Guyer Baumgarten Herder PDF

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 34

Guyer 1

“A Treasure Chamber of the Human Soul”:

Baumgarten, Mendelssohn, and Herder

Paul Guyer

1. Herder Across the Disciplines


Philosophy, psychology, linguistics, history, theology; poetry, painting, sculpture, music:

to write anything about Herder is to write about Herder across the disciplines. Here I will

discuss the relation of Herder’s thoughts about the arts of poetry and music to two main
philosophical predecessors, and that would seem an attempt to confine Herder within one

discipline rather than to discuss Herder across the disciplines. But what I will argue is that

although it might seem surprising, what Herder was aided to see by these two philosophers,
Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten (whose work was carried on by his disciple Georg Friedrich
Meier) and Moses Mendelssohn, presumed paragons of purely rationalist philosophy, was, at a

methodological level, precisely the fruitfulness of the miscegenation of philosophy, psychology,


and even physiology, and, at a substantive level, the importance of what he called energy to our

experience of poetry and music, the importance of the body to the experience of sculpture, and
the complexity of language in general. As with most education, no doubt Herder’s exposure to
the works of these philosophers only helped shape his own native tendencies, but if his method

and the substance of his thought had any external sources, then these two predecessors must rank
high among them.

In an early text on the recently and prematurely deceased John the Baptist of aesthetics,

“A Monument to Baumgarten,” Herder criticized his subject for his excessive reliance on “a
priori deduction” and “modern abstraction,”1 but more emphatically claimed that “it is

preeminently Baumgarten’s principle that teaches us to become initiated into the profoundest

secrets of our soul and to make a psychological discovery with each rule of beauty.”2 He

described Baumgarten as a “Wolffian philosopher and a Christgauian poet conjoined in a single


person”3 and praised Baumgarten’s early dissertation Philosophical Mediations on Some Matters

Pertaining to Poetry4 as “an attempt to transplant Wolffian philosophy into the soil so dear to our
Guyer 2

Baumgarten, the soil of his childhood sweetheart, poetic art.”5 In the “Fourth Grove” of his

Critical Forests or (as I prefer) Groves of Criticism, which went unpublished during his lifetime,
Herder again praised Baumgarten in the passage from which I have taken my title:

To me, Baumgarten’s psychology has ever seemed a rich treasure chamber of the human

soul and a commentary on it that was able to combine, in the sphere of sound

understanding, the poetic intuition of a Klopstock with the calm observation and serene
introspection of a Montaigne, and, finally, in the higher realms of human thought, with

the acute vision of a second Leibniz -- such a commentary would be a book of the human

soul, a plan for human education,6 and the gateway to an encyclopedia for all the arts and
letters.7

Thus, Herder saw Baumgarten as combining philosophy and poetics to yield a psychology, or

synthesizing philosophy, poetry, and psychology -- Leibniz (instead of Wolff), Klopstock, and
Montaigne -- to produce an encyclopedia of both all the arts and letters and the human soul.

Herder next praised Mendelssohn for developing “Baumgarten’s principle that teaches us
to become initiated into the profoundest secrets of our soul and to make a pyschological
discovery with each rule of beauty,” thus for continuing Baumgarten’s crossbreeding of

philosophy and psychology; he described the early line in Mendelssohn’s essay “On the Main

Principles of the Fine Arts and Sciences” that “If the philosopher pursues the traces of the

sentiments on their obscure paths, new perspectives in psychology must open themselves to him”
as if it were a “eulogy” to Baumgarten.8 But in the “Fourth Grove,” Herder also praised

Mendelssohn for distinguishing between “the contributions of both body and soul to agreeable

sentiments” in his Letters on the Sentiments and following Rhapsody, thus for comprehending
“man in the totality of his mixed nature,” and for doing this “more finely” than, for example,

Johann Georg Sulzer.9 So Herder saw Mendelssohn as adding physiology to Baumgarten’s

combination of philosophy and psychology, and presumably followed him in that amplification
of the resources for the discussion of the arts and their impact on us.
Guyer 3

Herder’s praise of Baumgarten and Mendelssohn for adding psychology and then even

physiology to philosophy in order to produce aesthetics might cause surprise in those

accustomed to the textbook characterization of Baumgarten as the author of an aesthetics that is

exclusively the logic of the lower of inferior cognitive faculties, that describes taste as the
analogon rationis or “analogue of reason,” and which generates its list of aesthetic qualities or in

the preferred terminology of the time “perfections” simply by prefixing the adjective “aesthetic”

to the properties or merits of ordinary cognition, and likewise accustomed to an image of


Mendelssohn as an appropriator of the learned academic Baumgarten for the elegant audience of

Berlin literary magazines and salons. There can be no doubt that Baumgarten did try to explain

what the discipline of aesthetics does as well as to dignify it by associating it with logic: thus in
the dissertation in which he first coined the new name for the age-old discipline, he said that it is
“a task for logic in a more general sense to direct [the lower] faculty [of cognition] in the sensory

cognition of things”10 and defined “aesthetics” as a form of cognition, “epistēmē aisthētikē” or

the form of cognition that has “aisthēta” or objects of the senses as its subject;11 and in his

incompleted Aesthetica of fifteen years later, the first textbook to bear the new name of the

discipline, he described his subject as the “theory of the liberal arts” and the “art of beautiful
thinking” but also as the “lower epistemology” (gnoseologia inferior) and the “art of the

analogue of reason” (ars analogi rationis).12 And in his essay on the “Main Principles” of the
fine arts and sciences, Mendelssohn adopted Baumgarten’s original definition of a poem as a

“sensuously perfect discourse”13 in its generalized form, applicable to all arts, as “the perfection

of sensuous cognition as such” (perfectio cognitionis sensitivae, qua talis),14 in his own
statement that “the essence of the fine arts and sciences consists in an artful, sensuously perfect

representation or in a sensuous perfection represented by art”;15 so if Baumgarten’s conception


of aesthetic qualities or merits is based solely on logic, if they are nothing but the merits of

logical cognition and exposition with the word “aesthetic” stuck in front of them, then it might
seem as if Mendelssohn’s conception of aesthetics would also be based entirely on logic, that is

to say, within philosophy at its most intradisciplinary. So whence Herder’s praise for
Guyer 4

Baumgarten and Mendelssohn as drawing on the resources of both philosophy and psychology,

on poetry itself, and even on physiology to create their aesthetics, not perfect but the best model

yet for this interdisciplinary discipline?

Herder’s praise for Baumgarten and Mendelssohn as forerunners of his own


interdisciplinary approach to aesthetics is not misplaced: in spite of Baumgarten’s comparison of

aesthetics to epistemology (“gnoseology”) and logic, and in spite of Mendelssohn’s adoption of

Baumgarten’s formula for beauty, Baumgarten was deeply attentive to the psychological impact
of art as well as to its particular way of presenting cognitive content, and Mendelssohn also

recognized the bodily aspect of aesthetic experience in a way that nobody before Herder himself

did. In what follows, I will first draw attention to these aspects of the accounts of aesthetic
experience in Baumgarten and Mendelssohn, and then highlight several of the key points in
Herder’s own aesthetics that can be thought of as developing the ideas of these two predecessors,

or at least as developing within a framework that they made possible.

2. The Interdisciplinary Aesthetics of Baumgarten and Mendelssohn


Let us begin with Baumgarten. Stout as they are, the two volumes of his Aesthetica
published in 1750 and 1758 are only the truncated torso of what was to be a much longer work.

