Benjamin Cardozo'S Opinion On Judicial Process: Name-Queency Pereira Fyll.M
Benjamin Cardozo'S Opinion On Judicial Process: Name-Queency Pereira Fyll.M
BENJAMIN
CARDOZO’S
OPINION ON
JUDICIAL PROCESS
TABLE OF CONTENTS
1 Introduction 3
8 Bibliography 34
3
CHAPTER 1
INTRODUCTION
Benjamin Nathan Cardozo (May 24, 1870 – July 9, 1938) was an American jurist
who served on the New York Court of Appeals and later as an Associate Justice of the
modesty, philosophy, and vivid prose style. Cardozo served on the Supreme Court
only six years, from 1932 until his death in 1938, and many of his landmark decisions
were delivered during his eighteen-year tenure on the New York Court of Appeals,
Cardozo was born in New York City, the son of Rebecca Washington and Albert
Jacob Cardozo. Both Cardozo's maternal grandparents, Sara Seixas and Isaac Mendes
Seixas Nathan, and his paternal grandparents, Ellen Hart and Michael H. Cardozo,
were Sephardi Jews of the Portuguese Jewish community, affiliated with Manhattan's
Congregation Shearith Israel; their families emigrated from England before the
American Revolution, and were descended from Jews who left the Iberian Peninsula
for Holland during the Inquisition.[Cardozo family tradition held that their ancestors
were Marranos from Portugal although Cardozo's ancestry has not been firmly traced
Benjamin Cardozo was a twin with his sister Emily. He was a cousin of the poet
Emma Lazarus. He was named for his uncle, Benjamin Nathan, a vice president of the
New York Stock Exchange and the victim of a famous unsolved murder case in 1870.
Albert Cardozo, Benjamin Cardozo's father, was a judge on the Supreme Court of
New York (the state's general trial court) until he was implicated in a judicial
corruption scandal, sparked by the Erie Railway takeover wars, in 1868. The scandal
led to the creation of the Association of the Bar of the City of New York and Albert's
resignation from the bench. After leaving the court, he practiced law until his death in
1885.
Early years
Rebecca Cardozo died in 1879 when Benjamin was young. He was raised during
much of his childhood by his sister Nell, who was 11 years older. One of his tutors
was Horatio Alger.At age 15, Cardozo entered Columbia University where he was
elected to Phi Beta Kappa,and then went on to Columbia Law School in 1889.
Cardozo wanted to enter a profession that could materially aid himself and his
siblings, but he also hoped to restore the family name, sullied by his father's actions as
a judge. When Cardozo entered Columbia Law School, the program was only two
years long; in the midst of his studies, however, the faculty voted to extend the
program to three years. Cardozo declined to stay for an extra year, and thus left law
school without a law degree. He passed the bar in 1891 and began practicing appellate
law alongside his older brother. Benjamin Cardozo practiced law in New York City
5
until 1914. In November 1913, Cardozo was narrowly elected to a 14-year term on the
In February 1914, Cardozo was designated to the New York Court of Appeals under
the Amendment of 1899, and reportedly was the first Jew to serve on the Court of
Appeals. In January 1917, he was appointed to a regular seat on the Court of Appeals
to fill the vacancy caused by the resignation of Samuel Seabury, and in November
1917, he was elected on the Democratic and Republican tickets to a 14-year term on
the Court of Appeals. In 1926, he was elected, on both tickets again, to a 14-year term
as Chief Judge. He took office on January 1, 1927, and resigned on March 7, 1932 to
His tenure was marked by a number of original rulings, in tort and contract law in
particular. This is partly due to timing; rapid industrialization was forcing courts to
look anew at old common law components to adapt to new settings. In 1921, Cardozo
gave the Storrs Lectures at Yale University, which were later published as The Nature
of the Judicial Process (On line version), a book that remains valuable to judges
today. Shortly thereafter, Cardozo became a member of the group that founded the
American Law Institute, which crafted a Restatement of the Law of Torts, Contracts,
and a host of other private law subjects. He wrote three other books that also became
the federal courts, and stated that: "The criminal is to go free because the constable
has blundered." He noted that many states had rejected the rule, but suggested that the
adoption by the federal courts would affect the practice in the sovereign states.
