American Society of Comparative Law Is Collaborating With JSTOR To Digitize, Preserve and Extend Access To The American Journal of Comparative Law
American Society of Comparative Law Is Collaborating With JSTOR To Digitize, Preserve and Extend Access To The American Journal of Comparative Law
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
American Society of Comparative Law is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The American
Journal of Comparative Law.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Comment
I
The contrast between case law and code law has long been one
of the commonplaces of comparative law.' Traditional accounts of
civil law systems denied to precedent the central place as a source of
law which it occupies in common law countries, emphasizing instead
the preeminence of legislative enactments as legitimate bases for
legal decisions.2 But even though orthodox theory insisted on por-
traying judicial decisions as logical deductions from preexisting stat-
utory premises,3 not all civilian scholars closed their eyes to the fact
that no code could be truly comprehensive, and that judges necessar-
ily had to make law, even as they were purporting to apply a past
legislator's words to novel circumstances unforeseen and unforesee-
able. And so when Benjamin Cardozo published in 1921 his Storrs
lectures on The Nature of the Judicial Process, in which he empha-
sized the creative role of "The Judge as Legislator" against a still
persistent similarly mechanistic American legal orthodoxy,4 he was
able to draw support freely from many Continental scholars such as
Brutt, Geny, Gmelin, Ehrlich, Kantorowicz, Salleiles, Duguit,
Michoud, Zitelmann, Stammler, Kohler, Berolzheimer, Charmont,
Jhering, Vander Eycken, and Demogue.5
But for all their theoretical recognition of judges' contributions
to the development of the law, these civilian authors on the whole
paid fairly little attention to specific cases in their writings. Prece-
dents were not recognized as a separate source of law which could
1. This is pointed out by M. Shaprio, Courts 135 (1981).
2. For a summary of such accounts see J.H. Merryman, The Civil Law Tradi-
tion 36, 46 f. (2nd ed. 1985).
3. On formalistic approaches in nineteenth-century civil law see J.P. Dawson,
The Oracles of the Law 392ff., 450ff.; W. Wilhelm, Zurjuristischen Methodenlehre im
19. Jahrhundert 80ff. (1958).
4. See G. Gilmore, The Ages of American Law 12, 60ff., 75ff. (1977).
5. See B.N. Cardozo, The Nature of the Judicial Process 15ff. (1921).
143
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
144 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW [Vol. 38
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1990] HOHMANN: LEGAL REASONING 145
11. These are particularly important in French law, where appellate opinions are
characterized by a very terse and strongly deductive style, see Goutal, supra n. 8, at
45, so that the underlying reasoning only emerges from the case notes, or from the
rapport written by one of the members of the court to prepare the decision, or the
conclusions submitted by the legal representative of the government; in important
cases rapport and conclusions may be published together with the decision, see Law-
son, supra n. 8, at 369; for examples of such decisions and notes see Wetter, supra n.
8, at 341ff.; for an overview of modern French practice see also Dawson, supra n. 3,
at 411ff.; for a collection of notes on decisions of the West German constitutional
court (Bundesverfassungsgericht), as well as a plea for more such case notes see P.
Haberle, Kommentierte Verfassungsrechtsprechung (1979).
12. See e.g. R. Alexy, Theorie der juristischen Argumentation 334-341 (1978),
where problems of determining the ratio decidendi, of distinguishing and overruling
are mentioned only very briefly at 340; H.-J. Koch & H. Russmann, Juristische
Begrundungslehre 373-375 (1981), where an answer is sketched to the question under
which conditions a precedent may be abandoned; A. Aarnio, The Rational as Reason-
able 81-86 (1987), where the main focus is on the question to what extent precedents
are sources of law, and the question of how the ratio decidendi may be identified is
given some attention at 83-85. Only Aarnio cites a single case in these discussions. A
relatively more extended discussion can be found in M. Kriele, Theorie der Recht-
sgewinnung 269-289 (2nd ed. 1976), but even this is still rather short; Kriele's inter-
est in precedents may not be unrelated to the fact that he received an LL.M. degree
at Yale.