Baumgarten’s ambitious plan for the work divided it into two main parts, a “theoretical” part that
would offer “general precepts” and a “practical part” that would show how to “utilize” these.16

Alluding to the opening paragraph of the Aesthetica, Herder characterized these two parts of

Baumgarten’s plan as “the science of the feeling of the beautiful” on the one hand and “the art of

thinking beautifully” on the other, and trenchantly objected that educating “philosophers of
taste” and “connoisseurs of taste,” or analyzing taste and improving it, are two very different

projects, the mixture of which “naturally results in a monstrosity of aesthetics.”17 But since

Baumgarten did not live to write the “practical” part of his aesthetics, we need not worry too
much about this criticism. Even the “theoretical” part of Baumgarten’s work remained

incomplete: it was to consist of a “heuristic,” concerning the “beauty of things and thoughts”
Guyer 5

represented by art, its subjects or contents; a “methodology,” concerning the “lucid order” or

“beauty of order” of artistic representation; and a “semiotics,” concerning the “signs of that

which is to be thought and disposed beautifully” or “the beauty of signification, which is

expression and manner of speech.”18 Thus Baumgarten intended to describe the contributions to

the aesthetic experience of art of both what is represented and how it is represented. But in fact
all that Baumgarten lived to produce was only part, even though it comprises 904 paragraphs, of

the intended “heuristics,” namely an initial characterization of the partially innate and partially

acquired characteristics of the “aesthetician,” himself part artist and part audience, and then

sections on five of the six merits or “perfections” of the contents of beautiful or successful works
of art that he intended to describe. These perfections, all named in analogy with the “logical”

perfections of cognition, were to be ubertas aesthetica, magnitudo aesthetica, veritas aesthetica,

lux aesthetica, certitudo aesthetica, and vita cognitionis aesthetica, or “aesthetic wealth,”
“aesthetic magnitude,” “aesthetic truth,” “aesthetic light,” “aesthetic certitude,” and “the life of
aesthetic cognition.”19 Baumgarten’s text thus breaks off precisely where it should have reached

that concept which I suggested was of most influence on Herder, namely the concept of vita

cognitionis or the “life” of aesthetic cognition. But Baumgarten’s loyal disciple Georg Friedrich
Meier did complete all three parts of a German exposition of Baumgarten’s plan, one that he

claimed was based almost entirely on Baumgarten’s lectures, namely his Anfangsgründe aller

schönen Wissenschaften or “Foundations of all the Fine Sciences” of 1748-54, and he not only
reached the category of “life” of aesthetic cognition but also claimed that it was the most

important of the aesthetic categories. Since Meier’s thought was uniformly accepted by

contemporaries as a faithful rendition of that of his teacher and friend Baumgarten, it is safe to
say that Herder would have taken Meier’s exposition of the life of aesthetic cognition as an

authentic part of the Baumgartian theory. In Meier’s version of Baumgartian aesthetics, as

expounded in his large Anfangsgründe and in a briefer Betrachtungen über den ersten Grundsatz
aller schönen Künste und Wissenschaften (“Considerations on the first principle of all the fine

arts and sciences”) published in 1757 (the same year as Mendelssohn’s “Main Principles),
Guyer 6

Baumgarten’s category of aesthetic “light” becomes the “liveliness and brilliance of cognition”

(Lebhaftigkeit und Glanz), and the category of “life,” while remaining the same in the

Anfangsgründe, is tellingly replaced by that of “the touching” (Das Rührende) in the

Betrachtungen.20 That gives us the key to what was meant by the category of “the life of

aesthetic cognition,” and places the ultimate focus in the analysis of beauty on the emotional
impact of a work of art upon its audience. But before we examine that category more closely, let

us take a quick look at several of the others.

By the first category, “aesthetic wealth,” Baumgarten means the “copiousness,

abundance, multitudinous, treasures, and resources” (copia, abundantia, multitudo, divitae, opes)
of material that a work of art presents for sensitive cognition.21 “He who would think

beautifully...offers...the overflowing fullness of objects...so that it seems to the observer that the

material is inexhaustible.”22 The category of “aesthetic wealth” thus develops Baumgarten’s


earlier famous thought that a poem should be “clear but confused,” that is, convey a maximal

amount of information but without articulating or sorting it out the way a “logical” or scientific
work must.23 This might sound as if it concerns solely the content of works of art, a requirement
that a work of art give its audience “much to think about beautifully.” In fact, in spite of

Baumgarten’s intended division between “heuristics” and “semiotics,” the category of “wealth,”
like all his other aesthetic categories, has both an “objective” and a “subjective” side, that is, can

be displayed in both the content of art and the manner of artistic representation. Thus,
AESTHETIC WEALTH is...either OBJECTIVE (the wealth of objects, of material),

insofar as in the objects and what is to be thought itself there lies the foremost reason

why the powers of the human genius [ingenii] can paint richly, or SUBJECTIVE (the
wealth of the genius and the person), the natural possibility and the resources of certain

people by means of which...a certain object can be richly represented [ubertim

representandi].24
Baumgarten continues the discussion under the rubrics of “wealth of material,”25 which clearly

concerns content, “topics”26 and “enriching arguments,”27 which both concern the ways in which
Guyer 7

ideas are presented rather than the complexity of the ideas themselves, and then “the wealth of

genius” (ubertas ingenii),28 which concerns the sufficiency of the powers of the mind of the artist

to “conceive the given material richly relative to the occasion, the time, and the place,”29 or to

invent appropriate ways of presenting his material. Thus “objective wealth” is the former is the
requirement that works of art represent sufficiently diverse or complex objects to hold our

interest, and “subjective wealth,” as Baumgarten’s word representare makes obvious, is the

requirement that they represent their content in sufficiently diverse or complex ways to hold our

interests.
Baumgarten’s second category is “aesthetic magnitude.” Here his concern is not the

quantity of information contained in and conveyed by a work of art; rather, “aesthetic

magnitude” is his term for the sublime, and he begins his discussion with a Latin translation from
Longinus, “That is truly great which always returns to our thought and consideration, which
hardly and not even hardly can be banned from our soul, but which is continuously, firmly, and

indelibly retained in our memory.”30 It may nevertheless seem as if “aesthetic magnitude”


concerns primarily the content of art, namely that it represent sublimia or “sublime things.”31
Baumgarten’s further distinction between “natural” and “moral” aesthetic magnitude (which

anticipates Kant’s later distinction between the “mathematical” and the “dynamical” sublime)
also seems to concern primarily the content of art:

AESTHETIC MAGNITUDE, absolute as well as relative, is further either NATURAL,


which pertains to that which is not closely connected with freedom, or MORAL, which is

to be attributed to things and thoughts insofar as they are more closely connected with

freedom.
Natural magnitude seems to be that which is vast or great in nature, and moral magnitude seems

to concern the greatness of human actors and their intentions, thus both seems to concern

greatness or sublimity in what is represented by art. But here too Baumgarten also has in mind
greatness in the manner of artistic representation as well as greatness in content. Thus the

passage just quoted continues to say that “If the themes that are to be found within the aesthetic
Guyer 8

horizon are richly thought, and you know how to use topics and enriching arguments, then these

will also have magnitude,”32 that is, the artistic representation as well as the content will have

magnitude. Indeed, the section on aesthetic magnitude began with the suggestion that magnitude
is to be found in both represented content and representation -- “under this name we comprehend

1) the weight and gravity of the objects, 2) the weight and gravity of the thoughts proportionate

to them, and 3) the fecundity of both together.”33 Baumgarten’s conception of the perfection of

sensuous cognition clearly comprises perfections on the side of both represented content and its
representation, in this case sublimity of content and sublimity in the manner of representation --

his illustration of the category of magnitude with passages from the Aeneid and Eclogues of