In 1932, President Herbert Hoover appointed Cardozo to the Supreme Court of the
United States to succeed Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes. The New York Times said of
Cardozo's appointment that "seldom, if ever, in the history of the Court has an
a Republican president has been referred to as one of the few Supreme Court
the nominee's contribution to law. However, Hoover was running for re-election,
eventually against Franklin Roosevelt, so a larger political calculation may have been
operating.
Cardozo was confirmed by a unanimous voice vote in the Senate on February 24. On
"the finest act of his career as President".The entire faculty of the University of
Chicago Law School had urged Hoover to nominate him, as did the deans of the law
schools at Harvard, Yale, and Columbia. Justice Harlan Fiske Stone strongly urged
Hoover to name Cardozo, even offering to resign to make room for him if Hoover had
7
his heart set on someone else (Stone had in fact suggested to Calvin Coolidge that he
should nominate Cardozo rather than himself back in 1925). Hoover, however,
originally demurred: there were already two justices from New York, and a Jew on
the court; in addition, Justice James McReynolds was a notorious anti-Semite. When
the chairman of the Senate Foreign Relations Committee, William E. Borah of Idaho,
added his strong support for Cardozo, however, Hoover finally bowed to the pressure.
Cardozo was a member of the Three Musketeers along with Brandeis and Stone,
which was considered to be the liberal faction of the Supreme Court. In his years as an
Associate Justice, he handed down opinions that stressed the necessity for the tightest
Death
In late 1937, Cardozo had a heart attack, and in early 1938, he suffered a stroke. He
died on July 9, 1938, at the age of 68 and was buried in Beth Olam Cemetery in
Queens. His death came at a time of much transition for the court, as many of the
other justices died or retired during the late 1930s and early 1940s. 1
1
en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Benjamin_N._Cardozo
8
CHAPTER 2
Benjamin N. Cardozo book the nature of judicial process deals with four chapters: 1.
The Method of Philosophy; II. TheMethods of History, Tradition and Sociology; III.
Benjamin Cardozo’s discussion on the nature of the judicial process begins with a
series of questions asking precisely what a judge does when he decides a case. In the
for guidance? In what proportions do I permit them to contribute to the result? In what
He sees as the force formulating "judge made law" some principle whether it is
judge in arriving at decisions in appellate cases are latent within the cases, and they
may be separated and classified. Of the subconscious forces which lie behind a judge's
decision he says: "All their lives, forces which they do not recognize and cannot
sense in James' phrase of the total push and pressure of the cosmos,” 3 Which, when
2
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 10
3
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 13
9
reasons are nicely balanced, must determine where choice will fall.-These
subconscious forces, however, and their influence in decision, were never treated very
completely by Cardozo. The questionnaires as to where the law is to be found that the
judge will apply. Cardozo does not deny that when constitution and statute are clear,
the judge' s search is at an end. In this event the role of the judge becomes secondary.
But not so clear is the area left by the gaps in the law. For these exigencies he
advocates a method of interpretation by the judges within the interstitial limits of the
Jus scriptum suggested by Geny and Ehrlich “ a method of free decision- Libre
important to note that Cardozo is urging this method of free decision in the instance
where statute and constitution fail. At this point the common law as interpreted by the
judge comes into play in filling the gap. He freely admits that stare decisis is “at least
the everyday working rule” 6 of the law. Yet he sees the method of free decision as the
process that gives a system of living law. Finally, he points to the need for a guide to
govern the choice of the judgments potentially applicable in a given case, in order that
the judgment rendered is not the personal whim or caprice of the judge.