13. On the relationship between prescriptive and descriptive theories of legal ar-
gumentation see U. Neumann, Juristische Argumentationslehre 10ff., 118 (1986).
14. See F. Haft, Juristische Rhetorik (1978), where precedent-based forms of
legal argumentation receive no particular attention at all.
15. In spite of the general recognition of the practical importance of precedent,
civil law scholars still tend to emphasize its limited binding force; see e.g. David,
supra n. 10, at 135f., and Koch & Riissmann, supra n. 12, at 187f.
16. See Merryman, supra n. 2, at 34ff., 56ff.
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
146 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW [Vol. 38
II
A central concern animating theories of legal reasoning is the
legitimacy of judges' decisions. Judicial law-making is a fact of life
which provokes ambivalent reactions; it appears that as a society we
cannot live without it, yet also cannot quite live with it. Here as
elsewhere, a frequent response to ambivalence has been denial:
much traditional theory has asserted that judges do not make rules,
but only apply them, and that their decisions are guided only by
legal, as opposed to moral or political considerations.2' Such asser-
tions were always less plausible in common law systems, which
lacked the comprehensive codes characterizing civil law systems,
and in which, therefore, large areas of the law were developed
through judicial decisions not based on any discernible rules of legis-
lative origin. Nevertheless, attempts have not been lacking to assign
to prior judicial decisions the same constraining role as that ascribed
to statutory norms.22 More recently, efforts to maintain the strict
separation between legislative and judicial rule-making have tended
17. See R.M. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (1977) and The Empire of Law
(1986), with their theoretical constructs focusing on the feats of a judge Hercules of
unabashedly mythical abilities.
18. See e.g. H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 120ff. (1961); cf. also N. Mac-
Cormick, Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory 195ff. (1978), where, however, some at-
tention is given to reasoning from precedent at 213-228.
19. See e.g. E.H. Levi, An Introduction to Legal Reasoning (1949) and M.P. Gold-
ing, Legal Reasoning (1984).
20. M.A. Eisenberg, The Nature of the Common Law (1988). Figures in paren-
theses in the text will refer to pages in this book.
21. Cf. supra n. 3.
22. On the rise of legal formalism in the United States in the nineteenth century
see M.J. Horwitz, The Transformation of American Law 1780-1860 253ff. (1977); on
the development of a strict doctrine of precedent in England see R. Stevens, Law
and Politics, The House of Lords as a Judicial Body, 1800-1976 77ff. (1978).
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1990] HOHMANN: LEGAL REASONING 147
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
148 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW [Vol. 38
III
Since social propositions play a pervasive role in common law
reasoning (2f., 75f.), the criteria that they must satisfy if they are to
figure properly in that process are of central importance. As Eisen-
berg formulates them, the principles governing the use of all three
types of social propositions are largely parallel. In order to be con-
sidered, moral norms must represent social morality, i.e. they must
be
"moral standards that claim to be rooted in aspirations for
the community as a whole, and that, on the basis of an ap-
propriate methodology, can fairly be said to have substan-
tial support in the community, can be derived from norms
that have such support, or appear as if they would have
such support" (15).
Policies must be those
"that claim to characterize a state of affairs as good for the
community as a whole, and that, on the basis of an appro-
priate methodology, can fairly be said to have substantial
support in the community, can be derived from policies that
have such support, or appear as if they would have such
support" (29).
The requisite support for experiential propositions differs some-
what, since these concern matters of expertise; so instead of depend-
ing on the support of the general community, they
"should be supported by (or be propositions the court be-
lieves would be supported by) the weight of informed opin-
ion28-including informed opinion of the courts themselves
in matters in which they are expert, such as the capacity of
fact finders" (40).
While he insists that the determination whether such criteria
are met is an empirical judgment (18, 31), Eisenberg is the first to
admit that it usually cannot be ascertained as a practical matter
whether the requisite support truly exists, particularly in the case of
moral norms and policies (18, 30f.). Therefore, it is very much the
judgment of the court that matters, and this judgment is normally
27. See J. Stone, Legal Systems and Lawyers' Reasonings 55 (1968); Koch &
Russmann, supra n. 12, at 22ff.
