Early Life and Career: Hilary Putnam
Early Life and Career: Hilary Putnam
Early Life and Career: Hilary Putnam
Get exclusive access to content from our 1768 First Edition with your
subscription.Subscribe today
Realism And Meaning
The unifying theme of Putnam’s philosophy is his defense
of realism, the view that, ordinarily, assertions (including theories,
beliefs, and so on) are objectively true or false. Putnam, like most
realists, also upheld the possibility of knowledge, distinguishing
between knowledge and mere belief, convention, dogma,
and superstition. Always self-reflective and self-critical, Putnam
frequently revisited and revised his earlier positions. The most-
pronounced change occurred in 1976, when he launched an attack
on the view he called “metaphysical realism,” recommending that
“internal realism” be adopted in its stead (see below Varieties of
realism). Internal realism, in turn, was also modified. Over the
years, however, it became exceedingly clear that Putnam’s
commitment to realism overrode the nuanced differences between
the various versions of realism he espoused. The clearest
indication of this core stability is the centrality of his theory
of meaning to all his versions of realism.
Hilary Putnam
QUICK FACTS
BORN
DIED
SUBJECTS OF STUDY
realism
Varieties Of Realism
Beginning in the mid-1970s, Putnam sought to distinguish his
understanding of realism from what he now called “metaphysical
realism.” According to Putnam (“Why There Isn’t a Ready-Made
World” [1983]),
What the metaphysical realist holds is that we can think and talk about
things as they are, independently of our minds, and that we can do this
by virtue of a “correspondence” relation between the terms in
our language and some sorts of mind-independent entities.
For Putnam, this picture of word-world correspondence is absurd,
pointing to a realism gone wild. Putnam considered metaphysical
realism to be blind to the autonomy and complexity of human
language. In particular, it is blind to the fact that the same reality
can be described in multiple ways.
Not surprisingly, this middle ground soon came under fire. Critics
considered Putnam’s realism unstable and at risk of collapsing
into either metaphysical realism or relativism. The latter option
was particularly repugnant to Putnam: in its thoroughgoing denial
of objective truth, relativism is but a form of
radical skepticism and is clearly at odds with Putnam’s realism.
One of Putnam’s striking insights at that time was that the two
polar positions—metaphysical realism on the one hand
and skepticism on the other—are equally vulnerable, and for the
same reason. Both positions construe truth as radically non-
epistemic, and, thus, both countenance the possibility that the
best scientific theory of the world—a theory that satisfies every
epistemic desideratum and is perfect in every methodological
and aesthetic respect—could still turn out to be false. But this
possibility, Putnam argued, is meaningless, and so are the
metaphysical views that countenance it.
RELATED BIOGRAPHIES
Philosophy Of Mind
Another area in which Putnam’s contributions have had enormous
impact is the philosophy of mind, where he introduced the
doctrine known as functionalism (sometimes referred to as
“machine functionalism”), which attempts to define mental states
in terms of their functional (or causal) roles relative to other
mental states and behaviours. This doctrine takes the mind to be
characterized not by the substance it is made of but by its
functions and functional organization. In “Philosophy and Our
Mental Life” (1975), Putnam put this idea as follows:
The question of the autonomy of our mental life…has nothing to do with
that all too popular…question about matter or soul-stuff. We could be
made of Swiss cheese and it wouldn’t matter.