia of the old material growth policies is holding back
the change.
(6) It seems that life conditions will have to worsen considerably before
the formulated goals are adapted by any major political parties.
(7) There is no point of no return.' This holds for the prospect of
stopping the accelerating devastation of life conditions on the planet. It
does not hold for a large number of devastations like that of the
rain-forests. But it does hold for an immense diversity and richness of life
forms and landscapes. Green political activism is one of the assets we
must count on.
7
Ecosophy T: unity and diversity
of life
From the point of view of analytical philosophy the term 'right', like
many other terms used in daily life - 'fact', 'verification' ('shown to be the
case'), 'duty', 'value in itself - is rather suspicious. Does it have any
meaning that can be clarified? Is it just a question of coercive power when
somebody says that we have no right to do so and so? I do not think so. As
I use the term I do not pretend that it has a clearly formulatable meaning,
but that it is the best expression I have so far found of an intuition which
I am unable to reject in all seriousness. But I completely accept that some
environmental philosophers avoid the term and advise others to do the
same.
When we attempt to live out our relationships with other living beings
in accordance with such a principle of equal rights of all fellow beings,
difficult questions naturally arise. (This always happens when a normative
idea in the central reaches of a norm system is practised.) It suggests a
guideline for our behaviour, but it does not tell anything about behaviour.
Additional norms and hypotheses are, for instance, necessary as premises
in order to derive a norm that killing violates the right. It is not some kind
of unconditional isolatable norm to treat everything the same way. It is
only a fragment of a total view. Our apprehension of the actual conditions
under which we live our own lives - that is, certain 'hypotheses' high up in
the systematised total view - make it crystal clear that we have to injure
and kill, in other words actively hinder the self-unfolding of other living
beings. Equal right to unfold potentials as a principle is not a practical
norm about equal conduct towards all life forms. It suggests a guideline
limiting killing, and more generally limiting obstruction of the unfolding
of potentialities in others.
Many contend that living beings can be ranked according to their
relative intrinsic value. The claims of rankable value are usually based
upon one or more of the following contentions.
(1) If a being has an eternal soul, this being is of greater intrinsic value
than one which has a time-limited or no soul.
(2) If a being can reason, it has greater value than one which does not
have reason or is unreasonable.
(3) If a being is conscious of itself and of its possibilities to choose, it is
of greater value than one which lacks such consciousness.
(4) If a being is a higher animal in an evolutionary sense, it is of greater
value than those which are farther down on the evolutionary scale.
None of these standpoints, so far as I can see, have been substantially
justified. They may appear to be reasonable at first glance, but they fade
after reflection and confrontation with the basic intuitions of the unity of
life and the right to live and blossom.
168 Ecosophy T: unity and diversity of life
The contention that one life form has a higher value than another
sometimes leads to the argument that the more valuable being has the
right to kill and injure the less valuable. A different approach is to specify
under which circumstances it is justifiable to hunt or kill other living
beings. We might agree upon rules such as will imply different behaviour
towards different kinds of living beings without negating that there is a
value inherent in living beings which is the same value for all. But it is
against my intuition of unity to say 'I can kill you because I am more
valuable' but not against the intuition to say 'I will kill you because I am
hungry'. In the latter case, there would be an implicit regret: 'Sorry, I am
now going to kill you because I am hungry.' In short, I find obviously
right, but often difficult to justify, different sorts of behaviour with
different sorts of living beings. But this does not imply that we classify
some as intrinsically more valuable than others.
Modern ecology has emphasised a high degree of symbiosis as a
common feature in mature ecosystems, an interdependence for the
benefit of all. It has thereby provided a cognitive basis for a sense of
belonging which was not possible earlier. Family belonging, the tie of
kinship, has a material basis in perceived togetherness and cooperation.
Through the extension of our understanding of the ecological context, it
will ultimately be possible to develop a sense of belonging with a more
expansive perspective: ecospheric belonging.
The task is to find a form of togetherness with nature which is to our
own greatest benefit. Any other definition is hypocritical.' If such a
statement is accepted, 'our own benefit' must then mean 'that which
serves the great Self, not merely the individual ego or human societies. If
a lesser self is implied, the sentences are misleading. One can desire
well-being for an animal or a plant just as naturally as one can for a
person. For some dog owners, their dog's well-being is more important to
them than that of their neighbour. The identification is stronger, and
empathy is greater. One can, without hypocrisy, desire something which
is for the benefit of other living beings - and one normally obtains great,
rich satisfaction from it.
The technical development together with our insight into mutual,
symbiotic relationships makes it possible for human beings to allow
cooperation and togetherness to colour our work days and leisure life
much more than before. Unfortunately this is at the moment primarily a
theoretical possibility. The coming decades will probably see certain
dichotomies between human societies play themselves out (e.g. the
North-South conflict), as well as between mankind and other living
beings (the destruction of habitats of other species).
The universal right to self-unfolding 169
'conquer the world' and complete the job of creating one great human
habitat of all the habitable parts of the Earth? Why should a creature limit
its Self-realisation by letting other life forms retain their habitats - if they
are not obviously useful?
Such questions seem, however, to be characteristic of only a fraction of
human cultures. Perhaps they reveal, not a concern for specific human
Self-realisation, but its neglect.
A biology which clearly states the biological peculiarities of human
beings, as well as the differences, e.g. between human and animal
communication, is fully compatible with an ecosophy of identification and
equal right. A specific feature of human make-up is that human beings
consciously perceive the urge other living beings have for self-realisation,
and that we must therefore assume a kind of responsibility for our conduct
towards others.
Ethology, the general study of behaviour of living beings, suggests that
the violence found within modern industrial societies is more malignant
and self-destructive than that found in almost any other mammalian
society. The methods other mammals use to avoid and reduce violence
appear to be more effective and less brutal than our own. These animal
societies are worthy of study and in some limited respects worthy of being
used as models for human behaviour. This does not imply a lower
evaluation of mankind and our future possibilities.
Modern ecologists almost unanimously emphasise the importance of
togetherness and cooperation in the plant and animal world. The
ecologists emphasise the restrained forms and conduct displayed in
conflicts, and the importance of the utilisation of dissimilar 'niches' in
existence, that is the avoidance of direct collision.
We regard some of the abilities of animals with admiration and
astonishment. For instance, the ability of salmon to cross untold reaches
of ocean, find a given river mouth, and brave the many rapids to reach
their spawning grounds. There is no reason to think of the human ability
to discover this about salmon as anything less awesome. My concern here
is the human capability of identification, the human joy in the identifica-
tion with the salmon on its way to its spawning grounds, and the sorrow
felt upon the thoughtless reduction of the access to such important places.
The principle of biospheric egalitarianism defined in terms of equal
right, has sometimes been misunderstood as meaning that human needs
should never have priority over non-human needs. But this is never
intended. In practice, we have for instance greater obligation to that
which is nearer to us. This implies duties which sometimes involve killing
or injuring non-humans. (Naess, 1984a.) But it is a serious matter when
Identification, wholeness, and Self-realisation 171
you, prefer to live rather than to die?' The point is grasped, the children
for a moment see and experience spontaneously and immediately the
insects as themselves, not only as something different but in an important
sense like themselves. An instance of momentary identification! Perhaps
it has no effect in the long run, or perhaps one of the children slightly
changes an attitude toward small fellow creatures.