28. Cf. the similar characterization of "generally accepted opinions," which can
properly serve as a basis for dialectical reasoning, in Aristotle, Topica lOOb18 (tr.
E.S. Forster): "those which commend themselves to all or the majority or to the
wise-that is, to all of the wise or to the majority or to the most famous and distin-
guished of them."
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1990] HOHMANN: LEGAL REASONING 149
IV
Once social propositions have been determined to be proper
components of common law reasoning, how are they to interact with
doctrinal propositions? To answer this question, Eisenberg develops
standards for the common law which in fact bear close resemblance
to standards also relevant in civil law systems. He first distinguishes
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
150 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW [Vol. 38
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1990] HOHMANN: LEGAL REASONING 151
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
152 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW [Vol. 38
arguments from prior cases are among the available means of foren-
sic persuasion which he discusses.47
In traditional civil law interpretation theories, the element of
doctrinal stability is represented by the notions of grammatical and
historical interpretation,48 which tend to focus on the meaning of
the text as it was initially conceived, and are thus more inimical to
adaptive change than teleological and systematic interpretation.
That the contrast is, however, by no means absolute is well illus-
trated by the uses of history in constitutional interpretation in the
United States: change can be brought about by reinterpretations of
history.49 The same ambiguity affects the notion of doctrinal stabil-
ity, since the content of the original doctrine may be reinterpreted
in a similar fashion.50
While Eisenberg juxtaposes the coherence standard as based on
social propositions with the stability standard as giving a major role
to doctrinal propositions (47), it might be argued that the special
standards of the legal system which this role reflects must, in turn,
be justifiable in terms of applicable social propositions if it is to be
maintained. Similarly as in the case of weak systemic consistency,
there must be at least a formal approval of the cleavage between
general social and special legal standards, presumably based on the
assumption that the latter serve some long-term social good. Thus,
in the last analysis there must be some social support for a legal pol-
icy which trades off some short-term satisfaction for greater long-
term stability.51
V
The core of The Nature of the Common Law is formed by Eisen-
berg's detailed and perceptive examination of the modes of legal rea-
soning employed in the common law, including overruling and other
modes of overturning (50-145). Because the author builds his theo-
retical conclusions on a strong descriptive foundation, he achieves a
successful synthesis of practical realism and systematic rigor. For
47. See Aristotle, Rhetoric 1376a 8; Aristotle does not specifically refer to legal
cases here, but generally to authoritative pronouncements on disputed points.
48. See supra n. 31.
49. See C.A. Miller, The Supreme Court and the Uses of History (1969); this issue
has attracted particular attention in the context of the recent debate about constitu-
tional interpretation, see e.g. C. Wolfe, The Rise of Modern Judicial Review (1986)
and H.J. Powell, "The Modern Misunderstanding of Original Intent," 54 U. Chi. L.
Rev. 693 (1987).
50. See Eisenberg's discussion (58-61) of Cardozo's treatment of relevant New
York precedents in MacPherson v. Buick Motor Co., 217 N.Y. 382, 111 N.E. 1050
(1916).
51. Eisenberg recognizes this when he states that "consistency with past institu-
tional decisions has only limited value for its own sake; it has substantial value only
if it serves some fairness or policy goal" (144).
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1990] HOHMANN: LEGAL REASONING 153
52. See Neumann, supra n. 13, at 112ff. on the relatively rudimentary state of
systematic empirical analyses of legal argumentation.
53. While Aristotle's own treatment of legal argumentation remains rather
sketchy (Rhetoric 1375a 22ff.), Quintilian's Institutio Oratoria provides a more fully
developed overview, which covers precedents (5.2), the use of principles and analo-
gies to restrict or extend legal norms (5.11.32f., 7.6, 7.8), uses of authorities in general
(5.11.36ff.) and of the legal literature in particular (12.3) (Quintilian's opinion of
legal experts is tinged by professional rivalry), and hypotheticals (5.10.95ff.).