Cardozo warns that common law, though a gradual development of judicial decisions
over the years, does not work from “pre-established truths of universal and inflexible
4
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 16
5
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 18
6
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 20
10
inductively, moving from the particular to the general. He observes the phenomenon
and ones allowed, is now prohibited, rights of action, formerly non-assignable, may
now be assigned. He has seen the process of gradual change in man-made law come
full circle, holding something lawful that was formerly unlawful, and it prompts the
remark: “nothing is stable. Nothing is absolute. All is fluid and changeable.” 8 There is
ceaseless change in law, the need for a stability upon which to predicate decision
“He must first extract from the precedent the underlying principle, the ratio decidendi,
he must then determine the path or the direction along which the principle is to move
or develop, if it is not to wither and die”. 9 He does not dwell long on the first part of
the judge’s method, the extraction of the principle from the cases decided in the past,
but turns quickly to his main concern, the application of the principles extracted to the
case before the judge. Edwin Patterson has observed, concerning the lectures
comprising the Nature of the Judicial Process, that they are “the most philosophically
native and yet the most vigorous and constructive of the three books” which Cardozo
wrote on the philosophy of law. The vigour and urgency of this work stems from the
7
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 22
8
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 28
9
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 28
11
formulation of what have now become the famous four methods of applying a
Cardozo states the four methods: “the directive force of principle may be exerted
along the line of logical progression, this I will call the rule of analogy or the method
of philosophy, along the line of historical development, this I will call the method of
evolution, along the line of the customs of the community this I will call the method
of tradition, along the line of justice, morals and social welfare, the mores of the day,
and this I will call the method of sociology. 10” These methods outlined, he turns to the
Cardozo treats the method of philosophy first because it has certain “presumption” in
its favour. “it has the primacy,” he says “that comes from natural and logical and
development”. 12 In the absence of some sufficient reason to the contrary, the method
of philosophy is to be used. It might seem that for Cardozo the method of philosophy
simply logic. But perhaps his real thought may be found in his observation on the
need for the use of this “logical” method”: “adherence to precedent must then be the
rule rather than the exception if litigants are to have faith in the even-handed
administration of justice in the courts. 13” Thus Cardozo did not simply equivalent
philosophy and logic, but rather considered that simple adherence to precedent was a
logical, and hence a philosophical, approach. Moreover, it seems that in this method
10
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 30 &31
11
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 31
12
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 32
13
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 34
12
Cardozo saw a partial solution to the problem of giving stability to judge-made law.
He views the work of the judge in applying this method as the task of “keeping the
To describe Further the method of philosophy he turns to case in which the method is
applied. The cases analysed are predominantly those in which a strictly logical and
unbending application of a principle of law has worked a grave injustice, or that class
when two lines of logical progression converges, both stemming from an established
legal principle, that “history or custom or social utility or some compelling sentiment
of justice.....must come to the rescue of the anxious judge, and tell him where to go.
He realizes that sentiment cannot yield to logic and the reason must control the play of
sentiment. Justice and sentiment guide in the choice between the two principles, and
reason “in its turn reacted upon sentiment by purging it of what is arbitrary, by
Cardozo points out that the misuse of this method of Philosophy “being when its
method and its ends are treated as supreme and final. 16” With Geny, he recognizes the
need for a human positive law that grows with the times. The method of philosophy
will furnish in part that principle of growth for human positive law. For the essence of
14
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 35
15
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 45
16
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 46
13
the germ of the conclusion.” 17 It will be interesting for one reading Cardozo’s first
17
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 49
14
CHAPTER 3
Cardozo describes the other three methods or principles of selection guiding the judge
in the path of developing the system of living law. This is the methods of history,
custom and sociology. It does not delay long on the method of history, For him the
method of philosophy or the logic which is mainly the work of reason. It is clear that
problem in law rather than solving it. Equally clear is Cardozo’s refusal to approve of
F.C. Von Savigny (1779-1861). Of this historical school A.P.D “Entreves has this to
say:
“ the historical school had begun by stressing the growth and development of law, it
ended by fostering its scientific study. It had begun with an apology for history. It
Cardozo did not give his approval. For him the duties of a judge went beyond bare
Cardozo admits that the development of positive law has taken place in a historical
context. He realizes also that the development of positive law considered apart from
that context would be meaningless for those interpreting it. It seems clear that his
15
sympathy does not lie with this historical method, though he admits its utility in areas
The third method or principle of selection to guide the judge in determining the
application of a principle of the law is the method of custom. Cardozo rejects Coke’s
theory that the common law is separated from customs, and Blackstone’s that custom
pervades all of the law. These were the old views, the views that prevailed at different
times in the thought of English Jurisprudence. Cardozo’s view is more moderate. “In
these days,’ he says, “at all events, we look to customs, not so much for the creation
of new rules, but for the tests and standards that are to determine how established
rules shall be applied.’ Customs, if it is to obtain the dignity of positive human law
must do so through legislation. It is enough for Cardozo that the method of custom
exercise its creative power “not so much in the making of new rules as in the
application of the old ones.” But the potential of custom to be extended until it
conduct,” brings the method of custom or tradition to the point of convergence with
CHAPTER 4
From the first three methods of selection, i.e., of philosophy of history and of
customs, we see that no one method is free from all trace of one or more of the other
methods. The same phenomenon is true of the last method, the method of sociology.