Before the intervention the children saw the movements of half-dead
insects but presumably did not react. From the point of view of ecosophy
they were alienated in a particular sense of the word, namely being
indifferent to something that with normal upbringing would have caused
empathy based on identification. Indifference, rather than feelings of
strangeness, apartness, aloofness, is of prime importance in the situation.
So much about insects. But what about identification with mountains?
The more usual terms are here 'personalising', 'animism', 'an-
thropomorphism'. For thousands of years, and in various cultures, moun-
tains have been venerated for their equanimity, greatness, aloofness, and
majesty. The process of identification is the prerequisite for feeling the
lack of greatness, equanimity in one's empirical self. One 'sees oneself in
the other', but it is not the empirical self, but the self one would aspire to
have. Given adverse conditions a mountain will stand for threat and
terror, an adversary to be overcome. The so-called conquest of mountains
relieves the threat.
The term 'identification' is used in many ways and the way it is used in
the story may be rare and difficult to make clear except through many
instances, positive and negative.
The relationship between identification and the narrower process of
solidarity is such that every deep and lasting state of solidarity presup-
poses wide identification. The essential sense of common interests is
comprehended spontaneously and is internalised. This leads to the depen-
dency of Ays Self-realisation upon B's. When B seeks just treatment A
supports the claim. A assumes a common stance upon the basis of an
identification with B. A may also assume a common stance upon the basis
of abstract ideas of moral justice, combined with a minimum of identifica-
tion, but under hard and long-lasting trials the resulting solidarity cannot
be expected to hold. The same applies to loyalty. When solidarity and
loyalty are solidly anchored in identification, they are not experienced as
moral demands; they come of themselves.
Continental European critique of western industrial society stresses the
alienation caused by a kind of technology that reduces everything to mere
objects of manipulation. Verdinglichungl Not only animals are thus
Identification, wholeness, and Self-realisation 173
are revealed. The egos develop into selves of greater and greater dimen-
sion, proportional to the extent and depth of our processes of identifica-
tion.
The conceptually simplest and historically speaking most ancient access
to such an ecosophy is perhaps the one which analyses dissimilar concep-
tions of the 'self. The first years of life, the self is not much broader than
the ego - the narrow selfish centre which serves to satisfy the simplest
biological needs. It is then best to eat the whole cake alone. About the age
of seven, and until puberty, a socialisation takes place which extends the
self appreciably: the self comes to comprise one's family and closest
friends.
The intensity of identification with other life depends upon milieu,
culture and economic conditions. The ecosophical outlook is developed
through an identification so deep that one's own self is no longer
adequately delimited by the personal ego or the organism. One experi-
ences oneself to be a genuine part of all life. Each living being is
understood as a goal in itself, in principle on an equal footing with one's
own ego. It also entails a transition from I-it attitudes to I-thou attitudes
- to use Buber's terminology.
This does not imply that one acts, wishes to act, or consistently can act
in harmony with the principle of equality. The statements about bios-
pheric equality must be merely taken as guidelines. Even under condi-
tions of intense identification, killing occurs. The Indians in California,
with their animistic mythology, were an example of equality in principle,
combined with realistic admissions of their own vital needs. When hunger
arrives, brother rabbit winds up in the pot. 'A brother is a citizen, but oh,
so temptingly nutritious!' - This exclamation is too easy: the complicated
rituals which surround the hunt in many cultures illustrate how closely
people feel bound to other beings, and how natural it is to feel that when
we harm others, we also harm ourselves. Non-instrumental acts develop
into instrumental.
Immanuel Kant's maxim 'You shall never use another person only as a
means' is expanded in Ecosophy T to 'You shall never use any living being
only as a means'.
A lack of identification leads to indifference. Distant objects or events
which do not seem to concern us are at best relegated to the indifferent
background.
The pesticide azodrin reduced the number of certain 'obnoxious'
insects to almost zero, which was the intention, but in addition it
exterminated the natural enemies of the pest. The result after some time
Identification, wholeness, and Self-realisation 175
was more unwanted insects than ever. Such accidents have motivated a
new slogan: you must know what will occur upon intervention in nature.
If you don't know the consequences, don't intervene. But is this realistic?
No more than a small fraction of the consequences can ever be known.
Our ignorance now and in the near future about the consequences of
intervention is appreciably greater than was initially assumed. Our
indifference to the environment of life has meant that it is ordinarily
experienced merely as a grey background. With identification, all this
changes.
Suppose we spread a chemical substance upon a piece of land and take
up a singly gram of earth. What is happening in this tiny piece of our 'grey
background' and what would happen in the event of our intervention? An
investigation of just such a small clump of earth revealed that an astound-
ing number of small organisms lived there: among other things 30,000
protozoa, 50,000 algae, 400,000 fungi and 2,500,000,000 bacteria
(Ehrlich, 1970, p. 180). The fertility of the Earth depends on an unsurvey-
able, intricate interaction - a crazily complex symbiotic network which
embraces all these small living beings.
The greater our comprehension of our togetherness with other beings,
the greater the identification, and the greater care we will take. The road
is also opened thereby for delight in the well-being of others and sorrow
when harm befalls them. We seek what is best for ourselves, but through
the extension of the self, our 'own' best is also that of others. The
own/not-own distinction survives only in grammar, not in feeling.
Philosophically, the concepts ego, self, and Self (the deep, comprehen-
sive and ecological self) are braided into dissimilar systems which origi-
nally were closely associated to the world religions. Because of the
reduced influence of these religions in our industrial societies, the
philosophies of identification have become almost inaccessible. The
hotbed for many kinds of spontaneous religious experience is no longer a
cultural gift of the cradle.
It is noteworthy that a 'democracy of life forms' is or was characteristic
of some primal societies. Their conception of the human situation is more
realistic than that offered in our techno-natural scientific education.
While we derobe nature as such of all sensory diversity, and assert that it
is really colourless, animism moves in the opposite direction.
While warning against an 'unconscious' plunge into the technocratic
society of the future, one of our foremost scientists has remarked: 'We
own nature together with our fellows'. But the ideology of ownership of
nature has no place in an ecosophy. The Norwegian people or the
176 Ecosophy T: unity and diversity of life
Norwegian state does not own Norway. The resources of the world are
not only resources for human beings. Legally, we can 'own' a forest, but
if we destroy the living conditions for life in the forest, we are transgres-
sing the norm of equality.
This egalitarian attitude is manifested when the hunter has a long
discussion with the spirit of the bear, and explains apologetically that the
larder is bare and that he must now kill the bear to nourish his family. In
return, the hunter can remind the bear's spirit that both he and his family
will die one day, and turn to dust, and so to vegetation, sustenance for the
descendents of the bear. In other words, this is a realistic egalitarian
attitude, an acknowledgement of the cycles of life and their interconnec-
tion in nature.
Wildlife and forest management, and other professions in intimate
contact with nature, change people's attitudes. It is only through work,
play, and understanding that a deep and enduring identification can
develop, an identification deep enough to colour the overall life condi-
tions and ideology of a society.
