Damian Valdez (Auth.) - German Philhellenism - The Pathos of The Historical Imagination From Winckelmann To Goethe-Palgrave Macmillan US (2014)
Damian Valdez (Auth.) - German Philhellenism - The Pathos of The Historical Imagination From Winckelmann To Goethe-Palgrave Macmillan US (2014)
Damian Valdez (Auth.) - German Philhellenism - The Pathos of The Historical Imagination From Winckelmann To Goethe-Palgrave Macmillan US (2014)
Damian Valdez
GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
Copyright © Damian Valdez, 2014.
Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 2014 978-1-137-29314-5
Introduction 1
1 The Age of Winckelmann and the Young
Herder I: Encounters 5
2 Winckelmann and the Young Herder II:
Historicity and Symbols 27
3 The Women of Athens I: The Varieties of
Enlightenment History 57
4 The Women of Athens II: Courtesans, Heroines,
and the Greek Polis 83
5 Iphigenie auf Tauris: German Theatre and Philhellenism 107
6 The Legacies of Iphigenie auf Tauris 129
7 From Sturm und Drang to Italy 151
8 The Loss of Paradise and the History of Freedom:
German Philhellenism in the 1790s 181
Notes 209
Bibliography 245
Index 259
Introduction
This book tells the story of the relationship between German letters
and ancient Greece in the second half of the eighteenth century. It
is a study of two generations; that of Winckelmann and Herder, and
that of Schiller and the younger Goethe. It tells the story of philhel-
lenic ideas in the half century before Romanticism and Napoleon
changed the terms in which the various legacies of Greek antiquity
were conceived and manifested in art, literature, and historiography.
This study is a complement to the work of Suzanne Marchand, whose
Down from Olympus has delineated the German interest in Greece
from the point of view archeology and educational institutions, and
to the work of Katherine Harloe, whose book, Winckelmann and the
Invention of Antiquity, elucidates philhellenic ideas in this period in
the context of their relationship with classical philology.1
This book concentrates on an analysis of the texts of four main
authors and a number of contemporaries, whose work informed,
challenged, developed, or contradicted that of the protagonists. In
the past, this story has often been told as a single-minded obsession,
whose literary output rested on an almost fanatical faith in the aes-
thetic purity and singularity of Greece. The traditional narratives, like
those of Eliza Marian Butler and Walther Rehm, to name the most
famous, retrace the origins and apogee of this “faith” and isolate
the German-Greek relationship as a phenomenon that stood above
history and whose radiance placed it beyond the complexities of the
Enlightenment, even if it assimilated what it needed from it in order
to reach its enraptured heights.2 This book tells the story instead
by the means of two juxtapositions that allow us to understand the
intellectual contexts and problems within which philhellenic ideals
were articulated, and how these ideals in turn underwent significant
transitions that transformed the significance of Greece in German
letters. Though the purity of the philhellenic phenomenon is thereby
diluted, we gain a better understanding of the intellectual problems
and enterprises in which it was embedded and of the paradoxes that
attended its central claims and literary endeavors.3
2 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
perennial beauty. That summit was Greek bodily form, captured for
posterity in the outstanding examples of sculpture and embodying
not only the highest conception of beauty but also bearing witness to
the noblest and happiest condition of mankind. This was the Greece
of Winckelmann, raised above and separated from a wider antiquity
that shone much less brightly.
Both ideals converged on the celebration of a manly youth, naïve
and natural for Herder, noble and heroic for Winckelmann. Youth
was understood both as the prime of the life of an individual and
in terms of the place of the Hellenic world in the philosophy of his-
tory: Greece was the youth of mankind. And yet, for them, Greece
was not only an ideal, but again, a rich historical formation, a com-
plex of histories and institutions, possessed of fragility and subject to
the vicissitudes of history. The philhellenic conversation initiated by
Winckelmann and Herder was thus also a confrontation between two
powerful impulses: the idealizing and the historicizing. The dialectic
of ideal and historicity at the heart of German Philhellenism engen-
dered significant problems and aporias that, as we shall see, disturbed
and enriched that conversation.
expressed.14 The 1755 essay has thus come to be seen as the first salvo
of anti-Roman revolt, a paean to an antibaroque aesthetic.
The only way for us to become great, the essay stated, is to imitate
the ancients. This injunction was followed by a speculative reflection
on the causes of ancient Greek beauty and the means by which it
was harnessed. The first models of beauty Winckelmann mentioned
were Spartan youths. They were made to do bodily exercises from
the age of seven; they slept on the bare earth and were trained in
wrestling and swimming. In the exercises, he said, the great games
were a powerful incentive for young Greeks, and the laws prescribed
a ten-month preparation period for the Olympic Games, preparations
that should take place at Elis itself. The greatest prizes were more
often given to youths than men, as Pindar’s odes told us. The high-
est longing of youth was to emulate the divine Diagoras of Rhodes
a famous Olympic victor. The schools of the artists were therefore
the gymnasia. And not only the artists but the wise went there too,
including Socrates. It was there that sculptors like Phidias studied
the imprint that young wrestlers had made on the sand.15 Thus for
Winckelmann, there was a direct causal link between the competitive
exercises done in preparation for Olympic contests and the masculine
form with which artists approximated divine beauty.
The frequent opportunities for the observation of nature, he
explained, made the Greek artists go even further. They began to
imagine certain universal ideas of beauties, both of individual parts
and of whole bodily proportions, which should surpass even nature
itself: their original idea was a nature created in the very understand-
ing of the mind. This is how the Greeks fashioned gods and men.16 It
was at this point that the differences with Bernini, renowned sculptor
of the baroque, came to the fore. Unlike the baroque, the Greeks
creatively synthesized what different parts of nature offered in order
to surpass it. To imitate nature in a single object, as Bernini advo-
cated, was to make a copy or a portrait; it was the path to “Dutch
figures and forms,” whereas the Greeks took the path of universal
beauty. “Our nature,” Winckelmann asserted, “will not easily create
for itself so perfect a body as that of Antinous Admirantus and the
idea will never imagine the more than human attributes of a beautiful
deity in the Vatican Apollo.” Thus the imitation of the ancients, he
confidently concluded, will teach us to become clever more speedily,
because it finds in one single concept that which is scattered in the
whole of nature.17
Alongside this idea of ideal beauty, this essay expressed what was
to become a fundamental philhellenic trope in Germany. This was
10 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
that existed alongside his love of Greek antiquity. The first set of
prisms was provided by Hamann, a formidable scholar of language
and the Bible. There could at first sight be no greater opposition than
that between Hamann and Winckelmann, Arnold Berger observed
in his 1903 study of the relationship between the young Herder and
Winckelmann. Here a longing for the highest beauty, for simplic-
ity, stillness, and greatness, there a resigned cynicism, the lack of
any sense of measure and beauty. Yet the two were united, Berger
asserted, by a drive toward the individual and original, toward the
life-giving sources of nature, and above all, by a belief in the “lower
faculties of the soul” that immediately revealed themselves to be the
truly life-creating ones.36
Berger’s reference to the lower faculties of the soul hints at a domi-
nant paradigm in mid-eighteenth-century German aesthetic ideas
derived from the work of Leibniz and Christian Wolff: that the senses
represented the lower faculties of cognition.37 The implication that
Hamann and Winckelmann and later Herder set out to rescue these
lower forces has profound significance for their interpretation of
Greece and was precisely the sensibility that accounts for the intensity
of their initial encounter with it. The passages of Homer and statues
by Phidias and Apelles depicted for the young Winckelmann virtues
and heroisms tied to physical form and vitality just as the language the
young Herder was to discover similarly appealed to a raw and naïve
human exuberance. The lower faculties of the soul corresponded very
neatly to the youthful coloring of their Hellenic enthusiasm. The
question was which form these lower faculties should take in order to
fulfill the aesthetic and ethical longings awakened by antiquity.
In January 1760, Hamann wrote to his brother in Riga that the
ideas of Wincklemann’s Thoughts on Imitation were applicable to
poetry to the highest degree of precision.38 It was mindset and lan-
guage that in their effect on each other, Hamann explained, deter-
mine the character of a people in contrast to others, and reveal their
character just as well as their external form.39 But alongside this vali-
dation of Winckelmann and alongside a shared disdain for cumber-
some scholarship, there was a repudiation of the pagan ethic that the
latter discerned in the expressions and bearing of Greek sculpture:
“Not the increase of knowledge can show us the way, not abstractions
which make us old and clever, but rather the naivety of feeling, in
which the warmth and exuberance of youth is renewed. The sources
of rejuvenation do not flow in classical antiquity: the materials of the
creative spirit are nature and scripture; salvation is of the Jews, comes
from the East, from the Bible, from the original conditions of human
14 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
may not have been impressed with Brown’s remarks on Greece, which
he thought were sketchy and unconvincing, but there is no doubt
that he shared Brown’s rapture at the idea of an original unity of
these arts and that he too sought to demonstrate with his own ideas
and scholarship the birth of a politics and ethics under the auspices
of nature. He also shared Brown’s premise that the decline of that
condition brought with it a measure of corruption. Thus alongside
the philosophy of Hamann, it was the speculations of Brown, and
the Jesuit travel reports on which they were based, which formed the
second prism through which Herder interpreted Greek antiquity.
So long as a person lives among the objects of nature and these
touch him deeply, Herder reflected, the freer and more divinely he
can express with language, that which he has received, the more we
can find a poetic art that lives and is creative (wirkt), and this is pre-
cisely the case in the times of quite wild nature or in the first stages of
political formation. But when art supplanted nature and finished laws
took the place of lively feeling, how could poetry and the creative lan-
guage of nature be possible anymore?46 Herder’s essay examined the
fate of this language of nature among the ancient Hebrews, Greeks,
and Romans. Speaking of the Hebrews, Herder began by saying that
not even its enemies could deny that this people had the most mar-
velous creative poetry. Its purpose was to turn it into the people of
God. Herder continued here the Christian apologetics of Hamann.
The phrase “salvation is of the Jews,” which, as we saw, Hamann, had
used as part of his moral exhortation to go after the early history of
language, was, after all, taken from the Gospel of John.47 But Herder’s
affinity for the ancient Hebrews was also part of a strong revival of
interest in the Hebrew Bible in eighteenth-century Germany, which
manifested itself most emphatically in the popularity of the Book of
Job. As Jonathan Sheehan has shown, this book and the Hebrew Bible
in general was admired by Herder and others as an instance of the
sublime, an aesthetic category, raised to prominence by the essays of
Edmund Burke in 1757 and Immanuel Kant in 1764 and particularly
suited to awe-inspiring, miraculous, and imposing divine interven-
tions.48 It was therefore a mixture of the moral imperative he shared
with Brown and Hamann and of the aesthetic interest he shared with
Kant and Burke, which engendered what was both a formidable coun-
terweight and a crucial foundation of his Philhellenism.
God saved them by miracles and signs, Herder enthused of the
Hebrews, and how did he impart to them the first ideas? Through
poetry! Through the glorious song of their Exodus. It was to be a
memorial of its lawgiver, Moses, a song that eternally shaped the
16 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
morals and heart of the people. Not even the famous Spartan lawgiver
Lycurgus could be compared with him, Herder asserted.49 If among
all peoples, said Herder, answering his own earlier question to Plato,
poets were the first idolaters, flatterers of the people and of princes,
corrupters of morals, so among the Hebrews they were the adversar-
ies of idolatry, of conceit and flattery, and of weak morals. Where is
the unique providence of God more convincingly praised and mani-
fested as in the history of this people? Christianity, he added, grew
out of the same seed.50
Here too, Herder wrote of early Greece, poetry was in the begin-
ning divine, and she shaped the morals of persons and peoples. The
oldest lawgivers, judges of secrets, and the innermost worship were
poets: Orpheus, Amphion, Linus, and Thales. Out of their old cos-
mogonies, hymns, secrets, and tales, they derived their political and
moral order (Sittlichkeit). Moreover, Herder argued that Plato with
all his wisdom was deeply enmeshed with every obscure and intri-
cate question of poetic sayings and tales of the old times. Without
them indeed, there could have been no Plato.51 To the apotheosis
of natural poetry celebrated by Brown and Lafitau, Herder added
a strongly esoteric note. Poets were custodians of secrets and pro-
tagonists of an innermost worship. And yet this esoteric material
leads Herder to the same place as them: that the first public laws and
customs had been articulated by a holistic poetic art that united in
a single act all its participants and fulfilled all political and religious
functions.
Having established that this was the case in Greece, Herder cel-
ebrated Greece very much in Winckelmann’s terms but with subtle
inflections of some significance. The gods Egypt, he explained,
became for the Greeks beautiful poetic beings, they threw off every-
thing heavy and superfluous and showed themselves naked, as mother
earth made them, in beautiful human form, and human, often too
human, action. Art came to compete with poetry. Out of two verses
of Homer, he observed, Phidias made his famous statue of Jupiter
as if from a revelation. Their education in the most beautiful ages
consisted of bodily exercise, music, and poetry, under the supervi-
sion of elders, and they became, thanks to the lawgivers of the states,
the foundation of their character. Homer was everything to them,
the fine eye with which he saw everything, each object depicted not
crassly, but with a light, pure outline, correct and finely measured.
From Homer they derived order (Sittlichkeit), art, and truth.52 In
this passage, it is the sculptor Phidias who is subordinate to the poet
Homer, whereas for Winckelmann, Phidias had been the artist who
THE AGE OF WINCKELMANN AND THE YOUNG HERDER I 17
with gentle tenderness on the proud edifice of his limbs.” Despite the
disdain discernible in his lips and up to his forehead, the peace, which
floats in a contended calm on that forehead, remains undisturbed. 60
That imperturbability that does not deny the passions but allows an
effortless sovereignty and restraint to overshadow them, was the ethi-
cal quality evinced for Winckelmann in Greek sculpture. This was less
idealistic than the Kalokagathia of Shaftesbury and Rehm’s attempt
to link the two thinkers as of one mind in this regard is less convinc-
ing. This was because the imperturbability Winckelmann admired
also allowed an admittedly subordinate but nonetheless palpable exis-
tence to capricious sentiments like disdain and anger. The moral core
was sovereignty rather than goodness.
Whether a moral core was discernible in bodily beauty and if so
in what measure was the subject of Herder’s essay Is the Beauty of the
Body a Sign of the Beauty of the Soul?, another prize entry. Herder
accepted as his premise one of the chief characteristics of Greek
beauty defined by Winckelmann: the right measure and proportion
of the features. He also understood the precise inflection of the link
between this type of beauty and its moral quality. A proportionate
form can indeed be a sign of a measured mind, Herder agreed, inca-
pable of great passions, be they good or bad. The stability of spirit,
however, which accompanies proportionate form may well be the
portal of every beauty, but often remains the portal. It belonged to
quiet charms that do not disturb but also do not enliven the spirit.
Indeed, the greatest men, Herder observed, have often been men of
unstable traits, since the passion that raised them to greatness also
determined from early on this unstable form.61 “Our imagination,”
Herder concluded, “finds in facial traits, for the most part, more than
nature has placed in them and usually as much as one wants to find.”
If Winckelmann, “on the wings of his imagination, finds in the statue
of the Apollo Belvedere in Rome, such unending beauties of spiritual
divinity, that he raises himself to rapture, then one must congratulate
someone who perceives in the bodies of others so much spirit, so
much beauty, and not vex them.”62
Herder’s skepticism about the possibilities of a purely visual rela-
tionship to beauty is part of his wider response to the aesthetic and
philosophical debates of his day turning on the nature of the senses
and aesthetic perception. As Paul Guyer argues, Herder rejected the
strident distinction between mind and body and the suggestion that
aesthetic pleasures are essentially distinct from the other sources of
happiness.63 His essay on sculpture, published in 1778 but composed
over a period of many years, was also an intervention in the debate
20 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
and classical freedom, though the former breathed life into the latter.
Political freedom in the sense of later classical democracy was there-
fore the last factor to take its place in Winckelmann’s historical whole.
It was not the foundation of the scene at Elis that was the composite
manifestation of Greek beauty and its causes.
But comments on the absence of tyranny are formulaic and com-
monplace. This led Winckelmann’s great nineteenth-century biogra-
pher Carl Justi to criticize this aspect of his philosophy of history:
“The author leads us through antiquity in order to show us continu-
ously the same spectacle: that every peace, every revival of the republic
magically brings forth a group of artists, every war by contrast, and
the loss of freedom brings about the ruin of taste and disaster.” In
such a scheme, the life of art would bear a resemblance to today’s
financial and business cycles, Justi observed, which are so sensitive
to the pulsations of the political world. In truth, he said, art has a
more robust constitution.18 Justi was a faithful and detailed expo-
nent of his subject’s ideas but he often sought to find the unintended
paradox or to put complexity in the place of a simplicity that had lent
Winckelmann’s ideas poignancy and a lapidary quality.
Classical as opposed to archaic freedom had a more complex fab-
ric than that evinced by political fluctuation. It was linked to the
prominence of the art of rhetoric and public speaking, making use of
Hardiou’s Dissertation sur l’origine et les progres de la Rhetorique dans
la Grece.19 As Gombrich noted in 1971, Winckelmann constantly
drew parallels in all of his works between the decline of rhetoric and
corruption in art.20 The art of public speaking, he explained, began
to flourish among the Greeks during the full enjoyment of freedom.21
“Freedom, the mother of all great events and changes of constitution
and of jealousy among the Greeks planted, even in the beginning, the
seeds of noble ideas, and just as in the view of the immeasurable sur-
face of the sea the proud beating of the waves upon the rocks of the
beach extends our gaze and leads the mind beyond petty things, so
could no one with this view think without nobleness.”22 The absence
of a single tyrant was significant because it allowed the Greek cities
to harbor envy and jealousy for each other, the foundation of com-
petition between cities and thus of the public spectacle and public
pride that gave rise to the encounter between noble beauty and art-
ists. One further claim in this part of the text is of some significance.