Virgil makes that clear. Of course, this is a central theme of (psuedo-) Longinus’s On the
Sublime, so it is only to be expected in a discussion that begins with a quotation from that source.
Baumgarten’s category of “aesthetic truth” is the requirement of possibility -- physical

and moral -- in objects depicted34 so that they may produce a sense of probability in the audience
for art, “that degree of truth which, if it does not rise to complete certainty, nevertheless may

contain nothing of noticeable falsehood.”35 This category thus clearly straddles the boundary
between content and representation; it places certain constraints on the permissible content of art

in order to ensure that the representation of the content can have a desired effect on the audience,
an effect of acceptance of the content of the work even in the absence of “logical” truth or truth

proper, an effect that is in turn necessary for the emotional impact of the work.36 Baumgarten’s
category of “aesthetic light,” by contrast, would seem to concern solely the way in which things

are represented, and thus to be the first of his categories to concern solely perfection on the side

of sensuous representation rather than perfection in what is sensuously represented. But even
here Baumgarten stresses that “light” can be achieved by the choice of objects to be represented

as well as by the manner of representing them strictly understood. He writes:

He who in thinking strives for a truer beauty and truer elegance must, in the fourth place,
strive diligently for LIGHT, for the clarity and comprehensibility of all of his thoughts,

but for AESTHETIC light...Quintilian, who recommends comprehensibility as one of the


Guyer 9

foremost virtues of eloquence...thus distinguishes entirely correctly between

comprehensibility in words...and the comprehensibility of things, by means of which

objects for a graceful reflection should be accessible and lucid even to those who listen

and attend only negligently.37

Aesthetic light or comprehensibility is to be achieved by the appropriate choice of distinctive


objects for artistic representation as well as by the lucid presentation of them; once again the

perfection of sensuous cognition comprises perfection both on the side of the represented content

of art and on the side of the manner of artistic representation. The concept of “aesthetic light” is

obviously related to the concept of “clarity” that figured in Baumgarten’s original conception of
“clear but confused representation,” and alludes to the particularly graphic but not analytic way

in which dense content is artistically represented.

The last section of the completed portion of Baumgarten’s Aesthetica concerns “aesthetic
certitude,” which clearly turns the focus of the work from the content to the manner of
representation: aesthetic certitude concerns how content can be presented persuasively. But the

work stops just where the discussion of the “life of aesthetic cognition” should have begun. So
we must turn to Meier for the exposition of this category. When we do, we find a category that

concerns primarily the emotional effect of art -- as noted, in Meier’s 1757 short presentation of
his theory, the category of “life” is replaced with that of “the touching.” It is the introduction of

this conception of emotional impact into the cognitivist account of art that represents for Herder

Baumgarten’s synthesis of the Wolffian philosopher and Christgauian poet, or of the acute vision
of a second Leibniz with the poetic intuition of a Klopstock, and the source of Baumgarten’s

enduring influence on Herder.

That the interpretation of “the life of aesthetic cognition” as emotional impact is Meier’s
fulfillment of Baumgarten’s plan and not his own addition to it is clear from Baumgarten’s

original Meditationes, a text which remained of great importance for Herder. There Baumgarten

employs the Leibnizo-Wolffian conception of sensation as clear but confused perception and of

sentiment as the clear but confused perception of perfection, and thus infers that aesthetic
Guyer 10

experience of the clear but confused content of poetry will have the form of sentiment.38 He then

infers that “Since affects are noticeable degrees of displeasure and pleasure, they will be the
sentiments of that which is represented in a confused way as good and evil....Hence it is poetic,

to arouse affects.”39 More fully,

The same can also be demonstrated by the following consideration: In what is


represented for us as good and evil, more is represented than if it were not so represented.

Consequently those representations of things that are presented to us in a confused way as

good and evil are extensively clearer than if they were not so presented. Thus they are

more poetic. But such representations are the mental arousals of affects. Hence it is
poetic, to arouse affects.40

Indeed, “Stronger sentiments are clear, consequently more poetic than less clear and powerless

[kraftloser] ones,” and “Thus it is more poetic, to arouse stronger affects than less forceful
[heftiger] ones.”41 On a superficial glance, Baumgarten’s aesthetics can seem the paradigm of a
purely cognitivist aesthetics, one that finds the value of art solely in the distinctive way in which

it conveys information, but in fact in his view the point of both the artistic representation of
content and the artistic manner of representation is the arousal of emotion. The kind of content

and representation that Baumgarten discussed under the rubric of “aesthetic magnitude” might
already have implied this, but Baumgarten’s doctrine of poetic affect makes it explicit. Thus

when Meier proclaims that “The final chief perfection of cognition” is “its life,” he is faithfully

developing the view of his master.

“A cognition is living,” Meier explains, “if through the intuition of a perfection or

imperfection it causes gratification or vexation, desire or aversion.” Insofar as it is a sensuous


cognition or cognition by means of the senses that has such an effect, then it has “aesthetic life

of cognition (vita cognitionis aesthetica).” Such a cognition “fills the entire mind” because it

occupies the “power of desire” as well as the “power of cognition”; it thus “inflames the spirits
of life” and “takes possession of the heart” and for that reason Meier holds “the aesthetic life of

cognition to be the greatest beauty of thoughts.” To convey the importance of the category of
Guyer 11

aesthetic life, Meier illustrates this claim with an extract from a poem by Albrecht von Haller,

which concludes with the lines “Certainly Heaven cannot enlarge the happiness/Of he who loves

his condition and never wishes to improve it”; as the complete engagement of the two basic

powers of the human mind, the power of cognition and the power of desire, aesthetic life is the
perfection that completes all the other forms of beauty.42 The hundred pages of Meier’s

extended discussion of the aesthetic life of cognition reiterate the preeminence of this perfection
over all the other perfections comprising beauty, a preeminence based in the fact that “touching”

works of art “fully move”43 us because by “representing future good or evil” as things that can be
“preserved” or “hindered” they “cause a sensory gratification or a sensory vexation.”44 Meier

emphasizes that although the depiction of the sorts of objects that naturally produce an emotional

response -- “a beauty” or “an ugliness” or “hatefulness” -- is a necessary condition for aesthetic


life, it is not sufficient; what is further necessary to produce this effect is that the content of the

work of art be presented in such a way that attention is focused on it for maximal emotional
impact: “Whoever would think in a touching way must (1) do everything by means of which
attention will be drawn entirely or preeminently to the object itself.”45 “The object must either

be really sensed [würcklich empfinde] or by means of the imagination made present to the mind”;

“attention must be entirely occupied with the object itself, so that one does not have time to think
of anything else by means of which the intuition of the object itself might be hindered,”46 and in

particular “everything must be avoided by means of which the contemplation of the object could

be diverted to the contemplation of the signs and images [Zeichen und Bilder] in which the
object is enveloped”; the presentation of the object must not be “symbolic” but must instead be

concrete.47 In spite of the rebarbative academic framework of their writing, Baumgarten’s and
Meier’s category of aesthetic life was meant to argue against symbolic or allegorical poetry in

favor of poetry with immediate emotional impact, and thereby prepared the way for the

impending literary movement of Sturm und Drang. This is precisely what Herder responded to
in them.
Guyer 12

But before Herder could respond to Baumgarten’s aesthetics as completed by Meier,