The egalitarian attitude is not restricted to pre-industrial societies.
'Nature mysticism', as it is often called, is a genuine aspect of Western
culture. To identify with all life does not imply an abandonment of our
cultural heritage. Moral exhortation, punishment of ecocriminals,
economic sanctions, and other negative tools have their place, but the
education towards greater and wider identification though widening the
Self is a thoroughly positive way.
and more people in the industrial societies are engaging in during their
leisure time. But in Norwegian, there is a clearer, more value-laden word
that refers to the type of outdoor recreation that seeks to come to nature
on its own terms: to touch the Earth lightly. Literally, 'friluftsliv' means
'free air life', but it has been translated as 'open air life' and 'nature life'
(see Reed and Rothenberg (1987)). In the following, we retain the
original term to indicate a positive kind of state of mind and body in
nature, one that brings us closer to some of the many aspects of identifica-
tion and Self-realisation with nature that we have lost.
The satisfaction of the need for outdoor life and the need for machine-
oriented technical unfolding cannot take place simultaneously. At pres-
ent, the socio-economic forces in the industrial countries are lobbying in
favour of priority for the capital-intensive apparatus: the apparatus-poor
life is a hindrance to 'progress'. We should see true friluftsliv as a route
towards paradigm change.
Friluftsliv plays a more and more important role as the dark shadows of
the urban lifestyle of the industrial states have become more evident. The
polar explorer and Norwegian national hero, Fritjof Nansen, remarked
that 'friluftsliv is a partial continuation of an aspect of an earlier form of
life'. Human beings, until quite recently, have been hunters and gather-
ers, that is, lived and worked in nature. Much less than one per cent of our
history has been devoted to the attempt to live a life characterised by
machines and crowded quarters. As recently as the beginning of this
century, many prominent futurists, including H. G. Wells, believed that
'progress' would succeed, and that human beings would be completely
happy in their new radical form of life.
At the same time, friluftsliv caught on: more or less playful kinds of
short excursions in nature. These excursions do not serve to procure food,
nor do they fit any other characterisation as work. Outdoor life has
assumed forms which resemble the physical activities in the hunter and
gatherer cultures: on water-swimming, diving, rowing, paddling, sailing,
fishing, infieldsand forests - hiking, camping, skiing, riding, hunting; in
mountainous terrain - glacial walks, climbing, cross-country skiing,
mountain climbing on skis, fishing, hunting. Where do the competition
sports fit in? Nils Faarlund (1973) says:
Competition as a value represents a form of self-realisation which is
reserved for the select. The competition-motivated lifestyle
presupposes 'losers'. Self-realisation for the elite presupposes that the
others are denied self-realisation. Competition as a value is thus
excluding and elitist. Outdoor life in the sense of exuberant living in
nature presupposes on the other hand the self-realisation of others to
Identification, wholeness, and Self-realisation 179
achieve one's own (i.e.: a presentation of self which does not separate
the individual from nature).
An important element is the necessity of effort. Without effort, no
quality, and without quality, reduced enjoyment. Enjoyment of the
quality in one's personal life conduct is an autotelic experiencing of
value, or inner motivation. Competitive motivation is external
motivation and thus a weaker mode of motivation.
With the near future in mind, it is important to stake out guidelines for
ethically and ecologically responsible friluftsliv. These can be formulated
as follows.
(1) Respect for all life. Respect for landscape. The elimination of plea-
sure hunting necessarily follows, except for 'photographic hunting'. Hunt-
ing must be restricted to ecosophically justifiable wildlife management.
Traceless passage through the wilderness: one leaves no tell-tale 'drop-
pings' in the landscape. No more cairn construction, and no expansion of
backwoods urbanisation (highways, motels, etc.) of the natural areas.
(2) Outdoor education in the signs of identification. Children's (and
adults') longing and capacity for identification with life and landscape is
encouraged. Conventional goal direction: to get there, to be skilful, to be
better than others, to get things done, to describe in words, to have and
use new and fancy equipment - is discouraged. The ability to experience
deep, rich and varied interaction in and with nature is developed.
(3) Minimal strain upon the natural combined with maximal self-
reliance. This is a great challenge today. Greater knowledge about the use
of local plants and other locally available material allows one quite often
to live in nature with local resources. But acquaintance with nature's
carrying capacity is simultaneously required. This limits the number of
people who can be almost self-sufficient within a given landscape.
(4) Natural lifestyle. All-sided forms of togetherness with as much
dwelling upon goals as possible, as little as possible upon that which is
solely a means. The greatest possible elimination of technique and
apparatus from the outside.
(5) Time for adjustment: those who come from urban life ordinarily
have a certain appreciation for peace, stillness, and other aspects which
contrast sharply with the stressful lifestyle of the city. After a few days, or
a week, a certain underestimation usually sets in: the lack of radio,
television, cinemas, etc. It takes time for the new milieu to work in depth.
It is quite normal that several weeks must pass before the sensitivity for
nature is so developed that it fills the mind. If a great deal of technique and
apparatus are placed between oneself and nature, nature cannot possibly
be reached.
180 Ecosophy T: unity and diversity of life
3 Cruelty in nature;
the tragedy and the comedy of life
We may 'praise nature' using unconditional superlatives in our
poetry and rhetoric, but not in our philosophy or our politics. The
phenomena of social Darwinism, fascism, and national socialism con-
tained an unrestricted 'cult of life' with special emphasis on exploitation
and brutal competition. These political trends made use of untenable
descriptions of life, but we should as ecosophers avoid making people
believe we say 'yes!' to everything in nature.
The process of identification leads us to see much cruelty in nature. But
it does not necessarily lead to conceiving any animal to be cruel. A
behaviour may be deplored without applying negative ethical standards
to the actor.
In the 'oneness and diversity' philosophy which Ecosophy T presents,
independent treatment of four different fields of phenomena is required:
(1) Identification with living beings individually (distributively) and
within limited life situations;
(2) Identification with living beings collectively or in their essence ('life
itself, ecosystems, species);
(3) Ethical judgement (by different scales) of the individual beings in
specific situations;
(4) Ethical judgement of life collectively or in its essence.
Contemporary inspiration from naturalism essentially leads to identifi-
cation with all life, distributively. Abhorrence and rejection are scarce,
and arise, for example, at the sight of or treatment of the cruel conditions
caused by overpopulation. Presumably these reactions often have an
182 Ecosophy T: unity and diversity of life
garden was small and presumably not a threat to the habitats of other
living beings.
In this and other passages, it appears that human beings must answer
for their activities on Earth. In certain situations, mankind must moderate
the effects of wild animals upon other beings, extermination, seeing to it
that a certain order and harmony reign. That which God has created is not
to be exterminated, not even snakes in the Garden.
Mankind is accountable to God, in the light of our uniquely responsible
position; regent, caliph, deputy, guardian, administrator, steward, and
servant are some of the terms used in the Bible and the Koran.
Unhappily, the role of guardian with its duties and responsibilities
cannot be said to be systematically outlined anywhere in the Bible. In the
New Testament it is natural to refer to the parable of the faithful and
unfaithful servants. 4A certain man planted a vineyard, and set a hedge
about it, and dug a place and went into a far country' (Mark 12:1). The
husbandmen did not give the owner any wine. Things did not go well for
them. The kingdom of God shall be taken from you and given to a nation
bringing forth the fruit thereof (Matthew 21:43).