method than any of the former three. Of this method he says: “finally, when the social
needs demand one settlement rather than another, there are times when we must bend
symmetry, ignore history, and bend custom in the pursuit of other and larger ends.”
He states as the final cause of law the welfare of society, and points out that all other
methods are dominated by this cause. Since this method of sociology is to be the tool
or instrument of the judge, there must be some limit to the method to prevent its
uncontrolled exercise by the judge. The method of sociology is, for Cardozo, the
method par excellence for filling up the “gaps in the written law.”
Many jurists and philosophers of the law have stressed the restrictions on the
discretion of the judge in his “filling in the gaps” Few summed it up more tartly than
legislate, but they do so only interstitially, they are confined from molar to molecular
motions.” But Cardozo is concerned not so much with the rise of the gap to be filled
as he is with “the principle that shall determine how they are to be filled, whether their
size be great or small.” Here again the emphasis is placed on the method of selection
rather than on what is selected, and the method of sociology in making this selection
17
he takes as its criterion the social welfare. Difficult enough is the task of formulating
the methods of selection, but more difficult by far is the task of interpreting them.
Cardozo realises that social welfare can mean public policy or the social gain from
adherence to a standard of right conduct- the mores of a community. “In such cases,”
he says “its demands are those of religious or of ethics or of the social sense of justice,
Cardozo’s theory of law within the judicial process had a high moral content will
emerge more clearly with time. One may see, however, that he constantly stresses the
need for a moral content in law within his concept of the social welfare so essential to
his method of sociology. This concept of the social welfare is in many respects
analogous to the bonum commune in the Thomistic definitions of law. For Cardozo
insists that one must look not only to individual reason for the rule but to the social
Cardozo analyses and describes the method of sociology with a class of cases both in
constitutional law and in certain branches of private law. He regards the area of
constitutional law as perhaps the most suited to the application of this method, since
the constitution extends to a larger area than other rules and laws. Accordingly, the
treatment of certain rights must be in larger and more general concepts. In the
reduction to the particular case, there is the opportunity and need for the judge to rule
18
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 25
18
Liberty within the due process clause of the constitution clearly requires the
interpretation of the judge to set its limits in particular cases. For Cardozo, the method
of sociology is to be used to define liberty in these cases, but with the reservation that
it may include a part of one or more of the other methods. Cardozo realizes the need
for an interpretation of the “liberty and property” are, but he also realizes the need for
with a caution against extreme subjectivity. His position may be said to be moderate,
though at the beginning of his philosophical writing on the judicial process he was
regarded as a liberal.
Of Cardozo’s method of sociology Edwin Patterson says: “the fourth method’ that of
sociology, is not coordinate with the other three. In a sense it is subordinate or inferior
to them, because of the probability that the logical attainment of established rules will
give the court a guide which will be adequate to the needs of justice.” The method of
sociology signifies, for Patterson, “an appeal to ‘equity’ in the Aristotelian sense” But
limit that method. Closer to Cardozo’s estimate of the role of that method is the
consideration of the Bonum commune, equity and social justice.’ The decision spoken
of by Coing is that of the appellate judge. So the method of sociology, rather than
being limited to determining exceptions to the law (as is equity), would provide
19
Benjamin N. Cardozo, the nature of the judicial process, page no 16
19
material for the formation of new laws where adherence to old laws would simply
result in injustice because of social change. Beyond a mere appeal to “equity,” then,
the method of sociology seems the method par excellence to exert the principles of
natural law. And though the method lacks the definiteness that may attach to the other
methods, it cannot, for that reason alone, be subordinate or inferior. The very fact that
for Cardozo this method of sociology regulated the other methods when they were in
The method of sociology is for Cardozo the method by which the end of law i.e, the
before the judge, and he concludes that the “common law at bottom the philosophy of
pragmatism.” But Cardozo insists that the fact that a law is successful has nothing to
do with its validity. He urges that such an extreme position would be destructive of
the consistency and uniformity secured by using the other methods. This method of
sociology is guided by viewing the end of law. As Cardozo puts it: “The final
principle of selection for judge, as for legislators, is one of fitness to an end.” But he
is careful to stress the duty of the judge in attaining this end: “nothing less than
conscious effort,’’ he says, “will be adequate if the end in view is to prevail. The
standards or patterns of utility and morals will be found by the judge in the life of the
community. They will be found in the same way by the legislator.” The analogy
between the function of judge and legislator now emerges in Cardozo’s thought. The
legislator creates by framing new laws suited to the needs of the community for which
he legislates, the judge legislates only in the gaps left by the legislation, but cannot, in
Cardozo’s opinion, be blind to the same needs he observes in the community. The
20
judge’s function is performed by using one of the methods of selection, in this way he
is said to legislate.
Cardozo points out the divergence of thought on the question of whether the judge
should use a subjective or objective standard to determine the norms of right and
useful conduct. He notes and approves the need for an objective standard to prevent
or feeling. He rejects the view that the subjective standard should prevail, and says the
standard should be that of the community, the mores of the time. But here he cautions
that this does not mean “that a judge is powerless to raise the level of prevailing
conduct.” Cardozo is concerned with the case in which practices that do not meet
believes that it is the duty of a judge to hold to the accepted standards of morality.
This action he seems to equivalent with a subjective measure, when in reality it would
be objective if measured by the “accepted standards of morality” in the event that they
are not interpreted subjectively. The predominating desire is to raise the standards of
morality at a high level and keep them there. This is one of the notes in his concept of
the judicial process the judge must insure that the law its application has a high moral
content.
Misleading both in its brevity and simplicity is his analysis of the judicial process
itself: “my analysis of the judicial process comes then to this, and little more: logic
and history and custom and utility, are the accepted standards that singly or in
combination shape the law” here the search for Cardozo’s concept of the judicial
process might stop, if this scant statement did not contain within itself the obvious
21
and at what point the desirability for symmetry the elegantia juris should be sacrificed
for larger interests. In the main, he urges adherence to precedent. But equity is not
or certainty must then be balanced against the social interest served by equity and
fairness or other elements of social welfare.” The balance of these interests in the
If it is the judge’s function to balance the social interests, there must be a standard by
which to check his action. That standard is the same for the judge as it is for the
legislator life itself. In exercising his functions the judge should be guided and
restrained by tradition, the members of his own profession, example of the other
judges, and the spirit of the law. Yet his work within these limits is still creative. “The
law,” Cardozo says, “is not found, but made.” If this remark is taken at face value, he
advocates usurpation of the legislative function. But Cardozo’s view is not so broad,
although he sees an analogy between the functions of judge and legislator. He notes
the development of the analogy in countries where the judicial initiative is more
restricted than in the U.S. drawing on Geny to state the limits of the judicial function,
general situation, which he regulates in a manner altogether abstract, the judge, who
concrete, ought, in adherence to the spirit of our modern organisation, and in order to
every influence that is personal or that comes from the particular situation which is
presented to him, and base his judicial decision on elements of an objective nature.
Both in Cardozo’s own remarks and in those he cites as authorities in support of his
view of the judicial process as creative, the need for free decision coupled with an
In affirming the power of the courts to declare law “and within limits the duty, to
make law when none exists,” Cardozo careful to point out that he does not ally
himself with Coke, Blackstone and hale, who held that judges does not legislate, nor
with Austin, Holland, or Gray, who held that there is no reality in law but the
decisions of the courts. Rules of law which are embodied in decisions do not, for
Cardozo, lose their force as law merely because judges overrule them. Rather, the
rules retain their force as law independent of the pronouncement of the judge in a
given case. Thus the creative work of the judge lies in his choice of methods of
selection, the law embodied in the precedent applied has existence apart from its
application by the judge. Concerning natural law Cardozo point out the revival of its
desire to enter into verbal speculation concerning the problem, but says: “what really
matters is this, that the judge is under a duty, within the limits of his power of
innovation., to maintain a relation between law and morals, between the precedents of
jurisprudence and those of reason and good conscience.” There will be a fuller
discussion of this question of natural law in the writings of Justice Cardozo in this
CHAPTER 5
Cardozo then turns his attention to the weight and importance that should be placed
adjective law, and sees the need for development in those fields. Although impressed
abandoned, he reasserts his position that adherence to precedent should be the rule
and not the exception. He will not sacrifice stability and symmetry of the legal order
for a number of isolated cases. The change he envisions is by degrees, and not by a
and dynamic precedents. The outcome of a case which involves a "static" precedent is
not of great importance; such a case can seldom admit of any decision but one, and
does not affect jurisprudence one way or the other. "Dynamic precedents," however,
are those which when decided will have an effect on jurisprudence, and will effect as
well a development in the law. "These are the cases," says Cardozo, "where the
creative element in the judicial process finds its opportunities and power." In
conclusion, then, in this first work, the Nature of the Judicial Process, Cardozo
elaborates the four methods of judicial decision. Their importance for understanding
his philosophy cannot be overestimated. He placed stress definitely upon the first and
fourth methods, the method of philosophy or logic, and the method of sociology. The
method of philosophy gave to the law certainty and stability--the symmetry needed
24
for reasonable predictability. The method of sociology gave room for the exercise of
judgment by the court to mitigate the harshness of strict application of a rule which
would work a hardship. The latter calls for the interstitial legislation of a judge in his
application of precedent to fill the gaps left by the law in certain instances. In his other
writings on the philosophy of law, Cardozo elaborates those principles, giving more
CHAPTER 6
Truth
One can locate it in Cardozo’s exposition of the first of his four forces-the method of
philosophy. He believes the merit of this method lies in governing the “affairs of men
with the serene and impartial uniformity which is of the essence of the idea of law”
and it will help shape “great and shining truths” from the “sordid controversy of the
litigants”. The strong belief that there are singular truths which all knowledge should
strive for is one of the most fundamental traits of the Modern. Cardozo does not
introduce this concept into legal discourses but he does indirectly make a case for it.
However, he refuses to engage with the contours of this truth, and thereby sidesteps
one of the most contested spaces within the modern. The major ideological battles
within the modern have been fought for the control of the terrain called truth. Often
these claims were made on the basis of the “rational” or the “scientific”, which were
acknowledged as the only possible way to reach the “truth”. For example, Lenins
much quoted claim for maxims is a classic example of such a technique- “ Marxism is
true, because it is scientific” Cardozo, though ideologically far removed from lenin,
shares this fascination for truth and also believes in the qualities that the path should
have- order, uniformity. It is highly problematic to claim one singular truth, since it is
subsequently likely to become the site of major operation of power. Power seeks to
enforce its own version of truth and in the process silences the various other “truth”.
become “unnatural” and therefore “criminal”. This insensivity to the order is not
Logic
The second center which Cardozo engages in is a center common to most post-
that is rare in practice. Nevertheless, he strongly argues for the need for logic in the
judicial process and the inherent good that is associated with a logical approach in
sociology (the other forces) may step in, but in case of a perfect legal problem, logic
many other modernist scholars, that a logical analysis and solution to a problem is
Uniformity
One particular sentence of Cardozo’s says that the lack of uniformity may “raise a
resentment arising out of the non-uniformity of justice also illustrates the particular
which purported to function on liberal capicities principles. Due to the rather short
remembered history of the white American man, he never had to deal with the feudal
27
but personal and tangible. An Indian scholar has to deal with this sort of a judicial
process not only because this was a prevalent feature of the present for a vast number
of Indians. In india, justice delivery does not end with the high court’s and the
Supreme Court but extends to the Panchayats and gram Sabhas where village elders
dispense justice. Such personalised and tangible justice is often more valued than the
impersonal and uniform kind handed out by courts. Therefore, unlike Cardozo, it is
not easy for an Indian scholar to claim that the lack of such qualities would lead to
On the method of sociology, which later scholars have termed the greatest of his four
methods in terms of its impacts, Cardozo’s belief was that “the final cause of law is
the welfare of society.” And he hoped that judges would always strive to shape the
law in such a way as to promote “the welfare of society” acting within the limits
imposed by the constitution and with respect for precedent, traditions and history. At
intention. Cardozo stated that there may be occasions when the mores of the day may
conflict with the personal views and morals of the judges. His solution was simple. He
felt that in the event of a conflict, the mores of the community must prevail. “a judge,
I think would err if he were to impose upon the community as a rule of his life his
conform to the accepted standards of the community”. This, however, is to beg the
28
question- how does one ascertain the accepted standards of the community? One is
inclined to believe that Cardozo was talking of a majoritarian principle, whereby the
morals of the majority are those which the judge should follow.
The problem of the mores of the day is heightened in the Indian Context where the
judges sometimes do not share class consciousness as the majority of the population
and therefore often have a drastically different set of moral and ethical values from
that of the majority. The ,mores of the day then end up becoming the mores of certain
educated elites who have come to control power in post-colonial India. At the risk of
India to bear out the arguments. Judges have often been sympathetic to environment
causes 9like automobile pollution) which trouble the urban middle class (with whom
the judges often share a consciousness rather than those which are important to the
rural poor. Cardozo brushed this issue aside by saying that the different moralities of
20
http://www.manupatra.co.in/newsline/articles/Upload/A149DB6F-9D09-4B63-B963-
D493286739D5.pdf
29
CHAPTER 7
CONCLUSION
was called by Frangois Geny. This free decision is the common-law as interpreted by
a judge in a case where statute or constitution are silent and precedent absent. In this
sense, free decision fills the gap in the Scriptum, but it is balanced by stare decisis as
at least an everyday working rule. Free decision also gives a partial explanation of the
phrase "judge-made law." For the judicial process is more than a description of the
merely static, imitative and administrative function of the judge applying an existing
rule or principle to a case before him for decision. Secondly, judicial process is both
science and art. The judge must first turn to statutes and precedents to extract the
underlying principle, the ratio decidendi then he must determine the path or direction
along which the principle is to move or develop. As the extraction of the underlying
principle or rule implies a science, the application of that principle to a case implies
an art. Although Cardozo's emphasis is on the latter of the two aspects of judicial
process, his concept of the whole process involved both elements of science and art.
Thirdly, judicial process is a methodology for applying the princip1e or rule of law to
a case to be decided according to one or more of the four methods: the method of
philosophy or Logic, the method of history, the method of custom, and the method of
sociology. The emphasis here is placed on the fact that judicial process is a method; in
other words, Cardozo’s view of the judicial process was radically structural rather
30
than contextual both in its origin and development. This concept of judicial process
as a methodology greatly influenced his notion on the question of natural law or the
meaning and genesis of law. For Cardozo s almost exclusive concern with method
undoubtedly influenced his decision to leave the more basic and fundamental
questions of natural or moral law to "the statesman and the moralist." ,Fourthly,
judicial process insures to law in general a high moral content. Cardozo freely admits
that the judge must be objective in rendering his decisions. There must be no mark or
trace of personal. Whim or caprice. This does not mean, however, that the judge is
powerless to raise the level of the prevailing standard of conduct. And though the
the initiative when either failure to act or resort to the legislature would leave the
threatened wrong un remedied or unchecked. This concern tor insuring a high moral
content in law will be treated more specifically when we treat his notion of legal
justice. Fifthly, judicial process balances the use of the four methods of decision in
such a way as to serve the social interests. The standard by which this balance is
achieved is the same for the Judge as for the legislator--life itself. In other words, the
Judge should be guided or restrained by such things as the example Of other judges,
the spirit of law, and the examples of the members Of his own profession. Yet with
all this as a guide the judicial Process is still creative, since creation consists in
applying principles and rules of law or in choosing the method for applying these
things; this means that law has an existence apart from its application by the judge.
Here again the methodology of Cardozo shows the structural rather than the
contextual approach to the question of law in the judicial process. Sixthly, Judicial,
31
process looks to social. welfare as an end to measure the effectiveness of law. The
four methods of decision are not ends in themselves but means to the end of securing
understanding of the prevailing canons of justice and morality, and his study' of the
social science. But for a given case, in default of objective standards furnished by the
social sciences, the judge must be guided by his own set of values. In this Cardozo
differs from those positivists who would maintain that in the absence of an objective
standard determined by the legislature the judge is not free to decide a case using his
for law. Hough Cardozo admits that the majority of law does and must come from the
legislature, he denies that the legislature is a sufficient agency for the growth of law.
Central to this notion is his insistence that the actual work of legislating occupies only
part of the time for those members of our government who act in the legislative
branch. While the judiciary devotes full time to the work of deciding cases and
diapens1.nc justice. The creative action of judicial process is, for Cardozo, a
necessary principle of growth for law. Eighthly. judicial process insures legal justice
which is "so much of morality as the thought end practice of a. given epoch shall
conceive to be appropriately invested with a legal sanction, and thereby marked off
from morality in general." In other words, Cardozo’s concept of the judicial process
would have this process translate a moral norm to a Jural norm. With this, duties
formerly considered only as moral, may be translated into law and invested with the
sanction of the power of society. While Cardozo agrees that the legislature can take
steps to insure legal justice, he would maintain that legal justice cannot be attained
32
without the aid of judicial process. ninthly, judicial process operates on a hierarchy
values. In cases where there are conflicting interests, the judge should prefer moral to
economic interests, and economic to aesthetic interests. These values are to be read in
the social mind--a phrase sufficiently vague to resist telling definition--but in the
event that the legislature has furnished no guide for the appraisal of values, and the
judge is unable to read the social mind, the judge is then to turn within himself to
determine these values.. It is in this instance that the judge is to be guided by the
hierarchy of values of the judicial process. Finally. Judicial process must work closely
with legislative process. This cooperation between legislature and judiciary Was
Cardozo's dream at the beginning of his career as a judge; and it furnished him with a
topic for discourse on more than one of his. Frequent speaking engagements. Indeed,
he advocated and promoted a plan for a ministry of justice that coordinated the work
of the the judicial and legislative branches of the government of New York State. In
his opinion. once a statute has been framed it must. if,: its effectiveness curtailed, be
determine in conjunction with the legislature, when a given case falls within the
rapport with the legislative branch it the work of either is to be effective. It seems
clear that Cardozo'. Contribution to the field to legal philosopher must be measured in
terms of his work on the concept of judicial process. This limitation was urged by
Cardozo himself, and most of the evaluations of his work have been made in these
terms. Certain writers however, have not been content to limit their criticism to
Cardozo's expressed purpose. Some would value his work by' Judging his writings &
33
his purpose. In the last analysis, Cardozo was a jurist and a judge not a philosopher. It
is true that he stressed the need for a philosophy as an aid to define the ends of law
and to govern its Application and growth. But his aim was to examine only one
process to which the name "law" could be applied. It see possible therefore, to
separate what he has done on method from the technical Implication and consequence
of his writings when this work is viewed as an attempted philosophical analyses of the
entire field.
34
BIBLIOGRAPHY
WEBSITES
1. http://journaloflaw.us/4%20Chapter%20One/1-1/JoL1-2,%20CO1-
1,%20Cardozo.pdf
2. http://www.manupatra.co.in/newsline/articles/Upload/A149DB6F-9D09-
4B63-B963-D493286739D5.pdf
3. en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Benjamin_N._Cardozo
4. 1http://universityoftexasatdallascomets.com/~mjleaf/Cardozo%20Handout.pdf