Mendelssohn also responded to their distinction synthesis of intellect and emotion, and added his

own account of the rôle of the body in aesthetic experience. Herder’s admiration for the quality

of Mendelssohn’s judgment in his literary criticism is evident throughout the “Fourth Grove,”48

but as we saw earlier, he specifically praised Mendelssohn for his recognition of “the
contributions of both body and soul” to aesthetic experience.49 The rôle of the body in such

experience is only touched upon in Mendelssohn’s 1755 Letters on Sentiments, when he


recognizes three distinct sources of pleasure, all of which can be exploited in our experience of

art: “sameness in multiplicity, or beauty, harmony in multiplicity or intellectual perfection, and

finally the improved condition of the state of our body or sensuous gratification” -- “How the
muses must rejuvenate us,” Mendelssohn exclaims, “they who draw upon [these] diverse sources
in full measure and our them out over us in a pleasant combination!”50 The first two of

Mendelssohn’s concepts here seem to correspond to Baumgarten’s location of beauty in both the

manner and content of artistic representation, and by the third, Mendelssohn seems to have in
mind the direct effect of the perception of, for example, colors and sounds on our visual and

aural organs: he says that “It is extremely possible that the neural parts of the eye and their
harmonious tensions can be altered by colors in precisely the same way that the vessels of

hearing can be altered by sounds,” and when the effect of the perception of some particular

sounds or colors is to improve the “harmonious tension” of our bodily parts, then “an obscure
feeling of an improved condition of our body makes them,” that is, the colored or sounding

objects, “into objects of pleasure”51 -- our pleasure in the improvement of our own bodily
condition is projected onto the objects -- in this dimension, beauty is “pleasure objectified,” as

George Santayana would argue more than a century later.52


This account of the rôle of the body in aesthetic experience is minimal, and it may also

seem as if there is no recognition of the emotional dimension of aesthetic experience in the


Letters on Sentiments. The essay on the “Main Principles of the Fine Arts and Sciences” that

Mendelssohn published two years after On Sentiments and then revised for his Philosophical
Guyer 13

Writings four more years later as well as the Rhapsody or additions to the Letters on Sentiment

that he wrote specifically for the 1761 collection certainly emphasize the emotional impact of art

as well as adding at least a little to Mendelssohn’s account of the bodily aspect of aesthetic

experience. The Rhapsody begins with Plato’s ancient question why we should take pleasure in
seeing unpleasant things or representations of them.53 This seems like a puzzle to Plato because

he focuses only on the things that are represented; Mendelssohn’s response is that we must
consider the potential for pleasure or displeasure not only in things but also in the act of

representing them, and he then argues that when we are dealing with fait accompli, that is, things

already done that we cannot prevent, then we can enjoy the activity of both our cognitive and
emotional responses to them even when the objects themselves are imperfections rather than
perfections in the grand scheme of things. In making this argument, Mendelssohn stresses the

engagement of our evaluative and affective powers as well as our purely cognitive powers.

Thus, he says that “recognizing an evil action and disapproving of it are affirmative features of
the soul, expressions of the mental powers of knowing and desiring, and elements of perfection
which, in this connection, must be gratifying and enjoyable,”54 and “in relation to the mind’s

projection, the movement and stirring which is produced in the soul cannot be anything else but

pleasant.”55 Mendelssohn then adds that artistic representation or “imitation by art” is a way of
creating the necessary separation between the object and our internal, mental representation of it

that is necessary for us to enjoy the latter even when the former is unpleasant: when “the most

terrifying events” are rendered “on the stage, on the canvas, and in marble,...an inner
consciousness that we have an imitation and nothing genuine before our eyes moderates the

strength of the objective and, as it were, elevates the subjective side of the representation,”56

allowing us to enjoy the cognitive activity and emotional arousal that comprise the latter.

Mendelssohn here acknowledges a version of what Edward Bullough would later call the

“antinomy of aesthetic distance,” namely that we must be sufficiently deceived by the art that
“our imaginations is so swept away...that we fancy we truly see nature,” but that this “magic”

must last only “as long as is necessary to give our conception of the object the proper vitality and
Guyer 14

fire” -- Leben und Feuer.57 Mendelssohn’s use of the word Leben here says it all: the impact of

artistic representations on our capacity for desire and emotion is his version of Baumgarten’s
conception of vita cognitionis aesthetica. Allowing us to enjoy our own emotions is clearly the

chief virtue of artistic representation for Mendelssohn, although in the essay on the “Main

Principles” he also adds that we can take yet another layer of pleasure in the perfection of the

artists who can produce such representations.58

In the Rhapsody, Mendelssohn also amplifies somewhat the connection between body
and soul he had already asserted in On Sentiments. Here he writes:

I have said of gratification of the senses that it consists in a feeling of the improved

condition of the body that is pleasant to the soul. I have also regarded the body’s
movements as the object, the soul merely as a spectator that takes pleasure in this
representation because it perceives an objective perfection...But there is yet another

source of the pleasure we take in sensuous gratifications that must not be disregarded.

The soul enjoys the well-being of its body not merely as a spectator, that is, not merely in
the general sense that it somehow perceives the perfection of an object with ease. Rather,
by virtue of sensuous gratification, there accrues to the soul itself a no lesser degree of

perfection, and by this means what is pleasant in the sentiment becomes incomparably
more lively. Harmonious sentiments in the soul correspond to harmonious movements in

the limbs and the senses. In a state of sensuous rapture, the entire neural structure
[Nervengebäude] is set in motion, one harmonious motion, and since this is the case, the

entire basis of the soul, the entire system of sentiments and obscure feelings, must be

moved and put into play as well, one harmonious play. By this means every capacity for
sentient knowledge, every power of sensuously desiring is engaged in the way most

conducive and sustained in the exercise.59

Here Mendelssohn emphasizes that the soul’s pleasure in the bodily effects of art is not just
cognitive, not just like the approbation of perfection in any external object, but is much more

direct than that, the direct effect of the transmission of the bodily condition to both the cognitive
Guyer 15

and the affective and emotional capacities of the soul -- “every power of sensuously desiring is

engaged.” So in this passage Mendelssohn stresses both the emotional as well as cognitive

impact of art but also the immediacy of the mind-body connection; explicitly rejecting the

ancient image of the soul as a spectator of its own body and implicitly rejecting the conception
shared by Leibniz, Wolff, and Baumgarten of the soul and body as two separate substances

linked only by a pre-established harmony, in the context of his aesthetics Mendelssohn evinces a

conviction of the unity of mind and body that could not but have been deeply influential for
Herder.

Let us now consider some of the ways in which these ideas of Baumgarten

(posthumously expressed by his faithful disciple Meier) and Mendelssohn bore fruit in Herder.

3. Energy, Immediacy, and Emotion in Herder’s Conception of Art and Language

Here I want to argue that the influence of Baumgarten and Mendelssohn on Herder can
be seen in a variety of ways in Herder’s aesthetics and beyond that in his philosophy of

language: the emphasis on energy in his account of the experience of poetry and music is the heir
to Baumgarten’s notion of the “life of aesthetic cognition” and its presence in Mendelssohn as
the “life and fire” of the emotional impact of art; his emphasis on the sense of touch and the

sense of one’s own bodly moton in the experience of sculpture, highly unusual in eighteenth-
century aesthetics, can be seen as at least licensed by Mendelssohn’s recognition of the role of

the body and not just purely cognitive capacities in aesthetic experience; and Herder’s

recognition of the dual elements of emotion and cognition in language and the dual rôles of self-
expression and the movement of others in its use can be seen as heir to Baumgarten’s and