Many have used this parable in support of the attitude that mankind
must be accountable for how he behaves ecologically. There is a great
deal of evidence which corroborates the importance this interpretation
has had throughout the ages.
The Earth does not belong to mankind, according to Paul: Tor the
Earth is the Lord's, and the fullness thereof.' (I Corinthians 10:26).
Everything which God has created is good (I Timothy 4:4). There is, all
in all, less mention of external nature in the New Testament. The world
has soon to end. The spiritual salvation of mankind is more central than
in the Old Testament. There was no time to lose by nature conservation
as James Watt among others let us understand.
But back to the Old Testament. . .
Everything which is created by God is good and more wisely arranged
than-anything mankind can create, and more diverse. Therefore, nature
bears witness to God, not only in its diversity, but also in the ecosystem
where the food chains lead to lower conditions:
The young lions roar after their prey, and seek their meat from God.
(Psalm 104:21)
O Lord, how manifold are thy works! in wisdom hast thou made them
all: the Earth is full of thyriches.(Psalm 104:24)
So is this great and wide sea, wherein are things creeping
innumerable, both small and great beasts. Psalm 104:25)
. . . the LORD shall rejoice in his works. He looketh on the Earth, and
it trembleth: he toucheth the hills, and they smoke. (Psalm 104:31,32)
186 Ecosophy T: unity and diversity of life
difficult to harmonise this with the basic views within the deep ecology
movement. For Schumacher it does not seem difficult. He cites the
greatest Catholic thinker of the Middle Ages:
The smallest mosquito, as St. Thomas Aquinas said, is more wonderful
than anything man has produced and will ever produce. So man must
never lose his sense of the marvellousness of the world around and inside
him - a world which he has not made and which, assuredly, has not made
itself. Such an attitude engenders a spirit of nonviolence, which is a form
or aspect of wisdom.
Schumacher scarcely means that mosquitoes are more wonderful for man
to make use of than anything man himself has made. He seems somehow
to refer to the wonderfulness of God's creations as such, and if he does he
acknowledges the intrinsic value of all living beings.
Schumacher makes use of vague and ambiguous key terms in order to
indicate rough guidelines for policy. This is akin to the To formulations
which I make use of. It is too late to interview Schumacher in order to
clarify how he stands in relation to the near-common points of the deep
ecology movement. But we may safely assert that a Christian 'Ecosophy
S' might be elaborated on the basis of his influential writings.
entirety. Or, ecosophically: one aspect of existence was isolated from the
others and named 'physical reality'.
A search for supernatural being can easily become an endeavour
hostile to man and environment. True enough, it can lead to splendid art.
And a violent striving upwards need not, in theory, imply depreciation of
physical reality in its entirety, but it seems to have done that. L'Orange
contends that this characteristic can be traced in all forms of art, in all
forms of philosophy, and in all forms of social thought in the West:
Classical art is therefore an expression of an equilibrium, a reconciled
relationship between mankind and the world. It is this happy
equilibrium between inner and outer which is lost in later antiquity.
Human beings denied themselves the immediate, sensual loyalty to the
external world, and withdrew to isolated positions in their inner lives.
This is the tower from which the art of later antiquity and the early
Middle Ages looked down upon reality.
Thus Petrarch suffered from a bad conscience when he admired nature:
'I was stunned . . . angry with myself that I still admired earthly things. I
ought to have learned, long ago, even from pagan philosophers, that
nothing is admirable besides the mind: compared to its greatness nothing
is great.' (Seneca Epistle 8.5, Petrarch (1966))
What a poignant example of glorification of mankind to the detriment of
something elsel 'If x is glorious and y is different from x, y cannot be
glorious!' But is not a Both-and solution presumably possible? (See
chapter 2.)
The role of inner reflection is obvious as the quote continues:
. . . I was completely satisfied with what I had seen of the mountain and
turned my inner eye towards myself . . . How often, do you think, did I
turn back and look up toward the summit of the moutain today while I
was walking down? It seemed to rise hardly higher than a cubit
compared to the height of human contemplation, were the latter not
plunged into the squalor of earthly mud and filth.
From the point of view of Ecosophy T Petrarch exemplifies the
regression from a wide self to a narrow. He cuts off his previous
identifications and reifies the distinction inner-outer, alienating himself
from the mountain.
The distinction between 'in the Self and 'out in nature' makes it quite
difficult to describe our relationship to nature. When this distinction is
successfully transcended, another concept of nature and another concep-
tion of 'self will arise - the concept that is the fundamental intuition
behind Ecosophy T.
This glorification of human beings at the expense of nature becomes
Respect and self-respect 191
For all we know, life may have a great future in which we are
participating and changing. As far as the cosmic possibilities are con-
cerned, we can, without contradicting any 'hard facts', embrace theories
such as those about the evolution of a consciousness which encompasses
the entire universe. Personally, I can make do with less, but it would be
arbitrary to set a theoretical limit to the development and power of
conscious entities in the cosmos.
Notes on life in the universe are ecopolitically relevant, for they have
expanded and presumably still can expand the perspectives of many
people. Without a certain expansion in perspective, an ecologically
responsible politics is impossible.
who became 'kind' and did no wrong. The ecological viewpoint presup-
poses acceptance of the fact that big fish eat small, but not necessarily that
large men throttle small.
The philosophy of oneness' is a name which can be misleading: it can
give the impression that one who honestly and fairly accepts such a
philosophy has thereby succeeded and behaved consistently and unprob-
lematically in a certain way and maintained a certain frame of mind
towards our fellow creatures. In that case, the 'philosophy of oneness'
would be the name of a total system with obvious consequences in every
kind of situation - otherwise one would be abdicating one's freedom as a
person. But history is full of examples in which abstract fundamentals and
an impressive number of admirable derived norms have been accepted,
while they have not been reflected in practice; the path of derivation
through norms and hypotheses is too long to be mastered and our ability
to act spontaneously is too great!
The theoretical starting points of the philosophy of the one and the
many cannot replace the concrete time- and situation-determined deliber-
ations which must be made in a choice of appropriate political action. An
egalitarian norm is not misleading, but only a guideline, if one wishes to
consider political decisions in the widest possible perspective. This can
and must be done without a review of philosophy before each choice and
action. The ecopolitical situation is such that one must elicit support from
experts of many professions, while on the other hand efforts must be
made to assimilate their insights into a whole which not only is interdiscip-
linary, but also comprises the articulation of profound basic attitudes.
In the terminology of Ecosophy T the capital S in 'Self-realisation'
carries a heavy burden. It insinuates a philosophy of oneness as does
chapter 6, verse 29 of the Gita. But of course the difference in content is
vast, Ecosophy T as a total view belonging to a vastly different cultural
tradition. The S insinuates that if the widening and deepening of the self
goes on ad infinitum the selves will realise themselves by realising the
same, whatever this is. Because the infinite level of Self-realisation only
makes sense metaphysically, the capital S should be used sparingly. At
any level of realisation of potentials, the individual egos remain separate.