54. Ecclesiastes 1.9.
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
154 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW [Vol. 38
55. Reasoning from precedent and principle are forms of deductive reasoning,
which fall into Aristotle's rhetorical category of the enthymeme (Rhetoric 1356b
1ff.); reasoning by analogy corresponds to Aristotle's rhetorical category of the ex-
ample, which also covers the process by which a doctrinal proposition is derived
from a number of similar cases (Rhetoric 1356b 13f.), and which is the equivalent of
induction in dialectics; an authority recognized by the audience can be a source for
opinions which may form premisses for rhetorical syllogisms (Rhetoric 1396a 1).
56. See R. Pound, "Mechanical Jurisprudence," 8 Col. L. Rev. 605 (1908); see also
supra n. 3; on the reactions of G6ny and the German Freirechtsschule see Stone,
supra n. 27, at 212ff., 227ff.; on connections between the Freirechtsschule and Ameri-
can legal realism see J.E. Herget & S. Wallace, "The German Free Law Movement
as the Source of American Legal Realism," 73 Va. L. Rev. 399 (1987).
57. For a treatment of legal argumentation which aims to "rehabilitate" the de-
ductive model see Koch & Russmann, supra n. 12, at 14ff.; for a critical evaluation of
such efforts see Neumann, supra n. 13, at 16ff.
58. See Levi, supra n. 19.
59. See e.g. J. Esser, Grundsatz und Norm in der 7ichterlichen Fortbildung des
Privatrechts (2nd ed. 1964), whose analysis of "'Principle and Rule' in Case Law"
(chapter X, at 183ff.) cites Levi as a source to be considered "above all" (vor allem)
in snnroachin_ the concent of "legal reasoning" (at 184 n. 187).
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1990] HOHMANN: LEGAL REASONING 155
decisions.60 Surely rules are not everything, but neither are they
nothing.
The parallel logical structure of different modes of legal reason-
ing is well identified by Eisenberg when he points out that
"[e]ssentially, reasoning by analogy in the common law is a special
type of reasoning from standards, like reasoning from precedent and
from principle" (87). But while he recognizes the similarity between
analogy and reasoning from hypotheticals as well, he feels that the
latter "differs in substance from both reasoning by analogy and the
other modes of reasoning previously considered [i.e. precedent and
principle]," because it "depends on an interplay between applicable
social propositions and conceivable [rather than actual] doctrinal
propositions and cases" (102). But one may doubt this assessment
insofar as in both major categories of reasoning from hypotheticals,
in which the object is to show either "that a rule should be adopted
because the case cannot be distinguished from hypotheticals in
which the rule seems clearly proper," or "that a rule should be re-
jected because the case cannot be distinguished from hypotheticals
in which the rule seems clearly improper," (101) the claim is that
the decision in the hypothetical case is so obviously predictable and
beyond doubt that in substance it is already part of the law. Eisen-
berg himself defines the common law as consisting "of the rules that
would be generated at the present moment by application of the in-
stitutional principles of adjudication," (154) and what the deciding
court does in using hypothetical reasoning is precisely to generate
such a rule for the hypothetical case, from which then a rule for the
actual case can be derived by analogy or its denial. Thus the rule
applicable to the hypothetical only lacks formal recognition, which,
however, the deciding court treats as a matter of course, and in fact
indirectly bestows in developing the hypothetical argument.61
Reasoning from precedent is clearly the central argumentative
mode of the common law. It converges with the interpretation of ca-
nonical legislative texts, at the core of civil law argumentation, not
only because both are reasoning from standards, and because usually
civil law norms come to a court with a gloss of scholarly and judicial
60. On the distinction between the process of discovery and the process of justifi-
cation see R.A. Wasserstrom, The Judicial Decision 25ff. (1961); for a similar distinc-
tion between creation (Herstellung) and presentation (Darstellung) of a decision see
N. Luhmann, Recht und Automation in der 6ffentlichen Verwaltung 51ff. (1966).
61. While technically courts are not supposed to give "advisory opinions," in fact
judges may give strong indications how they would decide a case other than the one
before them, in order to discourage or encourage litigation. Thus a number of re-
marks in opinions in Poe v. Ullman, 367 U.S. 497 (1961) helped to prepare Griswold
v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965), and indications in Jones v. Opelika, 316 U.S. 584
(1942) paved the way for West Virginia State Board of Education v. Barnette, 319
U.S. 624 (1943).