Winckelmann argued that what he was describing was made clearer
by a comparison with Rome. For the Romans, inhuman and bloody
games, fighters who contended with death, were the most pleasant
entertainments for the whole people even in its most polite ages. The
32 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
this intense form of friendship was premised on the contrast with and
absence of the emotional salience of women, a problem to which later
generations of philhellenic writers, as we shall see, would dedicate
more sustained attention.
In the first instance, the scholar who made the most sustained and
systematic attempt to link male friendship to the status of women
was Christoph Meiners. For him, it was precisely this problem that
eventually negated the creative effects of the institution. The Greeks
did not know a tender love of the female sex that looked to spiritual
completeness, Meiners observed at the beginning of his 1775 essay
Reflections on the Male Love of the Greeks. But they possessed a pas-
sionate love for the beauty of the male sex, which appeared outland-
ish to us in any fiction and would appear unbelievable but for the
evidence provided by the remains of antiquity. It was not a reality of
a single age or state but of all Greece and particularly of its bravest
peoples. Nothing in their way of thinking was so different to ours
as this.44
The chaste Seelenliebe (love of the soul) between men was the
mother of all virtues, the most sacred bond of virtuous souls inspired
to great and noble deeds, Meiners asserted. The greatest heroes of the
earliest ages, children of the gods, had passed on this heavenly male
love as a sacred legacy to their latest descendants. Thus it was hated
by tyrants and cowardly peoples and protected by the great lawgivers.
Perhaps Lycurgus the fabled Spartan lawgiver, had gotten the idea for
the regulation of male friendship from Crete, where, Meiners said, it
had been present in very early times. The Cretans had apprehended
the relationship between Seelenliebe and bravery, for a warrior ani-
mated by passionate love was nigh-on invincible. The Sacred Band of
Thebes, Meiners pointed out, had almost cost Philip victory at the
battle of Chaeronea.45 The sanction of lawgivers was strengthened by
the example of the great commanders, like Epaminondas, who fell
next to his Kaphisodorus at the battle of Manitnea in 362 BC. But
Meiners ended his celebration of Seelenliebe on an ominous note and
returned directly to the problem of the status of women. Among many
Greeks, particularly the Cretans and Thebans, this love had degener-
ated into unnatural vice, he said. Among the Greeks and Romans just
as in the Orient, it was linked to the bitterest hatred of the female sex
and necessarily became one of the chief causes of the depopulation of
both nations.46 With this critique of friendship, parallel to that of the
competitive athletics to which it was so closely linked, Enlightenment
historiography challenged once again the institutional and contextual
basis of philhellenic ideals.
38 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
und Drang. This movement of young writers in the 1770s was fasci-
nated by the individual creative genius and its capacity to articulate, in
the manner of inspired bards, the poetic wisdom of a people. In this
decade, Shakespeare and the supposedly Scottish poet Ossian were
the subjects of this fascination.63 Herder’s own essay on Shakespeare
from this time waxed lyrical about the bard’s ability to reproduce
with such precision and comprehensiveness, the political and social
life and personalities of his day.64 At the end of his prize essay of 1777,
Herder wrote that he wished that the spirit of Winckelmann would
set itself upon an artist, who would turn his theory into action and
marry his ideas with flesh and blood in works of sunlight and marble.
All the investigations of the researchers of antiquity prepared the way
for the genius, who revived and arrayed this antiquity with the magi-
cal powers of Medea. The theory of the beautiful, full of feeling, with
Winckelmann’s ancient simplicity, dignity, and strength, was but an
invitation for him who should come, the new Raphael or Angelo of
the Germans, “who could create for us Greek men and Greek art.”65
Just like Winckelmann before him, Herder had an acute sensibility
for the position and historical significance of the power of rhetoric in
ancient Greece and Athens in particular. As a young man of 20, he
had prepared a short essay entitled Do We Still Have a Public and a
Fatherland Like the Ancients? In it he lamented the passing of an active
and patriotic citizenry on the Athenian model.66 This was the begin-
ning of a long engagement with the character of civic life, a concern
that encompassed governance, rhetoric, public spectacle, and the link
between these and the problem of taste. An important exposition of
these issues and the connections between them was the Causes of the
Decline of Taste among the Different Peoples with Whom It Flourished.
For Herder, the power of rhetoric born alongside all the other Greek
arts, contained the seeds of a disequilibrium and threatened to rend
asunder the synchronicity between works of art and ethical aspirations
that he and Winckelmann affirmed with such passion. “Certain works,”
Herder wrote, “can in the end arouse a passion of a kind that is artisti-
cally but not morally good. They want storm rather than clear sunshine.
Brutus was no Cicero and Socrates no Pericles, no Demosthenes.”
The states in which the best taste flourished were not the most
virtuous, and Athens “with all its taste was itself no Sparta in terms
of civic virtue.”67 Taste was a synthesis of reason, of genius, and of the
sensual, desiring forces.68 It was thus for Herder a composite whole
that could yield different results in different polities. Taste upheld
good morals but not as good morals. Rather, it upheld them as beau-
tiful decency and fine order. This was the point of greatest divergence
WINCKELMANN AND THE YOUNG HERDER II 43
dismissed the claims by figures like Banier and Simon that Nemesis
was a bloodthirsty goddess of war.115 Sophrosyne was the virtue of
restraint and this was the message of Nemesis. To this end, Herder
mused, an Easterner would have given her a jug of confusion in
her hand, with which she sank the soul of those lacking control in
drunkenness or self-abandon. The Greeks, by contrast, retained for
her the symbols of justice and happiness: the wheel, the reins, the
scales, and thus portrayed Nemesis as benevolent toward the whole
of humanity.116
Many cultivated peoples, Herder explained toward the end of the
essay, had had excellent didactic proverbs that they derived from the
experiences of world history and of human life, and which expressed
a great deal in a single entity, sharpening the sense of the individual
for the good and the true. The orient too had offered sublime and
clever sayings on the articles of happiness and practical wisdom. Yet
no one had matched the Greeks in the combination of clarity and
beauty they brought to bear upon it. “To them the muse had given
that pure vision of all forms in art and poetry, that unexaggerated
feeling for the true and the beautiful in everything, itself incapable
of exaggeration, which also in philosophy remained true to itself and
endowed their shortest proverbs, their lightest symbols with such a
clear contour, such a meaningful elegance [Grazie], which we would
search for in vain among other peoples.”117 The conviction that the
Greek eye could discern ethical principles based on a sense of balance
and measure, that it could give them form and transform them into
beautiful art, and that this art reflected a lighter, less burdened exis-
tence was the most salient philhellenic idea of this generation. The
sense of lightness was conveyed by a comparison with a modern life
plagued by an excess of metaphysics, of feeling, and of knowledge.118
It is interesting to note that in this essay, at least, the ethical beauty
of Greece and Herder’s sophrosyne were a creation of the Greek eye,
whereas Winckelmann’s arête, with its more affirmative account of
the passions, could only flourish in the rapid movement of the poetic
imagination.
evoke but also sustain a milder humanity, that could preserve it from
the culture of the gladiatorial arena.
Herder’s essay of 1786, divided into a series of letters and his
second engagement with the subject, had the same title as that of
Lessing. He doubted whether one could read such a neat and con-
sistent symbolism into funerary art, noting also that the Romans
and Etruscans loved the festive depiction of centaurs and genii that
Lessing had read as solemn representations of death. The genii were
in any case merely symbols of rest and guardians of stillness.132 In the
third letter, Herder took up Lessing’s point about the clarity of the
Greek language but he insisted that the distinction was between ker
and moira, with moira the goddess of fate, signifying the hard neces-
sity of fate. This was the principal concept of the ancients concerning
death, and, Herder added, “the philosophically most worthy concept,
which man can create for himself about a necessity so contrary to his
will and yet so commensurate with his nature. Since the idea of a
high commanding fate passed out of the mind of man, his soul crept
along with glances of petty caution and with the anxieties of a low
resilience.”133
Whereas Lessing’s Greeks had elaborated a codified system of
signs that art could employ to craft the image of death in a gentler
light, Herder’s Greeks sought instead to nobly evade its countenance.
Thanatos was a terrible being to the Greeks, he wrote. Death was to
them so horrible and hated, that they did not dare utter its name.134
The dead, Herder wrote, had to cross the ocean or a tremendous
current. How did they get across? “One chose happier ship captains
[Schiffer]” These were birds, fish, genii in service, or dolphins. In
other grave paintings the transit was a festive bacchic procession.135
In any case, art in antiquity was a clearly defined visual language
obscure to us, Herder observed.136 Death and sleep had never been
portrayed together on a Greek grave. Indeed, if anywhere, this had
occurred in the grave paintings of the early Christians. This was a
correction of Lessing’s assertion to the contrary. It had only been
later that superstition had corrupted the original sentiments to arrive
at the Totentanz , the grotesque spectacle of the Middle Ages, equally
emphatically denounced by Lessing.137 Herder’s Greeks, despite their
oblique references to death and their gentle evasion, were more resil-
ient than Lessing’s. Yet both discerned in the funerary lexicon and
symbols of Greece, an ethic that predated the advent of superstition
and which spoke of the absence of many psychological burdens insep-
arable from modern lives.
C H A P T E R 3
out, liked to play around with the notion of an “inverted world” and
hence they would talk about women having seats reserved for them at
the theatre. Nothing could be more natural than the comic subject of
Aristophanes’s Lysistrata, which he associated with this “new-fangled
right of Women,” (citing this in English) and its champion, Mary
Wollstonecraft.29
Böttiger, however, did not fail to avail himself of the same come-
dians when they made observations that favored his case.30 As a final
argument he pointed out that such misogynistic works as those of
Euripides could not have been performed in mixed company and
compared it to modern English drinking clubs that “did not spare
women” in their harsh wit. Sparta represented a significant contrast
to Athens. Women were more at liberty to visit the theatre and some
of the games.31 His refutations had some credibility for subsequent
studies and as late as 1898 he was cited as the main authority of the
nonattendance camp of this question.32
Böttiger’s categorical refusal to allow any exceptions to the theatre
attendance prohibition, which went beyond even Rousseau’s austere
assumptions, threatened to obliterate the only public participatory
trace of Friedrich Schlegel’s historical Diotima. He manifested his
displeasure at Böttiger in the preface to the collection of essays enti-
tled The Greeks and the Romans, in which the Diotima essay was pub-
lished for the second time, and which appeared early in 1797.33 In
January, Böttiger wrote to Friedrich’s brother, August Wilhelm, with
whom Friedrich was in the closest personal and intellectual contact,
saying that he had gotten into trouble with the latter over the the-
atre issue.34 Friedrich Schlegel had until then been in friendly regu-
lar contact with Böttiger, who had acted as a go-between for him
and Wieland in order for some essays and translations of Schlegel’s to
appear in Wieland’s journals.35
In March 1797, Böttiger published a rebuttal of Schlegel enti-
tled “Were Athenian Women Really Excluded from the Theater?”36
Quickly grasping the point that mattered, he said that “Herr Schlegel
cannot bring himself to exclude Athenian women, which he would
very much like to raise to the rank of educated women, such as the
Platonic Diotima, from the sublime school of Athenian citizens, the
theatre.” In a city where men were careful not to utter the slightest
indecent word in front of them, Böttiger argued, visits to the theatre
by women would have contravened “all the sound Athenian manners
[Sittsamkeit] enshrined in law.” To appear nowhere in public was “the
first and holiest of the ethical prescriptions [Sittenvorschriften] of
Athenian women and girls.”37 Schlegel had accused him of neglecting
62 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
a passage of Plato’s Laws that he said proved the contrary. Plato had
said that if prizes in the poetic contests were to be granted to those
who had generated the most enjoyment, then the old men would
grant them for the Homeric rhapsodes and the educated women to
tragedy. In this instance, Böttiger pulled the historical carpet from
under Schlegels’s feet. He said Plato’s reference to educated women
was more likely to refer to those in his ideal state, “ennobled with
every element of male culture.”38
That there was a female contribution to Greek culture and that
this was based on the historical reality and visibility of a class of
educated Greek women were the two points that Böttiger now tried
to refute. Drawing on his love of art and archeology, he introduced
a final twist in the argument designed to bury the notion of his-
torical Diotimas. When the Athenians wanted to honor their heroine
Leana, he said, they had represented her in a monument as a lion-
ess and when the painter Polygnotus wanted to paint his beloved
Elpinice, daughter of the great Militades, he could do no other but
represent her as the legendary Trojan woman Laodice, in a painting
depicting the conquest of Troy. And so, Böttiger concluded, even in
images womanhood could only show itself under the name of a god-
dess or heroine.39
On March 13, 1797, Schlegel thanked him for sending him a copy
of the article, commenting that he was glad to have given occasion
for a discussion but that some of what Böttiger had said had “gone
beyond what was right” concerning himself. In any case, his point, he
wrote, had been not to make all Athenian women into Diotimas, but
rather to highlight the difference between Dorian (Spartan) and Attic
(Athenian) femininity.40 For Schlegel then, Attic-Athenian literature
contained the traces of a historical Dorian-Spartan femininity, where
women were freer and which had come into contact with Athens.41
The energetic publicist Böttiger had the last word on the matter but
behind the issue of the visibility of women at the theatre stood the
wider problem of the corruption of manners that such visibility might
intimate, a problem inextricably linked with sensuality, luxury, and
excess.
following year: “What was the luxury of the Athenians from the time
of Pisistratus till Philip of Macedon and how did it gradually bring
about the fall of the state?”42 The premise of the question left no
doubt as to the power attributed to luxury and its intimate relation to
the integrity of the state. The winner of the competition in 1781 was
Christoph Meiners, the professor at Göttingen and future author of
the immensely popular four-volume History of the Female Sex (1788–
1800). The eighteenth century had seen the culmination of a com-
prehensive challenge to a whole range of intellectual traditions hostile
to luxury, the most successful of which, and the one which engaged
all these hostile traditions in a wide-ranging rebuttal, was that of the
protagonists of the Scottish Enlightenment, particularly Adam Smith
and David Hume.43
“Luxury,” wrote David Hume in 1752, “is a word of an uncertain
signification and may be taken in a good as well as in a bad sense. In
general it means great refinement in the gratification of the senses
and any degree of it may be innocent or blamable, according to the
age, or country, or condition of the person.”44 In the first half of the
eighteenth century the contest over luxury had turned partly on the
question of the military fitness of the state, where the opponents of
luxury decried the “effeminacy: engendered by sensual and associated
excesses.” The more comprehensive defense of luxury mounted by the
new theories of commercial society advanced by Hume and Smith
had yet to be articulated.45 If Sparta was the focus of the idealization
of ancient frugality then Rome was the object of study of decline and
corruption where luxury played a role of varying magnitude. The rise
of Rome, and particularly the decisive confrontation with Carthage,
an opulent commercial power, was seen in terms of a praiseworthy
austerity by Montesquieu in 1734 and Rousseau in 1749.46
“What has chiefly induced severe moralists to declaim against
refinement in the arts,” David Hume explained, “is the example of
ancient Rome, which joining to its poverty and rusticity, virtue and
public spirit, rose to such a surprising height of grandeur and liberty”
but that having learned, supposedly, from the conquered provinces
the “Asiatic luxury,” it had been corrupted. Yet it would be easy to
prove against these writers, he said, that what they ascribed to lux-
ury had really been caused by ill-government.47 Between those who
decried Roman luxury as a chief cause of ruin and those, like Hume,
who absolved it of this charge completely, Montesquieu occupied a
middle position. In his essay of 1734 Montesquieu was more con-
cerned, like Theodor Mommsen a century later, to emphasize the role
64 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
of the expansion of the Roman state as the cause of its downfall.48 But
in the Spirit of the Laws of 1748, the treatment of sumptuary legisla-
tion was the occasion for a link between luxury, the wealth of women,
and the health of the republican state.
Sumptuary laws had been denounced by some eighteenth-century
defenders of luxury as a feudal institution designed to block the rise
of those from the lower estates and protect aristocratic interests.49 It
was in the Roman Republic at the moment of its decisive world-his-
torical confrontation with Carthage that the link between sumptu-
ary laws and the wealth of women was made by Montesquieu: “The
laws of the first Romans concerning inheritances thought only to
observe the spirit of the division of lands; they did not sufficiently
restrict the wealth of women and thereby left a door open to lux-
ury, which is always inseparable from this wealth.” The ill became
felt, Montesquieu explained, at the time of the Punic Wars (with
Carthage), which as we have seen, was understood by him and oth-
ers as a glorious contest between virtuous frugality and exuberant
opulence. This was the time (169 BC) when the Voconian Law,
which greatly restricted the inheritance rights of women, was pro-
mulgated. Cato the elder, another heroic figure for critics of luxury,
“contributed with all his power to the passage of this law.”50 It was
meant to deprive women, not of all inheritances, but only consider-
able fortunes.
Montesquieu confined himself to explaining that such laws had
been “in conformity with the spirit of a good republic, where one
should make it so that this sex cannot avail itself, for the sake of
luxury, either of its wealth or the expectation of wealth.” But he had
mitigated the force of this concession to the value of that law by say-
ing it had been contrary to natural feeling and that good men had
evaded it and arranged for their daughters to receive their inheritance
either by not enrolling themselves in the census or by arranging a
trust fund.51 A century later, in a study of the Voconian Law pub-
lished in 1843, Johann Jacob Bachofen, the Basel jurist and historian
later famous for his theory of “Mother Right,” made a more explicit
and emphatic link between that law and the survival of the Roman
state during its key formative crisis. Women were the main driving
force behind the excessive fortunes threatening to undermine the
military prowess of Rome. Whereas Montesquieu had balanced two
moral imperatives, there was no question in Bachofen’s study about
where right lay.52
It was this union of a single moral imperative with the great-
ness and stability of the state that Christoph Meiners applied to the
THE WOMEN OF ATHENS I 65
Wars. Because of the courtesans, not only was the health of the young
men weakened early but they hindered the formation of their hearts
and spirit . . . The thirst of noble ambition and the desire for glory
and great deeds was snuffed out.” The courtesans even embarked on
fleets with expeditions and wrote books about their arts, as if they
were philosophers.64
By the age of Demosthenes, Meiners lamented, courtesans where
everywhere.65 Though not the creators of luxury, Aspasia and her
successors, pounced on an Athens bloated by trade and profits.
Flattered by the presence of fine artists and sculptors, they developed
with cunning and power-seeking ingenuity, arts that had decisively
eroded Meiners’s own masculine ideal of youth engaged in games,
in the hunt, and in affairs of state. The story of luxury in Athens was
the story of the foundations of a more serious and formidable power
inimical to the vitality of the state. In this way, Meiners arrived,
ironically, at a similar conclusion to his contemporary Adam Smith
when the latter passed judgment in the Wealth of Nations on the
relationship between women and luxury as follows: “Luxury in the
fair sex, while it enflames perhaps the passion for enjoyment, seems
always to weaken, and frequently to destroy altogether, the pow-
ers of generation.”66 Questions about the significance of women in
matters of luxury and narratives of corruption could ultimately be
resolved by the comparisons and theses advanced in wider historical
accounts.
civic and political world. We find the Tacitean outlook in the work of
Antoine-Yves Goguet in 1758, in that of Lord Kames in 1774, and in
that of figures as far apart ideologically as Christoph Meiners in 1788
and Theodor von Hippel in 1792, who used it as historical evidence
in his plea for greater rights for women.76
This narrative, ubiquitous and impervious to political divides, was
itself an alternative not only to philhellenic notions of a more empow-
ered Greek femininity but also to an understanding of sacred scrip-
ture that was premised on an original prelapsarian holiness of the
feminine. It was mentioned in the work of the Glasgow law professor
(and disciple of Adam Smith) John Millar in 1771, whose version of
the condition of ancient Celtic women was drawn from Julius Caesar’s
unflattering picture rather than from Tacitus.77 German readers of
Luther’s Bible would also have found in Genesis 3:15 a verse that
says: “I will put enmity between you and the woman and between
her seed and your seed.” It was possible to read into this an original
innocence of the feminine and its enduring resistance to evil and that
text was interpreted in eighteenth-century Germany as presaging, at
the time of the creation, the Virgin Mary and the coming of Christ.78
It is important to remember that all these scenarios were most often
included in the same volume, offering a composite comparative per-
spective that betrayed the author’s preferred hierarchy of moral and
political virtues for women. The philhellenic ideals of Greek feminin-
ity for classical Athens, therefore, had to contend with the Tacitean
and the prelapsarian understandings of the ancient condition of the
female sex.
In 1788, Meiners published the first volume of his History of
the Female Sex, a large and ambitious project that, designed for the
instruction of young middle-class ladies, was the ultimate exercise in
Sittengeschichte or a history of manners, embedded in a racial scheme
of the history of humanity.79 Together with de Pauw’s Recherches
Philosophiques sur les Grecs published the same year, it represented
the latest modern authority for German readers on the condition of
women in ancient Greece and particularly in Athens.80 Other, less
recent but still contemporary and often-cited commentators on this
subject included Antoine-Yves Goguet’s Origins of the Laws, Arts
and Sciences, and the Abbé Jean-Jacques Barthélemy, whose multi-
volume work Voyage du jeune Anacharsis en Grèce dans le milieu du
IVe siècle was a comprehensive survey of Greek life and history and
the standard modern reference work in Germany at that time for that
subject.81
70 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
the town, and the facades of the houses about Demus, the son of
Pyrilampus, to transmit to posterity the fame of such an accomplished
mortal.”106 Dismissive about the beauty of women, de Pauw instead
quoted an ancient author: “The Athenians, says Isocrates, are not to
be distinguished from the other Greeks by an advantageous size or
any superior force of body: but no nation, in that part of the world,
ever produced men of such extraordinary beauty.”107 The propensity
to homosexuality, which de Pauw called a “corruption of instinct” in
the Greeks, was also denounced by Meiners as helping to account for
the disregard and ill-treatment of women.108
But de Pauw also provided an explanation for Greek mistreatment
of women different to that of Meiners: “The Athenians invented the
term Mysogyne, to define a class of men, who, like Euripides, vented
continual imprecations against women, or fled from their sight with
Melanion to inhabit the most solitary recesses of the desert, like wild
beasts, renouncing at once all obedience to civil ties and the laws
of nature.”109 Misogyny was a malady contracted by some Greeks
because the cold winds coming from their mountains predisposed
them to this form of melancholy, rather than, as Meiners would have
it, the result of the evolving relationship between an unhappy racial
mixture and social mores common to all Athenians.
the South Sea, one of the participants of which, Georg Forster, was
to marry Heyne’s daughter Therese and would become Christoph
Meiners’s chief antagonist. Its position as the center of academic
exchange from “Halifax to St. Petersburg” also made it the center of
discussion concerning the competing theories about man.117 It was
from these reports and older sources that Meiners devised his clas-
sification of the races. He assured his intended middle-class female
readership that after the horror stories of the East, Celtic women’s
history was premised on freedom and law.118 Gradual perfection
(Vervollkommnung) was granted only to the Celtic races. This was
the basis of Meiners’s Tacitean idealization of ancient Germanic
women.
“From that auspicious commencement,” wrote Lord Kames in
1774 after describing the process by which men could no longer sit
idly by while their wives toiled like slaves, “the female sex have risen
in a slow but steady progress, to higher and higher degrees of estima-
tion.” Like his fellow Scot John Millar, Kames was keen to emphasize
that “conversation is their talent” and that the advancing estimation
of women went hand in hand with an unfolding moral sense and more
polished manners.119 Kames explicitly used the term “conjectural” to
describe his enterprise. It had been Dugald Stewart, who had coined
the term to describe the historical methods of Adam Smith.120 In
its application to a history of the female sex Kames described it as
follows: “The progress of the female sex, a capital branch of the his-
tory of man, comprehends great variety of matter, curious and inter-
esting. But sketches are my province, not complete histories; and I
propose in the present sketch to trace the gradual progress of women
from their low state in savage tribes, to their elevated state in civilized
nations.”121 The concern of conjectural historians, as Höpfl explains,
was to trace the “typical” path that, by gradual stages, had led man
on the passage from savagery to refinement. The point of conjectural
history was also to show, as Walter Bagehot said, “how from being a
savage, man rose to be a Scotchman.”122 For Kames and Millar, the
two figures of the Scottish Enlightenment most concerned with the
progress of women, that progress consisted in the gradual liberation
of the conversational vocation of modern European women, a lib-
eration made possible by the change of manners brought about by
different economic structures. For both, it was the power of popular
opinion that was a universal constant. If Kames commented on how
it had it become unseemly for men in some parts of Africa to sit idly
by while their wives worked, Millar had been fascinated by how the
esteem for military virtue had transformed the possibilities of fatherly
78 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
Once neutrality had been fought off and the criteria of differentia-
tion extended to include body, heart, and mind, the next step toward
Meiners’s brand of ethnographic history of manners was to try to
prove a necessary connection between social systems and anthro-
pological data. This, says Marino, was relatively new. Drawing on
eighteenth-century literature on Oriental despotism like Boulanger’s
1762 study Recherches sur l’origine du despotisme Orientale, Meiners
tried to show that it was the “weaker” peoples who succumbed to
it.137 Following the tradition of Leibniz, the great Göttingen politi-
cal historian Schlözer had classified people according to language.138
Meiners’s classification of peoples was much closer to that of Theophil
Friedrich Ehrmann, whose Kurze Überischt der Völkerkunde appeared
in 1787 and based its classification on bodily form, moral character,
and then form of life, manners (Sitten), customs, and opinions.139 For
Schlözer, the great milestones of history where the great inventions,
and his focus was the political state. For Schlözer’s great enemy in
Göttingen academic politics, Gatterer, it was the life of nations. This
was Universalhistorie, where individual peoples and political states
were the units of historical development. This was what Gierl calls
the “identity of nation, people, state, culture and civilization.” In
Göttingen, Meiners was a defender of the popular philosophy of the
group around Feder and Spittler, one whose efforts were directed
against Universalhistorie. What was left over in this struggle, which
was still practical, empirical, and concrete, Gierl writes, was race.140
This was the organizing principle that served Meiners’s Geschichte
der Menschheit or “History of Mankind,” which he explicitly distin-
guished from Universalhistorie.141
The “History of Mankind,” with the development of manners
(Sitten) as the end point of the inquiry, was a strident discipline that
claimed to have superseded “Universal History” in its understand-
ing of causality and which aimed at a far greater comprehensiveness
than the typical path traced by “Conjectural History.” If Universal
History was political in the Aristotelian sense of seeing political life
unfolding in the state as the highest object of historical contempla-
tion, the History of Mankind was political in that the manners that
stood at the apex of its investigation denoted a political character:
Meiners repeatedly stated that the worth of a people could be mea-
sured by their treatment of women and vanquished enemies. Whereas
the successors of Universal History treated the history of women as
completely separate from anything properly political, Meiners, made
the history of women an integral part of the understanding of the
political character of the various races.142 Greek women were part
THE WOMEN OF ATHENS I 81
to morals than the ascendancy that the hetaerae of Athens had had
over respectable women, whose education was so neglected that the
Graces turned away in horror from their countenance.11
Jacobs’s ultimate motivation in writing the Contributions has so
far remained unclear. Why did he find de Pauw’s assertions offen-
sive and why did he choose to pursue his interest in the pedagogical
condition of women precisely with the hetaerae, the very example de
Pauw used to shame the educational level of Athenian women? One
answer is that the demonstration of a learned interaction with men on
an equal footing provided by these women was intended as a support
for his pedagogical goals for women.12 Another is provided by the
historiographical task that Jacobs had set himself. He was looking for
balance and measure. At the beginning of the first instalment he had
called the condition of slavery and the condition of unnatural rule
that women attained in overly refined circumstances, equal expres-
sions of barbarism.13 In an otherwise bleak historical landscape, to
which he evocatively alluded at the start of his piece, the hetaerae
offered, at least at times, a middle path studded with bursts of intel-
lectual brilliance, wit, and above all, an ability to live and deal with
powerful men.
De Pauw, Jacobs wrote, was a clever author who possessed more the
quick-wittedness than the patience of a critical historical researcher
and whose work was essentially an indirect satire of the contemporary
world rather than a critical and exhaustive treatment of the evidence
of antiquity.14 Jacobs’s argument and the point at issue were histori-
cal. He immediately acknowledged, in his first numbered note, his
two predecessors in the historiorgraphical dispute, Friedrich Schlegel
and Carl Gotthold Lenz, both of whom he praised for distinguish-
ing between the different epochs and peoples of Greek antiquity in
their treatment of women.15 Like Schlegel, who in 1794–1795 had
evinced the same passion and the same argument based on the prom-
inence and character of the women of literature so central to Gomme
in 1925, Jacobs sought, not to repudiate everything that had been
said about the real life of Athenian and Greek women, but to extend
the realm of the enlightened and spirited women, raise their number
and the worth of their accomplishments, and to assert this against
the sweeping and dismissive statements of a Christoph Meiners or a
Cornelius de Pauw. His concern with education rather than Schlegel’s
heroines of literature was one of the factors that led him to the het-
aerae and thus to meet de Pauw on his own ground.
Jacobs has been seen as the originator of a modern tradition that
has defended Athens and ancient Greece from the charges of imposing
86 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
And so the public games gave Greek education a very particular direc-
tion, in that it made bodily exercises the main part of it and brought
the advantages gained from it the attention of the whole nation. Never
has a branch carried finer fruit as the small ivy and fig, which crowned
the Greek victor. It made the young men, beautiful, healthy and lively:
it gave maneuverability, measure and well-being to their limbs: it
ignited in their soul the first sparks of love of fame and even post-
humous fame und engraved in them the indestructible resolve to live
publicly for their city, their country, what is most valuable, it implanted
in their minds that taste for interaction with men and male friendship
which distinguishes the Greeks. Woman did not constitute, in Greece,
the whole contest of life, to which the young man was committed;
the beautiful Helen, after all, could only give occasion to a Paris if the
enjoyment or possession of her had been the goal of all manly excel-
lence. The female sex, however beautiful the examples of every virtue
it brought forth in Greece, remained a subordinate aim of male life,
the thoughts of noble youths were directed towards something higher;
the bond of friendship, which they formed among themselves or with
experienced men, took them into a school, which an Aspasia would
hardly be able to grant them. Hence the male love of the Greeks in
several states, accompanied by that emulation, that instruction and
that constancy and sacrifice, whose feelings and consequences we can
read in Plato almost as the novel of a strange planet.62
Herder stated the problem that Greek historicity had thrown up for
the conception of a philhellenic femininity. Friedrich Schlegel’s essay
On the Representation of Female Characters in the Greek Poets, written
in Dresden and published in 1794, and his much more famous and lon-
ger essay On Diotima, published in 1795, made an elaborate case for
the existence and the ethical significance of an alternative Greek femi-
ninity. But, like Jacobs’s Contributions, it contained important para-
doxes. If the debate on Greek women in the 1780s and 1790s turned
on various aspects of their status with regard to public life and their
visibility, all such questions ultimately led to an appraisal of their rela-
tionship with ancient free constitutions. In the mid-1790s this was not
merely an academic question. The muse who was Schlegel’s Diotima,
96 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
because Schlegel, in this instance, was also taking about the theatre,
which, as we have seen, he insisted that Athenian women could attend.
It illustrates something of a fault-line in eighteenth-century thought,
so concerned with the ideal pedagogical scenario and its formative
models.69 Rousseau had criticized the tragedies of the French theatre
(admittedly of a different hue to Sophocles) among other things for
setting up unrealistic role models; the scenes of tragedy did not depict
the lives of ordinary citizens but those of exalted characters whose
mindsets and choices were of a different stamp.70 The formative
models that led to nobility of character were to found, ideally, in the
immediate vicinity, which he depicted as the good people of the Swiss
countryside near Geneva. The image of young men and women meet-
ing each other in innocent festivals and dances, which Lenz delighted
in when recounting stories of the heroic age, could have been taken
from a passage at the end of Rousseau’s Letter, though Rousseau also
emphasized the supervision of benevolent elders.71 Schlegel was more
skeptical about the interaction between the sexes during the heroic
age. The Homeric heroes, Schlegel disdainfully observed, knew of
no other perfection of a woman than her youth and her physical
attributes.72
From the very beginning of his chronological presentation in 1794,
Schlegel acknowledged the salience of what Mähly would assert with
reference to him 60 years later: the ideal of male friendship in ancient,
indeed, archaic Greece, set a very high benchmark of nobility and
emotional intensity. Mähly had pointed out that this was linked in
the minds of German scholars to the vitality of Greek states. Schlegel
evinced a profound admiration of Homer’s evocation of powerful
feelings:
The spirit of love for women had not yet in this age in general assumed
the character of the noble and the beautiful. Heroic friendship by
contrast, is the most beautiful combination of masculine and warring
greatness and tender feeling. It is the noblest fruit of this age, and
marks its character so much, that even from the darkness of the most
ancient legends the heroes shine forth for us in pairs, Castor and Pollux,
Hercules and Jolaus, Theseus and Pirithous. All outstanding heroes of
the Iliad are accompanied in friendship by a brave comrade. That such
heroic brotherhood is sublime and powerful can be taken as a given.
How noble and tender it was, is something of which Homer has left us
an eternal portrait in the friendship of Achilles and Patroclus.73
And yet the names of the famous Athenian women did not convey
the ideal that Schlegel was working toward. He was not satisfied, as
THE WOMEN OF ATHENS II 103
Friedrich Jacobs would be, simply to point out the paradox of com-
bining a “higher” education with a status originating in slavery and
purchased at a high price. The name of Diotima seemed to point in
another direction. And so Schlegel began to outline the reasons why
she could not have been a hetaira. First of all, she did not speak like
one in the Symposium —she was no Lais. Moreover, she had a priestly
office dedicated to the god of harmony and was therefore a “seer.”
“The stream of her speech is poured with a holy enthusiasm, which
no Venus hetaira can show.” “No slave,” he exclaimed, “exercised
this holy art of Apollo!” 91 The two religious personalities, that of
the typical eighteenth-century fascination with the Greek worship of
beauty in the form of hetaerae, and the association with the oracle
and Apollo, the “office” of seer, represent the two ends of Greek
female religious power within the city state. The center of gravity had
moved from the educated hetaerae of Venus to the educated priest-
esses of Apollo.
The identification with the oracle, moreover, was significant
because it was acknowledged as one of the few pan-Greek institu-
tions.92 The name of Diotima thus implied a national dignity. The
religious personality of the feminine in Schlegel’s imagination had
made a transition from the physical power of nature to the embodi-
ment of divine harmony. Politically, it had moved from cultivated if
scurrilous companionship with statesmen and philosophers to the
dignity and authority associated with the oracle that spoke to cities.
This was implicitly a more noble form of power from which men not
only learned, as they had done in the company of an Aspasia, but
to which they, like Socrates had done, also deferred. The power of
a Phryne, who inspired a religious awe as she disrobed in Eleusis by
the sea, and that of a Diotima who spoke sublime words about love
to the wisest man in Athens, was very different. Yet they were both
within the spectrum of the religious authority that the Greeks were
said to attribute to femininity. Schlegel was implicitly challenging the
salience of one end of that spectrum in favor of the other.
The hetaerae, he remarked, were excluded from the feasts attended
by female citizens and it was a peculiarity that in Corinth, where
thousands of girls of outstanding beauty graced the temple of Venus,
they took part in the feast of that deity.93 The feasts of Corinth, a
city that was seen in the eighteenth century as emblematic of the
Greek worship of female beauty, were in that respect a civic anoma-
ly.94 Where then could there be female participation within the civic
context—where was the true home of Schlegel’s Diotima? Diotima
the literary character had undergone a journey from one extreme of
104 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
the work of the historian Justus Möser, who had attacked the tyranny
of Roman law in favor of the old Faustrecht (right of private justice) of
independent knights.15 The sixteenth-century Götz fought a gallant
but losing battle in the name of legal and political autonomy against
the unseemly intrigues of an incipient courtly absolutism. A more vic-
torious advocacy of a similar cause would characterize Schiller’s ver-
sion of William Tell, first performed in Weimar in 1804.16 Goethe’s
Egmont, published in 1788, placed this confrontation, again with a
heroic and noble defeat, on the eve of the Dutch wars of indepen-
dence in the sixteenth century.
Schiller’s men struggled with the trials of the progression that
allowed one form of freedom to feed into the higher, transcendental
morality. Goethe’s men, particularly Egmont and Torquato Tasso,
struggled with the fatalistic affirmation of an autonomy that brought
them to deadly danger or dissolved the foundations of their life and
patronage. Yet only by assessing Iphigenia against the backdrop of the
female characters will we be able to understand the full import of the
specifically philhellenic dimension of the famous play, that is to say, its
relationship to the unresolved conflicts and longings that dominated
the dramatic work of the two authors. Karl Moor’s lover Amalia, in
Die Räuber, mirrored his delight in the freedom of an adventurous
and fighting existence, albeit with a melancholic nuance. She sang
a version of Hector’s farewell to Andromache, a poem that Schiller
published for the first time in this play.17 She and Karl had sung the
different verses together, she explained. Like for the young Herder
and the young Goethe, the Iliad represented for the young Schiller
a sublime portrayal of early heroic self-command and independence,
a joyful proximity to nature in the form of combat and danger. It
was the Homer of the Sturm und Drang.18 Amalia’s sonorous resort
to the Iliad ennobled the danger and implicitly sanctioned Karl’s life
as the bitterly resigned but still idealistic robber baron in the woods:
was paid for with her life. A very different death was that of Klare,
Egmont’s beloved, in a Brussels soon overrun with Spanish troops
and inquisitors. Klare contrasted herself, first of all with the formi-
dable Duchess of Parma, who governed the Low Countries before the
arrival of the feared Duke of Alba. She could not find herself in the
world in the same way, she said. The duchess was great, passionate,
and determined.20 But it was only when Egmont was taken prisoner
that this contrast occasioned a rupture in her life. It was precisely her
freedom, in contrast to his captivity, and, despite her spirited appeals,
her inability to rally his admirers and friends to his rescue, which
made her despair of the world and end her life. Yet the unpolitical but
loyal Klare imagined a gentle death and idyllic afterlife with imag-
ery from Greco-Roman antiquity: “I wander closer and closer to the
blessed fields, the consolation of that abode of peace is already beck-
oning me.”21
Klare and Amalia both embodied the pathos of loyalty and did
so in a largely unproblematic way. Their conflict was more with
external circumstances than within their soul. The high point of
internal conflict and the most poignant expression of an attachment
to duty was expressed by Luise Millerin, Schiller’s most compel-
ling female creation of those years. Her dignity and moral rectitude
stood comparison to Iphigenia, but the sharper confrontation of
conflicting loyalties rendered her a stark and instructive contrast.
She appeared as the beloved of Ferdinand von Walter in Kabale
und Liebe, published in 1784, and which was originally to be called
Luise Millerin.22 She was thus without a doubt the central char-
acter, and the play thereby structurally approximated Iphigenie.
Millerin was intelligent, articulate, and confident. In the beginning
she shared with Ferdinand the rejection of the divisions and pre-
tensions of estate society but gave that rejection an otherworldly
inflection. As a girl of modest background, she was not expected
to marry Ferdinand. She told her mother that she renounced him
“for this life” but that all titles would disappear when God came, as
her father, the musician Miller, had said. Beautiful thoughts would
count more than ancestors. “I would then be noble,” she concluded,
“and then what advantage could he have over his girl?”23 Here it
was unclear whether it was a kind of unspoken republicanism or
the afterlife that rent the chains of the estates. Her devotion to her
father was the intimation of a pathos of duty which threatened to
overcome her passion for Ferdinand. Her acceptance of necessity
and of the impossibility of marriage met with Ferdinand’s shocked
accusation: “cold duty against fiery love!”24
114 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
In the final act, she sank back into that passion and the anticipa-
tion of a future harmony now distinctly associated with death. She
used the specific distinctions and imagery of the ideas of death in
the philhellenic portrayals of the subject by Lessing. In a letter she
showed to her father, she invited Ferdinand to accompany her on the
journey to the afterlife, implying it was the only courageous route.
Consoling her father, she said, “only a wailing sinner could see death
as a skeleton; it is but a noble boy, just as they paint the god of love,
but less mischievous—a calm, amiable genie, who offers his arm to
the exhausted soul of the pilgrim across the divides of time.”25 Yet she
repudiated in horror this gentle imagination when she remembered
her duty to live for her adoring father. She resolved to live just when
Ferdinand, incensed at her presumed treason, resolved to kill her,
and died a Christian death: “Dying forgave my redeemer.”26 Just as
Amalia had blended the Homeric and modern German worlds, so
Luise Millerin blended the Greco-Roman gentleness of death with
her own social egalitarianism and loving passion. But the union of
duty with a Christian orientation, and finally, a Christian death,
superseded the unmistakably philhellenic motif about death. It would
fall to Goethe to reconcile duty, freedom, and Greek form, a Goethe
who in Verona, as we shall see, would starkly contrast ancient and
Christian representations of death, just as he came to render Iphigenie
in verse.
aroused the ire of the fearful Thoas, who reminded her of the terrible
prognostications given by the oracle if he did not kill the foreigners.
Iphigenia responded that it was to truth that one must sacrifice and
that she wanted to send word to her family by means of the strang-
er.53 This courageous truthfulness in a confrontation with Thoas
was something that Goethe would incorporate in his portrayal of the
story, but at a later point in the play and in the face of a Thoas who,
as T. W. Adorno would later point out, was anything but a true bar-
barian.54 La Touche’s Iphigenia united her truthfulness to an act of
courage that was the all the greater because her interlocutor was less
enlightened than Goethe’s equivalent. The denouement of the play
was the kind of action and confrontation that delighted the audi-
ence. Orestes confronted Thoas, defiantly announcing he had come
to take the statue of Diana and that he wished to avenge and console
the earth, to wash in Thoas’s blood the atrocity of a destructive cult.
Pylades arrived just in time with a troop of Greeks, Thoas was killed
and the statue was taken.55
The second and third acts were mostly taken up with Pylades’s
sentimental and defiant declarations of love for Orestes. Troas told
him he was to be his successor only for Pylades to disdain his wedding
with the princess and the whole kingdom for the sake of Orestes, now
condemned to death. The third act contained a long monologue on
his love for Orestes as well as a confrontation with Tomiris, who was
disdainful of his preference for friendship. Iphigenia, again an adjunct
to such scenes, reported that the oracle foresaw a “crowned victim”
at the altar. Once again, the quintessentially Greek institution of the
oracle was turned into a handy device for modern plot entanglements.
Pylades took this as an opportunity to die for his friend and claimed
that he was Orestes, something denied, of course, by the equally ded-
icated Orestes.77 The cruel and impulsive Troas decided to kill them
both. The climax of the play in the fifth act was the description given
by Tomiris’s confidante, Zarine, of the procession taking the two men
toward the temple and their sacrifice. “Their eyes were turned with
pleasure towards each other, in whose glance one discerned a satisfac-
tion that triumphed over death and Troas.”78 Compared to this, the
actual resolution of the play seemed but an afterthought designed to
fulfill the simpler criteria of entertaining spectacles: Orestes, “lion-
like” and seconded by the arrival of Greek soldiers, killed Troas, and
Tomiris became queen.
gods, was able to rescue her from the underworld but when Admetus
asked him how he accomplished this, he replied: “do not desire to
know it! A sacred veil, which the gods themselves do not dare to draw,
lies upon the secrets of the spirit realm. The hand of the Eumenides
seals my mouth!”88 Both Admetus’s vision of the underworld and
Hercules’s concession that the dark deities of the underworld had a
secure domain, would be features of Goethe’s play. In this respect,
and as one important modern current of interpretation reminds us,
the power conceded to a merciless and terrifying underworld in these
plays directly qualified and countered the image of death among the
ancients, which Lessing, Herder, and Goethe himself, would other-
wise celebrate. The didactic Philhellenisms of Herder’s Nemesis or of
Lessing’s essays, as well as Goethe’s Italienische Reise, all of which
focused on the silent remains of graves in Italy, removed themselves
from a facet of Greek experience concerning ideas about death, which
Greek drama and later the sonorous sentimentality of eighteenth-
century plays powerfully brought to the fore.
At the end of April 1773, Wieland published a set of letters in his
Teutscher Merkur that contained a kind of manifesto about the princi-
ples of his play and a critique of Euripides’s treatment of the legend.89
Wieland’s fundamental complaint was that Euripides’s Alceste fol-
lowed the principles of rhetoric rather than those of sentiment. “How
infinitely different is the language of sentiment from the language of
the rhetorical schools! What wonderful things she can express with
one look, one gesture!” 90 His letters in the Teutscher Merkur show
better than any other document the distance between the thoroughly
contextual and holistic Philhellenism of the first generation, and the
occasionalist enthusiasm for the malleable individual Greek legend.
Herder’s essay on the history taste, which we have already discussed,
as well as Winckelmann’s History of the Art of Antiquity, celebrated
Greek art and Greek rhetoric as a powerful and creative unity, as a sin-
gle whole. Beauty and excellence were publicly displayed and publicly
rewarded. The civic pride of achievement, which Pindar expressed in
odes that sang of the ancestry and the city of the athletes, had con-
tributed to an idea of Greece as permanently assembled, constantly
sitting in judgment, in politics, in art, and in theatre. For Wieland,
it was precisely this that stood in the way of Empfindsamkeit, of
sentiment.
Euripides, wrote Wieland in the first letter, “makes the voluntary
sacrifice of Alcestis a public affair. The whole of Thessaly takes part.”
The piece thereby lost, he argued, the most touching scene—the
moment of that voluntary sacrifice.91 In the second letter, Wieland
IPHIGENIE AUF TAURIS 127
sought to purify the raw Greek manners of Euripides for the require-
ments of the eighteenth-century cultivated audience. The tears that
Euripides’s Alceste shed over her marriage bed, the trouble she had
tearing herself away from it, had “something selfish about it,” Wieland
observed, “which vitiates the value of her tenderness.” The same was
true of the oath that the dying wife demanded of her husband, to
remain true to her memory and their children.92 Wieland wanted to
create the most touching, venerable, and dignified figure, which the
tone of his letters intimated was an artistic challenge more than it was
an ethical or theological statement. The Greek Alceste’s emotional and
physical attachment to the marriage bed was far too sensual a regret
for the German Alceste, whose departure from this world took place
in a spirit of unblemished selflessness. If Wieland’s Alceste evinced
traits that would later be adopted by the chaste and single-minded
Iphigenia of Goethe’s creation in 1779, the younger Goethe of 1773
found Wieland’s project objectionable and ridiculous. In September
of the latter year, Wieland had published an ambivalent and lukewarm
review of Goethe’s Götz and this hardened Goethe’s mood against
him.93 He wrote a farce entitled Gods, Heroes and Wieland. He sent it
to his friend Lenz in Strasburg, who was so taken with the piece that
he convinced Goethe to publish it and it appeared early the following
year.94
Many years later, in his autobiographical reflections Dichtung und
Wahrheit, Goethe explained the reasons for writing it. Wieland’s dis-
regard for the “raw and healthy nature” of ancient drama and his
arrogant self-promotion in the letters irritated Goethe and his young
friends.95 Wilhelm Heinse and the young Sturm und Drang welcomed
the piece enthusiastically.96 In the farce, Wieland found himself taken
in his sleep to the afterlife and confronted with Euripides and the
characters of the drama. Defending himself for having denied his char-
acters the regret at having to depart from life, Wieland said proudly
and laconically, “only cowards fear death.” Admetus responded that
this was true of heroic deaths, but that death when one was a father of
a household was feared even by heroes and that this corresponded to
nature. “Do you think I would spare my own life,” Admetus contin-
ued, “to win back my wife from the enemy, to defend my possessions
and yet . . . ” Wieland interrupted him and said to all of the sprits pres-
ent: “you speak as people from a different world, a language whose
words I hear but whose meaning I do not comprehend.” “We speak
Greek,” they told him. Admetus added, “is that so incomprehensible
to you?” He went on to explain the difference between Wieland’s play
and the Greek notions he claimed to have improved upon: “A young,
128 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
quite happy, contented prince, who had received from his father
realm, earth and goods and sat there with satisfaction, enjoyed and
was whole, needed nothing but people who enjoyed with him . . . and
who did not tire of giving, who loved all that they may love him, and
thereby befriended gods and men, and Apollo forgot the heavens at
his table. He should not wish to live forever!”97
Wieland is particularly shocked by the imposing physical dimen-
sions and wild vitality of Hercules, who tells him, “had you not sighed
so long under the yolk of your religion and morality, you could have
become something.” 98 That potent vitality of gigantic forms, was in
the words of Hans-Jürgen Schrader, the “titanic antithesis” that the
young Goethe’s antiquity, in contrast to Winckelmann, opposed to
modern moral and aesthetic sensibilities.99 It was intimately linked
with the understanding of artistic creativity as a wild, defiant, and
sensual force.100 It is interesting to note that it was the need to deal
with divergent understandings of death that provided the occasion and
the foundation of the argument between Wieland and the ancients.
Death was not, as in the didactic Philhellenism that contemplated
ancient graves, a peaceful and idyllic rest, but rather a terrible mate-
rial loss, a separation from the freedom of an unreflective sensuality,
embodied at its best by Admetus and Hercules.
C H A P T E R 6
love for Orestes and the latter’s reciprocation lose the salient status
accorded to them by most of Goethe’s predecessors. It was through
the struggle of Orestes and Iphigenia with guilt, exile, and redemp-
tion that their personalities were articulated, and this made Goethe’s
play markedly different.
Goethe’s drama revealed another facet of a creative problem at
the heart of the philhellenic imagination in Germany: the relation-
ship between a given artistic medium and the embodiment of ethical
aspirations. We have already seen how considerations that in given
instances favored poetry over sculpture or sculpture over poetry
affected the tenor and inflection of ethical ideals. This discussion
also points toward the first significant departure from the contextual
Philhellenism of the earlier generation. As the commentary to the
Frankfurt edition of Goethe’s works remarks concerning this drama,
it constitutes “an internalization of the dramatic conflict.” The politi-
cal theatre, “understood as the theatre of the Polis, experiences an
introversion towards the moral-humane spiritual exercise.” 9 Gone was
the public character of the drama, which as we have seen, is one of the
key claims of contextual appraisals of Greece. There is no chorus and
the number of actors is greatly reduced. With the absence of the cho-
rus the public forum disappeared, which, as Emil Staiger observed,
was indispensable for Greeks but would have disturbed Germans.10
Humphrey Trevelyan’s classic study, Goethe and the Greeks, pub-
lished in 1941, argued that Iphigenie auf Tauris was the culmina-
tion of a classical Greekdom derived from Winckelmann’s insights
on sculpture, a confirmation and continuation of his ideal: “He saw
before him a Greek youth in naked simplicity and self-assured repose,
and knew that this was the visible expression of his new wisdom.”
Goethe, he wrote, had read Anton Raphael Mengs’s Reflections on
Beauty in July 1778, shortly before starting work on the play. He
found no room there, Trevelyan continued, for the gigantic figures
of the fables, which he was trying to escape. Balance and proportion
was the goal at which Goethe had arrived. Here, as we might expect,
Trevelyan made reference to Herder’s essay on sculpture, also finished
in 1778.11
The problem that preoccupied Trevelyan was that of Goethe’s
deeply personal relationship to the harsher, fatalistic, merciless aspects
of Greek myth. As a classic of the German literary canon, Iphigenie
was understood by its readers as the scene of struggle between pow-
erful and antithetical moral forces. In the later twentieth century
it became the scene of a contest about the legacies of the German
Enlightenment and about the overcoming of radical evil. The Greek
132 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
fundamental purpose of the drama.15 For him, the play was deeply
embedded in an Enlightenment theology that rejected orthodox and
authoritarian models both in religious and political life.
In detaching the play from Goethe’s personal context and plac-
ing it within a narrative of eighteenth-century theological polem-
ics, Rasch broke with a tradition, most powerfully represented by
Friedrich Gundolf’s 1916 intellectual biography of Goethe, to which
we will return.16For Gundolf, Prometheus, Proserpina, and Iphigenia
were “three stages of Goethe’s idea of fate.” The Goethe of Werther
and Prometheus had stood in irreconcilable struggle with the fate
embodied in the external world; their entire being was a desperate
negation born of deep spiritual desires anchored in Goethe’s own
constitution. The ethical power of Iphigenia signified the overcom-
ing of this opposition.17
The Iphigenia of personal overcoming thus served as a window
onto Goethe’s deeply held personal beliefs and as the key to his trajec-
tory. In this way the modern rendering of Greek drama was the prism
of a personal theology and ethic that unfolded in live dramatic action.
The appeal and pathos of drama as a medium was therefore much
greater than sculpture or poetry when the Philhellene himself was as
much a subject of admiration and inquiry as the philhellenic founda-
tion. What had to be overcome was the harsh and melancholic mes-
sage of the Parzenlied. The Parzen, as messengers of death, were the
negative counterpart of the soft and amiable genii that Lessing had
admired as ancient representations of death. Both had a powerful hold
on the philhellenic imagination. In his Alceste of 1773, Wieland had
conveyed the chilling effect that the very thought of their approach
produced. “They have heard it! They are coming, they are coming!,”
shouted the dying Alceste.18 In his letters on the play, Wieland had
suggested that this terrible sentence alone sufficed to communicate
the magnitude and nobility of the sacrifice.19 Goethe too had been
fascinated by the melancholy and desolate mood of the Greek under-
world and by the merciless and abrupt break that the youthful death
of a blooming figure signified. The monologue Proserpina, taking up
one of the most famous Greek legends, represented the eponymous
character in Pluto’s realm and was published in Wieland’s Teutscher
Merkur in 1778.20
The monologue was then inserted into Goethe’s satire, The Triumph
of Sensibility.21 According to Trevelyan, this was done in a mood of
frustration with the Greek ideal and the result was to “destroy its
whole effect,” that is, the effect of Proserpina’s monologue.22 “They
have torn me away, the swift horses of Orcus; the unmovable god
134 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
held me with firm arms . . . Torn down into these endless depths!
Queen here? Queen? Before whom only shadows bow!”23 Such was
Proserpina’s lament in the mouth of Queen Mandanane, a charac-
ter of Goethe’s satire. The courtiers asked why she was declaiming
alone, and the king replied that “if you could speak Greek, you would
know that a play means to act alone.”24 Prince Oronoro, the main
character, possessed a doll in the likeness of Mandanane, which was
discovered to contain the main texts of “sentimentality,” among them
Rousseaus’s Nouvelle Heloise of 1761 and Goethe’s own Werther. The
texts tumbled out of the doll when curious courtiers secretly violated
Oronoro’s sanctuary, an imitation of the greenery of nature purged
of all its inconveniences. The satire thus portrayed the summit of
melancholy as a conscious choice, as a cultivated mood and way of
life, which removed itself from interaction with social life and nature.
Oronoro himself said at the end of the play that he longed for the end
of the “stormy stirrings of my heart,” and “this Tantalid striving for
eternally flowing enjoyment.”25
Far from “destroying” its whole effect, the Parzenlied in Triumph
of Sensibility actually helps Trevelyan’s overall argument. Nowhere is
it clearer, that for Goethe, the melancholy and darkness of the under-
world are forces within the individual life and personality that we
can choose to indulge or to overcome. Trevelyan’s Goethe creates
the Iphigenia myth as an act of personal overcoming and as a way
of resolving a painful aporia in the legacy of Greek tragedy. Pylades,
Trevelyan tells us, was Greek: comely, life-loving, yet prone to trick-
ery and the use of force. But he was “pushed into the background by
Iphigenia, whose new morality of universal trust and love resolves the
dangerous situation which his code of violence would have aggravated
into a catastrophe.”26
This sense of a Manichean struggle between opposing worldviews
as the message of the play was retained with a more philosophical
inflection by the Swiss literary critic Emil Staiger, whose essay on
Iphigenie was published in 1957.27 The action of Iphigenie, he wrote,
takes place in the twilight, “insofar as in the depths the darkness of
fate is brewing, yet on the summit shines the clarity of a belief in prov-
idence.” The poet, Staiger asserted, moves in an intermediary realm,
which here borders on Euripides and there on almost Protestant zones
and he finds his peace neither here nor there, but in a place where
fate and providence are resolved (aufgehoben) in a manner peculiar to
Goethe.28 The appeal to providence, which Staiger’s Goethe pitted
against fate, and which he sublimated in a secret, esoteric, and idio-
syncratic reconciliation between the two, recalls Rousseau’s famous
THE LEGACIES OF IPHIGENIE AUF TAURIS 135
And yet, just such a decision [i.e., to tell the truth], presupposes a long,
never shaken tranquility, getting used to holy stillness, through which
alone the harmony of the interior [des Innigen] reveals its will. Only in
the priesthood are both permitted and secured: the untouchable and
unmixed essence of the pure and the grace of being initiated and at
one with that which is deepest. From within the temple, mediated by
the priestess, the spirit of purity spreads outwards in concentric rings,
penetrates the alien, incorporates it, pronounces, calms and convinces
with its fine-tuned music, until all selfishness disappears and a higher
dispensation triumphs.50
Tasso, and he might have added, for Werther too.74 Both of these
characters seal their downfall with a passionate hug of their platonic
beloved, a violation that both completed and negated the world their
imagination had cultivated. The principle of distance, a postulate
Adorno tacitly borrowed from Nietzsche’s own aristocratic “pathos
of distance,” restricts, he writes, Humanität to a social privilege, for
the sake of which the artist distances himself.75 The feeling of injus-
tice, Adorno observes, comes from the fact that Thoas, the barbarian,
gives more than the Greeks, who, with the agreement of the work,
believe themselves to be superior. The course of the play was an apol-
ogy by Humanität of its immanent inhumanity. In order to defend it,
Goethe resorts to an extreme: “Iphigenia, obedient to the categorical
imperative of the as yet unwritten Critique of practical reason, dis-
avows, out of freedom, out of autonomy, her own interest, which
required her to lie. In so doing, she recreates the mythical context of
guilt which she is supposed to overcome.”76
For the contest between the Iphigenias of autonomy and the eternal
feminine, which we have been following, Adorno’s analysis contains
an important irony. The most powerful weapon of the proponents
of the eternal feminine had been, as we have seen, Iphigenia’s asceti-
cism. This quality was now conscripted by those who saw the play
through a Kantian lens, that is, that her autonomy was the central
message. But whereas Rasch explains autonomy in terms of the inde-
pendence of the self-helper following her own interests with practical
acumen, Adorno instead indicts the aristocratic exclusivity and there-
fore inhumanity that it defended. Adorno’a interpretation contains a
further irony for our story. The underlying aristocratic sensibility that
Gundolf, the founder of the modern Iphegenie myth, discerned in the
play, was rendered a component of Enlightenment, the very condition
of autonomy.
Adorno, Rasch, and Heller, though authoritative, were relatively
lone voices. Both Gundolf and Staiger speak of Iphigenia projecting
her power outward. There is no question that her truthfulness, born
of purity and humanity, lift the curse and heal Orestes. That sense
of ethical power was also evoked by Hermann August Korff in the
second volume of his Geist der Goethezeit, published in 1930.77 The
recent commentary of the Frankfurt edition of Goethe’s works con-
tinues the tradition in a similar vein. In Goethe’s Iphigenie, the furies
yield not to a masculine but to a new feminine law: that of sisterhood,
which we should see as Goethe’s equivalent to the fraternity postu-
lates of the revolutionary Enlightenment.78 This in turn builds on
THE LEGACIES OF IPHIGENIE AUF TAURIS 147
the great orators, had been for their state. Everything radiant about
Greece, Herder concluded, was due to the activity of its lively energies
and everything lasting and healthy was accounted for by the equilib-
rium of its striving forces.60
the gymnasia and at the Olympic Games. For Goethe, Homer hinted
at truths evoked by the landscape, especially of Magna Grecia and
Sicily, the once Greek-dominated part of southern Italy. These truths
were inseparable from the features of contemporary Italian life that he
described with such dedication and precision, and which outlined in
their most quotidian and mundane details, the contours of that utopia
which he discerned more intimately with every step on Italian soil.
When reflecting in 1932 on what made a journey in this mind-
set possible, Curtius spoke of the “classlessness of the German spirit
between Leibniz and Romanticism.” The French spirit, he said, once
it had overcome Calvinism and the disturbances of the Fronde in
the seventeenth century, was that of the court. In Germany in the
eighteenth century, by contrast, there was no politically mature and
cultivated citizenry—it was strewn across the country and doubly
powerless due to the confessional division. There was, moreover, no
unified leading court. This German classlessness was a weakness but
also a strength, since within it lay “the root of its fundamental vision
of a pure humanity, whose development in a free spirit, in a moral-
aesthetic self-cultivation, in a social state, is to this day an unfilled
program.”67 Speaking under the shadow of the rise of National
Socialism in Weimar Germany, Curtius’s lecture contained indict-
ments of right-wing extremism. Goethe’s Italy was thus the sanctu-
ary of a universal German humanity. In distinguishing the origins
of that humanity specifically from the spirit of the French court, he
anticipated what Walther Rehm would do in 1936 in his discussion of
“Iphigenian humanity.”68 And just as the interpreters of Iphigenie auf
Tauris discerned a “pure humanity” so Curtius now read that into
Goethe’s Italy. The idealized adjective “pure” and the noun “purity”
were the ciphers of the twentieth-century imagination for the kind of
relationship to Greek themes that had overcome historicist barriers.
It implied that it was possible to recover the edifying and beautifying
core of Greek humanity independent of its context. What this meant
and what “moral-aesthetic self-cultivation” might be taken to mean
are the subjects of this chapter.
The passage from Winckelmann’s Achilles to Goethe’s Ulysses
meant the eclipse of that heroic exertion in the scene of great histori-
cal action, burdened and enlivened by the pathos of male friendship.
It gave way to the settled utopia of an idyllic garden, the possession
of which proved transient or elusive for a hero in search of private
fulfillment removed from historical responsibility. It was a transition
that privileged the Odyssey over the Iliad. “It would have meant lit-
tle to him to stand on the Pnyx and reflect that here Themistocles
FROM STURM UND DR ANG TO ITALY 165
and Pericles and Demosthenes had swayed the Athenian demos with
the magic of words” Trevelyan wrote of Goethe.69 By September
16, 1786 Goethe had reached Verona. There he stopped to ponder
ancient graves:
The wind which blows from the graves of the ancients comes with
pleasant scents like over a hill of roses. The graves are agreeable and
touching and always convey life. There is a man, who next to his wife
looks out of a niche as if out of a window. There stand father and
mother, the son in the middle, looking at each other with inexpress-
ible naturalness. Here a couple holds hands. Here the father appears to
be entertained by his family. To me the immediate proximity of these
stones was very moving. They are of a more recent art, but simple,
natural and universally meaningful. Here there is no anguished man
on his knees who awaits a joyful resurrection. The artist has, more or
less with elegance, represented the simple presence of people, thereby
prolonged their existence, rendered it permanent. They do not fold
their hands, do not look to heaven, rather, they are down here, what
they were and what they are.70
that were more like performances than the dry juristic drudgery his
father had forced on him during his brief career as an active law-
yer in Wetzlar 14 years before. The vast, enticing panoply of Italian
life contrasted sharply with the unnatural and darker complexion of
modern Christian art. In Bologna, he remarked that though faith
had raised the arts once again, superstition had become their ruler
and had brought them to ruin.72 It could be said that Italian life
reproduced for Goethe that mimetic quality with regard to nature
which the Sturm und Drang had valued both in Greek culture and
in that of the north. Yet the breadth of his vision and curiosity as
a traveler introduced a second, competing motif that was to act as
the second portal within his mind to the fruits of Greek antiquity
that could be discerned on Italian soil. There had been something
nebulous and fantastical about watching the ball game in Verona
and the court cases in Venice. And yet, as he wrote, “when one does
not proceed here with fantasy, but instead takes the surroundings
as real, as they are, so they become the decisive site, which makes
for the greatest deeds and thus I have always up to this point used
the geological and landscape points of view, in order to suppress the
imagination and sensibility und preserve for myself a clear overview
of the locality.”73
Goethe’s imagination inclined him to drink in and assimilate the
manifestations of vitality and hints of utopia that he encountered in
Italian life and which enchanted him in such small details as the ritual
of welcoming in the night with the exclamation felicissima notte! But
his ambition drove him toward an objective estimation of essential,
original, fundamental forms of life, instantiated in antiquity and to be
deciphered and recovered in the soil, the landscape, and the physiog-
nomy he so carefully observed at every station of his trip. These two
conflicting but complimentary approaches to the search for nature
and antiquity, a scientific attention to the landscape and a creative
imagination, were to yield a productive tension for the whole Italian
enterprise. Both of these approaches entailed throwing off the bur-
den of history, sometimes in a tone that anticipated the arguments
in Nietzsche’s Untimely Meditations, that we are weighed down and
stifled by an excess of historical knowledge.74 In Palermo, in April
1787, the landscape began to assume a greater spiritual and aesthetic
significance for Goethe. “The most beautiful spring weather and a
gushing fertility conveyed the feeling of a vivifying peace over the
whole valley, which the uncouth guide spoiled for me with his learn-
ing, recounting in detail how Hannibal once fought a battle here and
FROM STURM UND DR ANG TO ITALY 167
what great deeds of war took place on this spot. I curtly rejected the
dreadful recall of such departed phantoms.”75
Goethe’s Sicilian guide was perplexed that his charge would go off
and examine rocks rather than listen to tales of Hannibal’s martial
exploits. Just as Italy itself mediated the legacies of Greece, so rocks
and gardens evoked antiquity’s unreflective identity with nature.
Goethe’s companion by this stage was Christoph Heinrich Kniep, a
young painter. The public garden in Palermo, Goethe observed on
April 7, though of recent foundation, “places us in antiquity.” The
impression of this “marvelous garden” by the sea sat too deeply, he
reflected: “The black waves on the northern horizon, their struggle
at the bends of the bays, even the distinctive scent of the misty sea,
all of that recalled the blessed isle of Phaeacia to my senses as well as
my memory.” He rushed immediately “to buy a Homer,” to share
and read aloud a translation of that edifying song to Kniep, who
deserved to rest from his exertions with a good glass of wine. The
Homeric scene at the garden was immediately contrasted with the
“noisy joy about the happy resurrection of the Lord,” which began at
dawn on the day after Goethe visited the garden. The procession, he
wrote, could confuse the ears of those not used to such a noisy divine
worship.76
The belief that Homer could best be understood by an engage-
ment with the landscape and the wider geography in which the epics
were situated, and that an attentiveness to the contemporary life and
manners of the ordinary people of these places could yield a good
impression of the manners of Homer’s times, were the principal theses
advanced by the British traveler and antiquarian Robert Wood. His
book, An Essay on the Original Genius and Writings of Homer, had
been first circulated among friends in London in 1769 with an edi-
tion appearing in 1775.77 A German translation appeared in 1773.78
“A review of Homer’s scenes of actions,” Wood wrote in the preface,
“leads naturally to the consideration of the times, when he lived; and
the nearer we approach his country and age, the more we find him
accurate in his pictures of nature, and that every species of his exten-
sive Imitation furnishes the greatest treasure of original truth to be
found in any Poet, ancient or modern.” Thus Wood articulated an
almost Faustian inclination to arrive at the purest manifestation of an
original genius with an unsurpassed tact for nature and an unreflec-
tive truthfulness. The subject of the inquiry, Wood explained, was a
consideration of Homer’s “mimetic powers” and that “we shall admit
his ancient title of Philosopher only as he is a Painter.”79 At the same
168 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
his way back to Rome. The process must have been encouraged by
the fact that Johann Heinrich Tischbein painted the young woman
as Iphigenia.91 What a thousand artists would like to have achieved
was not just to be found in Hamilton’s companion but was also cap-
tured, as Winckelmann had asserted in 1755, in the works of Greek
sculpture, which united the scattered beauties of nature in a single
object. For Winckelmann, it was Greek beauty and the context that
produced it which was captured for the contemplation of posterity.
For Goethe, such works harbored fundamental, universal forms of
character; in other words, they could tell us much about human form
and character today. The point of departure was a principle, con-
tained in Herder’s Plastik, the essay on sculpture completed in 1778,
which contended that Greek sculpture was a powerful approximation
to truth in its portrayal of humanity and human expressions. Goethe
yearned to revive that truth and to approach it scientifically in the
present, to tease out all its secrets. From the pedagogical hopes of
Winckelmann, who wanted to educate artists in good taste, and from
the formative hopes of Herder, who wanted to aid a better contem-
plation of God’s manifestation in history, Goethe made Greece into
the potential source of vast knowledge. Ancient Greece had become
a key to unlock contemporary secrets of human form. This was the
Faustian turn in his relationship to Greece.
His addresses to Herder in the pages of the Italienische Reise
asserted that the possibility of such knowledge was premised on the
elimination of all that was arbitrary and superfluous in the contem-
plation of great art, of the landscape, and of antiquity. The kernel
of truth that remained, purged of all that oppressed and stifled the
natural vitality that connected contemporary Italy to ancient Greece
in his imagination, acquired something of an affinity to providence.
The existence of that kernel was thus not only a stimulus to research
and speculation but also a consolation and a resolution, an intimation
of and a companion to Herder’s theodicy and the ideas contained in
Karl Phillip Moritz’s work on Greek fable.92 Taking these two aspects
together, Goethe’s Philhellenism became a Faustian theodicy. It was
Faustian not least because the treasure trove of knowledge envisaged
in Rome and in the immediate post-Italian Weimar years remained
an ambition. For Herder, the theodicy in which Greek antiquity was
embedded and came to epitomize advanced two powerful ethical
motifs: freedom and the harmony of organic forces.
The problem of evil, of justifying or balancing the existence of
the destructive power manifested in nature and humanity, was ren-
dered all the more poignant by the devastating Lisbon earthquake
172 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
Karl Philipp Moritz. Goethe was delighted with them and wrote to
thank Herder, commenting on the happy contrast they provided to
the superstitious and overly doctrinal piety he often encountered
there. Moritz was in awe of Goethe, who became a venerated mentor,
and cited his poems frequently in the writings produced during, and
inspired by, his own stay in Italy. Early in September 1787, Goethe
reported that Herder’s Gott “had done Moritz a lot of good” and that
he “glowed in bright flames like well-dried wood,” having imbibed
Goethe’s own enthusiasm for it.99
Mortiz’s Über die bildende Nachahmung des Schönen was writ-
ten in 1788 and cited at length in Goethe’s Italienische Reise.100 His
Götterlehre oder Mythologischen Dichtungen der Alten was published
in 1790.101 These two works and Herder’s dialogues had principles in
common, which tied them to the enterprise of Herder’s philosophy
of history in the Ideen. They made more explicit some of the ideas
underlying the latter work. Both contained a theodicy that culmi-
nated in aesthetic analogies derived from Greek examples, whereby
the examples themselves possessed the didactic power, implicitly or
sometimes explicitly unique to Greek art and fable, to impart these
truths. Moreover, both emphasized, contrary to Kant, the self-
sufficiency of nature and of each manifestation of nature as morally
satisfying phenomena that were to be contemplated and enjoyed. The
object of that contemplation was ultimately a youthful vitality, the eter-
nal renewal of which, in a natural dialectic of creation and destruction,
constituted the consolation of existence, the philhellenic theodicy.
“The fine form of Apollo represents eternal youthful humanity,”
Moritz wrote in the Götterlehre, “which, like the leaves of an ever-
green tree, only retains its perennial bloom and lively color by means
of the gradual fall and destruction of wilting. Among the creations
of the ancients, this is one of the most sublime and lovely, because
she resolves the concept of destruction, without recoiling in hor-
ror, into the concept of youth and beauty and in this fashion gives
a harmonious tone to a fundamental opposition.” The ancients had
reached an ideal of beauty, Moritz averred, which contained within
itself everything else, the countenance of which filled the soul with
wonder because of its unending variety.102 The evocation of Apollo
would have particularly resonated with Goethe, who as Curtius, tells
us, always had Apollo with him.103 Even the Fates, the uncompromis-
ing minions of death, which in Wieland’s Alceste had inspired such
terror, were in Moritz’s rendering “after all, feminine and beauti-
fully formed, weaving and singing the song of the sirens.” It was the
“lightest work of feminine hands, whereby the secret course of things
174 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
in his creativity was a legacy of the Sturm und Drang. His creative
power had now become the medium through which the truths of
Herder’s theodicy could be apprehended. Its purest manifestations,
the images that brought that mediation to life, were drawn from
Greek art and fable.
Goethe’s relationship to human form as evoked by ancient sculp-
ture was more immediate in the physical sense, and more integrated
in the wider array of his scientific interests, in such a way as to give a
Faustian inflection to the theodicy he shared with Herder and Moritz.
During his second stay in Rome he surrounded himself with pieces of
sculpture, most notably the head of the Juno Ludovisi, which later had
a prominent place at his house on the Frauenplan in Weimar, where
he lived from 1792. Goethe could not know, Neutsch remarked, that
the Juno Ludovisi was not an image of a deity but rather the represen-
tation of a Roman princess. “It is remarkable,” he added, “with what
visionary gifts Goethe was able to discern, even in the faded Roman
image, the essence and form of the Greek original.”116 “When one
opens one’s eyes in the morning,” Goethe recalled in his later report
for April 1788 in Rome, “one feels touched by the highest; all our
thinking and feeling is accompanied by such forms, and it thereby
becomes impossible to fall back into barbarism.”117 This remark, as
Curtius pointed out, was in the tradition of the sentimental journeys
to Italy of the earlier eighteenth century, that of the contemplating
and experiencing subject. The traveler who reflected on and enjoyed
art out of “fundamental historical, philosophical or poetic convic-
tions” was at the heart of the narration.118 Rousseau’s postulate of
1755 that we are corrupted by our sense of sight was thereby tuned
into its opposite.
The redemptive and ennobling insight of 1788 was arrived at in
stages. “My greatest joy,” Goethe enthused in July 1787, “is that my
eye is being trained in true forms.” It reawakened, he said, his feeling
for deportment (Haltung) and for the whole. It was all about prac-
tice.119 That practice was not only part of his endeavor to understand
form, something related to his often frustrating efforts at improv-
ing his drawing. It was also akin to an initiation, by means of the
exalted sense of sight, into something divine. “I was with Angelika
[Kaufmann] in the Rondanini Palace,” Goethe reported at the end
of July. Kaufmann, a distinguished painter and collector, painted
portraits of Winckelmann and Goethe in Italy. Goethe respected her
opinion and her companionship in Rome was of great significance.
The Medusa in the Rondanini Palace now gave him the greatest ela-
tion, he said. “Just the idea that something like that is in the world,
FROM STURM UND DR ANG TO ITALY 177
that it was possible to make that, makes one doubly human.” What
words could express about such a work would be insignificant. Art
was not there to be spoken about, but to be seen.120
Early in September, Goethe remarked that Herder’s Gott had
“encouraged me to push deeper into natural matters.” His work on
botany had brought him closer to the insights of the dialogues that
each organism, each individual unit was complete in itself and repre-
sented the manifestation of God and that this was to be preferred to
the notion of a personal God who interfered in specific instances and
determined the course of events. He recounted that his search for the
principle that unlocked works of art, for which artists and critics had
been searching, was becoming clearer. The ancient artists, he said,
had just as great a knowledge of nature, and just as clear an idea as
Homer of what could be represented and how. These high works of
art were at the same time “the highest works of nature which men
had brought about according to true and natural laws. Everything
arbitrary, contrived is removed, there is necessity, there is God.”121
For Walther Rehm, these sentiments and Moritz’s work consti-
tuted the announcement of a “Greek-German humanist aesthetic
and ethic.”122 For the East German scholar Hans-Heinrich Reuter,
Goethe’s Italian journey was a purely aesthetic interest compared to
the genuinely ethical inspiration that Herder’s later stay in the same
country had brought about.123 Rehm’s Goethe was a seer, enlivened
from the beginning by a religious vocation of discovery and the Italian
journey was the pivotal episode of his development. The sacralization
of Greek art that Rehm’s Goethe effected like a philhellenic saint, was
the almost conscious creation of a German ethic and liturgy. Ludwig
Curtius’s Goethe was a much more sober inquirer than Rehm’s.
Iphigenia’s formula “searching for the land of the Greeks with the
soul” was Iphigenia’s and not his, Curtius asserted. Rather, Goethe
gained from antiquity in general the “free personal way of life” that
liberated him from the bourgeois convention of his social class and
from the lifestyle of his age.124 Curtius’s individual self-fashioning
and Rehm’s national-pedagogical message were thus two possibili-
ties of interpretation that pointed to different inflections within a
German humanism.
In April 1788, Goethe visited the French Academy in Rome with
his friend Heinrich Meyer, the painter and later renowned art histo-
rian who from then on would become his most trusted confidant in
matters of painting and sculpture.125 The reproductions of the best
statues of antiquity evoked the idea that the noblest preoccupation
was human form, which appeared there in all its manifold glory. And
178 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
yet, for all one’s preparation one felt at the same time “devastated”
in front of it. Form, he concluded, “encompassed everything; the
purposefulness of limbs, proportion, character and beauty.”126 Ernst-
Richard Schwinge has shown how this sense of an ancient purity of
form in art was valued by Goethe, particularly in the 1790s, in terms
of the genres of literature. The ancient Greeks had developed each
separate form, dramatic, epic, and lyrical, to its fullest manifestation,
whereas the moderns provided mixed pieces that adopted different
forms in the successive acts of a given piece.127
Schwinge’s Goethe struggled throughout his career with the
alternative between “idealizing” and “historicizing” approaches to
Greece. Yet it is perhaps more useful to see his relationship to Greece
as mediated by different artistic and philosophical imperatives at dif-
ferent periods. It was not a swing of the pendulum toward the idealis-
tic that brought about the idea that the secrets of Greek nature could
be at least partly retrieved by the contemplative pilgrim in the right
frame of mind. It was rather the inspiration of Herder’s idea of the
divinity instantiated in nature and its forces and the holistic under-
standing of the form of nature in botany, geology, and anatomy that
encouraged him to see Greek art and Greek naturalness as a mani-
festation of these truths. If the ethical and philosophical imperatives
that impelled his studies, exercises, and contemplation came from
Herder and his own attachment to a synthesis of natural sciences,
the faith in the purity of Greek form was supplied by a reading of
Winckelmann’s History of the Art of Antiquity, which he undertook in
1786–1787. Winckelmann’s careful discernment of the periods in the
history of art and the identification of the high points, as well as his
assertion that the depiction of deities was intended by the Greeks to
serve as universally valid portrayals of particular human characteris-
tics, were decisive in grounding that faith. But while scholarly interest
has focused on that grounding, it is the evolution of the ethical and
philosophical longings of the 1780s that lent Goethe’s experience and
reflections their distinctive purpose.
The ancient evocation of human form, with its universal, fine, and
precise grasp of everything that such form could convey appeared
to portent the threshold of a Faustian knowledge. It was the key to
understanding the relationship between art, nature, and necessity.
It would ennoble man, preclude barbarism, and provide true enjoy-
ment in producing and contemplating. All the Greek ethical values
and other types of excellence that the younger Herder and Lessing,
as well as Winckelmann had themselves evoked, the Greek sense for
measure and equilibrium, the truthfulness of sculpture, the youthful
FROM STURM UND DR ANG TO ITALY 179
Faust about his own condition once Mephistopheles was able to grant
so many of his wishes.15 But abandoning paradise by means of Kant’s
experiment, man “threw himself,” Schiller said, “into the wild game
of life, made his way into the dangerous path towards moral free-
dom.” Man’s disobedience against God in the Garden of Eden was
nothing less than his emancipation from instinct. It brought moral
evil into the creation but only in order to make possible moral good.
It was “the happiest and greatest event in the history of man; from
this moment is derived his freedom, here was laid the first, remote
foundation stone of his morality.”16
The consequences of the loss of paradise for the philosophy of
history and for the theodicy, in which ancient Greece had an enno-
bling or a redemptive message, were plain. The natural vitality in
which manifestations of Greek public life, like the Olympic Games
and contests of all kinds had been clothed, the mimetic relation-
ship to nature that the Sturm und Drang and subsequent thought
had celebrated and regarded as the threshold of ethical values, clus-
tered around the idea of balance and truthfulness, might now seen
as inimical to the awakening of man’s reason and the attainment of
moral freedom. Nature was now equated with the instinct a free,
reasoning being had left behind. Schiller’s lecture on the origins of
human society developed a dialectic between idleness and purposive
activity. The envy of the shepherd for the seemingly pleasant sed-
entary life of the farmer, the hunger that turned men into robbers,
and the adventures that turned robbers into heroes, were all features
of man’s freedom, of the “wild game” that would have led to new
institutions, monarchies, and states had it not been for the catas-
trophe of the flood, which filled Europe and Asia with wild beasts.
The early Greeks excelled in combating these beasts and Oedipus
became King of Thebes after defeating the Sphinx.17 The Greeks of
the heroic age thereby acquired, for Schiller, a place of honor at the
inception of that struggle between man’s idleness and his activity
that nascent reason had occasioned.
Schiller’s lecture, The Mission of Moses, was printed in early
September 1790 in Thalia.18 The title was a provocative variation
on the Anglican clergyman William Warburton’s Divine Legation
of Moses, published 1738–1741.19 By leaving out “divine” from his
title, Schiller was indicating his intention of challenging the story of
divine revelation and removing it from the narrative of early history.20
Presenting an account sympathetic to deism, Schiller resorted to the
idea, propagated by such seventeenth-century figures as John Toland
that the doctrine of the immortality of the soul was to be found
186 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
decline, which had kept them to itself, and made them the foundation
of the state. This was his great merit.
In August 1789, Schiller delivered a lecture entitled, “The leg-
islation of Lycurgus and Solon.”31 This was a concerted attempt to
apply to early Greek history the template of Kant’s conjectural nar-
rative and to delineate the struggles of a nascent freedom in its vari-
ous facets. Lycurgus had created a state admirable in many respects
for its political cohesion and discipline. The famous resistance of the
Spartans against the Persians at Thermopylae was the “most beauti-
ful memorial of political virtue.” And yet that impressive constitution
was in the highest measure objectionable, and the fate of man would
have been sad had all states been organized on this model. The state
could never be an end in itself, since the purpose of mankind was
the extension and application of all its capacities.32 The Spartan citi-
zen renounced friendship, maternal and conjugal love, for the sake of
citizenship. “A tender mother,” Schiller observed, “is by far a more
beautiful phenomenon in the moral world than a heroic hybrid being,
who denies natural sentiment.” Lycurgus had not only built a state
on the ruins of morality but had also designed its institutions to keep
Spartans permanently bound to the same stage of their political and
spiritual development.33 In decrying the extreme primacy of citizen-
ship, Schiller anticipated the arguments about the distinction between
ancient and modern freedom advanced by Benjamin Constant in his
lecture of 1816 “The Liberty of the ancients compared with that of
the moderns.”34
When one descends from our heights ever lower, William Tell
explained to his young son Walter in Schiller’s play Wilhelm Tell
finished in 1804, “one sees freely under all the heavens, the corn
grows in long, beautiful valleys and the land looks like a garden.”
Answering the boy’s question about why they did not at once descend
to these lands, Tell said that though the land may be beautiful, its
occupants did not enjoy the fruit of their toil. “Not free on their own
patrimony?,” asked the astonished Walter. The land, Tell said curtly,
belonged to the bishop and the king.35 The Swiss alpine republican-
ism embodied one kind of political freedom that Schiller discerned
in the contrast between Sparta and Athens. Solon, by contrast both
to Sparta and to earlier Athenian legislators like Draco, had a heart
“sensible to joy and love” and “some weaknesses of his youth made
him more considerate towards humanity and gave to his laws the
marks of leniency and mildness.” In cancelling debts in his famous
Seisachtheia, he only took from the rich the means to be unjust. The
land, which before was worked by slave hands, was now free and the
THE LOSS OF PARADISE AND THE HISTORY OF FREEDOM 189
citizen worked the fields as his own property, which he had previously
worked as a day laborer for his creditor.36
And yet Athenian republican freedom also evinced a “childish
mentality” in that citizens, who by means of extraordinary merit or
exceptional good fortune had risen to such great influence as was
incompatible with republican equality, were banished even before
they merited such banishment.37 This was the famous ostracism of
the Athenians. What Schiller regarded as the “childish politics” of
Athens was to be taken very seriously by Nietzsche as the guaran-
tor of the health and vitality of the Greek state. In the short essay
entitled, Homer on Competition, Nietzsche argued that all features of
Greek culture stemmed from the primacy of the contests. The truth
of this could be glimpsed by considering the original meaning of
ostracism. A fragment of Heraclitus, which Nietzsche quoted, said:
“Among us nobody should be the best; but if somebody is, let him
be somewhere else.” “Why should nobody be the best?,” Nietzsche
asked. The answer was that otherwise competition would dry up.38
For Schiller, then, Athenian political freedom, in its primitive charac-
ter was ambiguous, in that it embodied the young boy Walter’s idea of
property just as it applied the childish policy of ostracism and carried
out an act of injustice against individual citizens.
Two reflections at the conclusion of the lecture recalled the moral
freedom born of the dialectic between idleness or stagnation and
the purposive conscious activity of reason that he and Kant saw as
the kernel of truth in the story of the Fall. Ancient lawgivers had
the advantage over moderns, he observed, that they could form men
according to the content of their laws and united the citizen with the
person. Yet it was wrong to give to moral duties the compulsion of
law. Freedom was the precondition of the moral beauty of actions.39
The second reflection was that Lycurgus had commanded idleness
by the laws and Solon had punished it severely. Hence were born in
Athens all the virtues, trades, and arts and all the fields of wisdom.40
Lycurgus’s shortcoming was that he had closed his mind to posterity
and to the possibility of development. This was a fundamental differ-
ence with Herder’s philosophy of history. For Herder, to demand of
a lawgiver that he look consciously to posterity would be to detract
from the completeness of his own arrangement. It was that arrange-
ment, as conceived within the limited horizons of any given polity, in
and for itself, which Herder saw as the true bequest of each people.
Schiller instead looked to an ideal of freedom realized in installments,
releasing and encouraging the moral conscience of individuals with
ever greater consistency and sagacity.
190 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
depart from him. “If the modern stage only has this single fragment
to show, it could still triumph over the ancient.” The Genie of this
poet, Schiller enthused, who need fear no comparison with an ancient
tragedian, had united the finest fruit of moral refinement and the
most beautiful fruit of the poetic art, supported by the progress of
ethical culture and “the milder spirit of our times.” It was, moreover,
“a happy idea” that he had used the only possible space, madness
(Wahnsinn), to introduce our morals into the Greek world without
doing the least damage to it.47 The favorable comparison of Goethe
with Euripides was the beginning of a chain of ideas that were artic-
ulated in 1790, when Schiller delivered a lecture on the theory of
tragedy at Jena. This served as the basis of two essays finished in
1792 entitled On the Grounds of Enjoyment in Tragic Pieces and on the
Tragic Art. The revision of the material had followed an intense study
of Kant’s aesthetics early in 1791.48
The first dichotomy that began to ground the philosophical dis-
tinction between Greek antiquity and modernity was that between
the acceptance of fate and a teleological consciousness, outlined in
On Tragic Art. A “blind submissiveness to fate” was always humili-
ating and painful for a freely determined being, Schiller protested,
and it was that latter being that was missing in even the finest pro-
ductions of the Greek stage. The appeal to necessity in these pieces,
he observed, always left behind an unresolved knot. That knot was
loosened only when morally formed man climbed to the highest stage
to which he can rise through fine art (rührende Kunst). Even the dis-
content caused by fate lost itself in a “clear consciousness of the teleo-
logical connection of things, of a sublime order, of a good will. Greek
art never reached those heights, since neither the popular religion nor
even their philosophy was able to light their way that far ahead.”49
The philosophy that underlay his courses on universal history, with its
teleological affirmation of a present that was the product of struggles
for freedom like the Reformation and Thirty-Years War, was applied
to moral qualities of art. The moderns had the advantage over the
Greeks that they could imagine a chain of causes and events governed
by an uplifting end.
In On the Grounds of Enjoyment in Tragic Pieces, Schiller explained
a further reason for the repudiation of the centrality of fate. The
moral law, he explained, can only demonstrate the full extent of its
power when it is shown to be in conflict with all other natural forces
and the latter lose their hold over a human heart. This moral determi-
nation was at its most radiant, he elaborated, when it won the upper
hand against opposition. By natural forces was meant “everything
192 GERMAN PHILHELLENISM
that is not moral, everything that does not stand under the high-
est law-giving of reason: sentiments, drives, affects, passions, just as
physical necessity and fate. The greater the adversary the more glori-
ous the victory.” The highest consciousness of our moral nature, he
concluded, can only be obtained in a violent situation, in struggle and
the highest moral pleasure must therefore be accompanied by pain.50
The struggles of the generations that fought the wars of freedom
that Schiller the historian wrote about, the Thirty-Years War and the
Dutch Revolt, were superseded by qualitative advantages of the strug-
gle experienced in tragic art. Schiller implied that tragic art could
deliver a teleological vantage point and unfold the triumph of moral
freedom against natural instinct in a single performance. Moreover,
it could depict that struggle in the most exquisite fashion, choosing
each element of the plot for the most moving and edifying effect. Art
could stage the sublimity of the contests that engendered moral free-
dom with better exactitude and emotional poignancy than history.
The French Revolution and its presumed intellectual origins ren-
dered the division between nature and freedom more acute. Man
could not be ennobled by the demands of reason and the laws of
morality alone, since this did violence to his nature as a sensual,
physical being. But neither could he be left to the stifling tutelage of
nature, since that would be to forfeit his purpose as a rational being.
In the course of essays on aesthetics and poetics that appeared in
the mid-1790s, Schiller offered a solution to the dilemma. Drawing
on Kant’s Critique of Judgment, published in 1790, he argued that
it was the play of our faculties in experiencing aesthetic beauty that
allowed us to reconcile both sides of our being in a way that made us
conscious of acting for the future, toward the perfectibility of man. It
was in how we felt and thought about beauty that we could rediscover
at a higher level the harmony between nature and humanity that had
characterized the ancient world and especially Greece.
This project of reconciliation and higher unity was surrounded on
all sides by dangerous and enticing pitfalls. In his essay, On Naïve and
Sentimental Poetry, the extremes of these pitfalls were represented
by Goethe’s Werther and by Rousseau, two powerful and seductive
figures in the European literary mind in the years before the revo-
lution. The main problem these figures represented was either the
sentimental aspiration to return to the lost paradise that he and Kant
had shown had been abandoned for good, or the terrible effects of
sentimental discontent at the disunity between freedom and nature.
Two aspects of Schiller’s solution to this problem transformed the
character of Greece and reversed several value judgments of the
THE LOSS OF PARADISE AND THE HISTORY OF FREEDOM 193
Herder’s celebration of the Greek games, their vitality and the stark
contrast with the bloodthirsty gladiatorial spectacles of the Romans.
One will never go wrong, he mused, if one sought the ideals of
beauty that men had by asking how they satisfied their play drive.
The “bloodless contests of strength, speed, nimbleness and the noble
competition of talents” were, for Schiller, the Greek manifestations
of the play drive. Again, drawing on Winckelmann, he said that this
explained the quality of their art. The noble pursuits of this play drive
accounted for the pleasing features of the statues of the Greek dei-
ties.63 The portrayal of this early noble play drive rounded off the
image of the life in close proximity to nature of which Greek antiquity
was the highest example. Schiller borrowed the historical reasoning
of Winckelmann and Herder that attributed to Greek institutions,
like the games, the excellence of Greek art. Yet he saw that reality only
as a spur to the moderns to surpass its achievements, to add to the
laurels of the games the unmistakably modern accolade of individual
moral freedom.
In late July 1794, Schiller attended a lecture on natural science
at the University of Jena. One of the hearers was Goethe. They
walked out together, animatedly discussing the content of the lec-
ture. It was the first friendly encounter between the two poets. The
young Schiller had first glimpsed a rather aloof and stern Goethe at
Mannheim in 1781, shortly after his dramatic escape from Stuttgart.
Arriving in Weimar in 1787 while Goethe was still in Italy, Schiller
had been fed a dose of poisonous remarks about Goethe by the dis-
gruntled Charlotte von Stein: that he was ruining the mining works
in Ilmenau under his responsibility and that the duke had fallen out
with him. Their next encounter in 1788 was hardly warmer than the
first.64 Yet on August 23, about a month after the lecture, Schiller
wrote a letter to Goethe in which he outlined his idea of the latter’s
literary development. If you had been born a Greek, he said, every-
thing would have come to you effortlessly, but since you were born
a German, you have had to make your way back to Greek life with
a conscious effort of your Genie.65 Goethe was deeply moved by the
letter and replied that it had helped him overcome a serious bout of
doubt and anxiety.66 The letter developed the idea that Schiller had
begun to articulate in the Letters on the Aesthetic Education of Man
that the Genie was the mediator between historical epochs and liter-
ary styles.
It was at this point that the individual-esoteric origin of cultural
achievement and the transmission of wisdom, which had been hinted
at in the Letters, received its definitive sanction. It was a question that
THE LOSS OF PARADISE AND THE HISTORY OF FREEDOM 197
of the ancient world and the Greek proximity to nature, which was
evoked with such warmth in its pages, but with the distinctly modern
pathos of freedom, of what the free sentimental mind can resort to in
its despair. The Greek world, with its art, its vitality, and its religious
ideas was a static idyll, complete within itself. It was not Werther’s
reading of Homer but his passage onto Ossian that signified the new
burden of freedom. The Greek world had been closed and the Genie
that would shape the destinies of man for good or ill could neither
return to it nor be led astray by it.
effect and countereffect, assimilate the hidden, the still, the foun-
dation of appearance, “if one truly wants to see and imitate, that
which moves as a beautiful, single whole in lively waves before our
eyes.”109 It was a Faustian aspiration, seeking the interior founda-
tions, the organic substance of the edifying visual whole. Schlegel’s
active whole, depicted by the tragedian, was superseded in Goethe’s
mind by the human form, whose humanizing power he had expe-
rienced firsthand in Italy: “Any artist who has spent time in Italy
should ask himself whether the presence of the best works of ancient
and modern art have not stirred in him the endeavor to study and
recreate the human form in its proportions, forms, characters, to exert
himself in the execution with complete diligence and care, to approxi-
mate those works which entirely rest on themselves, to bring about
a work, which, in that it satisfies sensual vision, raises the spirit to its
highest reaches?”110
Schlegel, a reader of Schiller and Kant, yet acutely sensitive to
Winckelmann’s and Herder’s senses of Greek historicity, demanded a
more complex ethical good from Greek art and history than Goethe’s
release from oppressive powers like fate, guilt, and severity. Moreover,
contrary to the emphasis on Selbsttätigkeit or consciously willed activ-
ity, which Schlegel shared with Schiller, Goethe’s visual approxima-
tion to morality was one of aesthetic surrender.111 The best art, he
wrote in the Introduction, clasped our feelings and our imagination.
It took away our discretionary power and we could no longer do what
we wanted with that which is completeness. We are obliged to give
ourselves up to it, so that it may give us back to ourselves raised up
and improved.112 The poetological historian Schlegel reflected on the
embryonic moral freedom already portended in Greek tragedy, with
which the protagonists defied the empirical triumph of fate: “the calm
dignity of a beautiful disposition resolves the terrible struggle and
leads the bold preponderance which had violently broken through the
dam of order, once again into the mild pathway of the eternally tran-
quil law.”113 The poetological approximation to morality prescribed
a constancy that negated fate rather than an aesthetic surrender and
passivity.
German philhellenic thought had endured three losses of paradise
in the 1780s and 1790s, which affected it directly or indirectly: that
of the initial unity of sensuality and freedom in antiquity discerned so
poignantly by Schiller, that of the old order of Italy in the Napoleonic
invasion and his own departure felt by Goethe, and, finally, that her-
alded in Kant’s philosophy of history, taken up by Schiller, and cul-
minating in an affirmation of the Fall as the origin of conscious moral
THE LOSS OF PARADISE AND THE HISTORY OF FREEDOM 207
choice. The challenge to the unity of the Homeric epics was an addi-
tional threat of loss as well as incentive to produce, for Herder and
Goethe respectively. Goethe’s Propyläen project was a response that
sought to recover the humane, mitigating, and uplifting excellence
of Greece by understanding the foundations and relationships that
constituted its visual aesthetic. The Faustian premise was that Greece
was not trapped in the historicity in which Winckelmann and Herder,
in different ways, had enveloped it and that it was possible to peer into
the secrets that held it together and utilize them for the benefit of
mankind. Schlegel discerned in Greek literature the “pure and simple
elements in which one must analyze the mixed products of modern
poetics.” The character of each Greek poet was at the same time a
“pure and simple aesthetic fundamental knowledge.”114 Both Goethe
and Schlegel wanted to put the pieces of Greek aesthetic excellence
back together, an ambition that owed its scope and impulse to the
losses of paradise. Both sought to find in Greece, in human form and
literature respectively, the fundamental pieces of a new and universal
aesthetic for mankind.
The search for elemental forms contained within Greek art had
superseded the search for an understanding of the institutions that had
flourished around it and had made it possible. The recovery Greece by
looking within and dissecting the salient products of its art and litera-
ture for the sake of modern educational goals negated the holism that
the loss of paradise had been unable to sustain. It portended the later
dominance of a professional classical philology and in transcending
historicity by suggesting we could recover its basic units, it opened the
possibility of an intelligible dialogue between modern creativity and
ancient achievement. Here it stood on the threshold of Romanticism.
The intimation of such a dialogue had existed from the beginning
in the very processes that shaped earlier philhellenic thought, in the
Sturm und Drang and the personalities of the Genies. The formative
and historical power that Schiller attributed to the Genie in molding a
given period had added another layer to its plausibility. But it was only
in the late 1790s that the programmatic statements of Schlegel and
Goethe implicitly negated the Greek whole that their predecessors
and mentors had so painstakingly postulated, in order to make out
of the purer units a new synthesis, robust enough to make good the
losses and ruptures that history, politics, and philology had brought
about.
No tes
Introduction
1. See Katherine Harloe, Winckelmann and the Invention of Antiquity:
History and Aesthetics in the Age of Altertumswissenschaft (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2013) and Suzanne Marchand, Down from
Olympus: Archaeology and Philhellenism in Germany, 1750–1970
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996).
2. See Eliza Marian Butler, The Tyranny of Greece over Germany: A
Study of the Influence Exercised by Greek Art and Poetry over the Great
German Writers of the Eighteenth, Nineteenth and Twentieth Centuries
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1935) and Walther Rehm,
Griechentum und Goethezeit. Gechichte eines Glaubens (Leipzig:
Dietrich, 1936).
3. Interesting essay-length surveys of the German relationship to Greece
that link the eighteenth with the twentieth century are Brian Vick,
“Greek Origins and Organic Metaphors: Ideals of Cultural Autonomy
in Neohumanist Germany from Winckelmann to Curtius,” Journal of
the History of Ideas 63, no. 3 (2002), 483–500 and Manfred Landfester,
“Winckelmann und Nietzsche,” in Johann Joachim Winckelmann.
Seine Wirkung in Weimar und Jena, ed. Jü rgen Dummer (Stendal:
Winckelmann-Gesellschaft, 2007), 135–150.
54. Judith Shklar, “Rousseau’s Two Models: Sparta and the Age of Gold,”
Political Science Quarterly 1, no. 81 (1996), 25–51.
55. Herder, “Denkmal Johann Joachim Winckelmanns,” in Herder,
Werke, vol. 2, 643.
56. Ibid., 659–660.
57. Ibid., 664.
58. Ibid., 665.
59. Herder, “Auch eine Philosophie der Geschichte zur Bildung der
Menschheit,” in Herder, Werke, vol. 4, Schriften zu Philosophie, Literatur,
Kunst und Altertum, ed. Jürgen Brummack and Martin Bollacher
(Frankfurt am Main: Deutscher Klassiker Verlag, 1994), 9–108.
60. Beiser, The German Historicist Tradition, 138.
61. Herder, “Ä lteres Kritisches Wä ldchen,” 52–53.
62. Herder, “Auch eine Philosophie,” 28–29.
63. Rehm, Griechentum und Goethezeit, 59–86.
64. Herder, “Shakespeare,” in Herder, Werke, vol. 2, 498–549.
65. Herder, “Denkmal,” 672–673.
66. Herder, “Haben wir noch jetzt das Publikum und Vaterland der
Alten?,” in Herder, Werke, vol. 1, 40–56.
67. Herder, “Ursachen des gesunkenen Geschmacks, bei den Völkern da
er geblü het,” in Herder, Werke, vol. 4, 120.
68. Ibid., 121.
69. Ibid., 123.
70. Herder, “Auch eine Philosophie,” 26.
71. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der
Geschichte (Frankfurt: Sukrkamp, 1986), 297, 308–309.
72. Herder, “Auch eine Philosophie,” 28.
73. See Wilhelm von Humboldt, “Über die mä nnliche und weibliche
Form,” Die Horen 3 (1795), 80–103.
74. David Hume, “The Stoic,” in Essays Moral, Political and Literary, ed.
Hume (London: Cadell, 1793), vol. 1, 146–156.
75. See Christopher Brooke, Philosophic Pride: Stoicism and Political
Thought from Lipsius to Rousseau (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 2012).
76. See Wilhelm Heinse, Laidion oder die eleusinischen Geheimnisse
(Lemgo: Meyer, 1774).
77. Berger, Der junge Herder und Winckelmann, 14–15.
78. Winckelmann, Versuch, 76.
79. Schadewaldt, Winckelmann und Homer, 28.
80. On the Fragmente in relation to Greece see Aron, Die Erweckung,
77–98.
81. Adam Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, ed. Knud Haakonsen
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 37.
82. Simon Richter, Laocoon’s Body and the Aesthetics of Pain: Winckelmann,
Lessing, Herder, Moritz, Goethe (Detroit: Wayne State University Press,
1992), 13.
NOTES 217
86. For an account that emphasizes the “ideal whole” where the people
dominated Greek drama and which Schlegel read into Greek life
generally see Klaus Behrens, Friedrich Schlegels Geschichtsphilosophie
(1794–1808): ein Beitrag zur politischen Romantik (Tübingen:
Niemeyer, 1984).
87. Schlegel, Sämmtliche Werke, vol. 4, 97.
88. Ibid., 95.
89. Meiners, Geschichte des Weiblichen Geschlechts, vol. 1, 357.
90. Schlegel, Sämmtliche Werke, vol. 4, 101.
91. Ibid., 104.
92. For a later philhellenic account of the significance of the oracle see
Ernst Curtius, “Die Unfreiheit der alten Welt,” in Altherum und
Gegenwart: Gesammelte Reden und Vorträge, ed. Ernst Curtius
(Berlin: Hertz, 1875), 163–182.
93. Schlegel, Sämmtliche Werke, vol. 4, 105.
94. For the role of women in religious feasts see Pomeroy, Goddesses,
75–78.
95. Schlegel, Sämmtliche Werke, vol. 4, 106–108.
96. Ibid., 109.
97. Ibid., 110–111.
98. Ibid., 115.
99. Ibid., 133.
100. Ibid., 119.
101. Ibid., 130–131.
10. Ibid., 98 .
11. See Beiser, The German Historicist Tradition.
12. Boyle, Goethe, vol. 1, 99 .
13. Bernd Witte, “Goethe und Homer. Ein Paradigmenwechsel,” in
Goethes Rückblick auf die Antike, ed. Bernd Witte and Mauro Ponzi
(Berlin: Erich Schmidt, 1999), 23–24.
14. Boyle, Goethe, vol. 1, 197.
15. Valk, Der junge Goethe, 107–113.
16. Goethe, Werke vol. 28 ed. Wilhelm Große (Frankfurt: Deutscher
Klassiker Verlag, 1997).
17. Goethe, Die Leiden des jungen Werther, 73.
18. Goethe, “Der Triumph der Empfindsamkeit,” in Goethe, Sämmtliche
Werke, vol. 5, 83.
19. Boyle, Goethe, vol. 1, 194.
20. Goethe to Herder, July 10 1772. Goethe, Werke vol. 28, 255–256.
21. Mauro Ponzi, “Eines Schattens Traum: Goethe und Pindar,” in
Goethes Rückblick auf die Antike, ed. Bernd Witte and Mauro Ponzi
(Berlin: Erich Schmidt, 1999), 39–57.
22. Johann Gottfried Herder, “Shakespeare,” in Herder, Werke in zehn
Bänden, vol. 2, 525–527.
23. Ibid., 520.
24. Montesquieu, Persian Letters, trans. Margaret Mauldon (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2008), 175.
25. For a survey of the history of the appraisals of Athenian democracy,
particularly in the modern history of ideas see Jennifer T. Roberts,
Athens on Trial: The Antidemocratic Tradition in Western Thought
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994).
26. On rise of Academies and on Leibniz see Dilthey, “Das achtzehnte
Jahrhundert und die geschichtliche Welt.”
27. Johann Gottfried Herder, Vom Einfluß der Regierung auf die
Wissenschaften und der Wissenschaften auf die Regierung (Berlin:
Decker, 1781) and Christoph Meiners, Geschichte des Ursprungs,
Forgangs und Verfalls der Wissenschaften in Griechenland und Rom,
vol. 1 (Lemgo: Meyer, 1781).
28. Meiners, “Vorrede,” in Meiners, Geschichte des Ursprungs.
29. See Edward Gibbon, Essai sur l’étude de la littérature (London:
Becket and Hondt, 1762).
30. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, “Discourse on the Sciences and Arts,” in
Rousseau, The Discourses and Other Early Political Writings, 9.
31. See Sheehan, The Enlightenment Bible, 160–168.
32. Ibid., 159.
33. This was a rivalry more common in terms of poetry where Athens was
often explicitly juxtaposed to Jerusalem. This is discussed by Sheehan
and in the case of baroque and Enlightenment Germany by Joachim
Dyck, Athen und Jerusalem: Die Tradition der argumentativen
NOTES 237
Verknüpfung von Bibel und Poesie im 17. und 18. Jahrhundert (Munich:
Beck, 1977).
34. Herder, “Vom Einfluss,” 10 . “Alles mag die Kunst schaffen können,
nur nicht Natur.”
35. Ibid, 16.
36. On the relationship between Herder and Rousseau see the long and
detailed treatment by Hans M. Wolff, “Der junge Herder und die
Entwicklungsidee Rousseaus,” Publications of the Modern Language
Association 57 (1942), 753–819.
37. Herder, “Vom Einfluss,” 23 .
38. Herder, “Vom Einfluss,” 24. “Die Regierung unter der allein Natur,
rechtes Ma ß und Verhä ltnis stattfindet ist, -Freiheit.”
39. Meiners, Geschichte des Ursprungs, 1.
40. Ibid.
41. Herder, “Vom Einfluss,” 27 .
42. Meiners, Geschichte des Ursprungs, vol. 2, 2.
43. Johann Gottfried Herder, “Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte
der Menschheit,” in Herder, Werke in Zehn Bänden vol. 6, Ideen
zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit ed. Martin Bollacher
(Frankfurt am Main: Deutscher Klassiker Verlag, 1989), 568.
44. See the introduction in Beiser, The German Historicist Tradition.
45. Hans-Dietrich Irmscher, “Die geschichtsphilosophische Kontroverse
zwischen Kant und Herder,” in Hamann, Kant, Herder: Acta des
vierten Internationalen Hamann-Kolloquiums im Herder-Institut zu
Marburg/Lahn 1985, ed. Bernhard Gajek (Frankfurt am Main: P.
Lang, 1987), 113.
46. Hans-Dietrich Irmscher, “Goethe und Herder- eine schwier-
ige Freundschaft,” in Johann Gottfried Herder: Aspekte seines
Lebenswerkes, ed. Martin Kessler and Volker Leppin (Berlin and New
York: De Gruyter, 2005), 256.
47. Irmscher, “Die geschichtsphilosophische Kontroverse,” 119.
48. Immanuel Kant, “Review of Herder’s Ideas on the Philosophy of the
History of Mankind,” in Immanuel Kant, Political Writings, ed. H.
S. Reiss (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 201–220.
49. Irmscher, “Die geschichtsphilosophische Kontroverse,” 128–131.
50. See Irmscher, “Nationalität und Humanität im Denken Herders,”
Orbis Littterarum 49 (1994), 189–215.
51. On the problem of sociability in the eighteenth century, see John
Robertson, The Case for the Enlightenment: Scotland and Naples
1680–1760 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007) and
Brooke, Philosophic Pride.
52. Irmscher, “Goethe und Herder,” 239.
53. Herder, “Ideen,” 523.
54. Ibid., 527.
55. Ibid., 550–551.
238 NOTES
Primary Literature
Abel, J. J., Historisches Gemälde der Lage und des Zustandes des weiblichen
Geschlechts unter allen Völkern der Erde von den ältesten bis auf die neues-
ten Zeiten (Leipzig: Schumann, 1803).
Acosta, José de, Historia natural y moral de las indias. En que se tratan de
las cosas notables del cielo, elementos, metales, plantas y animales dellas y de
los ritos y ceremonias, leyes y gobierno de los indios, ed. Mart í Soler (Mexico
City: Fondo de cultura económica, 2006).
Bachofen, Johann Jacob, Die lex Voconia und die mit ihr zusammenhängenden
Rechtsinstitute, eine rechtshistorische Abhandlung (Basel: Schweighausers
Buchhandlung, 1843).
———, Johann Jakob Bachofens Gesammelte Werke, ed. Ernst Howald (Basel:
Benno Schwabe, 1954).
Barthélemy, Jean-Jacques, Voyage du jeune Anacharsis en Grèce dans le milieu
du IVe siècle avant l’ère vulgaire (Paris: Didier, 1843).
Beloch, Karl Julius, Griechische geschichte (Strassburg: K. J. Tr übner,
1912–1927).
Böttiger, Karl August, “Die Revolutionsdammen im neuen Paris und im
alten Rom,” Neuer Teutscher Merkur I (1794), 68–88.
———, “Waren die Athenierinnen wirklich vom Theater ausgeschlossen?,”
Teutscher Merkur (1797), 224–233.
———, “Waren die Frauen in Athen Zuschauerinnen bei den dramatischen
Vorstellungen?,” Teutscher Merkur (January 1796), 23–46.
Brandes, Ernst, Über die Weiber (Leipzig: Weidmann Erben und Reich,
1787).
Brown, John, A Dissertation on the Rise, Union and Power, the Progressions,
Separations and Corruptions, of Poetry and Music (London: L. Davis and
C. Reymers, Royal Society, 1763).
Brumoy, Pierre, Théâtre des Grecs (Paris: Cussac, 1785–1789).
Caylus, Anne Claude Philippe, Recueil d’antiquités egyptiennes, etrusques,
greques et romaines (Paris: Desaint & Saillant, 1752–1767).
Chardin, Jean, Journal du voiage du Chevalier Chardin en Perse (Amsterdam:
Jean Wolters & Ysbrand Haring, 1686).
Constant, Benjamin, Political Writings, ed. Biancamaria Fontana
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988).
246 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Lenz, Carl Gotthold, Über Rousseaus Verbindung mit Weibern: mit einer
Abhandlung über den Geist und die Geschichte der Rousseauischen
Bekenntnisse und einigen Beylagen (Leipzig: Reinicke, 1792).
Lessing, Gotthold Ephraim, Werke und Briefe in zwölf Bänden, ed. Wilfried
Barner et al, (Frankfurt: Deutscher Klassiker Verlag, 1985–2003).
Mä hly, Jacob August, Die Frauen des griechischen Alterthums. Eine Vorlesung
(Basel: J. J. Mast, 1853).
Mann, Thomas, Der Tod in Venedig in Gesammelte Werke, vol. 8 (Frankfurt
am Main: Fischer, 1974), 444–525.
Meiners, Christoph, “Beitrag zur Geschichte der Behandlung des weibli-
chen Geschlechts bei verschiedenen Völkern,” Berlinische Monatsschrift
(1787), 105–117.
———, “Betrachtungen über die Mä nnerliebe der Griechen, nebst einem
Auszüge aus dem Gastmahle des Plato,” in Vermischte philosophische
Schriften, ed. Christoph Meiners (Leipzig: Weygand, 1775).
———, Geschichte des Luxus der Athenienser von den ältesten Zeiten an bis
auf den Tod Philipps von Macedonien (Cassel: Hamper, 1781).
———, Geschichte des Ursprungs, Fortgangs und Verfalls der Wissenschaften
in Griechenland und Rom, vol. 1 (Lemgo: Meyer, 1781).
———, Geschichte des Weiblichen Geschlechts, vol. 1 (Hannover: Verlag der
Helwingschen Hofbuchhandlung, 1788).
———, Grundriss der Geschichte der Menschheit (Lemgo: Meyer, 1785).
Millar, John, Observations Concerning the Distinction of Ranks in Society
(Dublin: Ewing, 1771).
Montesquieu, Charles-Louis de Secondat, Baron de la Brede et de,
Considerations on the Causes of the Greatness of the Romans and Their
Decline, trans. David Lowenthal (Indianpolis and Cambridge: Hackett,
1965).
———, Persian Letters, trans. Margaret Mauldon (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2008).
———, The Spirit of the Laws, ed. Anne M. Cohler, Basia C. Miller, and
Harold S. Stone (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989).
Moritz, Karl Philipp, Werke, ed. Horst Gü nther (Frankfurt am Main: Insel,
1981).
Mosheim, Johann Lorenz, Sittenlehre der heiligen Schirft (Helmstadt:
Weygand, 1753–1770), vol. 5, 1762.
Nietzsche, Friedrich, Sämtliche Werke: Kritische Studienausgabe, ed. Giorgio
Colli und Mazzino Montinari (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1988).
———, On the Genealogy of Morality, ed. Keith Ansell-Pearson (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1994).
Pauw, Cornelius de, Philosophical Dissertations on the Greeks (London:
Faulder, 1793).
Reinhold, Karl, Die Hebräischen Mysterien oder die älteste religiöse Freymauerei
(Leipzig: Göschen, 1788).
Reitemeier, Johann, Geshichte und Zustand der Sklaverey und Leibeigenschaft
in Griechenland (Berlin: August Mulius, 1789).
BIBLIOGRAPHY 249
Secondary Literature
Adorno, Theodor W., “Zum Klassizismus von Goethes Iphigenie,” in Noten
zur Literatur, ed. Theodor W. Adorno (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp,
1981), 495–514.
Alt, Peter-André, Friedrich Schiller (Munich: Beck, 2004).
Ardener, Edwin, “Belief and the Problem of Women,” in The Interpretation of
Ritual: Essays in Honour of A. I. Richards, ed. J. S. La Fontaine (London:
Tavistock, 1972), 135–155.
Aron, Erich, Die Erweckung des Griechentums durch Winckelmann und
Herder (Heidelberg: Kampann, 1929).
Baeumer, Max, “Winckelmanns Formulierung der klassischen Schönheit,”
Monatshefte 65, no. 1 (1973), 61–75.
Baeumler, Alfred, Das mythische Weltalter (Munich: Beck, 1965).
Behler, Ernst, “Einleitung,” in Behler ed., Kritische Friedrich-Schlegel-
Ausgabe.
Behrens, Klaus, Friedrich Schlegels Geschichtsphilosophie (1794–1808): ein
Beitrag zur politischen Romantik (Tübingen: Niemeyer, 1984).
Beiser, Frederick, Enlightenment, Revolution and Romanticism: Genesis of
Modern German Political Thought, 1790–1800 (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1992).
———, The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987).
———, The German Historicist Tradition (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2011).
Berger, Arnold, Der junge Herder und Winckelmann (Halle: Niemeyer, 1903).
BIBLIOGRAPHY 251
Robertson, John, The Case for the Enlightenment: Scotland and Naples 1680–
1760 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007).
R üdiger, Horst, “Winckelmanns Geschichtsauffassung: Ein Dresdner
Entwurf als Keimzelle seines historischen Denkens,” Euphorion 62
(1968), 99–116.
Safranski, R üdiger, Goethe und Schiller. Geschichte einer Freundschaft
(Munich: Hanser, 2009).
Schadewaldt, Wolfgang, Winckelmann und Homer (Leipzig: Barth, 1941).
Schmitt, Aborgast, “‘Antik’ und ‘modern’ in Schillers Über naive und sen-
timentalische Dichtung,” in Friedrisch Schiller und die Antike, ed. Paolo
Chiarini and Walter Hinderer (Wü rzburg: Königshausen und Neumann,
2008), 259–298.
Schmitt, Carl, Politische Romantik (Munich: Duncker & Humblot, 1925).
Schönborn, Sybille, “Vom Geschlechterkampf zum symbolischen
Geschlechtertausch: Goethes Arbeit am antiken Mythos am Beispiel der
Iphigenie auf Tauris,” in Goethes Rückblick auf die Antike, ed. Bernd
Witte and Mauro Ponzi (Berlin: Erich Schmidt, 1999), 83–100.
Schrader, Hans-Jü rgen, “Götter, Helden und Waldteufel: Zu Goethes Sturm
und Drang-Antike,” in Goethes Rückblick auf die Antike, ed. Bernd Witte
and Mauro Ponzi (Berlin: Erich Schmidt, 1999), 59–82.
Schuller, Wolfang, Die Welt der Hetären: Berühmte Frauen zwischen Legende
und Wirklichkeit (Stuttgart: Klett Cotta, 2008).
Schwinge, Ernst-Richard, ed., “Uralte Gegenwart ”: Studien zur
Antikerezeption in Deutschland (Freiburg im Breisgau: Rombach, 2011).
Selle, Götz von, Die Georg-August-Universität zu Göttingen. 1737–1937
(Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1937).
Sheehan, Jonathan, The Enlightenment Bible: Translation, Scholarship,
Culture (Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2005).
Shklar, Judith, “Rousseau’s Two Models: Sparta and the Age of Gold,”
Political Science Quarterly 1, no. 81 (1996), 25–51.
Sichtermann, Helmut, “Lessing und die Antike,” in ed. Jungius Gesellschaft
Lessing und die Zeit der Aufklärung (Göttingen: Vandenheock und
Rupprecht, 1968), 168–191.
Sondermann, E. F., Karl August Böttiger: Literarischer Journalist der
Goethezeit in Weimar (Bonn: Bouvier, 1983).
Sonenscher, Michael, Sans-Culottes: An Eighteenth-Century Emblem in the
French Revolution (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008).
Staiger, Emil, Goethe 1749–1786 (Zü rich: Atlantis, 1957).
Starobinsky, Jean, “Eloquence and Liberty,” Journal of the History of Ideas
38, no. 2 (1977), 195–210.
Stieglitz, C. L., Archaeologie der baukunst der Griechen und Römer. Zweyter
Theil, Erste Abtheilung (Weimar: Verlag des Industrie-Comptoirs, 1801).
Stollberg-Rilinger, Barbara, “Väter der Frauengeschichte? Das Geschlecht
als historiographische Kategorie im 18. und 19. Jahrhundert,” Historische
Zeitschrift 62 (1996), 39–71.
BIBLIOGRAPHY 257
Christianity, 12, 15, 16, 147–8, and history, 59, 65–6, 69, 76–81
166, 167, 186 and symbols, 44
and death, 55, 114, 165 Euripides, 50, 100, 126, 141, 191
and friendship, 34–6 Iphigenia in Aulis, 107–8,
Cicero, Marcus Tullius, 48 114–19, 121, 127, 190
Clytemnestra, 94, 99, 100, 108, and Schiller, 110, 116
116, 136
competition, 9, 22, 31, 33, 161, fate, 48–9, 51, 53–5, 68, 99, 173–4
189, 196. See also body, and Goethe, 133–5, 203
friendship, games, sensuality in theatre, 108, 114–15, 117, 191
Constant, Benjamin, 188 femininity. See also women,
Constantine, David, 203 friendship
courtesans. See Hetaerae Greek, 58–9, 62, 99, 101–5
Curtius, Ernst (1814–1896), 34 religious power of, 68–9, 71, 86,
Curtius, Ludwig, 162–4, 176–7 89, 93, 103, 132, 139–40,
death 144, 147
ancients and, 52–5, 114, 165 Fontius, Martin, 11
in philhellenic theatre, 113, Forster, Georg, 77, 79, 96
125–8, 133 freedom
in ancient Greece, 30–1, 120,
Decultot, Elisabeth, 11 155–60, 188–9
democracy, 30, 70, 83, 87, 96, 102, in morality, 110–14, 159, 182–5,
104–5, 156 189, 191–3
Derschau, Christoph Friedrich, French Revolution, 96, 190,
122–3 192, 194–5
Diderot, Denis, 6, 21 friendship
Dilthey, Wilhelm, (1833–1911) 17, between men in ancient Greece,
27–8, 30, 68 33–7, 94–5, 98, 169, 203
Diotima, 58, 75, 81, 83. See also between Orestes and Pylades,
Schlegel, Friedrich 119, 121–3
Dubos, Jean-Baptiste Winckelmann and, 7, 34–6
(1670–1742), 11
duty, 110, 113–14, 130, 132 games, 9, 22, 50, 66, 95, 161, 196
Genie, 3, 42, 109, 153–5,
education, 12. See also women 167–8, 175–6
Egypt, 16, 40 in philosophy of history, 152,
Empfindsamkeit, 125–6 190–1, 195–8
Enlightenment, 28–9, 41, 133 George-Kreis, 17, 141
and historiography, 2, 12, 37, George, Stefan, 35, 141
67, 75 Gesner, Johann Mathias, 36
Epaminondas, 17, 23, 33, 34, 37 Gibbon, Edward, 34, 68
Ephraim, Charlotte, 47 God, 15, 109, 111, 137, 151, 153,
Eros, 17 173–5, 177, 187, 200
ethics Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von
and ancient Greece, 5 (1749–1832)
INDEX 261