They do not dissolve like individual drops in the ocean. Our care
continues ultimately to concern the individuals, not any collectivity. But
the individual is not, and will not be isolatable, whatever exists has a
gestalt character.
Speaking about human individuals, it is in our competitive society
unavoidable to ask: Who have in historical times been pre-eminent in
approaching Self-realisation? There can be no good answer, because in
196 Ecosophy T: unity and diversity of life
written history such pre-eminence does not count: there must be regis-
tered influence on a great scale. And the extraordinary level must be
manifest, which is perhaps never the case. What about Gandhi? After all,
he was under close, in part very critical, scrutiny for half a century. Yes,
a genius of nonviolence, but also a fierce fighter, a cunning politician.
Talking about pre-eminence in approaching Self-realisation I suspect
more anonymous persons have reached higher. The manner of posing the
question may however reveal a rather provincial western way of thinking.
relation is not like that between a big elephant and a small mouse.
Microcosm is essential for the existence of macrocosm. Spinoza was
influenced by the idea when demanding an immanent God, not a God
apart. The door is open for positive evaluation of an increase of the
realisation of potentialities, that is, of the possibility that more poten-
tialities will be realised. This is meant to imply continued evolution at all
levels, including protozoans, landscapes, and human cultures.
The realisations should be qualitatively different. Numerical abundance
as such does not count. One way of emphasising this distinction is to
distinguish diversity from (mere) plurality. The term 'diversity' is well
established in biology, mostly used in talking about diversity of species or
of other qualitatively different living beings.
Further elaboration of the conception of diversity and the introduction
of the concepts of complexity and symbiosis clearly require the support of
hypotheses about the kind of universe we live in. Such support was,
strictly speaking, necessary even when starting to talk about Self-realisa-
tion, but only now is explicit mention of such support clearly needed. The
universe which we shall limit ourselves to mentioning is our planet, the
Earth, which we may also call 'Gaia' to emphasise its status as a living
being in the widest sense.
I make a lot of implicit assumptions about the life conditions of Earth,
especially its limitations. Any total view requires that.
Diversity may be defined so as to be only a necessary condition of the
growth of realising of Self-realisation potentialities. Then 'maximum
diversity!' does not make sense, because many differences may not
involve Self-realisation and may be inconsistent with symbiosis. Better to
imply qualitative difference as mentioned above to introduce concepts of
difference which distinguish it from mere plurality. The ambivalence of
plurality stems from finiteness - not only of our planet as a whole.
However, the adjective 'maximum' is added to some expressions of
Ecosophy T when diversity is introduced. The intention is to proclaim
that there is no inherent limit to the positive character of growth of
diversity. It is not intended that an increase is good even if it reduces the
conditions for realising other norms. If the adjective 'maximum' is to be
retained, it must, at a more precise (Tj) level, be taken as an abbreviation
for 'maximum, without hindering the realisation of other norms in the
system'. The presence of a norm of 'symbiosis!' in the system should
re-emphasise this - it knits the bond between complexity and diversity.
Now let us turn to complexity.
If we are permitted to vary three factors a,b,c in spatial horizontal
arrangements, we can only realise six different patterns: abc, acb, bac,
202 Ecosophy T: unity and diversity of life
bca, cab, cba. If we add one more basic factor, d, the number of
arrangements increases to 'four factorial', 24. This illustrates the intimate
relation between complexity and diversity. When the number of elements
increases linearly, the number of possible relationships increases facto-
rially.
Let us then think that abc is a pattern of life, conceived as a kind of
organismic or personal life. The pattern is characterised by three main
functions or dimensions, a, b, c working together as a highly integrated
system abc. Let the other five arrangements of a, b, and c symbolise five
other systems with the same number of dimensions.
The principle of self-preservation now may be said to consist minimally
in an internal mechanism such that the system defends itself against
reduction to 2-, 1-, or zero-dimensional ones, and also against transitions
to systems symbolised through the other five patterns, and tends posi-
tively to develop into systems with more dimensions, thus more diversity
and more complexity.
Complexity as opposed to complication is in Ecosophy T a quality of
organisms and their relation to their environment. It is characterised by
intimate interrelations, deep interdependence of a manifold of factors or
elements. After death a rhinoceros as a breathing entity is no more, but it
remains a tremendously complicated part of nature inhabited and invaded
by millions of other, less complex organisms. A human victim of African
sleeping sickness manifests the intimate interrelations between a human
individual and colonies of the flagellate Trypanosoma gambiensis. Each
of the flagellates has an unfathomable complexity of structure, but we
recognise the human being as a still higher order of complexity.
If complexity is defined in the biological direction of the opposite of
simplicity, 'maximum complexity!' cannot support Self-realisation. Only
if, as in the case of 'diversity!', some restraining clause is inserted, could
maximising make sense.
Since the great time of the reptiles limbs much more complex than the
human hand have developed. The simplicity of the human hand is from
this point of view a combined victory of simplicity and effectiveness over
complexity. There should be no cult of complexity.
In biological texts coloured by the conception of lower and higher
animals, the term complexity nearly always is used in descriptions of
advantageous cases of increases in complexity. 'Higher' functions are
made possible through certain more complex differentiations of tissues.
Eyes are developed from an earlier homogenous surface of skin. Less is
said about unsuccessful increase of complexity, presumably because only
species of great stability through millions of years have left fossils for us to
Systematisation of Ecosophy T 203
Figure 7.1
A/K\ /'y'*\*\
<Nd A b> f > < a? < ai A aj > a£ )
\\cX/ \ \ /'
a
/
\ a6 \ aj f 4 /
v
\ ' /
206 Ecosophy T: unity and diversity of life
will the control by single persons tend towards zero. Centralisation is here
intended to be defined through the above factors.
Using the reasoning suggested above, a set of hypotheses and norms
are proposed for Ecosophy T:
H8: Local self-sufficiency and cooperation favours increase of Self-
realisation.
H9: Local autonomy increases the chances of maintaining local self-
sufficiency.
H10: Centralisation decreases local self-sufficiency and autonomy.
N6: Local self-sufficiency and cooperation!
N7: Local autonomy!
N8: No centralisation!
Comments:
Doubt no. 1: Does not the realisation beyond a certain point of the
three norms N6, N7, and N8 interpreted individualistically lead to strange
conditions of life, in some ways similar to the famous terrifying 'state of
nature' in the political philosophy of Thomas Hobbes? Doubt no. 2: Do
the lessons of ecology really support the norms? Rejecting the indi-
vidualistic interpretation, we are therefore confronted with the difficult
task of making them more precise with the help of other justifications,
taking into account a serious concern of both individuals and collectives.
Seattle on the great change the White Man would bring to the land: 'the
end of living and the beginning of survival'.
The transition from the discussion of such ethically basic norms to more
political norms may be formulated in many ways. Here is one.
(1) The requirement of minimum conditions of Self-realisation should
have priority before others.
(2) This requirement implies that of minimum satisfaction of biologi-
cal, environmental, and social needs.
(3) Under present conditions many individuals and collectivities have
unsatisfied biological, environmental and social needs, whereas others
live in abundance.
(4) To the extent that it is objectively possible, resources now used for
keeping some at a considerably higher level than the minimum should be
relocated so as to maximally and permanently reduce the number of those
living at or below the minimum level.
One can say that the derivation of basic norms in Ecosophy T splits in
two different directions. The last level we have outlined presents the
norms and hypotheses of the local community, a characteristic ideal of
many Utopian systems. Now we are ready to follow an argument towards
politics to justify the norms and hypotheses against exploitation, as
developed through debates with the Marxists in Norway in the early
1970s.
Hll: Self-realisation requires realisation of all potentials.
H12: Exploitation reduces or eliminates potentials.
N9: No exploitation!
H13: Subjection reduces potentials.
N10: No subjection!
Nil: All have equal rights to Self-realisation!
H14: Class societies deny equal rights to Self-realisation!
N12: No class societies!
H15: Self-determination favours Self-realisation.
N13: Self-determination!
Comments:
The above formulations are put forth mainly to show that the funda-
mental norms of Self-realisation do not collide with norms of increasing
the reign of justice on Earth. On the contrary, the class differences inside
societies and between nations are clearly differences in conditions of
Self-realisation. Exploitation may be defined in terms of semi-permanent
or permanent reducing of the possibilities of some groups in favour of
others. Furthermore, calculations showing differences in the use of
energy and other resources support an ecological approach in the fight
208 Ecosophy T: unity and diversity of life
Figure 7.2
lifestyle' is a tenet of the deep rather than the shallow ecological move-
ment. Between 1975 and 1987 the deep ecological movement has gained
formidably in strength, and the outlook is optimistic for further
strengthening. But forces opposing the implementation of deep ecology
policies have gained even more in strength, and the outlook here is also
one of continuation.
One per cent increase in Gross National Product today inflicts far
greater destruction of nature than one per cent 10 or 20 years ago because
it is one per cent of a far larger product. And the old rough equivalency of
GNP with 'Gross National Pollution' still holds. And the efforts to
increase GNP create more formidable pressures against ecological
policies every year.
So significant deterioration of ecological conditions may well colour the
next years in spite of the deepening of ecological consciousness. The
situation has to get worse before it gets better.
The general attitude among politicians has been that if a major type of
interference in the ecosystem cannot be proven to be bad then it is justifi-
able to continue with business as usual. But the concern on acid rain has
increased slowly and steadily over the past decade. The warnings of one
government to another not to 'export' acid rain have been until recently
rather polite. It is to be expected that the tone will be harsher and that the
suffering involuntary 'importers', such as the Scandinavian countries,
will do more to stop their own serious sources of pollution in order to give
their complaints greater weight. The outlook is dark, however, especially
in regard to the export of acid rain from Eastern Europe. From the point
of view of the deep ecology movement, acid rain has had the positive
effect of helping people understand more clearly that to conserve forests
and fisheries one has to conserve worlds of micro-organisms, soils, and
systems of life which most people never noticed or cared for before.
Much broader ranges of identification and wonder have been opened!
Continued deterioration of life conditions may strengthen and deepen
the urge to stop acid rain production to the extent that radical political
measures will be taken against the offenders. Major changes in economic,
political, and ideological structures may then at last begin to unfold.
Supporters of the deep ecological movement constitute a small minor-
ity, quite badly organised compared to established pressure groups. They
are (sometimes for good reasons) reluctant to organise in large units. But
there are lessons to be learned. Big demonstrations and other forms of
large-scale, nonviolent direct action seem to work when what we try to
communicate, and the way the action is done, come as a kind of surprise
212 Ecosophy T: unity and diversity of life
to the general public and cause people to stop and reflect for a moment -
an increasingly difficult job, because of an increasing sense of repetition.
The years to come may see a greater emphasis on direct action directed
to crucially important groups, such as politicians and heads of anti-ecolog-
ical institutions. Other important groups to reach: teachers, experts,
scientists, specialists in mass communication. Study of mass communica-
tion and cooperation with masters of that trade has been used to advan-
tage by environmental groups such as Greenpeace.
The late 1970s saw cooperation between the peace movement and deep
ecology. No calamity could be worse from the latter point of view than
nuclear war. The arms race today supports the detrimental 'big is
beautiful' trend and involves the misuse of millions of mammals in
experiments with weapons, radioactivity and poisons.
Moving from the rich industrial portions of the world to the poorer
majority, we find that the same type of destruction of natural systems
which occurred hundreds of years ago in Europe and North America is
now under way in the rest of the world, particularly Africa. But there is a
major difference: in the former regions the process of destruction has
been concomitant with a vast increase of wealth and standard of living,
whereas in the latter this is far from the case. Thus, even the potential
forces of wide- and long-range, responsible ecological policy are absent.
Aid from the rich is essential, but it can so easily be misused that
extreme care and dedicated cooperation between institutions in both
regions of the world must be at its foundation. It is important to note that
the traditional cultural beliefs and practices of much of the world are
favourable to the norms of the deep ecological movement.
The deep ecology demand for the establishment of large territories free
from human development has recently gained in acceptance. It is now
clear that the hundreds of millions of years of evolution of mammals and
especially of large, territory-demanding animals will come to a halt if large
areas of wilderness are not established and protected. Wild areas previ-
ously classified as 'voids' are now realised to be of vital importance and
intrinsic value. This is an example of the kind of consciousness change
that strengthens deep ecology. It must continue.
These guesses about the future of the deep ecological movement are
inevitably influenced by hopes and fears. It is my hope that beings
endowed with a brain like ours, developed through hundreds of millions
of years in close interaction with all kinds of life will inevitably support a
way of life not only narrowly favourable to this species, but favourable to
the whole ecosphere in all its diversity and complexity. A uniquely
endowed part of this ecosphere will not turn into its eternal enemy.
Bibliography
Porritt, Jonathan (1984) Seeing Green: the Politics of Ecology Explained Oxford:
Blackwell
Pratt, Dallas (1980) Alternatives to Pain in Experiments on Animals, Argus
Archives
Reed, Peter and David Rothenberg, eds. (1987) Wisdom and the Open Air:
Selections from Norwegian Ecophilosophy Oslo: Council for Environmental
Studies
Rensch, Bernard (1971) Biophilosophy New York: Columbia University Press
Rolston, Holmes III (1985) 'Valuing wildlands' Environmental Ethics 7 23-48
Rothenberg, David (1987) 'A platform of deep ecology' The Environmentalist 1
No. 3,185-90
Schrader-Frechette, K. S. (1985) Science Policy, Ethics, and Economic
Methodology Dordrecht: Reidel Publishers
Schultz, Robert C. and J. D. Hughes, eds. (1981) Ecological Consciousness
Lanham, Md: University Press of America
Schumacher, E. F. (1973) Small is Beautiful - Economics as if People Mattered
New York: Harper Torchbooks
Schumacher, E. F. (1974) The Age of Plenty: A Christian View Edinburgh: Saint
Andrew Press
Sessions, George (1981) 'Shallow and deep ecology. A review of the
philosophical literature' Schultz and Hughes (1981)
Sessions, George (1987) 'Aldo Leopold and the deep ecology movement' A
Companion to a Sand County Almanac ed. B. Callicott, Madison: University of
Wisconsin Press
Simon, Julian, ed. (1984) The Resourceful Earth New York: Blackwell
Soule, Michael E. (1985) 'What is conservation biology?' BioScience 35 No. 11
727-34.
Soule, Michael E. (1986) 'Conservation biology and the real world' Conservation
Biology, ed. Michael Soule, Sunderland, Mass.: Sinauer Associates
Soule, Michael E. (1987) Viable Populations Cambridge University Press
Spinoza, Baruch (1949) Ethics New York: Hafner
van Liere, Kent D. and Riley E. Dunlap (1980) 'The social bases of
environmental concern' Public Opinion Quarterly 44 181-97.
Watson, Richard A. and Philip M. Smith (1970) Focus/MidwestMagazines40-2
Watson, Richard (1985) 'Challenging the underlying dogmas of
environmentalism' Whole Earth Review 5-13
Weiss, Paul (1971) 'The basic concept of hierarchical systems' Hierarchically
Organized Systems in Theory and Practice New York: Hafner
Wenstrup, Fred (1985) Arbeidsm0tet Norwegian School of Management, No. 4
Whitehead, A. N. (1972) Science and the Modern World Cambridge University
Press
Wilcox, Allen R. (1981) 'Basic needs, ethics, and quality of life' Applied Systems
and Cybernetics, ed. G. E. Lasker, Oxford: Pergamon Press
Winner, Langdon (1977) Autonomous Technology Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press
World Conservation Strategy (1980) Gland, Switzerland: International Union for
the Conservation of Nature (IUCN)
Zapffe, Peter Wessel (1941) Om det tragiske [On the tragic], Oslo
Index
communication diversity
importance 18, 136-7 cultural 31, 50, 98, 100-2, 123, 140,
inter-cultural 61 143, 155
see also precisations; relationalism of nature 4, 23-4, 29-30, 31, 34, 46-7,
Communication and Argument 21n. 85, 162, 169, 177, 199
communism 156 and plurality 201-2
communities of technologies 155
green 144-5 domination of nature, by man 171
local 115, 144-6, 183, 204-6 Dostoyevsky, F. M. 9, 11
competition, in sports 178-80 Duncan, Otis Dudley 122
complexity, ecological 46, 199, 200-3
conflict resolution 71, see also
environment, conflicts; norms, ecocatastrophe, threatened, see
conflict environment, crisis
conformity, pressures for 159 ecocentrism 15-16
consciousness, change in 89-91, 212 ecologism 39-40
effects 91-2 ecology
conservation, politicisation 132-3 definition 35-6
consumption limited knowledge of 26-7
as a basic norm 109 neglect of economics 105-6
changes in 91-2, 129, 162 scientific 3,24, 26, 27-8, 32, 39-40,41,
current patterns 23, 24-6, 31, 87, 44
89-91, 104 ecology movement, deep 4, 12, 27-9
andGNP 114 central themes 32-^1
contents, concrete 20, 35, 56-7, 60, 66-7 compared with environmental
control, see nature philosophies 14-20
costs, social 106-7, 115-16, 143, 157-8, critique of 17, 19, 132
see also shadow prices critique of technical reports 152-3
crisis, ecological, see environment, crisis future 210-13
cruelty in nature 181-2 and peace movement 160
platform 4, 28, 29-32, 38, 102, 199
specific cases 12-13
Dammann, Erik 88-90, 92, 157 system pyramid 13, 72-8
Darling, Frank Fraser 41 and value priorities 71-2
Debreu 119 ecology movement, shallow 14-20, 27-8,
decentralisation 115,204 33,39-40,96,151,211
need for 97, 98, 101-2, 142-3 and politics 136, 139, 162
decision-making 38, 79, 131-2, 193 Ecology Party, Britain 135
economic 106, 124-8 economics
political 135 and centralisation 145
defence, nonviolent 160 classical 33
demand, and needs 107, 116, 122, 171, definition 104-5
see also quality of life; standards of global/local 115
living neglect of 105-6, 110-11, 128
democracy 173, 175 pure 106-7
direct 144, 158 see also Gross National Product;
depth 12-14, see also ecology growth, economic; system,
movement, deep normative; welfare theory
derivation, logical 10, 37,42-4,74-5,77, ecophilosophy 3-4, 12, 14, 32
196, 197-8, 20&-10 definition 36-8
Descartes, Rene 39, 52, 191 ecopolitics, issues 135-8, see also
descriptions 41 politics, green; pollution;
phenomenological 50-1 population; resources
relational 48, 49-50, 54-6 ecosophy
subjective/objective 47-50, 69-70 definition 4, 32, 36-8, 45
Devall, Bill & Sessions, George 18, 135 as personal philosophy 5, 6, 33, 36-7,
differentiation, need for 97 41,80,88
distribution 112, 113, 116 see also lifestyle, ecosophical
Index 219
Ecosophy T 4-6, 34, 37-8, 39, 46, 55, exploitation 151, 152, 191, 207-8
163, 166, 174, 183 extinction 31, 46-7, 173, 185
key terms 7-14, see also depth;
derivation; environment; Faarlund, Nils 17&-9
identification; Self-realisation; facts, and values 24, 41, 60, 67, 6&-72,
value, intrinsic 73, 77, 188
norms and hypotheses 196-210 Falkenmark, Malin 21n.
see also gestalt Fechner 39,53
ecosystems fields, relational, see relationalism
balance 27 forests, devastation 87, 96, 100, 162, 211
interests of 4 formulations
needs 11 To 5-6,8,9,12,14,18-19,189,197-8,
Ecotopia (Ernest Callenbach) 157 20&-10
Eddington, Arthur Stanley 53 Tx 201
education 144, 159-60, 176, 179 Fox, Warwick 19
ego 173-5,195, 198 Fravar, M. Tagi & Milton, John 101
ego-realisation 84-5 Frege, Gottlob 39
Einstein, Albert 49 friluftsliv 126,178-81, 210
Elders, Fons 14 Frisch, Ragnar 105
elites, and control of technology 24, 93, Future in Our Hands, The, Norway 88-
94-5, 10O-1 90, 91, 137, 157
emotion 32, 63-5
in Ecosophy T 65-7 Gaia-hypothesis 138
empathy, need for 65, 172 Galbraith, John Kenneth 131
employment 116 Galileo Galilei 48, 52, 56-7
ends, richness of 33 Galtung, Johan 40, 98,152-3, 157
energy Gandhi, Mahatma 18, 71, 101-2, 146,
consciousness 92-3 148, 157, 194-6, 203-4
conservation 18,210 generalism
waste 93, 161 and local communities 145-6
environment in values 44-5
attitudes to 17 Georgescu-Roegen, Nicholas 128, 139
conflicts 64, 125-6, 128-9, 131, 204; gestalt
direct action 146-50, see also apperceptive 60
nonviolence in Ecosophy T 6-7, 10, 11, 20, 52,
crisis, extent 23-4, 25-6, 27, 104 66-7, 79-80, 82-3, 163, 195
see also milieu; technology, and solution lower and higher order 57-63, 109
to crisis switch 8
environmentalism Glacken, C. J. 186
philosophies of 2, 14-20, 32, 45-6, 67, goals 12,33,44-5,71,8<M, 112,148-50,
87,92 204
values 4 economic 108-10
equality 174, 176, 183 political 153, 162
ethics 2, 8, 20, 23-4, 66-7, 181-2 see also Self-realisation, as ultimate goal
and economics 105, 107, 125-6 Goldsmith, Edward 157
ethology 170 good life, see quality of life
evaluation, normative 40-7, 64-5, see Greenpeace, methods 212
also values Gross National Product
evolution 46, 173, 182, 201 and consumption 114
creative 85, 166 critique of use 110-11, 129, 211
see also speciation growth as irrelevant 114-15
existentialism 83-4 ignoring 111-16
experience, spontaneous 7, 20, 32, 35, and needs/wants 113
172 reform 115-16
gestalts in 57-63 as welfare measure 112,112-13
and joy 1-2 growth, economic 17,26,31,91,96,108,
and reality 63-5, 65-6 133, 145, 179-80
see also intuition; relationalism critique of 110-11, 153
220 Index
population local 98
non-human 136 revisability principle 69
policies needed 23, 29, 30-1, 100, 136, richness of nature 29-30, 31, 34, 46-7,
140-1, 142, 156 85, 93, 162, 169, 177
Porritt, Jonathan 135 rights
power structures 131-2, 147 human 29-30
precisations 5-4, 19, 42-3, 84, 165, 197, see also life, right to
208 rules, and systems 68-9
pressure groups 131-2
prices, see shadow pricing satisfaction 116-18, 123, 173^, 205
priorities, see action; values Schopenhauer, Arthur 82
production Schumacher, E. F. 97, 128, 132, 143,
changes in 92, 97, 129, 132, 162 187-9
control 157-8 Seattle, Chief 207
current patterns 23, 24-6, 87-8, 90-1, self
94, 97, 104 and nature 3, 11,85, 164
definition 110-11 and Self 9, 11, 56, 85-6, 174-5
direct 144, 157 Self, quest for 6, 168-9
and welfare 118 self-determination 141-3, 157, 159, 207
projection, theory of 52-4, 57, 61 Self-realisation 8-9, 10, 19, 62, 84-5,
Protagoras 54-5 141,166,195-6,204
protection, 'Master Plan' 128 and identification 11, 163, 164, 172,
Pythagoras 39 173-6, 178, 197-9
potential 199-200, 201, 205, 207
qualities in nature 51 as ultimate goal 84-6, 116, 118, 144,
primary 52, 54, 56 169-70, 207
secondary 52-3, 55-6, 57 and welfare theory 120-1
tertiary 52-3, 56, 57, 63, 65 Self-realisation! (as norm) 6, 33, 120,
quality of life 24-5, 29,31, 33, 80, 84,155 197, 200
and economics 111-12, 113, 121-3 self-reliance/self-sufficiency 3,76, 101,
and ecosophical lifestyle 88-91,93, 103, 143-4, 179, 204-6
100,210-11 semantics 5
see also life quality research; standard of Sessions, George 28, see also Devall, Bill
living & Sessions, George
Quesnay, Francois 105 shadow pricing 116
of nature 123-8
Shankara, Indian philosopher 194
Rader 119 Simon, Julian 26
rationality simplicity 202
in economics 107 and economics 109
as relational 33, 63 slogans 75-6
reality Smith, Adam 105
depreciation of 189-91 social structures, change in 4, 17, 26,
descriptions 48-54, 54-6, 57, 60, 79; in 91-2, 131-3, 153, 161
natural sciences 61, 65-6 socialism 119, 156, 157-60
differences in experiences of 66-7 soils, degradation 100
as totality 84 solidarity 172
recreation, outdoor 177-8 Sosial0konomen (The Economist',
regulation 159, 162 Norway) 112, 115
relationalism 6,10,28, 33, 36,48,49-50, Soule, Michael 45-6,47
54-6,65 Soviet Union, economics in 119-20,
in system thought 78-9 157-8
religion, and attitudes to nature 163, speciation, evolutionary 30, 46-7
165, 175, 191, see also Bible, the Spencer, Herbert 39
Rensch, Bernhard 51-2 Spinoza, Baruch 10,14, 39, 63,82-3,85,
reserve, nature 46-7, 199 166, 198, 201
resources spontaneity, see experience, spontaneous
depletion 139-40; and technology 96, sports, competitive 178-80
113, 114, 136; and Third standard of living 24-5, 29, 33, 40-1, 71,
World 150-1 80,84
Index 223
and ecological crisis 88, 98, 143, utility 116-17, 124-6, 177
210-11 marginal 117-18
see also quality of life
structures, abstract 57, 60, 66-7 Valery, Paul 96
subjectivity 32, 65-6, 125-6 values
of attitudes to nature 47-50, 51-3, 63 future 127
of values 68-9 instrumental 65, 75
sustainability 113, 116 intrinsic/means 74-6, 97, 112, 143-4,
symbiosis 168, 171, 175, 199, 200-1, 167-8, 184, 189
203-4 of nature 3, 11-12, 19, 29, 34
symbols, importance 62-3 neutrality of 112, 129
system, normative 33, 36, 38, 41-4, 47, priorities in economics 116, 119-20,
72-8, 84 122-3
ecological 78-80 to humanity 176-7
economics 107-10, 119-20, 122-3 values, experiential 23-5, 28, 32, 74
of Ecosophy T 196-210 priorities 24, 32-3, 36, 44-5, 64,
and evaluation of technique 95-6 68-72, 73, 87, 96, 123
and reality 63-5, 191
Tagore, Rabindranath 194 as subjective 68-9
technocentrism 15-16 see also evaluation; facts, and values
technocracy, see technology, culture of voluntarism 118, 161
technology
alternative 15-17,31 waste
as autonomous 93-6 nuclear 127
culture of 23-4, 33, 71-2, 82, 92, 97, reduction 90, 92
100, 102-3, 113, 175 see also energy, waste
intermediate 31,97 Watson, Richard 63
soft 31, 96, 97-100, 101, 113, 144-5 Watson, Richard A. & Smith, Philip
and solution to crisis 4, 96-7, 114 M. 140-1
in Third World 100-2, 151, 212 welfare
theorems 68-9 GNP as measure of 112-13
Third World non-human 117
aid 137,150-1 welfare theory
technology 100-2, 151, 212 economic 109, 116-18, 129
thought, mythic 61, 165 and normative systems 119-20
time scale, importance of 127, 136, 137, and Self-realisation 120-1
192 Wells, H. G. 178
Tiutchev, F 48 Wenstrup, Fred 126
transition, to soft technology 98-9 Whitehead, A. N. 51,54
translation, problems 7-14 wilderness
need for 138,212
UCIN, World Conservation Strategy 30, preservation 30
45 Winner, Langdon 96
unemployment, as consequence of Wittgenstein, Ludwig 12
change 92,98-9 World Conservation Strategy (UCIN) 30,
unity 45,151,157,208
concept of 4, 166, 168, 173, 193-6
and plurality 20O-1 Xenophon 104
universalisation, of systems 39-40, 76-7,
100 Zapffe, Peter Wessel 37, 194
utilitarianism 33, 44, 51, 85, 118, 176,
187, 191