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
156 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW [Vol. 38
62. The parallel between the activities of civil law and common law judges is
pointed out by Merryman, supra n. 2 at 43; see also infra text after n. 64.
63. For a discussion of the treatment of this complex in ancient rhetorical theory
see U. Wesel, Rhetorische Statuslehre und Gesetzesauslegung der r6mischen Juristen
42ff. (1967).
64. This is the title of the book by Ruthers, supra n. 30. On the problem of a
hierarchy of interpretive techniques see J. Esser, Vorverstandnis und Methodenwahl
in der Rechtsfindung 122ff. (1970); Kriele, supra n. 12, at 85ff.; Alexy, supra n. 12, at
288ff.
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1990] HOHMANN: LEGAL REASONING 157
65. Eisenberg here collapses the standard of systemic consistency into that of so-
cial congruence, "[s]ince systemic consistency usually depends on social congruence"
(75).
66. The maintenance of a higher burden of proof on those who propose to devi-
ate from a rule in favor of particularized reasons is also a concern expressed by
Schauer, supra n. 23, at 862, 869.
67. See Koch & Russmann, supra n. 12, at 373ff.
68. See supra sec. III and infra sec. VII.
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
158 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW [Vol. 38
VI
Since the common law process requires such complex judg-
ments at every step-from the identification and interpretation of
foundational principles, over the determination and weighing of ap-
plicable social propositions, to the assessment of the social congru-
ence and systemic consistency of doctrinal propositions, and the
adjustment between these requirements as well as the demands of
doctrinal stability, which is effected through the choice between dif-
ferent modes of legal reasoning and overturning-it is not surprising
that one of the points which Eisenberg emphasizes in his concluding
chapter is "the uncertain nature of the common law" (157-159). He
states quite clearly that these key judgments all concern "matters
on which certainty is not possible," and that consequently among
common law rules "few if any are completely certain" (157). He also
shows that legal rules need not be certain to make planning possible
(157f.), and that the idea of the rule of law does not require that the
law consist of fixed previously existing substantive rules (158f.).
Since judgment is such a pervasive feature of the common law,
69. Given the considerable attention paid to this technique by civilian scholars,
Eisenberg's reminder that it "is used in only a very small fraction of overturnings"
(132) may be useful.
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1990] HOHMANN: LEGAL REASONING 159
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
160 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW [Vol. 38
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1990] HOHMANN: LEGAL REASONING 161
cially since in that case the possibility remains that actually both
sets of norms will be violated.
Since Eisenberg assures us that the assumption that judges es-
tablish legal rules and determine outcomes according to personal
convictions "describes neither what judges claim to do, what they ac-
tually do, nor what they should do," (143) but since we also know of
Holmesian "can't helps" and are told by Cardozo that "[t]he training
of the judge, if coupled with what is styled the judicial tempera-
ment, will help in some degree to emancipate him from the sugges-
tive power of individual dislikes and prepossessions. It will help to
broaden the group to which his subconscious loyalties are due.
Never will these loyalties be utterly extinguished while human na-
ture is what it is,"72 and since, furthermore, we have just seen that
under conditions of uncertainty some reliance on personal standards
is inevitable, we must assume that the prohibition on the use of indi-
vidual norms needs to be limited to purely idiosyncratic preferences.
But then the training and selection of judges will likely elimi-
nate these anyway, and a judge will be well advised to restrain re-
maining ones for purely prudential reasons, since a decision based
on them would not likely prevail in practice. If, on the other hand,
the judge sees some chance that an unusual view, while not yet pre-
dominant, could represent an emerging social norm which will soon
attract substantial social support-a possibility for which Eisenberg
allows, assuming that the judge is ready to pull back if that belief
proves incorrect (17)-then the judge's individual convictions must
again play an important part: the personal evaluation of the
strength of the moral position in question will influence the assess-
ment of how clear the initial traces of emerging social support need
to be, how soon how much additional support has to be forthcoming,
and how long the judge may endeavor to garner further approval
before the effort must be abandoned.