Mendelssohn’s emphasis on both the “subjective” and the “objective” sides in artistic

representation.
First, then, Herder’s notion of aesthetic energy as the heir to the notion of life as the

central aesthetic category for Baumgarten, Meier, and Mendelssohn: Herder develops this idea

in his polemic with Lessing in the “First Grove” of the Groves of Criticism. In Laocoön, Lessing
Guyer 16

had added to the argument, already hinted at by Du Bos,60 that since visual arts represent by a

stationary spatial array while poetry represents by a succession of sounds, the visual arts must
represent a pregnant moment while poetry can represent a sequence of action,61 the further claim

that the visual arts are constrained by the requirements of beauty in a way that poetry is not.62
Lessing objected to the failure to distinguish between painting and sculpture in this account of
the visual arts (to which we will return), and to the characterization of poetry merely in terms of

the successiveness of sounds and images in its linguistic medium. Herder observed that “the

successiveness of sounds is actually characteristic not of poetry but rather of all language, and

thus it does little to help define or distinguish [poetry] in its inner essence”63 -- that is, not just
can successiveness be only a necessary but not a sufficient condition of poetry, but it does not

bring out what is unique about poetry. This lies rather in the fact that poetry concerns and
communicates “action, passion, feeling”; it does not merely describe the sequence of actions in

for example assembling an object rather than presenting an image of the finished object, as
Lessing had argued in his famous discussion of Homer’s passage on the shield of Achilles,64 but

it communicates the energy and feeling that continuously pervades that action. “If I have learned

anything from Homer,” Herder asserts,


it is that poetry operates energetically: never with the intention of delivering (albeit

successively) a work, image, picture, down to every last detail, but rather that the whole

force must be experienced and felt while the energy endures....That is how I set poetry
against painting, and I regret that Mr. L[essing] did not pay heed to this focal point of

poetry’s essence, its “effect on our soul, its energy.”65


Herder’s equation of energy with the effect of a poem on the soul of its audience in his last

phrase, set in quotation marks for emphasis, shows how he understands the concept: not
objectively but subjectively, not as something that explains the action but as the emotional

impact of the object on the audience. This subjective dimension is emphasized in his further
statement that “poetry is energetic; that is, the soul must already feel everything while poetry

operates and not begin to feel only after the energy has ended and not wish to feel through a
Guyer 17

recapitulation of the succession.”66 To be sure, since the poet himself is also a feeling as well as

thinking human being, and the kind of poetry that Herder has in mind also typically describes the
actions of human beings, or very human gods, poetry can express -- in both senses of being the

effect of and giving voice to -- the energy of the poet, and can describe energy in the subject of

the poem, and thus produce subjective energy in the audience in response to objective energy in

the poet or the representation of energy in the poem. But whether it can produce its response
only by these means or by other means as well, what is indispensable is that it produce this

feeling of continuous energy, or continuous emotional arousal, in its audience. And this, I

suggest, is what Baumgarten and Meier called the life of aesthetic cognition, and what
Mendelssohn called the life and fire produced by the magic of artistic representation that must
both take us in and yet also remind us that it is only imitation. Perhaps one could argue in

Lessing’s behalf that the continuous emotional response of the audience is a natural response to
the continuing action successively described in a poem that does not need to be separately

identified by the theorist, but at the very least Herder’s emphasis on this subjective aspect of the
experience of poetry can be seen as a lesson learned from the school of Baumgarten.

In the “First Grove,” Herder also credits James Harris, the nephew of Shaftesbury and
author of Three Treatises including A Dialogue concerning Art and A Discourse on Music,
Painting, and Poetry (1744) as well as Hermes, or a Philosophical Inquiry concerning Universal

Grammar (1751),67 both works of great interest to Herder, with the distinction between “arts that

deliver a work and those which operate through energy,” and notes that the arts that operate by

energy include not only poetry but also music. “The subjects of music,” Herder writes after

Harris, “are all such things and incidents as are most eminently characterized by motion and
sound; these include all species of motions, sounds, voices, passions expressed through sounds,

and so on.”68 Thus the objective side of music, motion and sound, includes the sound of

passions, which in turn arouse passion or energy as its subjective side. Herder then expands on
this account of music in the “Fourth Grove.” With music, Herder writers there,
Guyer 18

Here a new sense opens up, a new gateway of the soul, and perceives tones: tones, whose

every simple moment the ear absorbs with pleasure; tones, whose every simple moment

touches the soul in a thousand new ways and produces a thousand new and different, yet

inward and immediate, sensations; tones, the instrument that most directly affects the
soul. Whereas the expression of visual art was nothing but surface, music is inner

essence; that is, energetic force, pathos -- how else shall I name it. That which penetrates

deep into the soul: the world of a new feeling.69

Again, under the rubric of energy, Herder is clearly emphasizing the emotional impact of music
above all other possible aspects of it or our experience of it, and thus characterizing the

experience of music in terms of what Baumgarten and Meier identified as the most important

aspect of aesthetic experience even though Baumgarten said nothing about music in the little he
lived to write, Meier apparently nothing in the vastly more that he wrote, and Mendelssohn only
a little.70

Herder particularly emphasizes the immediacy of the emotional impact of music:

“Impression and tone directly affecting the soul, accent of sensation, harmony, and beautiful
succession -- wherever we find these, whether in thoughts or images, languages and colors, they

are musical in nature; they have been borrowed in nature.” He is willing to say that “Music as
such imitates human passions,” but only because it so immediately arouses passions in the

auditor: “Music lamented; it sighed, it raged, it exulted”; that is, “you felt everything, your

responded sympathetically as each string was struck,” but you did that without the intermediation

of any determinate idea of an object or event being represented by the music -- “There was nary

a hint of contemplation; everything stirred only in the darkest abyss of your soul.”71 Here
perhaps we should say that Herder has gone beyond Baumgarten: focusing as he did solely on

poetry, Baumgarten could assume that the subjective dimension of life always accompanied the

objective dimension of aesthetic cognition, that is, that emotional impact accompanied
determinate although dense representational content; but in the case of music, the emotional

impact is produced by the immediate impact of the music on our senses, without the
Guyer 19

intermediation of any determinate intellectual ideas about what it might represent. Yet the very

fact that music can succeed in doing this may only confirm Baumgarten’s and Meier’s point that

among the perfections of aesthetic cognition, its life or emotional impact is the chief one,

sufficient by itself when it can occur by itself, that is, without representation, to make a powerful
aesthetic experience. If only Herder’s “Fourth Grove” had been published before Schopenhauer

gave his famous account of music as the imitation of the will itself rather than of any of its

phenomenal objectifications,72 we might even claim Herder’s account as an ancestor of

Schopenhauer’s and thus trace a line from Baumgarten’s foundation of eighteenth-century


German aesthetics through Herder to one of the most characteristic productions of nineteenth-

century German aesthetics.73

Although Herder concentrated on Lessing’s contrast between visual art and poetry in the

“First Grove,” differentiating within visual art between painting and sculpture became central to
his project in the unpublished “Fourth Grove” and in 1778 publication Sculpture (Plastik) that

traversed much of the same ground.74 The basis of Herder’s critique is that the sense of touch is
the foundation of our knowledge of a three-dimensional world of bodies, of which sight alone

would give us only a two-dimensional representation, and that “The beauty of bodies, as forms,
is thus tactile”75 as well. Of course, the philosophical debate from Descartes through Locke,
Berkeley, and Diderot about how we place a three-dimensional interpretation upon the

supposedly two-dimensional information provided by sight alone had really been a debate over

the precise role of other bodily senses in this cognitive process: Descartes’s argument that we
tacitly compute the third dimension of bodily depth from differences in the tension on our optical

muscles76 treats our visual organs as parts of our own three-dimensional bodies providing

information kinaesthetically as well as visually, and Berkeley’s alternative theory that we

correlate two-dimensional visual representations with the information about distance provided by

our own bodily motions in approaching to or receding from objects77 also treats us as three-
dimensional bodies and not mere retinas feeding two-dimensional information to an as good as

disembodied brain. But Herder moves from this to an emphasis on tactile and kinaesthetic
Guyer 20

experience within his account of aesthetic experience that is novel in eighteenth-century

aesthetics. As he puts the point, “there are three main senses, at least so far as aesthetics is

concerned, although it has been customary to concede to it only two, the eye and the ear.”78

Indeed, he presents his recognition of the importance of this aspect of experience for aesthetic
experience as a critique of Baumgarten among others. He maintains that physical beauty, “the

beauty of a form, of a body, is not a visual but a tactile concept; thus every one of these beauties

must originally be sought in the sense of touch.” His argument for this claim, as is so often the

case with Herder, is from our language to our thought or experience itself: “all aesthetic terms
that describe such beauty, regardless of the context in which they are used, derive from touch:

rough, gentle, soft, tender, full, in motion -- these and countless others derive from touch.” This

is particularly evident in the case of sculpture, which is “above all tangible.”79 We might argue
for this point, empirically, by saying that our first impulse is to run our hands over sculpture, and

that it is only convention and museum guards that prevent us from doing this, so that we settle
for the enjoyment of visual experiences associated with tactile ones rather than enjoyment of the

tactile experience itself. Herder does note that the tactile experience of sculpture would be less
susceptible to deception than visual experience, so that from a cognitivist point of view “it
approaches to the truth.”

In the next section of the “Fourth Grove,” Herder complicates this initial statement. Here

he says that there are three “senses of the beautiful,” namely sight, hearing, and touch, and that
these three senses perceive different things or aspects of things, namely “sight, which perceives

external things alongside one another; hearing, which perceives things in succession; and touch,

which perceives things in depth” -- or “surfaces,” “tones,” and “bodies”80 -- but does not say that
one of these objects is more true than another or one of these senses more veridical than another.

He also goes on to argue that of course the experience of sculpture does involve sight as well as

touch, but a use of sight that is in turn dependent on bodily motion: “From no single point do I
survey the work [of sculpture] in its entirety; I must walk around it in order to have seen it.”81

Even the observer who does not appear to be moving, “the viewer sunk deep in silent
Guyer 21

contemplation of the Apollo Belvedere,” in fact has a visual experience that is dependent upon

his past experience of motion and perhaps imagined present motions, and that also runs in his

sense of his own bodily motion with his sense of touch:

He seems to stand in a fixed position, but nothing could be further from the truth. He
adopts as many viewpoints as he can, changing his perspective from one moment to the

next so that he avoids sharply defined surfaces. To this end he gently glides only around

the contours of the body...He tries his hardest to destroy every recess, every ceasura,
every superficiality, and, as far as possible, to restore to the many-angled polygon, to

which his eye has reduced the body, its beautiful ellipse, which had been blown into

being only for his touch....And so he demonstrates in the very act of seeing that to
experience the effect of sculpture, which is achieved only through bodies, he wanted only
to feel, and he did.82

Here Herder does seem to argue that the experience of sculpture is not only more complex but

also more truthful than purely visual experience, thus than painting. But even if Herder does not
mean to rank the different visual arts, it is clear that his account of sculpture depends on a

recognition of the rôle of the body in the generation of both tactile and kinaesthetic sensation.
He could not have given his account of sculpture within a framework that treated all imagery as

if could be the experience of a bodiless eye.

Mendelssohn’s conception of the rôle of the body may have gone only so far as to
recognize the effect of visual perception on the state of the body and then the transmission of that

state to the mind in the form of an experience of pleasure. He did not single out the distinctive

contributions of touch and kinaesthesia to aesthetic experience, in particular to the experience of


sculpture. So he can hardly be claimed as a direct predecessor of Herder’s treatment of

sculpture. Nevertheless, Mendelssohn’s addition of the bodily effect of aesthetic experience to

the intellectual and emotional aspects of it recognized by Baumgarten might be considered at


least to have opened the door to Herder’s fuller exploration of the rôle of the body in aesthetic

experience.
Guyer 22

I want to make one last point here, about Herder’s conception of language. Of course this

is not the place for an extensive treatment of that large subject, and the text I am going to draw

on because of its proximity to the texts in aesthetics that I have been discussing, the 1772

Treatise on the Origin of Language, may not be representative of all of Herder’s thought about
language.83 Nevertheless I do want to propose that Herder’s philosophy of language as presented

in this work suggests that language is typically meaningful in two complementary ways, on the
one hand pointing to aspects of objects and to objects through their aspects, and on the other

hand expressing the emotional response of humans to objects and communicating that response

to others by arousing it in them. Herder thus recognizes both an objective and a subjective
dimension of meaning in language, and this is analogous to Baumgarten’s distinction between
the objective and the subjective aspects of aesthetic qualities in particulars as well as in the

general recognition of both the cognitive content and the emotional impact of art on the part of

Baumgarten and his followers Meier and Mendelssohn. Baumgarten does not discuss language
as such nor does Herder refer to Baumgarten in the Treatise on the Origin of Language, but we
might still use Baumgarten’s conceptual framework to illuminate Herder’s philosophy of

language and at least speculate that Baumgarten’s way of thinking opened up a path for Herder
in this area too.
As early as the Fragments on Recent German Literature of 1767-8, the youthful Herder

had stressed the immediacy of expression of in language -- the oldest languages, “formed

immediately according to living nature,” “had much living expression” -- and thus the close
original connection or even identity of language with song -- “For a long time with the ancients

singing and speaking...were one thing”84 -- because of the immediacy of expression in both. In

the Treatise on the Origin of Language, Herder attacks the view of Condillac, Maupertuis, and

Rousseau that all of language can be considered to have emerged from the musical or quasi-

musical expression of sensation and emotion.85 But he does not deny that human beings have a
natural language of the passions. He begins with the claim that “Already as an animal, the

human being has language. All violent sensations of his body, and the most violent of the
Guyer 23

violent, the painful ones, and all strong passions of immediately express themselves in cries, in

sounds, in wild, unarticulated noises.” And he immediately adds that these expressions of

sensation and especially emotions sympathetically communicate the feelings they express to

others: “This is how little nature has created us as isolated rocks, as egoistic monads! Even the
finest instrument strings of animal feeling...are directed in their whole play, even without the

consciousness of foreign sympathy, at an expression to other creatures. The struck string

performs its natural duty: It sounds!, it calls to a similarly feeling Echo.”86 What Herder does

deny is that this emotionally expressive aspect is what is distinctively human in language. This
aspect of language is shared with other creatures; what is distinctively human is the use of

language to designate properties of objects and through them objects themselves. What is

distinctively human is the capacity for recollection and reflection, the ability to pay attention to
particular aspects of objects, recall that one has encountered them before, then the ability to
name them and to use those names of properties for names of objects themselves. Thus Herder

states that

The human being demonstrates reflection when the force of his soul operates so freely
that in the whole ocean of sensations which floods the soul through all the senses it can,
so to speak, separate off, stop, and pay attention to a single wave, and be conscious of its

own attentiveness...freely dwell on a single image, pay it clear, more leisurely heed, and
separate off characteristic remarks for the fact that it is this object and no other....not only

recognize all the properties in a vivid or clear way, but...in his own mind acknowledge
one or several distinguishing properties.87

This is what Herder calls “taking-awareness” (Besinnung) or “awareness” (Besonnenheit).

Herder then argues that the sounds that objects -- at least an animal, such as a lamb -- make are
particularly striking, and that we focus our awareness on them, using them both to identify the

object as we re-encounter it and to name the object that we so encounter -- thus early naming
takes the form “Aha! You are the bleating one!” It is in such a way that the human being

recognizes an object “in a human way” and “names it distinctly, that is, with a characteristic
Guyer 24

mark.”88 Herder thus argues that the distinctively human aspect of language begins with naming,

the use of sounds to designate objects through their distinctive properties, in particular the use of
sounds coming from the objects to name them, and he then develops an elaborate account of how

verbs and other aspects of language emerge from the primordial activity of naming.

But Herder does not deny that the emotionally expressive aspect of language that we

share with other animals remains a part of the human use of language. On the contrary, he
makes it explicit that it does. Thus he says that “In all original languages remains of these

natural sounds still resound.” In particular, he suggests that this common, expressive aspect of

language is especially present in the poetic or artistic use of language. He continues that the
remains of the natural sounds of expression “are not the main threads of human language,” but
they are “the juices which enliven the roots of language.”89 The “natural sounds” or more

precisely “our tones of natural language (unsre Töne der Natursprache) that “are destined for the

expression of passion” are “the elements of all moving” or touching” (Rührung) of other people
are crucial to poetry and other artistic forms of speech, both in ancient and modern languages:

“how much ancient poetry and music [were] enlivened by these natural sounds.”
And even in our case too, where, to be sure, reason often puts and end to the role of
feeling and the artificial language of society to that of natural sounds, do not the loftiest

thunders of oratory, the mightiest strikes of poetry, and the magical moments of

accompanying gesture still often come close to this language of thought, through
imitation? What is it that there among the gathered people works miracles, penetrates

hearts, and bowls over souls? Spiritual talk and metaphysics? Metaphors and rhetorical

figures? Art and cold persuasion? To the extent that rapture is not blind, much must
happen through these things, but everything? And precisely this highest element of blind

rapture, what brought this about? A quite different force! These sounds, these gestures,
those simple courses of melody, this sudden turning point, this twilight voice --90
in other words, the natural language of passion, or the aspect of language that represents the

survival of the immediate, primitive, and shared expression of passion. Thus Herder explicitly
Guyer 25

argues that specifically artistic language combines the function of expressing and arousing

feeling and passion, specifically of touching or moving others, with the referential function of

specifically human cognition and the specifically human use of language. Thus artistic language,

and presumably artistic media in general, both bind us to the rest of animate creation and also
distinguish us from it.

As I said, this conception of language goes beyond anything to be found explicitly in

Baumgarten or his immediate followers, who did not develop a full-fledged philosophy of
language.91 But Herder’s emphasis on both the cognitive, object-referring and expressive,
emotionally revealing and moving sides of language do, as I suggested, reflect the emphasis on
both objective and subjective, content and response, information conveying and emotionally
arousing sides of art that we find in Baumgarten and in Mendelssohn. Herder’s contrast between

“metaphor and rhetorical figures” on the one hand and the immediate emotional impact of the
expressive side of language might also remind us of the attack upon allegorical poetry in favor of
more concrete and immediately moving poetry launched by Baumgarten and Meier. As I

previously argued, Herder’s emphasis on the role of the body in the experience of art, which

leads, among its other implications, to his insistence on the distinctness of sculpture from
painting, can also be seen as a development of Mendelssohn’s recognition of the bodily aspect of
aesthetic experience, even though it leads Herder to criticize an argument of Mendelssohn’s

close friend and colleague Lessing, even an argument that Lessing may have derived from

Mendelssohn92 (who in turn may have derived it from Du Bos). Thus I think it safe to conclude

that Herder’s high praise for Baumgarten both in his “Monument” to him and in the Groves of

Criticism and his equally high praise for Mendelssohn make sense, and that his own aesthetics
and philosophy of language can be seen as building upon basic features of the aesthetics of

Baumgarten and his followers although also of course going beyond them in both breadth and

depth.
Guyer 26

Notes
1
Johann Gottfried Herder, “A Monument to Baumgarten,” from Herder, Frühe

Schriften, 1764-1772, ed. Ulrich Gaier, in Herder, Werke (Frankfurt am Main: Deutscher
Klassiker Verlag, 1985), Vol. I, pp. 681-94; translation from Herder, Selected Writings on

Aesthetics, translated and edited by Gregory Moore (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2006,

pp. 41-50, at p. 49.

2
Herder, “Monument,” p. 45.

3
Herder, “Monument,” p. 41. The philologist and literary scholar Martin Georg
Christgau (1697-1766) was among Baumgarten’s early teachers in Berlin and later the rector of

the Viadrina university in Frankfurt an der Oder where Baumgarten taught; the catalogue of his
works at the Staatsbibliothek Berlin includes Biblical commentaries, linguistic works, and

orations, but no obvious works of poetry.

4
Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten, Meditationes philosophicae de nonnullis ad poema
pertinentibus/Philosophische Betrachtungen über einige Bedingungen des Gedichtes [1735], ed.

Heinz Paetzold (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1983).

5
Herder, “Monument,” p. 42.

6
Herder’s phrase is Menschlicher Erziehung, which I have translated as “human

education” rather than, as Moore did, “a humane education.” See Johann Gottfried Herder,

Schriften zur Ästhetik und Literature, 1767-1781, ed. Gunter E. Grimm, in Herder, Werke
(Frankfurt am Main: Duetscher Klassiker Bibliothek, 1993), Vol. 2, p. 260.

7
Herder, Critical Forests: Fourth Grove, in Herder, Selected Writings, pp. 177-290, at p.

184.
Guyer 27

8
Herder, “Monument,” p. 45. Following Daniel Dahlstrom rather than Moore, I have

translated Mendelssohn’s word Empfindungen as “sentiments,” not “sensations”; see Moses


Mendelssohn, Philosophical Writings, ed. and trans. Daniel O. Dahlstrom (Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press, 1997), p. 169. The sentence that Herder quotes occurs in he 1761

version of Mendelssohn’s essay in his Philosophische Schriften, not in the 1757 version

published under the title “Betrachtungen über die Quellen und Verbindungen der schöne Künste
und Wissenschaften”; compare the text of the 1757 version in Moses Mendelssohn, Ausgewählte

Werke: Studienausgabe, ed. Christoph Schulte, Andreas Kennecke, and Grażyna Jurewicz

(Damrstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 2009), Vol. I, p. 173, with the text from the
improved 1771 printing of the 1761 collection in Moses Mendelssohn, Ästhetische Schriften, ed.
Anne Pollok (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2007), p. 188.

9
Herder, “Fourth Grove,” p. 274. Again I have translated Empfundungen as
“sentiments” rather than “sensations”; see Schriften zur Ästhetik und Literatur, p. 392.

10
Baumgarten, Meditationes, §CXV, pp. 84-5.

11
Baumgarten, Meditationes, §CXVI, pp. 86-7.

12
Alexander Gottieb Baumgarten, Ästhetik, bilingual Latin-German edition by Dagmar

Mirbach, 2 vols. (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2007), §1, pp. 10-11..

13
Baumgarten, Meditationes, §IX, pp. 10-11.

14
Baumgarten, Ästhetik, §14, vol. 1, pp. 20-1.

15
Mendelssohn, “Main Principles,” Philosophical Writings, pp. 172-3.

16
Baumgarten, Ästhetik, §13, vol. 1, pp. 16-19.
Guyer 28

17
Herder, “Fourth Grove,” pp. 189-90.

18
Baumgarten, Ästhetik, §§13 and 18-20, vol. 1, pp. 16-19, 22-3.

19
Baumgarten Ästhetik, “Synopsis,” vol. 1, pp. 4-11.

20
Georg Friedrich Meier, Betrachtungen über den ersten Grundsatz aller schönen

Künste und Wissenschaften (Halle: Hemmerde, 1757), §22, reprinted in Georg Friedrich Meier,
Frühe Schriften zur ästhetischen Erziehung der Deutschen, ed. Hans-Joachim Kertscher and

Günter Schenk, 3 vols. (Halle: Hallescher Verlag, 2002), vol. III, p. 192.