The realities of the selection process for judges in the civil as
well as in the common law world suggest that whatever we might
desire judges to do in theory, we know that in practice their per-
sonal values do and must play a part in their decisions.73 The con-
trast between judges and legislators is in this respect by no means as
strong as it might initially appear. Since legislators are representa-
tives of the people, they are also morally bound to consider social
norms in making their decisions. They are by no means free to dis-
regard generally held views in favor of purely idiosyncratic prefer-
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
162 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW [Vol. 38
ences, but must always be able to argue that any deviation from
current popular desires is justified by long-term gains for the com-
mon good, or by requirements of a higher social morality to which
the electorate ultimately remains committed. The real test of the
appropriateness of a change, be it legislative or judicial, cannot lie in
an advance determination of whether it is based on institutional
principles or personal values, but only in the retroactive assessment
and control exercised in a process which Eisenberg aptly calls the
"check of discourse." This process must determine whether the pro-
jection of critical morality and right policy, which is implied in the
decision to make a change, can attract the degree of social support
which is required if the change is to succeed.
VII
The "check of discourse" is necessary because the institutional
principles governing the process of generating the common law do
not provide monologically testable criteria. Thus, if these principles
are to exercise true normative control over the actions of judges,
their application by judges must be controlled by others, even as
judges themselves must ensure that legal rules do not merely obey
those who are meant to obey the rules. The guardians are guarded
by those they guard.74 In recognizing the central role of discourse in
the process which aims at separating mere assertions about the law
from warranted claims, Eisenberg develops for the common law a
perspective similar to views which have been gaining increasing cur-
rency in the literature on legal reasoning in the civil law as well.
For all their considerable differences, these views share the insight
that legal argumentation cannot be evaluated by abstract formal cri-
teria, but must prove itself through its ability to win the assent of an
audience in a process of discourse.75
This development in legal theory is part of a larger philosophi-
cal movement away from dichotomies between demonstrable knowl-
edge and idiosyncratic opinion, and towards criteria of truth which
do not consign questions of value to the realm of irrational prefer-
ences.76 What keeps the pragmatism of such process- and audience-
74. This is the answer, in a democracy, to Juvenal's famous question "Sed quis
custodiet ipsos custodes?" ("But who shall guard the guardians themselves?", Satires
6.347).
75. Cf. e.g. Alexy, supra n. 12, at 219ff.; Koch & Russmann, supra n. 12, at 363ff.;
Aarnio, supra n. 12, at 185ff.
76. Cf. e.g. C. Perelman & L. Olbrechts-Tyteca, Traite de lArgumentation. La
nouvelle rhetorique (2nd ed. 1970); S.E. Toulmin, The Uses of Argument (1958); J.
Rawls, A Theory of Justice (1971); J. Habermas, "Wahrheitstheorien," in Wir-
klichkeit und Reflexion. Festschrift fur Walter Schulz 211 (H. Fahrenbach ed. 1973);
W. Booth, Modern Dogma and the Rhetoric of Assent (1974); R. Nozick, Philosophi-
cal Explanations (1981).
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1990] HOHMANN: LEGAL REASONING 163
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
164 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW [Vol. 38
79. On risk analysis see generally M.T. Douglas, Risk Acceptability According to
the Social Sciences (1985).
80. See Aristotle, Rhetoric 1357a 4ff.: 'The subjects of our deliberation are such
as seem to present us with alternative possibilities: about things that could not have
been, and cannot now or in the future be, other than they are, nobody who takes
them to be of this nature wastes his time in deliberation." (tr. W. Rhys Roberts).