21
Baumgarten, Aesthetica, §115, vol. I, pp. 92-3.

22
Baumgarten, Ästhetik, §117, pp. 94-5.

23
See Baumgarten, Meditationes, §XV, pp. 16-17.

24
Baumgarten, Aesthetica, §118, vol. I, pp. 94-5.

25
Baumgarten, Aesthetica, §§119-29.

26
Baumgarten, Aesthetica, §§130-41.

27
Baumgarten, Aesthetica, §§142-8.

28
Baumgarten, Aesthetica, §§149-57.

29
Baumgarten, Aesthetica, §150, vol. I, pp. 126-7.

30
Baumgarten, Aesthetica, §177, vol. I, pp. 152-5.

31
Baumgarten, Aesthetica, §179, vol. I, pp. 154-5.
Guyer 29

32
Baumgarten, Aesthetica, §181, vol. I, pp. 156-7.

33
Baumgarten, Aesthetica, §177, vol. I, pp. 152-3.

34
Baumgarten, Aesthetica, §§424-34.

35
Baumgarten, Aesthetica, §483, vol. I, pp. 460-3.

36
The German translator of Baumgarten’s work indicates this by translating his Latin

terms probabilia and improbabilia as “believable” and “unbelievable things” (glaubhafte and
unglaubhafte Dinge) (Baumgarten, Ästhetik, §485, vol. I, pp. 462-3.).

37
Baumgarten, Aesthetica, §614, vol. II, pp. 602-3.

38
Baumgarten, Meditationes, §XXIV, pp. 24-5.

39
Baumgarten, Meditationes, §XXV, pp. 24-5.

40
Baumgarten, Meditationes, §XXVI, pp. 24-7.

41
Baumgarten, Meditationes, §XXVII, pp. 26-7.

42
Georg Friedrich Meier, Anfangsgründe aller schönen Wissenschaften, second edition,

vol. I (Halle: Hemmerde, 1754), §35, vol. I, pp. 59-61.

43
Meier, Anfangsgründe, §179, vol. I, p. 425.

44
Meier, Anfangsgründe, §180, vol. I, p. 426.

45
Meier, Anfangsgründe, §181, vol. I, p. 427.

46
Meier, Anfangsgründe, §181, vol. I, p. 428.
Guyer 30

47
Meier, Anfangsgründe, §181, vol. I, p. 429.

48
See Herder, “Fourth Grove,” p. 275.

49
Herder, “Fourth Grove,” p. 274.

50
Mendelssohn, On Sentiments, Eleventh Letter; Philosophical Writings, p. 48.

51
Mendelssohn, On Sentiments, Eleventh Letter; Philosophical Writings, pp. 49-50.

52
See Santayana, The Sense of Beauty (1896).

53
Mendelssohn, Rhapsody; Philosophical Writings, p. 131.

54
Mendelssohn, Rhapsody; Philosophical Writings, pp. 133-4; emphasis added.

55
Mendelssohn, Rhapsody; Philosophical Writings, p. 137; emphasis added.

56
Mendelssohn, Rhapsody; Philosophical Writings, p. 138.

57
Mendelssohn, Rhapsody; Philosophical Writings, p. 138; see Edward Bullough,
“‘Psychical Distance’ as a Factor in Art and an Æsthetic Principle,” British Journal of
Psychology 5 (1912): 87-118, reprinted in his Æsthetics: Lectures and Essays, edited by

Elizabeth M. Wilkinson (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1957), pp. 91-130, at pp. 98-100.

58
Mendelssohn, “Main Principles”; Philosophical Writings, p. 174.

59
Mendelssohn, Rhapsody; Philosophical Writings, p. 140.

60
Jean-Baptiste Du Bos, Critical Reflections on Poetry, Painting and Music, trans.

Thomas Nugent, 3 vols. (London: John Nourse, 1748), Part I, ch. XIII, pp. 69-91, at pp. 69-72.
Guyer 31

61
Gotthold Ephraim Lessing, Laocoön: An Essay on the Limits of Painting and Poetry

[1766], trans. Edward Allen McCormick (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1962), Ch XVI, pp.78-84.

62
Lessing, Laocoön, ch. II, pp. 12-18.

63
Herder, “First Grove,” Selected Writings, p. 144.

64
Lessing, Laocoön, ch. XVIII, pp. 94-7.

65
Herder, “First Grove,” p. 154.

66
Herder, “First Grove,” p. 155.

67
Both works were reprinted in The Works of James Harris, with an Account of His Life
and Character, by His Son, the Earl of Malmesbury, 2 vols. (London: F. Wingrave, the

Successor to Mr. Nourse, 1801), further reprinted (Bristol: Thoemmes Press, 2003).

68
Herder, “First Grove,” p. 156.

69
Herder, “Fourth Grove,” p. 283.

70
See Mendelssohn, “Main Principles”; Philosophical Writings, pp. 185-8.

71
Herder,”Fourth Grove,” p. 284.

72
See Arthur Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, trans. E.F. J. Payne,

2 vols. (Indian Springs: Falcon’s Wing Press, 1958), vol. I, Third Book, §52, especially pp. 257-

61.

73
Alas, the “Fourth Grove” was not published until 1846, two years after even the

second edition of Schopenhauer’s work. See Schriften zur Ästhetik und Literature, 1767-1781,

p. 967.
Guyer 32

74
Johann Gottfried Herder, Sculpture: Some Observations on shape and Form from

Pygmalion’s Creative Dream, ed. and trans. Jason Gaiger (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
2002).

75
Herder, “Fourth Grove,” p. 210.

76
René Descartes, “Optics,” from the Discourse on Method and Essays; in The

Philosophical Writings of Descartes, trans. John cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald
Murdoch (Cambridge: Cambridge University press, 1985), vol. I, pp. 152-75.

77
George Berkeley, Essay towards a New Theory of Vision (1710), in The Works of
George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne, ed. A.A. Luce and T.E. Jessop, 9 vols. (London and

Edinburgh: Thomas Nelson and Sons, 1948-57), vol. I, pp. 159-248.

78
Herder, “Fourth Grove,” p. 211.

79
Herder, “Fourth Grove,” p. 210.

80
Herder, “Fourth Grove,” p. 216.

81
Herder, “Fourth Grove,” p. 217.

82
Herder, “Fourth Grove,” pp. 218-19.

83
See Michael N. Forster, “Herder’s Philosophy of Language, Interpretation, and

Translation: Three Fundamental Principles,” Review of Metaphysics 56 (2002): 323-56.

84
Herder, Fragments on Recent German Literature; in Johann Gottfried Herder,
Philosophical Writings, ed. Michael N. Forster (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002),

p. 61.
Guyer 33

85
See Treatise on the Origin of Language; Philosophical Writings, pp. 75-7.

86
Herder, Treatise, pp. 65-6.

87
Herder, Treatise, p. 87.

88
Herder, Treatise, p. 88.

89
Herder, Treatise, p. 69.

90
Herder, Treatise, pp. 74-5.

91
Although it should be noted that Meier did write a “general art of interpretation” of
signs, the only one of his works to be given a modern edition in the Philosophische Bibliothek at

a time when the works of prolific eighteenth-century authors selected for canonization in that
series often reflected a linguistically-dominated conception of philosophy; see Georg Friedrich

Meier, Versuch einer allgemeinen Auslegungkunst, ed. Axel Bühler and Luigi Cataldi Madonna
(Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1996).

92
At least Mendelssohn put it in print before Lessing; see “Main Principles,”
Philosophical Writings, pp. 180-1.
Guyer 34

You might also like