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1990] HOHMANN: LEGAL REASONING 165
VIII
The generative conception of the common law which Eisenberg
develops, with its emphasis on the responsiveness of courts to social
propositions and on the check of discourse, is illuminating to civil
lawyers precisely because it dispenses with a presupposition which
still distorts much civil law argumentation: that canonical texts
form the true foundation of legal reasoning. It is perhaps easier for
a common lawyer, dealing with an area of the law which is on the
whole less controversial (26), and standing in a tradition which is
not overly troubled by the notion that judges establish legal rules
(4ff.), to address with unaffected clarity and purposeful directness
the interactions between judicial and social processes which hold out
the promise of a more responsive law.82 But it may be hoped that
civil lawyers will recognize in Eisenberg's account of the common
law enough that is similar to their own legal experience to en-
courage them to take a fresh look at the civil law, a look less encum-
bered by traditional theoretical assumptions and political
nervousness. The Nature of the Common Law can thus provide not
only a better understanding of the common law, but also contribute
to a comparative perspective for a broader assessment of civil law
reasoning.
The common law system, particularly in the United States, has
been more comfortable with the idea of the judge as a visible and
vocal participant in public discourse, while the civil law has tended
to assign to the judiciary the role of a "silent power."83 Insofar as
81. See M.R. Kadish & S.H. Kadish, Discretion to Disobey 69f. (1973) on the
"retrospective fallacy" in the explanation of legal phenomena.
82. See generally P. Nonet & P. Selznick, Law and Society in Transition: To-
ward Responsive Law (1978).
83. This is the title of a book by R. Lautmann, Justiz-die stille Gewalt (1972), in
which the author describes and analyzes his experiences as a participant-observer
while serving as a judge on a West German court. On the political background for
this perception of the judicial role see e.g. Merryman, supra n. 2, at 15f., 35f. In
Montesquieu's famous phrase the judge is supposed to be only the mouth which
speaks the words of the law ("la bouche qui prononce les paroles de la loi," De
l'esprit des lois 11.6; it is somewhat ironic that this phrase appears in a chapter enti-
tled "Of the Constitution of England."
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
166 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW [Vol. 38
84. The example of Sweden is particularly instructive in this context, since there
the change from the classical style, rather similar to the French approach, to a more
open modern style was quite pronounced: see Wetter, supra n. 8, at 79ff.
85. The West German Federal Constitutional Court (Bundesverfassungsgericht)
publishes dissenting opinions; on the general absence of the practice in civil law
countries see Merryman, supra n. 2, at 121f.
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1990] HOHMANN: LEGAL REASONING 167
Ix
Comparative law is not addressed directly in The Nature of the
Common Law, but nevertheless the book illustrates an important
function of comparative law, which gives an answer to those who
may wonder what comparative lawyers can do, beyond showing the
similarities and differences between legal rules in different coun-
tries, and using other jurisdictions as the legal equivalent of test lab-
oratories for potential new products.90 Eisenberg concludes his
discussion of reasoning from doctrines established in the profes-
sional literature (96-99) by pointing to the relative uniformity of tort
86. This is illustrated by the school desegregation and abortion decisions of the
United States Supreme Court.
87. See e.g. Esser, supra n. 59, at 54 n. 174.
88. On judicial style as persuasion see R. Posner, Law and Literature 270ff.
(1988).
89. See K. Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition (1960).
90. See Shapiro, supra n. 1, at vii.
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
168 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW [Vol. 38
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1990] HOHMANN: LEGAL REASONING 169
95. See BVerfGE 5, 85, 135 and BVerfGE 35, 202, 233; the former quotation is ac-
tually given in English in the German text.
96. See BVerfGE 39, 1. The dissenters acknowledged the difference between the
constitutional situations in West Germany and the United States, but still used the
legal treatment of abortion in America as well as in other European countries as an
indication that the legislative decision to liberalize abortion was not obviously mor-
ally wrong.
97. 410 U.S. 113 (1973).
98. See ?? 516ff. of the German Civil Code (BGB).
99. Esser, supra n. 59, at 327ff. discusses the prospect of "universal legal princi-
ples," and their future significance for supranational legal communities.
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
170 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW [Vol. 38
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Sat, 14 Nov 2015 12:33:22 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions