Abrahamov Islamic Theology PDF
Abrahamov Islamic Theology PDF
Abrahamov Islamic Theology PDF
Binyamin Abrahamov
Typeset in B a s k e ~ l l e
by Koinonia, Bury, and
Pnnted aad bound m Great Bntam by
CPI Aiiton> Rone, Eastboiii'iie
A CIP record for this book is available
from the British Libran/
Introduction vii
I T h e Foundations of Traditionalism 1
you should accept it, othenvise, you should reject it'.'g Thus the
Qur'an judges the Sunna, which has n o independent status, and
the Qur'án contains the criteria of what man must know. However,
according to al-Suyüti, whoever denies that a prophetic tradition
may be used as an argument is an unbeliever.'" Basing himself o n
great authorities such as al-Shafi'i (d. 205/820) and Abu Bakr
Ahmad ibn al-Husayn al-Bayhaqi (d. 458/1065), he states that the
Qur'an (4.171,24.62 and 3.164 cited above) connects the belief in
Muhammad with the belief in God and that God orders the Mus-
l i m ~to follow His revelation as well as the Prophet's traditions
Varada Allah 'ala al-nüs ittiba' wahyihi wa-sunan rasulihi)." The
Sunna is compared to the Qur'an in traditions which state that if
the believers adhere to the Qur'an and the Sunna they will never
err." The equalisation of the Sunna to the Qur'an is expressed
also from three other points of view: ( 1 ) the S u m a was sent down
like the Qur'an;'3 (2) the Sunna should be studied as the Qur'an is
studied;'+ (3) the sanctity (or inviolability, hunna) of the Messen-
ger's traditions is like that of the Qur'an.l5 This last notion is also
expressed in a slightly different manner in another tradition cited
by the Málikite scholar Abü 'Umar Yüsuf ibn 'Abd al-Barr (d. 463/
1070). It reads: 'What God's Messenger prohibited (ma harrama
rasül allah) is like what God prohibited (mithl mü harrama allah)'.'"
Again, in the context of refuting the rationalists, there appears the
view that the Sunna contains what the believer should know. Al-
Suyüti, basing himself on Abü Bakr al-Khatib al-Baghdadi's (d.
463/1070) Sharaf ashab al-hadith, says that whoever is content with
the Tradition does not need anything else, for it contains the prin-
ciples of religion, such as God's unity, His attributes, the prophets'
stories, history, the biography of the Prophet, Qur'án interpreta-
tion, laws and so on."
In sum, the authoritativeness of the Sunna is proved not only
because it is the summa of the Prophet's sayings and actions which
were trarismitted through chains of reliable Muslims, but also
through the idea that the Sunna is equal to the Qur'án in rank
and, hence, should be regarded as such. Thus the Qur'an is not
the sole Islamic revelation.
The authoritativeness of the Consensus (hujjiyyat al-ijma') has
been thoroughly discussed by H o u r a n i . 2 ~ m üis' sometimes based
o n the Qur'an, for example, Qur'an 4.115, from which o n e can
learn that man must follow the 'way of the believers' which
amounts to c ~ n s e n s u s . ~ ~ o m e t i m
it eissbased on prophetic tradi-
tions such as 'what the believers regard as good is good in God's
eyes and what they regard as evil is evil in God's eyes'3' o r 'my com-
munity does not agree on an error',3' and the trustworthiness of
the tradition itself is based on t~watur.3~
The attitude towards reason
as a means to prove the authoritativeness of the Consensus is not
definite. Although most of the usulis (those who treat the subject
of the principies of law - usul al-fiqh) did not consider reason a
source for proving the authoritativeness of consensus, some of
them did attempt to d o so.33 According to Hourani, generally in
the discussions of the basis of ijmarthe kind of group which consti-
tutes the zj'müris not specified.34 1 have the impression, however,
that many traditionalists regard the consensus of the first genera-
tions of Muslim community, especially the Companions of the
Prophet and their Followers, as the best consensus. Contrary to
Hourani,35 not only the Hanbalites regard the zj'ma'of the ancient
scholars as obligatory, but, as we shall see, so do scholars of other
schools of t h o ~ g h t . 3 ~
In this context, it is worth noting the meaning of the word
jamara (literally 'group'), which occurs in the term ahl al-sunna
wa'l-jamaa. According to al-Shatibi in his al-l'tisámj7 as quoted by
al-Lalaka'i,J8Muslimscholars have five definitions of jamü'a: ( 1 ) the
majority of the Muslims; ( 2 ) the leading scholars of the Muslim
community; (3) Muhammad's Companions; (4) al1 Muslims when
they agree on a certain matter; (5) al1 Muslims when they agree on
a certain leader. Generally, the extreme traditionalists adopt the
second o r the third definition o r both of them,Jg while the moder-
ate wing of traditionalism speaks of the consensus of the commu-
nity. In al-Lálaka'i, many traditions enjoin Muslims to adhere to
the community (aljamá'a). Arnong them is a tradition traced back
to 'Umar which tells that the best people are the Sahüba; those who
canie after them are inferior and so forth until lies will diffuse. In
this case, one should have recourse to the community, since the
Devil exists with the individual. The jamüra, theri, is presented as a
device which prevents people from believing in lies.4" Although
the best consensus remains that of the &haba, that of the commu-
nity is not rejected.
The need to adhere to the public ('jamüra) is stated by the
Hanbalite scholar Ibn al-Jawzi (d. 5g7/1200) by means of a tradi-
tion uaced back to 'Umar ibn al-Khatgib, which reads: 'Whoever
wants the pleasure of Paradise must join the community (al-
jamüra), for the Devil exists with the individual and he is remotest
from the two'."' According to other traditions, God protects the
community, and whoever leaves the community may be liable to
6 ISLAMlC T H E O L O G Y : T R A D l T l O N A L l S M A N D R A T l O N A L l S M
the Devil's attack, like a sheep which may be liable to the wolf S
attack when it leaves the flock. God unites the people for the purpose
of their keeping the right ~ay.~'Jamü'ais the opposite of iftiraq
(division), and division causes perdition. The adherence to the
community, meaning the consensus, serves as a guarantee to the
preservation of the Muslims. Uniformity protects any group of
people from being led astray. Hence, dispute (jadal) should be
rejected.43 As we shall immediately see, the holding of different
opinions, which endangers the community, also appears in
polemical context when dealing with the principle of homogeneity.
The second foundation of traditionalism is the idea that the
principles of religion, which derive from the above-mentioned
roots, namely, the Qur'an, the Sunna and the Consensus, are h o m e
geneous. Hence, any disagreement concerning these principles is
reprehensible. Referring to Qur'an 3.105, 'Be not as those who
scattered (tafawaqü) and fell into variance ( i k h t a w ) after the
clear signs (bayyinat) came to them' (tr. Arberry), the Shafi'ite
scholar al-Bayhaqi (d. 458/1065) states that the Qur'án, the Sunna
and the Consensus of Muhammad's Companions have affirmed
God's attributes (sifat),M the believers' seeing of God in the World
to Come ( mjat allah)+5and the Intercession (shafa'a).4%oever
denies these principles and contradicts them does so after the
coming of the clear signs, meaning the Qur'an, the Sunna and the
Consensus. Al-Bayhaqi adds that the Prophet's Companions have
agreed on the principles of religion, and as for the branches (furil,
the laws), which stem from these principles, and matters for which
there is n o text either in the Qur'an o r in the Sunna, they have
agreed on some of them and disagreed on others.47 T h e Law-giver
(sühib al-shar) has allowed his Companions this kind of disagree-
ment which originates from the system of deriving conclusions
(istinbat) and the system of formulating independent judgements
( ijtihad) .t8
Apart from introdiicing traditions which defame dispute (jadal)
in theological issues, such as 'They [meaning the ancient scholars]
hated diversity in religion (aldin) ' or 'Beware of debates in religion',49
the traditionalists tried to prove the principle of homogeneity by
referring to real experiences of scholars. The famous traditionist
Muhammad ibn Isma'il al-Bukhári (d. 257/870) says that over forty-
six years h e has met more than 1,000 scholars from different dis-
tricts - some of the most prominent of them are indicated - al1 of
whom were agreed upon the tenets of Islam.5" A similar notion
appears in a creed related by two scholars of Rayy, Abü Zur'a 'Ubayd
THE FOUNDATIONS OF TRADITIONALISM 7
Allah ibn 'Abd al-Karirn (d. 264/878) and Abü Hatim Muharnmad
ibn Idris ibn al-Mundhir (d. 277/890), who were critics of Hadith.5'
Both of thern stated that the scholars frorn al1 the cities in Hgáz, al-
'Iraq, al-Sham and al-Yaman had agreed on the sarne articles of
faith.5' According to Ibn Qutayba, the traditionists (ahl al-hadith)
are characterised by agreernent and homogeneity.53 It seems that
the underlying assurnption of the traditionalists, who sought
hornogeneity, was the idea that adhering to the same sources, the
Qur'án, the Sunna and the Consensus, would bring about identi-
cal results."Also the tendency to stress the prophetic tradition was
the result of the aspiration to hornogeneity.55
A part of the notion of homogeneity is the polemical statement
that while the Mutakallirnün move from one notion to another,
the traditionalists are stable and d o not change their minds even if
they are subjected to severe trials. Stability in one's opinions is a
sign of certain belief and truth. In Ibn Tayrniyya, agreement in
views, absence of divergencies and, hence, stability serve as criteria
for rneasuring one's proximity to truth. Thus, for exarnple, the dif-
ferences in the philosophers' notions testify to their remoteness
from truth." Uniformity, which is the outcome of following the
Qur'an and the Sunna, causes stability, and also serves the aim of
preserving the cornmunity from destruction. Nations have per-
ished because of heresies.57
As a result of the above-mentioned notion, one should not
accept without reservation Goldziher's statement that 'indeed, the
conception of diversity as a divine favour was not limited to the
ikhtihf alfuqaha (dissent among legal experts), but was extended even
to doctrinal difference' ('Catholic Tendencies and Particularism in
Islam', p. 130). Goldziher rightly points out that orthodox Islam
never produced formal institutions for the establishing of dogmas
(ibid.), but ignores the fact that uniforrnity in rnatters of theology
rnay be achieved, as indeed happened, through informal dyna-
mism rnotivated by the strict adherence to the Qur'an, the Sunna
and the Consensus.
A logical consequence of following the Sunna of the Prophet is
the adherence to those who are responsible for the collection and
transmission of traditions, which is the third foundation of tradi-
tionalisrn. In the first rank stand Muhammad's Companions
($haba)" and their Followers (Tabirun).In the second rank stand
ahl al-hadith or ashüb al-hadith, rneaning the people who deal with
traditions, or, as we have stated, the traditionists. The Sahaba are
the best, the purest and the rnost just people whom God has
8 I S L A M I C THEOLOGY: TRADITIONALISM A N D R A T I O N A L I S M
Both the traditionalists and the rationalists use reason, but there is
generally a clear difference between the two parties with respect to
the status of reason within their systems. This difference is per-
spicuously stated by al-Taymi. According to him,' the innovators
base their doctrines on reason ('aql), while stating that traditions
are subject to reason. The traditionalists, on the other hand, say
that the basis of religion is following the traditions, and reason
comes after traditions. They argue that if religion were based on
reason, people would not need revelation arid prophets,' the orders
and the prohibitions would be cancelled and people would follow
their wills. Moreover, it would be posible for the believers not to
accept anything unless it appears reasonable to them. In al-
Taymi's view, there are many issues in religion, such as God's
attributes, Paradise and Hell, the Punishment in the Tomb ('adhab
al-qabr), the Balance (al-mizün) and so o n , whose true meariings
believers cannot perceive through reason, notwithstanding that
they are obliged to believe in and to accept them. If people under-
stand anything of religion, they must thank God, for He causes
their understanding.3 The right method of dealing with religious
issues, which cannot be understood through reason, is not to
make a decision (tawqzf) concerning such issues, and to delegate
their knowledge to God ( t a f i i d ).+
A similar notion is put forth by al-Lalaka'i. He states that the
necessity (wujub) of man's knowledge of God and His attributes
derives from the sam' (here the meaning is the Qur'án and the
Sunna, but sometimes the term includes also the Consensus) and
not from reason. To prove his statement, the author cites some
verses, for example Qur'an 47.19 'Know therefore that there is no
god but God'; 6.106 'Follow what has been revealed to you from
your Lord; there is no god but He; and turn away from the
idolators'; 21.25 'And We sent never a Messenger before you except
T H E PLACE O F REASON IN TRADITIONALISM '3
for God is everywhere and His position does not change. The tra-
ditionalist scornfully attacks this argument saying that it belongs to
the kind of arguments used by women and children. However, he
does not content himself with ad hominem argument. In his view,
their argument does not hold water, for God's command and
mercy descends to the earth every minute, thus there is n o need to
particularise a part of the night for this descent. Moreover, does
God cal1 people to ask forgiveness through His command and
mercy? Or does He make His command and mercy speak in His
name? An affirmative answer to the last question obliges the oppo-
nent to ask the command and the mercy forgiveness, which is an
absurdity. The traditionalist regards the opponent's stand as rejec-
tion of the truth even if the latter knows it (mukabara)."
Another argument used by al-Darimi against al-Marisi can be
named as the a forlion' argument. Al-Darimi states that 'we do not
allow independent reasoning (ijtihad al-ra y) in many juristic issues
which we see and hear, the more so concerning God's attributes
which we d o not see and on which we cannot conjecture'.33
According to al-Marisi, one must not intei-pret the word 'finger'
which occurs in the famous tradition 'the people's hearts are
between two of God's fingers734as God's power (qudra). From the
point of view of the Arabic language, says al-Dárimi, this interpre-
tation is untenable, because the identification of 'finger' with
'power' is not found in any of the Arabic dialects. Moreover, people
always speak of God's powerand not of His powers.35
Linguistic considerations are also put forth when dealing with
the problem of God's attributes. The Mu'tazilites distinguish
between two kinds of attributes: essential attributes (sifat al-dhat)
and factual attributes (s@t al$?) .36 God is entitled to factual atttibutes
only when He acts, whereas essential attributes are regarded as al-
ways inhering in Him. Consequently, the attributes Creator, Bene-
factor, Provider, and so on refer to God only after He creates, gives
support, provides and so on. Thus they are not eterna1 and inher-
ent attributes of Him. Al-Tayrni refutes the notion of factual
attributes through putting forth linguistic examples taken from
the ordinary use of language. We say a cutting knife, a satiating
bread and quenching water, for we know that cutting, satiating
and quenching will come into effect through these three objects,
even if now these acts d o not exist. In like manner, God is the
Creator, the Benefactor, the Provider and so on before He created,
gave support and provided, for these acts will come into effect in
the future on behalf of God.37 It is worth noting that the Sháfi'ite
T H E PLACE OF REASON I N T R A D I T l O N A L I S M '7
Resurrection, the Qur'an states that if God was able to create the
world and man, it will be easier for Him to revive the dead (Qur'an
17.50). Likewise, the Resurrection is compared to God's causing
the earth to give birth to plants. Whoever can revive the earth can
revive the dead (Qur'an 35.9). And the existence of one Creator is
proved through the argument that many gods would destroy the
heaven and the earth. Qur'an 21.22 reads: 'Were there gods in
earth and heaven other than God, they would surely go to ruin'
(tr. A r b e r ~ y ) .According
~' to Ibn Taymiyya, one should consider
the Qur'an not only as a basis of information in religious matters
but also as a source of rational proofs concerning God's existence,
His unity, prophecy and the world to come." This notion can be
traced back to al-Ash'ari's Risálat istiban al-khawd fi 'ilm al-Kalam,43
and from him it might have reached al-Ghazali who developed the
idea in his al-Qistas al-mustaqzm. Al-Ghazali's work might have influ-
enced the traditionalist Malikite scholar Abü Bakr Muhammad ibn
'Abdallah ibn al-'Arabi (d. 543/1148), who met al-Ghazali and
learned from h i m . Answering
~ the question relating to the excuse
of scholars who deviate from the teachings of the Qur'an and deal
extensively and profoundly with rational proofs concerning the
knowledge of God, Ibn aLfArabi states that the Qur'an includes
rational proofs in a concise manner and in allusions. The Qur'an
sets forth the roots of rational proofs and not their branches and
related topics. The function of extending and explaining these
proofs and supplying their branches in a complete form is to be
carried out by the scholars. The second excuse of the author is
connected with polemics; the scholars wish to show to the unbe-
lievers (mulhida) and to the innovators (mubtadiá) that the use of
reason does not belong to them exclusively. The unbelievers and
innovators are thus aware that they are refuted by means of every
kind of argument.45 Thus, according to the traditionalists, rational
arguments constitute an integral part of the Qur'an.
In sum, we have seen that reason plays an important role for the
traditionalists, whether as a device for proving their tenets, or as a
polemical tool. However, since reason was not the basis of uadi-
tionalism and because it served as the core of the teachings of
their adversaries the rationalists, the traditionalists have criticised
the use of rational arguments. How they have treated this issue is
the subject matter of the next chapter.
TRADITIONALISM AGAINST
RATIONALISM
greater, and others were mistaken in their striving for truth, and
God forgave them. Answering, elsewhere, the question of how
'A'isha opposed two traditions of the Prophet through using
Qur'an verses, Ibn Taymiyya says: 'We d o not deny that they con-
tradicted one text by another. We only deny that they contradicted
the texts through their reason. T h e texts themselves d o not contra-
dict each other except for command and prohibition where one
text is abrogative (násikh) and the other is abrogated (mansükh).
As for pieces of information (akhbür), it is inconceivable that they
should contradict one another" (Dar', vol. 5, p. 23of.). By akhbür,
Ibn Taymiyya means non-practica1 doctrines like the question of
attributes and predestination. In h e , Tradition contains the solu-
tion to the problem of self-contradiction; n o externa1 device
should be used to solve it."+
In addition to his preceding conten tion, Ibn Taymiyya states
that traditional matters such as the affirmation of God's attributes
and His predetermination, whose truth the rationalists contest, are
known through necessary knowledge which ensues from the process
of tawütur.'s As a result of using tawatur, this knowledge cannot be
false; moreover it is certain, contrary to the opponents' rational
arguments which convey doubts and hence ~ n c e r t a i n t y .It
' ~is to be
noted that there are some other issues concerning which controver-
sies arose, such as the traditional docuine that the spirit was created
before the body while, according to the Kalám, ari accident, in this
case the spirit, cannot exist without a substrate, namely, the body.'7
Dealing with rational proofs leads not only to doubts and confu-
sion, but also to a mixture of truth and fal~eness.~'
'Those who oppose
the Qur'an and the Sunna through what they cal1 rational proofs
('aqliyyüt), such as speculative proofs (kalümiyyüt) and philosophi-
cal proofs (falsafyyat) and the like, base their doctrines only on
general and ambiguous opinions which bear many nieanings, and
their ambiguity in form and sense requires them to also include
truth and falseness.""bn Taymiyya regards the mixture of truth
and falseness as the origin of innovations (mamha'al-bzda'),for if
an innovation were totally false, this would be manifest and hence
it would be rejected; and if, on the other hand, it were totally true,
it would agree with Tradition, because Tradition does not contra-
dict pure truth. An innovation combines both truth and falseness,
and hence misleads people. Ibn Taymiyya explains that the
ancient sages applied rieither afirmation nor negation to the
innovations, for these two devices would have applied to both truth
and falseness.Jo
TRADITIONALISM AGAINST RATIONALISM 23
Ibn Taymiyya also rejects the technical terms used by the theo-
logians and the philosophers. In their doctrines, they employ
terms which d o not belong to the pure Arabic of the Qur'an, the
Sunna arid ordinary linguistic usage.3' This is a part of the general
contention according to which the Qur'an and the Sunna did not or-
der people to engage in Kalam and the ancients did not deal with it.3'
O n e of the ways to fight against rationalism is to show the dan-
gerous consequences of the preference of reason over revelation.
This preference means that nothing can be learned from the
Qur'án and the Sunna, a notion which may cause unbelief and
heresy.33 Very probably following the Hanbalite scholar al-
Barbahári (d. 33o/g4r), Ibn Taymiyya goes even further, saying
that a deviation from revelation in one issue leads to total devia-
tion.34 Possibly, he alludes here to Mutakallimün who preferred
reason as a source of knowledge concerriing some theological
subjects such as God's attributes and predetermination, whereas
on other issues tliey remained loyal to the doctrines of traditional-
ism. Two more evil results are indicated: speculation, as experience
attests, does not bring about piety and indeed, those who engage
in it are usually immoral;35 and the preference of reason leads to
considering the comrnon people, who coristitute the majority of
the Muslims, unbelievers (takjir al-'awümm), for they know religion
only through adhering to the teachings of the Qur'án, the Sunna
and their ancest0rs.3~
Another main traditionalist target is the rationalists' figurative
interpretation (ta Wil) of the Qur'an and the Sunna. The rational-
ists justify their use of this device by stating that without it the
Qur'an and the Sunna are full of anthropomorphisms37 whicli
debase the true perception of God as eterna1 being unlike any
other being. It is not our aim here to elaborate on anthr-oponior-
phisrn, but rather to shed light on the reaction of the traditional-
ists to the method of ta'wil. However, an example is needed to
illustrate the problem. Let us put forth the famous verse in Qur'an
20.5 to which books and chapters were dedicated." It reads: 'The
All-Compassionate sat himself upon the Throne'. This verse was
interpreted by the likeners (mushabbihun) to rnean that God's
place is o n the Throne. Following the Jahmites, the Mu'tazilites
hold that God is everywhere, for if He were in a certain place, He
would be limited as a body.jWost of the Mu'tazilites think that
'God is everywhere' means that He directs and rules (istnrua, which
literally mearis 'he sat', is figuratively interpreted by using the verb
istawlü, meaning 'he ruled') every place.+"
24 ISLAMIC T I I E O L O G Y : T R A D I T I O N A L I S M A N D RATIONALISM
that God hears, sees, knows and lives through instruments, just as
man carries out these actions through instruments (organs, and
body in the case of life). Consequently, God is likened to His crea-
tion, a notion rejected by the Mutakallimün. Ibn Qudama employs
here the Kalam method of ilzüm w h i ~ hmeans forcing the imagi-
nary opponent to admit views which are absurd or heretical, or
contrary to the opponent's own views. It is carried out through
inferring conclusions from the opponent's opinions.55 In the
present argument, the basis is the opponent's method of istidlal
which is exploited to refute the Mutakallimün's rejection of
tashbih this procedure finally leads to the conclusion that the
Mutakallimun hold tashbih. Ibn Qudama, who vehemently attacks
the Mutakallimün, uses their method in order to render their
thesis untenable.
presence of many people and then it will be said: this is the punish-
ment of those who abandoned the Qur'án and the Sunna and
turned to the Kal~m.7~ However, as attested in the Shafi'ite scholar
al-Husayn ibn Mas'üd al-Baghawi (d. 516/1122),7' the attitude
towards the sectarians (ahl al-ahwa )' depends sometimes o n their
doctrines. The traditionist Abü Sulayman Ahmad ibn Muhammad
al-Busti al-KhatGbi (d. 388/998)73 did not cal1 the sectarians who
interpreted the Qur'an and made mistakes unbelievers, and he
also allowed their testimony to be accepted74 as long as they did
not cal1 Muhammad's Companions unbelievers. 'Abd Allah ibn
Ahmad ibn Hanbal related in the name of his father that o n e
should not pray behind whoever held the createdness of the
Qur'an.75 Again, it should be noted that when speaking of the
people of innovations (ahl al-bida') o r of the sectarians (ahl al-
ahwü'), the scholars d o not always mean to speak of those who
hold rational doctrines, for these appellations also refer to the
possessors of mystical o r political notions and to performers of
unusual practices. The different kinds of attitude seem to refer to
al1 kinds of heretics, the rationalists occupying a central place
among them.
Another important note is the fact that the Qur'an contains
many verses in which the word hawan (literally 'passion') occurs.
These verses are exploited for the purpose of refuting the
sectarians (ahl al-ahwa'), for example Qur'án 18.28 'DO not obey
o n e whose heart We have made neglectful of O u r remembrance
so that he follows his passion' (or his sectarian doctrine, hawahu) .76
T h e rationalists are described, along with despotic kings (mulük
ja 'ira) and ignorant ascetics (juhhal al-mutasawwifa), as those who
corrupt religion. They are evil scholars (ahbar su'), who deviate
from religion through their views a n d untrue analogies which per-
mit what God forbids and forbid what God permits.77
In al-Taymi there exists even the notion, which 1 have not seen
elsewhere, that the Mutakallimün are not religious scholars
( %lama') . Basing himself o n the ancient scholars ( 'ulamá 'al-salaf) ,
al-Taymi states that, in order to justify his position, a religious
leader (imüm 3'1-din) must have the following characteristics: he
must know the language of the Arabs with al1 its divergencies,7' the
different views of the religious scholars, the rules of grammar, the
Qur'án, its interpretations, its different recitations and several
issues relating to the Qur'an, such as the selfevident and ambigu-
ous verses, and he must know the Traditions a n d their kinds.
Moreover, h e must be a pious man. Whoever has these properties
3O ISLAMIC T H E O L O G Y : T R A D I T I O N A L I S M A N D R A T I O N A L I S M
Sunna. The Devil caused the clever people to think that if they
were content with the teachings of the Qur'an and the Sunna and
accepted their plain meanings, they would be like the masses (al-
'ümma), which means, naturally, degradation. As a result, they
began to deal with speculative theology in order to distinguish
thernselves from the mas se^.^' Another reason for the strengthen-
ing of the Kalám was the weakness of the belief in finding the truth
in the Qur'an and the Sunna, which in turn caused the unbelievers
to attack Islam on the basis of unsound arguments. The Muslirns
thought that only a reaction through speculative means would
overcorne their opponents, a thought which proved to be a grave
error.HiAl-KhatGbi accuses the Mutakallimün of taking their doc-
trines from the philosophers, who were obliged to turn to these
doctrines, because they did not affirm the prophecies83 Whoever
accepts Muhammad's prophecy needs n o speculative methods, for
prophecy contains what man must know concerning r e l i g i ~ n . ~ +
In sum, there are divergent attitudes towards the rationalists in
Islarnic theological literature. These attitudes range from total
rejection and excommunication to permission to debate with
thern. The Hanbalites d o not appear as the sole extremists in this
issue; traditionalism in its different forrns again exists in al1 Islamic
schools of law. When al-Suyüti defarnes the Kalam in his Sawn, he
uses the writings of scholars frorn various schools, Hanbalites (al-
Harawi), Shafi'ites (al-Muhasibi), Malikites (Abü Talib al-Makki)
and Ibn Jarir al-Tabari, who established his own school of law.
THE FOUNDATIONS OF
RATIONALISM
the Qur'an; (3) the Sunna; and (4) the Consensus (al-zj'ma'). Now,
the knowledge of God cannot be obtained through the last three
proofs, since they are the branches Vuru') of the knowledge of
God, and it is inconceivable to use the branches in order to affirm
the existence of the root (asl). T h e Qur'án, says Mánakdim, is
approved as a proof only when one proves that it is a just and wise
speech, and this derives from the knowledge of God, His unity and
justice.5
Another foundation of Islamic rationalism is the ovenvhelming
power of reason over revelation. Since reason is the goveming prin-
ciple of the world, the contradiction between revelation and reason
must be solved according to reason. For example, anthropomorph-
isms in the Qur'an and the Sunna should be interpreted in a figu-
rative way, otherwise God loses His atuibutes of being the Creator
and the Everlasting; if God is like the created things, He can be
neither the Creator nor the Everlasting.
I t is not o u r airn in this treatise to deal with the rationalists'
proofs of creation and God's existence, o r to consider their advan-
tages and disadvantages from the point of view of reason," but
some examples are needed to illustrate their activity. Early on, two
Mu'tazilite theologians, al-Iskafi (d. 240/854) and al-Nazzam (d.
221/836 o r 231/845), used the proof for creation from the impossi-
bility of an infinite number: 'The world must have a beginning
since an infinite past time could not have been traversed'.'
The proof from accidents is the standard Kalam proof for the
creation of the world. Its basis is the structure of the world as seen
by the Mutakallimün. According to them, there are two elements
which compose each body: (1) atom (jawhar, pl. jawahir o r aljuz'
allazi lü yatajatz'u, an indivisible particle), an unchanging particle
devoid of properties; and ( 2 ) accident ('arad, pl. arrüd), the
changeable element of each body, which comes into existence and
disappears, like motion and rest in a body. Each existent body is
composed of atoms and accidents. Since accidents come into exist-
ente and are necessarily parts of the body, the body also comes
into existence. The universe is a body, hence i t also came into
existence. Abü al-Hudhayl al-'Allaf (d. 235/849) is said to have
been the first Mu'tazilite Mutakallim who put forth tliis argu~nerit."
Other arguments for creation arid God's existence are h e argu-
ment from c o m p o s i t i o n , ~ t h eargument from particulari~atiori'~
and the argument from dcsign."
Basically, there is no difference between the Mu'tazilite and the
Ash'arite Mutakallimün in introducing rational proofs for creation
34 ISI.AMIC TtlEOLOGY: TRADITIONALISM A N D RATIONALISM
than Him, they claimed that they inhered in Him. Thus the
Ash'arites used reason in order to defend traditional views.
The discussion on free will and predestination supplies us with
another example of rationalism in Islamic theology. In the range
of our work it is impossible to set forth even a limited exposition of
the history of the debate and its various arguments, therefore we
shall only give the principles. According to the Mu'tazilites, man is
free to choose his acts and he is capable of carrying them out due
to the power that God grants him before he acts. They hold that
'ought implies can'; if God had predetermined a man to be an
unbeliever and then ordered him to be a believer and punished
hirn on account of liis unbelief, He would have been unjust and
irrational, because after having been predetermined to unbelief a
man cannot be a believer. Here again, we see that the Mu'tazilites
judge God in keeping with their rational understanding. The prin-
ciple which applies to man applies also to
In contrast, the Ash'arite point of departure is different; it is
God's ornnipotence. Since God creates al1 things, He also creates
rnan's acts. T o safeguard both nian's responsibility and God's
omnipotence, al-Ash'ari developed the theory of kasb (literally
'acquisition'), whereby God creates rnan's actions arid as man
appropriates them, he becomes responsible for them. How nian
can be responsible for an action for which God creates the power
and also the power of appropriation is a question which al-Ash'ari
and his followers tried to answer.'4 The theory of kasb was a
rational attempt to harmonise the rational requisite of free will
and the traditional dogma of predestinatiori whether this dogma
derives from the sacred texts or from the people's nientality. For
other attempts at harmonisation, see Chapter 6. What is important
in this context is that the Kalam theory of kasb penetrated into
traditionalist circles. In his interpretation of al-'aqida al-ta?~üwiyya,
whose author the Hanafite Abü Ja'far Ahrnad ibn Muhammad al-
Taháwi (d. 322/g33) says that 'man's actions are God's creation
and rnan's appropriation' (afal al-'ibüd khalq allah zua-kasb min al-
Z'bad), the Hanafite scholar Ibn Abi al-'Izz (d. 792/1389), who is ari
example of traditionalism in Hanafism, adopted this theory.'5
Elsewhere, we see that although this scholar criticises the Kalam,2G
he uses a Kalam argument - the argument from hypothetical
mutual prevention (da12 al-tamanu') - to demonstrate God's
unity." The core of this argument is the liypothcsis that two
producen cannot act harmoniously, and that inability or weakriess
is necessarily attached to orie or to both of theni. The argument
has its basis in the Qur'an ( 2 3 . 9 1 , 2 1 . 2 2 ) , but owes its elaboration to
the Mutakallim~n.'~
The Mu'tazilites hold that rnan understands what is good and
what is evil through his own intelligence, which can intuit these
values. Good and evil actions have intrinsic properties which can
necessarily be known through man's reason. God reveals to rnan
what h e generally knows and also supplies him with the details of
his obligations.'q Contrary to this view, the Ash'arites hold divine
subjectivism: to wit, what God forbids is evil and what He orders is
good. Thus rnan cannot know by his reason before revelation the
ethical values. And also, God is not subject to the reasonable rules
which rnan understands.jo That God, in the rationalists' view, is
subject to such rules is exemplified once more in the issue of
God's assistance ( l u f ) . The Mu'tazilites think that rnan knows that
God created him purposefully, that is, to benefit him.3' If God had
created rnan purposelessly, His creation would not have been wise.
A purposeless act ( 'abath) is considered an act performed unwisely,
and it is inconceivable to speak of God as unwise. The best benefit
that God can give rnan is a reward obtained only through carrying
out duties which God imposes on him. Two conditions are required
for man to perform his duties in order to obtain reward: he must
have the power to d o them; and he must freely choose his acts, and
his choice requires different motivations or rational alternatives.
God must give rnan the power to act (tamkin) and the motivation
to d o good deeds. This last assistance is called lutJ If He did not d o
this, H e would be unjust, which according to 'Abd al-Jabbár corre-
sponds to his being irrational.9 The pains caused by God raise
doubts about God's justice. The Mu'tazilites solve this problem by
stating that pains caused by God benefit man. When God inflicts
pains on rnan for the latter's benefit, He must @ve him compensa-
tion ( 'iwarl) which exceeds the measure of the pains.33 Again, we
see that, according to the Mu'tazilites, God does not act arbitrarily,
but rather in keeping with reasonable rules which rnan can under-
stand.34 In contrast, the Ash'arite doctrine does not impose any
rules on God. According to them, God can inflict pains on rnan as
He without be~towingbenefit o r c o m p e n s a t i ~ nWe . ~ ~see
thus that the Mu'tazilitec are more rationalist than the Ash'arites.
The discussion of the proofs for the trustworthiness o f pi-ophet-
hOOdcan also be carried out according to either the traditional or
[he rationai íine. This can be best
5hown lhrough examining a
passage in a treatise of the Ashfarite scholar Fakhr al-Din aH&i
(d. 606/1210) entitled al-nubuwwat wa-ma yataizllagu bi-ha (Prophecies
THE FOUNDATIONS OF RATIONALISM 37
to him, the ijmürof the %haba was wrong on account of their con-
tradictor~ statements in matters of Iaw.+['Abd al-Jabbar, who
accepts the Consensus as proof (al-Mughni, vol. 17, pp. 16off.),
states that the Consensus is not necessarily the consensus of the
majority. In his view, the jamü'a, a term which is equal, as we have
seen, to the zjmü: is the agreement with (mujümara) the people of
truth (ahl al-haqq) even if they are few. He accepts the notion of al-
Nazzám that many people may err, and cites Qur'an verses, such as
11.40, 'Only a few people believed with him (Nüh),' which praise
the few.4' Other verses are cited to show that the Qur'an recom-
mends asking and obeying the wise people and not the jam'a.
'Ask the people of remembrance if you d o not know' (Qur'an 21.7)
and 'Obey God and obey the Messenger and those who are wise,
(literally 'those in authority', ülü al-amr).43 Also, the beginning of
Muhammad's career proves that the truth may be with the few,
Muhammad and his first followers, and not with the many, the
pagans in Makka. The experiences of other prophets prove the
same notion.44
The criticism of rituals and commandments which occupies a
central place in the works of heretics such as Ibn al-Rawandi (see
notes I and 4 above) is almost absent from the writings of the
rationalists. 1found only a few examples in Ibn Qutayba's treatise.
He relates that the Baghdadi Mu'tazilite Thumama ibn Ashras
(d. 213/828), when seeing people run on Friday to the mosque for
fear of missing the prayer> said: 'Look at the cattle, look at the
donkeys . .. What this Arabian [meaning the Prophet] has done to
the pe0ple.'4~According to Ibn Qutayba, the Mutakallimün even
regard some of God's prohibitions as essentially unbinding. For
example, wine is not forbidden in itself, but only for the purpose
of education.47 Other Mutakallimun, says Ibn Qutayba, consider
the fat and the skin of swine permitted for use, for God only for-
bade the flesh of swine (Qur'an 5.3 'Forbidden to you are carrion,
blood, the flesh of swine . . .'@).Here, the literal meaning of a verse
serves as a weapon of libertinism against traditionalism. However,
this criticism remained marginal; the main target of the rational-
ists' attacks was the hadith and its transmitters.
COMPROMISE BETWEEN
RATIONALISM AND
TRADITIONALISM
proves that Ibn Taymiyya thinks that apart from the rational argu-
ments located in the Revelation, there are arguments which man
gains by means of his intellectual efforts. If these arguments are
built in an appropriate way, they do not contradict the contents of
the Revelation. Contradiction between the Revelation and reason
occurs only when either the intellect produces false arguments, or
a tradition is weak or apocryphal.'s It seems to me, contrary to what
1 have stated e l ~ e w h e r e ,that
' ~ in addition to Qur'ánic arguments,
there are arguments which man produces. Thus Ibn Taymiyya also
maintains the independent status of rational proofs.
Apart from general systems of harmonisation of reason and
Tradition, there have also been efforts aimed at specific theologi-
cal issues. Thus the theory of kasb may be viewed as an attempt at
harmonising the rational requisite of free will and the traditional
dogma of predestination.17
7
SUMMARY
(p. '76)
I. Belief is action and saying (qawl wa-'amal), it increases and
decreases (yazidu zua-yanqusu).'
2. T h e Qur'án is God's uncreated speech (kalüm Allüh ghayr
makhlüq) in al1 its aspects."
3. Predestination (qadar),whether good o r evil, derives from God.4
4. The best persons of this commilnity after its Prophet are Abü
Bakr al-Siddiq, then 'Umar ibn al-Khattáb, then 'Uthmán ibn
'Affan, then 'Ali. (p. 177) They are the rightly giiided caliphs.5
5. There are ten persons whom God's Messenger called the peo-
ple of Paradise and testified that they would be there. It is his
true statemerit. O n e must have mercy upon al1 Muhammad's
Companions and abstain from [dealing with controversies]
which took place among them.6
6. God is on His Throne ('arshihi) a n d is separated from His
creation as He described Himself in His Book and through
His Messenger 'without modality' (bi-la kayfa) . 7 God knows
everything thoroughly: 'There is none like Him and He is the
All-Hearing and the All-Seeing' (Qur'án 42.11 ) .
7. God will be seen in the world to come.' The people of Para-
dise will see Hini with their eyes (literally 'glances') and will
hear His speech in the manner He wills and as He wills.
8. Both Paradise and Hell really exist. Both of them are created
eritities which will never perish.q Paradise is reward for God's
friends (aruliya'ihi) and Hell is punishment for sinners (liter-
ally 'those who disobey God', ahl maSiyatihi), unless God will
have mercy upon them.'"
9. T h e Way (akirüt) is true."
10. Tlie Balance (al-miran) is true. It has two scales in which rnari's
good and evil deeds are weighed. [All this is] true."
I 1. The Basin (al-hawd), through which our Prophet is honoured,
is true.I3
12. The Intercessiori (al-shafa'a) is true."
13. The Resurrection (al-ba2h) after death is true.I5
14. People who commit grave sins are subject to God's ~ i l l . ' ~
15. We d o not declare the Muslims (literally 'the people who direct
their prayer toward the Ka'ba', ahl al-qibla) to be unbelievers
on account of their sins, and we entrust their secrets to God.I7
16. We carry out the precepts of the Holy War (jihad) and Pilgrim-
age (ha~j]with the leaders of the Muslims in every period."
I 7. We d o not consider rebellion against the leaders of the com-
munity and strife in civil war appropriate. We listen to and
obey those whom God appoints as o u r leaders and we shall not
stop obeying [them]. We follow the Sunna and the Consensus
(jama'a) and abstain from deviations (shudhüdh), controversy
(khikllf) and disunion Vurqa) . ' g
18. The Holy War continues from the time of Muhammad until
the Resurrection with the powerful leaders of the Muslims,
nothirig will cancel it.
19. Likewise the Pilgrimage and giving obligatory offerings in the
form of cattle to powerful leaders of the Muslims [continue].
20. People must be treated as believers (literally 'people are
believers') in accordance with the rules of believers and their
inheritarice. We d o not know what they are in the eyes of
God.'"
21. Whoever says that he is truly a believer is an innovator. Who-
ever says that he is a believer in the eyes of God is a liar." And
whoever says that he is truly a believer in God is right.
22. The Murji'ites and the innovators are deviators (dulál).
23. The innovative Qadarites are deviators. Whoever, among
them, denies that God knows what happens before it happens
is an unbeliever."
24. The Jahmites are unbelievers.'"
25. The Rafidites re~ected(rafadü) Islam.'4
26. The Kharijites are apostates (muraq) .li
27. Whoever claims that the Qur'an was created (makhlüq) does
not believe in the Mighty God. His unbelief removes him from
the community. Whoever doubts his unbelief, among those
who understand, is an unbeliever.
28. Whoever has doiibts concerning God's speech hesitating and
saying: 1 d o not know whether it was created or not, is a
Jahmite.'6
29. Whoever hesitates concerning the Qur'an without knowing is
an innovator and n o t a n unbeliever.'7
(P. '97)
Q: What must the person obliged know concerning the principles
of religion (usül aldin)?'
A: He must know four issues: (1) God's unity (tawhid);3 ( 2 ) God's
justice ('ad1);4 (3) Prophecies (nuhruwüt); and (4) Laws
(sharü 'ir).
(P. '99)
What is the first obligation incumbent o n man?
It is speculation and reflection which leads to the knowledge
of God.
First, what is the source of our knowledge that speculation and
reflection are obligatory, whereas some people, such as the
traditionists (ahl al-hadith), oppose this notion and state that
knowledge is gained through uncritical acceptance of ideas
(al-'ilm bi'l-taqlid)?5 Moreover, some learned people state that
knowledge is obtained necessarily and there is no need to
reflect and speculate.
The learned man knows that there are people who are wrong
in their speculation (yukhti'u) and others who are right
(yusibu), however each of them claims that he is right. Why,
then, is the taqlid of one of them better than the taqlid of the
other? Why is the taqlid of the believer in God's unity better
than the taqlid of the unbeliever? Why is the taqlid of whoever
believes in the seeing of God better than the taqlid of whoever
denies this seeing?
Q What is the proof that the learned man must speculate in or-
der to obtain the knowledge of God?
A: That is because if he hears the people's controversies concern-
ing these systems of thought, the charge of unbelief through
which they accuse each other (takjir) and each of them fright-
ening his colleague as a result of the controversy, and if he
knows that it is impossible that al1 these systems of thought
should be right, for each contradicts the other, for example
the notion that the world is eternal vis-54s the notion that the
world was created, the notion that God can be seen vis-54s the
notion that H e cannot be seen, and [if he knows] that it is also
impossible that al1 these systems can be wrong, for the truth
lies within one of them, that is, it is inconceivable that the
world should not be eternal and should not have been created,
[he will necessarily know that] there are systems which are
right and others which are wrong.
APPENDIX 111
TWO PASSAGES O N REASON AND
TRADITION
Know, may God have mercy upon you, that al1 the known princi-
pies of religion (ahküvf al-din al-ma'lüma) must be divided into
three kinds: ( 1 ) what may be known only through reason (al-'aql)
and not through Tradition (or Revelation - al-sam'); ( 2 ) what rnay
not be known through reason, but may be known only through
Tradition; and (3) what may be known both through reason and
Tradi tion.
As for what may be known only through reason and not
through Tradition, these are the creation of the world (hudüth al-
'ülam), the proof of the existerice of its creator (muhdith),j His
being one (wahdñniyatihi), His attributes, the prophecy of His
messengers and al1 that which is connected to these matters,
namely, the knowledge of God's unity and prophecy which may
oniy be obtained through reason.
The proof of this is that Tradition (al-sam') is only God's speech
(kalüm allah, meatiing the Qur'an) and the statements (qarul,
meaning the hadith) of him who is known as God's Messenger and
the Consensus (ijmü') of those who are reported not to have erred
in their opinions. It is impossible to know that the speech is God's,
that the statenients are 1-Iis Messenger's and the trustworthiness
arid rightness of those whom the Messenger declared to be trust-
worthy and right, unless one knows God's existence beforehand.
That is because the knowledge that the speech is God's and that
A P P E N D I X III 61
INTRODUCTION
1. Arberry, Reuelation and Reason, p. 9.
2. Cicero, De Natura Deorum, 111.
3. Al-Fürübi on the Perfect State. AW Nasr al-Farübi's Mabadi' Arü' Ahl al-
Madina al-Füdila, ed. trans. a n d comm. R. Walzer, Oxford 1985, PP.
474-81. D. Gutas, Auicana and the Aristotelian Tradition, Introduction to
Reading Auicenna's Philosophical Works, Leiden 1988, pp. 299-307- Ibn
Rushd tries a kind of compromise between reiigion a n d revelation,
according to which since the Qur'an itself urges people to speculate
in order to attain the truth, there can be n o contradiction between
the demonstrative inquiry a n d revelation; both of thern are true
devices. Fwl al-magül wa-tagñr mii bayna al-shañ'a wa 'lhikmu min al-ittisül,
ed. G. F. Hourani, Leiden 1959, p. 5f. Ed. Muhammad 'Imára, p. 31f.
4. Tr. by S. van d e n Bergh, London 1954. This work includes the transla-
tion of both al-Ghazali's Tahüfut alfalasifa a n d Ibn Rushd's Tahüfut al-
tahüfut.
5. T h e Zaydite theologian al-Qasim ibn Ibrahim (d. 246/860), who was
prone to Mu'tazilism, wrote a treatise against a philosopher o r a s c e p
tic entitled K. al-radd úlü al-mulhid, MS Berlin (W.Ahlwardt, Vena'chnis
der arabischen Handschriften der Koniglicha Bibliothek zu Berlin, Berlin
1887-9, vol. 4, p. 290, no. 4876, Glaser I O I )fols
, 58b-63b, ed. Muhamrnad
Yahya 'Azzan, San'a' 1992. In this epistle, the main issue is the refuta-
tion of the eternity of the world. In his al-Mabühith al-Mashnqiyya,
Fakhr al-Din al-Razi sometimes criticises Ibn Sina's views but also
accepts sorne notions of the philosopher. Ibn Taymiyya seerns to have
been the most prolific theologian in refuting philosophy. See, for
example, Kitüb bughyat al-mufiüdfi'l-radd 'ala al-mutafalsifa rua'l-qaramita
wa'l-bütiniyya, Cairo AH 1329. In his N q d al-mantiq (p. 44), Ibn
Taymiyya points out that the Ash'arite theologian al-Baqillani (d. 404/
1013)wrote a work entitled K. aldaqü'iq in which he refuted the views
of the philosophers concerning the spheres, the stars, the intellects,
the souls, logic and so on. Al-Suyüti's refutation of the Aristotelian
logic Vahd al-qarihaf2 tajrid al-nasi/~a[The Exertion of Effort in Divest-
ing the Nasiha], which constitutes the second volurne of his Sawn) is
an abridgement of Ibn Tayrniyya's Nasihat ahl al-iman JZ al-radd 'ala
mantiq al-yunün (the alternative title is al-Radd 'ala al-mantiqiyyin - T h e
66 NOTES
CHAPTER 1: T H E FOUNDATIONS O F
TRADITIONALISM
1. Al-Lálaká'i, Sharh usül, vol. I, p. 9. Through these sources of knowledge
o r proofs, man knows what h e should know concerning the principles
of religion, namely, God's iinity, His attributes and the belief in His
messengers. Tine belief in these principles is not characteristic only of
68 NOTES
17. Sharh al-sunna, vol. 1, p. 201f. Cf. al-Tabari, TafsIr, part N , p. 108. Other
verses such as ' 0 b e y ~ G o darid the ~ e s s e i i ~ (e ~r u r ' a nj.32, 4.59), in
which God represents the Qur'an and the Messeriger the Sunna, and
'Those who denied the Book and that which we have sent with o u r
messengers' (Qur'an 40.70; 'That which we have sent ...' stands for
the Sunna) are cited for ttie same purpose. It is worth noting that the
term kitüb a l h h (the Book of God) in alShafiri's al-Risála refers to al1
forms of divine revelation. Calder, 'Ikhtilaf and Ijma", p. 55.
18. U. Rubin, The Eye of the Behoidm, p. 6.
19. Mijtüh al-janna, p. 15. In p. qg, alSuyüti clearly rejects tlie authenticity
of this tradition. For a similar tradition, see Chapter 5, p. M .
20. Ibid., p. 16.
21. Ibid., pp. 17f.. 26.
22. Ibid., pI28: '1 have left among you something that if you adhere to it
you will never err, it is God's Book and my (Muhammad's) Sunna'.
23. Ibid., p. 38.
24. Ibid., p. 105.
25. Ibid., p. 107.
26. Ibid., p. 28. Ibn 'Abd alBarr, Jümi, vol. 2, p. 1,187. Al-Shafi'i states that
'Muhamrnad's rulings are God's rulings'. Quoted by Burton (Introduc-
- ~
tion, p. 85) from K al-umm. It is thus n o wonder that when one of tlie
four imams of jurisprudence (Abü Hanifa, Malik, al-Shafi'i and Ibn
Hanbal) expresses a notion whicti is contradicted by a tradition, he, in
Ibri Taymiyya's view, must make excuses for his deviation. These excuses
are divided into three kinds: (1) the imam's thought that Muharnmad
did not say this tradition; (2) the imam's assurnption that the tradition
is riot relevant to the question discussed; (3) the imam's thought that
the judgement of the tradition was cancelled. Ibn Taymiyya, Raf al-
malam, p. I 8f.
27. Al-Suyüti, Sawn, vol. r , p. 194.
28. G. F. Hourani, 'The Basis of Authority of Consensus in Siinnite Islam',
i r i his Reason and Tradition i n Islamic Ethics, Cambridge 1985, PP. 190-
226.
29. Ibid., pp. 197, 200-3. Cf. Talmud ofJerusalem, Pe'ah, ch. 7, 2oc: 'Go out
and see what the action of the people is and act likewise'. Tr. Calder,
'Ikhtilaf and Ijma", p. 75.
30. Ibid., p. 195.
31. Ibid., pp. 198, 203. In al-Shafi'i's view, the common people coiild not
unite ori a notion wliicli contradicts the Prophet's statements. Calder,
Ibid. This is a slightly different versiori of the tradition rneritioned
above.
32. Hourani, ibid., p. 205f. For more verses and traditioris in favour of tlie
ijmü: see al-Jassas, al-ljma', pp. 137-51.
33. Al-Jassas, al-ljma: p. 66f. Al-Jassas bririgs as an example the proof of tlie
Hanafite scholar 'Ala' al-Din 'Abd al-'Aziz ibn A l ~ m a dibii Muhammad
al-Bukhári (d. 730/1330). Accordirig to him, it is logically proved that
the Prophet is the seal of the prophets (khatam al-anbiyü'),and that his
Law will eridure until the Resurrection. Now when ttiere occurred
events to which n o decisive text of the Qur'an and the Sunna can
apply, tlie commuriity agreed upon the laws concerning these everits.
72 NOTES
traditionists ( a h l abhadith) follow the true way ('ala al-hqq) is the fact
that if you examine al1 their works from first to last, their ancient
works and modern ones, notwithstanding their different cities and
epochs and the distance between their abodes ... you will find them
agreeing on the creeds without deviation ... their view is o n e and their
transmission (naql) is one. You will not see among them divergency ...
If you joined al1 that which they said and transmitted from their ances-
tors, you would find it as if it came from one heart ... 1s there any
clearer proof for the truth than this?' Al-Taymi, al-Hujja, vol. 2, p. 224.
However, the examination of the creeds which appear in al-Lalaka'i
shows that there are some differences among these creeds and that
not al1 the creeds point out the same theological dogmas. See Appen-
dix 1.
51. Dickinson, p. q f .
52. Al-Lalaka'i, Sharh usüi, vol. I , pp. 176-82. For the creed of Abü Zur'a
and Abü Hátim, see Appendix 1.
53. Ta'wil, p. 16. Al-Suyüti, Sawn, vol. I , p. 219.
54. Cf. Dickinson, p. 4.
55. Ibid., p. 6.
56. Ibn Taymiyya, Naqd, pp. 42-4.
57. Al-Suyü~,&wn, vol. 1, pp. 69-72.
58. A Companion (sahübi) is whoever associated with the Prophet for a
period of a year, o r a month, o r a day, o r an hour, o r saw him. The
measure of companionship is established in accordance with the dura-
tion of association. In any case, the inferior companion is better than
o n e who did not see the Prophet, even if the latter carried out al1 the
good acts. Al-Lalaka'i, Sharh usüi, vol. r , p. 160.
59. Ibn Rajab, Fadl 'ilm al-sala. p. 29f. Ibn Hajar aL'Asqaláni, al-Isüba fi
tamyiz al-sahüba, Beirut n.d. (repr. of Cairo AH 1328), vol. 1, pp. 9-12.
Cf. Y. Friedmann, 'Finality of Prophethood in Sunni Islam', J e r u s a h
Studies i n Arabic and Islam 7 (1986), p. 208f. Muslim scholars have
devoted whole chapters to the praises of the Cornpanions (fadü'il al-
sahüba). See, for example, al-Taymi, al-Hujja, vol. 2, pp. 319-78. Ibn
Rajab says quoting al-Awa'i (d. r57/774) that knowledge is what the
Sahüba have brought, a n d everything else is not knowledge. Fadl 'ilm
al-sakJ p. 33. And Ibn Taymiyya tries to prove logically that the
traditionists are the most learned ~ e o ~ lIn
I I
e .short. this ~ r o o runs
f as
follows: Since Muhammad is the most erudite person, those who know
him best, that is, the &haba and their followers, must be the most
learned people. Naqd, p. r16f.
According to G. H. A. Juynboll (Muslim Tradition: Studies in Chrono-
logy, Prouenance and Authurship of Early Hadith, Cambridge 1983, PP.
171-6), Ibn Abi Hatim al-Rázi (d. 327/938) was the first scholar who
expressed the dogma of the collective reliability of the first genera-
tions of Muslims. Cf. Dickinson, p. 118.
A typical statement concerning the attitude towards the Sahüba is
the following: 'If you see a man who loves Abü Hurayra, prays to God
for him and asks God to have mercy on him, hope for him good and
know that h e is free from innovations'. Al-Lalaka'i, Sharh usül, p. 170.
'The principies of the Sunna in our view (usül al-sunna 'indana) are to
NOTES
adhere to the Sahaba' says Ibn Taymiyya (Naqd, p. 128) quoting Ibn
Hanbal. T h e adoration for the traditionists seerns to have n o limit;
sometimes traditions raise the rank of the traditionists above the rank
of the angels, the prophets a n d the martyrs. Al-Suyü., Sawn, vol. 1 , p.
196 (quoting al-Khatib al-Baghdadi's Sharaf ashüb al-hadith).
A Mutakallim who repents of his way also serves as a means to praise
the traditionists. Al-Walid al-Karabisi is said to have bequeathed his
sons before his death to follow the traditionists, for truth is with them.
Ibid., p. 197.
60. Cf. ~ a k d i s i'Hanbalite
, Islam', p. 263.
61. Tr. by W. M. Watt in his Islamic Creeds: A Seiection, Edinburgh 1994,p.
72. Ibn Hanbal stopped relating traditions from the traditionist al-
Husayn ibn al-Hasan al-Ashqar (d. 208/823-4) when h e heard that the
latter defarned Abü Bakr and 'Urnar. Melchert, 'The Adversaries', p.
237.
62. Al-Lalaka'i, Sharh usül, vol. 1 , p. 24.
63. Ibid., pp. 23, 25.
64. Naqd, p. 9. Ibn Tayrniyya notes here (p. 16), without proving it, that
there is a consensus on praising those who adhere to the teachings of
the Sunna.
65. Ibid., pp. i r , 17.
66. 1. Goldziher, Muslim Studies, vol. 2, pp. 33-7. Al-Qurtubi, al-Bida: p.
r7rf. According to Ibn Taymiyya, a notion concerning religion which
has n o religious proof (meaning Qur'án, Sunna and Ijrná') is an inno-
vation. Dar', vol. r , p. 224. Many traditions, such as 'beware of innova-
tions' (iyyükum wa'l-bida? are recorded in the traditionalists' literature.
See, for exarnple, al-Qurtubi, al-Bida', p. 173.Cf. Abü Shama, al-Bü'ith,
pp. 24-8. For innovations concerning practices see Abú Shama, ibid.,
and Ibn Abi Randaqa, Abü Bakr Muharnmad ibn al-Walid al-Turtüshi,
Kitüb al-hawüdith wa'l-bida: ed. Bashir Muharnmad 'Uyün, Damascus
and Beirut 1991.
67. Al-Suyúti, Sawn, vol. 1 , p. 78f.
68. Al-Lalaka'i, Sharh usül, vol. 1 , pp. 114-50. 'DO not sit with those who
adhere to the doctrine of free will ( a h l alqadar) and d o not dispute
with thern', ibid., p. 118. 'Do not dispute with the people of contro-
versy' (ashab al-khusümat), ibid., p. 129. Cf. Ibn aljawzi, Talbis iblis, p.
12f.
69. al-maSiya yutabu minhü wa'l-bid'a Lü yutübu minha. Al-Lalaka'i, Sharh
usül, p. 132. Al-Qurtubi, al-Bida: p. 198. 'God does not permit the
innovator to repent'. Ibn Batm, Sharh, p. 40 of the Arabic text.
70. 'Beware of whoever sits with an innovator', Talbis Iblis, p. 14.T h e for-
mula 'do not sit' (Ia tujülisü) appears frequently in collections of
hadith. Wensinck, Concwdance, vol. 1 , p. 358. Al-Qurtubi, al-Bida: pp.
rgzff., 313, n. 2. It is important to note that most of the traditions cited
in al-Qurtubi's chapter 'The prohibition to sit and to associate with
the innovators' refers to innovations pertaining to dogma, such as ' d o
not sit with him, for h e is a Mu'tazilite'. Ibid., p. 196.
71. Talbis iblis, p. 14. Cf. Abü Shama, al-Bü'ith, p. 27.
72. Bishr ibn Ghiyath (d. 218/833 o r 228/842), a Murji'ite theologian
known for his dispute with the Mutakallim 'Abd al-'Aziz al-Makki (d.
NOTES TO CHAPTER 2 75
240/85~)on the nature of the Qur'an. 'Abd al-'Aziz al-Makki, Kitüb al-
Hayda, ed. Janiil Saliba, Beirut 1992.EIz, vol. 1, p. 1242. For this issue,
see below, p. 54.
73. Talbis iblis, p. 14f The Hadith literature is replete with notes on the
innovations and their degrees in the Muslim sects. See, for example,
Abü 'Ubayd al-Qasim ibn Salam, K al-iman, ed. Muhammad Násir al-
Din al-Albáni, Kuwait 1985, p. 82. The severe attitude towards the inno-
vations is exemplified through traditions which compare the & d a to
other calamities. 'It is preferable to me', says the traditionist, 'to see in
the mosque fire which 1 cannot extinguish than to see in it an ii-inova-
tor whom 1 cannot change.' Al-Qurtubi, al-Bida', p. 181.
74. See above, p. 2.
75. Al-Lálaka'i, Sharh usiil, vol. 2, p. 524. Cf. Plato, Laws, 8zra. See above, p. 2.
76. Ibid., p. 629.
77. Ibid., p. 633. For the term zandaqa, see below, pp. 28, 41.
78. Those who affirm man's capability of producing his acts. This term
refers mainly to the Mu'tazilites.
79. This can be proven also through the succession of traditions in al-
Lalaka'i, ibid., p. 62gf.
80. Ibid., pp. 639-46. For this term, see Chapter 3, n. 65.
81. Ibid., p. 633. 1 do not know whether this tradition has any historical
basis.
82. Ibid., p. 712.
83. Ibid., pp. 730-6.
84. Such as likening God to man (tashhh: ibid., pp. 528-33). not making a
decision concerning the question whether the Qur'an is created or
uncreated (Ibid., vol. 1, p. p 3 ) , and the belief that the act of reciting
the Qur'an is created. Ibid., p. 349.
85. Al-Suyüu, Miftüh al-janna, p. 127, n. 5.
86. Al-Lalaka'i, Sha. usül, vol. 1, p. 123.
87. For this term, see al-Tabari, part 1, p. 25f. Wansbrough, Quranic Studies,
pp. 208-11. A. Rippin, 'Lexicographical Texts and the Qur'an', in
Appfoaches to the Histmy ofthe Interfwetation of the Qur'ün, ed. A. Rippin,
Oxford 1988, pp. 167-71.
88. Al-Suyüti, Miftüh al-janna, p. 128.
pp. 72-91. It seems very probable that al-Taymi had some knowledge of
the Baráhima's views as occur in the writings of some theologians, for
example al-Bliáqillani, K. al-tamhid, ch. g. See below. p. 42.
3. Al-Taymi, al-Hujja, vol. I, pp. 320-2. Al-Taymi (ibid., quoting o n e of ahl
al-sunna) regards the intellect ('aql) as divided into three kinds: (1)
inborn intellect ('aql mawlüd mal&') through which God distin-
guishes man frorn animals. God's imposition of precepts on man is
turned to this intellect. It has the function of distinction between
things (tamyiz) and direction of things (tadóir). (The understanding of
áql as natural disposition was already advanced by al-Harith al-
Muhásibi (d. 243/857), who regarded this intellect as a means to know
God and what benefits man and what harms him. In his view, knowl-
edge is the outcome of the activity of the intellect. K mü'iyat al-%l,
pp. 2oif., 205. Ibn Taymiyya pointed out later that through necessary
natural knowledge man knows that God is above and distinct from his
creation. This is general knowledge which revelation details and
explains. Naqd, pp. 38f, 52. Even in a traditionalist there is a place for
necessary knowledge as proof. Cf. Abrahamov, 'Necessary Knowl-
edge'. Moreover, the notion that one can attain general knowledge
through the intellect and that details of this knowledge are supplied
by revelation (al-fitra ta'lamu al-amr mujmalan wa'l-shanra tuJassiluhu
wa-tubayyinuhu) reminds one of the Mu'tazila's attitude towards moral
values. See below, p. 36. Thus Ibn Taymiya seems to have learned
from his bitter adversaries. This shows again that sometimes the
boundaries between traditionalists and rationalists carinot be defi-
nitely fixed.) (2) Revelational intellect ( ' q l al-ta )id) which God gives
to the prophets and to pious people. (3)-Intellect which is attained
through experience and contacts among people. For a distinction
between intellect and knowledge, see below, p. 17.
4. Ibid., vol. 2, p. 66.
5. This verse might have served the Hanbalite scholar and Ibn
Taymiyya's eminent disciple Ibn al-Qayyirn aljawjiyya (d. 751/1350),
who stated that actions are good o r evil by virtue of themselves, but
reward o r punishment are deserved only through God's orders o r pro-
hibitions. Madünj al-Sülikin, Beimt 1983, vol. I , p. 127. Al-Tayrni, al-
Hujja, vol. I , p. 315. n. 2. In expressing such a view, h e partly accepts
the doctrine of the Mu'tazila concernirig the intrinsic value of man's
actions. See below, p. 36.
In the Ash'arite Mutakallim Fakhr al-Din al-Kizi's view, the messen-
ger mentioned in this verse is the intellect through which one affirms
the existence of revelation. Had intellect not been sent to man, n o
prophetic revelation would have existed. Mafátih al-ghayb, part XX, p.
rpf. Al-Suyüti ascribes this notion, as a logical possibility, to al1 the
Mutakallimún, saying: 'If one said 'There is n o god but God and my
intellect is God's messenger", h e would not b e considered an unbe-
liever in the eyes of the Mutakallimun'. Sarun, vol. i , p. 232.
However, we should stress again that al1 the pure traditionalists
share the notion that theological dogmas must be deduced from rev-
elation and not from reason. This is clearly stated by the Malikite
scholar Ibn 'Abd al-Barr (d. 463/107o): 'There is n o controversy
NOTES .ro C H A P T E K 2 77
among the jurisprudents in al1 the countries and al1 the people of the
Sunna, ¡.e., the people ofjurisprudence and tradition (ahl al-fiqh wa'l-
hadith) o n the denial of analogy (qiyüs) i r i the matter of God's unity
(tawhid, which means theological issues; sometimes theology is called
'the knowledge of God's unity' - 'ilm al-tawhid) and o n the affirmation
of it in the matter of law (ahküm)'.Jümi', vol. 2, p. 887.
6. Al-Lalaká'i, Sharh, vol. 1, pp. 193-203. Cf. al-Taymi, al-Huj'ja, vol. 1 ,
p 3'4f.
7. In al-Suyüti's wording: 'We have given people the intellect only to
establish worship and riot to perceive Godship (li-iqümat al-'ubudiyya lü
li-idrük al-mbúbiyya). Whoever uses what h e has been given ir1 order to
establish worship for the purpose of perceiving Godship, misses worship
arid does not perceive Godship ... The iritellect is a device of distin-
guishing between good and evil, tradition and innovation, hypocrisy
arid sincerity. Without the intellect there woiild not b e imposition of
precepts (taklzf).' Sawn, vol. 1, p. 233.
8. Cf. H. Lazarus-Yafeh, 'Some Notes o n the Term Taqlid in the Writings
of al-Ghazzali', Israel Oriental Studies 1 ( r g j ~ ) pp.
, 249-56. Frank, 'Al-
Ghazali o n Taqlid'. For taqlid in Ibn Tayrniyya, see Laoust, Essai, pp.
226-30.
9. Al-Hujja, vol. 2, p. 116.
10. Cf. Ibn 'Abd al-Barr Vami', vol. 2, p. 787). who adds to the uriderstand-
ing of this phenornenon saying that sometimes the muqallid kriows the
mistaken view but is afraid to oppose it.
r 1. Al-Taymi, al-Huja, vol. 2, p. 116f. T h e intellect is a condition of under-
standing but not its cause, which is God. Al-Suyüti, Sawn, vol. 1 , p. 2 p f .
12. Ibid., p. 117. Cf. Manakdim, Sharh, pp. . . 39, 69. Al-Lalaka'i, Sharh usÜ1,
vol. 1, p. 193, n. I . See Chapter 5.
~ ~
23. Al-Lálaka'í, Sharh, vol. 1, p. z17f. Cf. al-Tavmi, al-Huja, vol. r , p. 227f.
'Abd al-Qadir aljilaní ( a Hanbalite Sufí d . 56r/rr65), K al-ghunya li-
tülib? tañq al-haqq, Cairo 1956, p. 60.
24. Al-Lalaka'i, ibid., p. 2r8f. Khalg is an infinitive (masdar) of klrakzqa and
as such iridicates both the action and the objects of this action. T h e
traditionalists exploit this linguistic phenornenon to support their
thesis of the uncreatedness of the Qur'an.
25. Al-Lalaka'i, Sharh usüi, vol. 1, p. 221.
26. A qadañ is a pejorative name used by the predestinarians against those
who believe in free will, for whoever believes in free will ascribes to
hiniself the power to decree (qadara) his actions. Al-Ash'ari, al-Ibana,
p. 54. Watt, TheFormative Pa'od, p. 116f.By ahl al-tawhid the author may
rriean traditionalists, or traditional Mutakallimün, for exarnple
Ash'arites who oppose the Mu'tazila concerning the issue of God's
decree. If the second possibility is right, it is n o worider tliat a
Mutakallim uses reason to refute a Mu'tazilite.
27. Manakdím, Sharh, pp. 323ff.
28. Al-Shirazi, K. al-ishüra, p. 24.
29. Manakdíni, Sha-, p. 396.
30. 'The bi-la ka-fa Doctrine', p. 371,
31. For ari exhaustive discussion of this traditiori, see Ibn Taymiyya, Sharh
hadith al-nuzül, ed. Muharnmad ibn 'Abd al-Rahman al-Kharnis,
Rivadh 1993.
32. For this term, see aljurjání, K al-tanifát, p. 245. T h e argument appears
in al-Darirrii, al-Radd a l a al-Marisi, p. 377f:
33. Al-Dárirni, ibid., p. 380.
34. Abrahamov, 'The &-la kalfa Doctrine', p. 371.
35. Al-Dárimi, ibid., p. 417.
36. Madeliing, Der Imatn, pp. r 12-14. Peters, God's Created Speech, p. 248f.
37. Al-Tayrni, al-Hujja, vol. 1, p. goof.
38. Al-I'tiqüd wa'l-hidüya, p. 52.
39. Al-Hujja, vol. 2, p. 502f. For another definition of 'aql, see above,
p. 76, ri. 3.
40. Ibid., pp. 504-6.
41. See below, Chapter 3, n. 32.
42. Maarij al-ruu~ül,p. 179.
43. Ed. R. J. McCartliy in his The Theolog~of al-Ash'an, Beirut 1953. Cf. al-
Subkí, Tabaqat, vol. 3, p. 421: 'One wonders at whoever says that the
science of the Kalarn does not occur in the Qur'an'.
44 Ibn aLCArabi,Qanün al-ta'uizl, pp. 111-14. Ibii al-'Arabi called al-Ghazali
dánishrnand which rneans in Persian 'the sage'.
45. Ibid., pp. 176-8.
41. For further details concerning this verse, see Abrahamov, Anthropomm-
phism, ch. 2. Idem, '&la Kajifa', p. 374.
42. Ibn Qudama, Tahrirn al-nazar, p. 29. For a survey of Ibn Qudama's ar-
guments, see J. Pavlin, 'Sunni Kalam and Theological Controversies',
H i s t q of Islamic Philosophy, ed. S. H. Nasr and O . Leaman, London
and New York, vol. r, pp. 113-15.
43. Al-Taymi, al-Hujja, vol. 2, p. 384.
44. Ibn Qudama, Tahñm al-nazar, p. 30. An opponent would have said that
also analogy (qiyas) was not ordered by the Prophet, notwithstandirig
the fact that thejurists employed it. See above, n. 31.
6.
45. Tahrim al-nazar, 32.
46. Al-Huja, vol. I, pp. 175, 288f. Abrahamov, '6-la Kayfa', p. 375. For affir-
mation of the existence of God's attributes, see also Daiber, 'Ibn
Qudama', p. r 10.
47. Al-Taymi seems to refer to the method used by some Mutakallimun
who state that just as man knows by virtue of his knowledge so God
knows by virtue of His knowledge. Al-Baqillani, al-Tamhid, p. r97f.
48. Ai-Tayrni, al-Hujja, vol. 1, p. 111.
49. O n this method, see above, p. 14. Although the author attacks the
Kalam, he, like Ibn Taymiyya, does not refrain from using its methods.
50. Ibn Qudama, Tahnm al-nazar, pp. 30-4, 47.
51. It is also called: qiyñs al-ghü'ib 'ala al-shahid íjudging what is absent by
analogy with what is present). This is a Kalam way of proving God's
existence and attributes from His actions observed on earth. Sháhid
means the present world which is perceived by the senses, whereas
ghü'ib means the hidden world, namely, things which are not per-
ceived by the senses, mainly God and His attributes. God has created
manifest things whose aim is to serve as an indication (dalil) of the
hidden ones.-One must find the connection (ta'alluq) between the
manifest a n d the hidden things, and that is the act of istidlal o r qiyas.
B. Abrahamov, 'Ai-Qasirn ibn Ibráhim's Argument from Design',
Onens 29-30 ( 1 9 8 6 )p.~ 279, n. 103.
52. Tahrim al-nazar, p. 50.
53. H e refers here to asma' allüh al-husnü (God's most beautiful names,
most of which occur in the Qur'an). There is a controversy among the
theologians concerning the origin of God's names. Some of them
allow namirig God according to rational considerations, wliether rev-
elation affirms this o r not (al-Baqillani's stand), whereas some others
(e.g. al-Ghazali, Faklir al-Din al-Razi) state that God's names derive
from the Revelation, but His attributes can be learned by means of
reason. Fakhr al-Din al-Rázi, Laruami' al-bayyinát, p. 40. For a list and
disciissions of these names see al-Ghazali, al-Maqsad al-asna, sha. asma
allah al-husnü, ed. Muhammad Mustafa Abü al-'Ala', Cairo n.d.; Al-
Razi, ibid.; D. Gimaret, Les n o m divins en islam, exégise lexicographique et
theologique, Paris 1988.
54. It is to be noted that this argument is a part of the general argument
against the use of reason in religious matters, for religion means fol-
lowirig what is stated ir1 the Qur'an, Sunna and the statements of the
ancient scholars without comment (taqlid). Cf. al-Barbahari, Sharh al-
sunna, p. 42, para. 75. In his Risülat al-istihsan (p. 95, para. 23), al-
NOTES T O CHAPTER 3 83
70. For the developrnent of this terrn in Muslim religious literature, see
Abrahamov, al-Qüsim, p. 18of., n. 1. Ibn Abi al-'Izz, Sharh al-'aqida, vol.
1, p. 17.According to a staternent traced back to Malik ibn Anas and to
Abü Yüsuf al-Ansan, whoever seeks religion through the Kalam becornes
an infidel ( m a n talaba al-din bi'l-kaiüm tazandaqa). However, in Ibn
'Asakir's view, here the terrn Kalarn applies to the Kalarn of the inno-
vators (kalüm ahl al-bida') and not to the Kalarn of the traditionalists
(ahl al-sunna). This is his response to other staternents against the
Kalarn which are traced back to al-Shafi'i. Tabyin, pp. 334-7. T h e
Kalarn which agrees with the teachings of Qur'an and the Sunna and
which clarifies the true principles of religion when a controversy takes
place is praised by the scholars. Abstaining frorn dealing with the
Kalarn methods in the period of the Mihna is explained by Ibn 'Asakir
through the scholars' unwillirigness to be involved in debates in the
courts of rulers, which can bring about persecutions. Ibid., pp. 348-51.
Alternatively, h e says that if one engages only in the Kalarn and aban-
dons the learning of the Law and also does not carry out the precepts,
o n e becomes an infidel. Tabyin, p. 334. Al-Suyiiti, quotes a question, to
the contents of which he does not agree, frorn which one learns the
value of the Kalarn as a good innovation, for it fights the unbelievers
and the heretics, distinguishes between truth and lie, cancels man's
doubts and supplies proofs for the trustworthiness of the Prophet and
other religious principles. Sazun, vol. 1, p. 209f. As we have shown (see
above, pp. igff.), the use of Kalarn systerns of discussion was not carried
out only by professional theologians, but also by scholars from differ-
e n t systerns of thought, Shafi'ites, Malikites, Süfis. Cf. Frank, Al-Ghazüli
on Taqlid, p. 218. However, in rnany cases, what was learned through
the Kalarn did not serve as the basis of religious principles, but rather
as a corroboration for what was already known through taqlid. 'Abd al-
Jabbar explains that those who narne the Kalani an innovation d o so
out of ignorance; whoever does not know something, hates it. Fadl al-
i'tizül, p. 184.
71. Ibn Abi al-'Izz, Sharh al-'aqida, vol. I, pp. 17f., 247. O n e should note the
possibility that both al-Ansari's stand and al-Shafi'i's are not authentic
and rnay be a projection of the ideas of later generations in order to
garner legitimation from the ancients, a phenornenon which is well
known in Islarnic religious literature. Anyhow, we can say confidently
that the tendency to discredit the Kalarn is evident in classical Islam at
least in later generations. Likewise, al-Shiifi'i is depicted as favouring
'ilm al-kalüm. E. Chaumont, 'Al-Shafi'i', EI2, vol. 9, p. 183.
72. Sha- al-sunna, vol. 1, p. 228.
73. Among his works there is Marülim al-sunanfi sha- kitüb al-sunan li-abi
da'üd.
74. This is also the view of al-Shafi'i. Al-Baghawi, ibid.
75. Al-Baghawi, ibid., p. 229. This stand is contrary to Ibn T a y m i ~ a ' state-
s
ment that ahl al-sunna neither declare a Muslim an unbeliever on ac-
count of a sin nor prevent people frorn praying behind hirn. A Muslim
should be a friend of his co-religionist, n o t a n enerny. Rmü'il riia-fatüruü
shaykn al-islam, ed. Muharnmad Rashid Rida, Cairo 1992 (repr.), vol. 2,
part 5, PP. 241-4.
NOTES TO CHAPTER 4 85
12. For example, Al-Baqillani, aGTamhid, pp. 22ff. Al-Juwayni, al-Zrshüd, pp.
39ff. Al-Baghddi, UsüL,pp. 33ff.
13. Gimaret, La doctrine d'al-Ash'an, p. 213. Cf. Al-Rázi, Muhqsal, p. 134.
14. Al-Baghdádi, Usül, p. 256f. Al-Nasafi, Tabsirat al-adilla, vol. 2, p. 452. See
Appendix 11. Reinhart, Before Revelation, p. 19. Frank, Al-Ghazüli and the
Ash'arite School, p. gf.
15. Manakdim, Sharh, p. 151.
16. Ibid., p. 156.
17. Ibid., p. 161.
18. Al-Baqillani, al-Tamhid, p. 197.
19. Quoting Ibn Manda, Abü 'Abdallah Muhammad ibn Ishaq (d. 395/
I O O ~ al-Taymi
), says: 'Traditions concerning God's attributes have
been transmitted from the Prophet through tawütur. These traditions
are compatible with God's Book. Al-Taymi, al-Hujja, vol. 1, p. gi. 'God
has described himself as being hearing and seeing and said: "There is
nothing like Him; H e is the All-hearing, the All-seeing (Qur'an
42.11)". H e had informed that H e hears al1 the voices from al1 direc-
tions. H e has not ceased to hear and see and He will never cease to
hear and see.' Ibid., p. gq.
20. Wolfson, Kalam p. 132.Abrahamov, al-Qüsim, p. 21.
21. Sctimidtke, al-Hilli, p. 166f.
22. T h e Qur'an mentions God's knowledge ('ilm, e.g. Qur'an 4.166, 2.255)
and power (quwwa, e.g. Qur'án 51.58, 41.15).
23. Abrahamov, al-Qasim, p. 37, n. 229.
24. Abrahamov, 'A Re-examination', pp. 21c-21.
25. Sharh, vol. 2, pp. 639, 65-2.
26. Ibid., vol. 1, pp. 242-8. According to Ibn Abi al-'Izz, some eminent
scholars of the Kalam, such as al-Ghazali, al-Shahrastani and aljuwayni,
have regretted their preoccupation with the Kalam. Ibid., pp. 243-5.
27. Ibid., vol. 1, p. 39f.
28. Abrahamov, al-Qüsim, pp. 190-2, n. 89. See above, Chapter 3, n. 32.
29. R. M. Frank, 'Several Fundamental Assumptions of the Basra School
of the Mu'tazila', Studia Islamica33 (1g71),pp. 5-18. Idem, 'Reason and
Revealed Law: A Sample of Parallels and Divergences in Kalam and
Falsafa', Recherches d%lamologie - Recueil d'articles offd a George C.
Anauiati et Louis Gardet par leurs collegues et amis, Louvain 1978, pp. 124-
9. Idem, al-Ghazali and the Ash'arite School, p. 32. Reinhart, Before Revela-
tion, p. 13. G. F. Hourani, 'The Rationalist Ethics of 'Abd al-Jabbar', in
his Reason and Traúition in Zslamic Ethics, pp. 98-108. It is important to
note that almost al1 the eminent Sháfi'itie theologians beginning with
two generations after al-Anmati (d. 288/900) considered the intellect
as a source of knowledge. Al-Qaffal (365/976) seems to have been
influenced by the Mu'tazilites in this subject matter. Reinhart, ibid., p.
17ff. O n e of the exceptions is Abü Sa'id 'Abd al-Rahman al-Naysabüri
(known as al-Mutawalli al-Shafi'i, d. 478/1085), who says: 'Only Revela-
tion obliges man, and before Revelation there was n o rule'. Al-Ghunya
JZ usül aldin, ed. 'Imad al-Din Ahmad Haydar, Beirut 1987, p. 138. Also
among the Mutakallimün of ahl al-hadith we find Abü al-'Abbas al-
Qalanisi (fl. in the second half of the third/ninth century), who held
rational imposition of duties (taklif 'aqli) and the possibility to know
88 NOTES
45. According to the Shi'ite Muhammad ibn al-Hasan al-Tüsi (d. 460/
ro67), they are so called because they are detested by the tormented
person: al-Iqtisád, p. 221. They are the angels of death. A. J. Wensinck,
'Munkar wa-Nakir', EIz, vol. 7, p. 576f.
46. Al-Tüsi notes that o n e must not take into consideration 'Amr's view,
since it came after a consensus on the belief in this dogma had been
achieved. Ibid., p. 219. But according to 'Abd al-Jabbar, the denial of
'adháb alqabrwas ascribed to the Mu'tazilites because Dirar ibn 'Amr
was the first to deny this doctrine and h e was one of (the Mu'tazilite)
Wasil ibn 'AtaMsfollowers. Faúl al-l'tizüí, p. 201.
47. Manakdim, Sharh, p. 733.
48. Ibid., p. 730f.
49. Ibid., p. 731, l. I to p. 732, 1. 1.
50. Ibid., p. 732.
51. Cf. Abrahamov, 'A Re-examination', p. 219.
52. For the description of the Balance, its actions and related topics, see
al-Ghazali, Ihyü', KV, pp. 520-4. Al-Qurtubi, aCTadhkira fi ahwal al-muruta
wa-umür al-akhira, Cairo 1980.
53. Manakdim seems to regard light and darkness as bodies and not as
accidents.
54. Mánakdim, Sharh, p. 735.
55. Al-Ghazali, Ihyü', vol. 4, p. 524.
56. Here this term denotes traditionists who accept anthropomorphic tra-
ditions as true. Cf. Abrahamov, al-Qasim, p. 188, n. 69.
57. Sharh, p. 737.
5. Ibid., p. 385.
6. According to al-Ghazali, quoting an anonymous Hanbalite, even Ibn
Hanbal used figurative interpretations regarding some anthropomor-
phic expressions such as 'The Black Stone is God's right hand o n the
earth'. Ibn Taymiyya, who relates this report, does not tmst it. Sha-
hadith aCnuzül, pp. 203-5. T h e Máturidite scholar al-Bazdawi (d. 493/
1099) states that Ibn Hanbal was a pious man who did not hold anthro-
pomorphism. Usül a l d i n , p. 253.
7. Al-Iqtisüd fi- al-l'tiqüd, ed. 1. A. Cubukcu a n d H. Atay, Ankara 1962, p.
212.
8. Frank, Al-Ghazüli and &heAsh'arite School, p. 7f.
9. Al-Qistüs al-mustaqim. See above, p. 18. Cf. Reinhart, Before Rtwelation,
p. 158. Peters, God's Created Speech, p. 15.
10. 'Imara, Rasü'il al-'adl wa'l-tawhid, vol. 2, p. 301f.
i r . Al-Zamakhshari, al-Kashshüj vol. 2, p. qqrf.
12. For this term in the Mu'tazilite 'Abd al-Jabbar, see Peters, God's Created
Speech, pp. 65-8.
13. Ibn Taymiyya, Rasü'il wa-fatüwü, vol. 2, part V, p. 45.
14. Ibid., vol. 1, part 1, p. 246. Instead of al-manqül al-sanh, one should read
al-manqül al-sahih. This notion is stated again and again in his volumi-
nous work Dar' taarud al-'aql uia'l-naql (The repuision of the contra-
diction between reason and tradition) o r Muwüfaqat sahih al-manqül
li-sañh al-marqul (The agreement of the t m e tradition with clear
reason). T h e term sanh al-'aql (the plain perception of the intellect)
was already used by Fakhr al-Din al-&¡ in his Ma'ülim usül aldin, ed.
Taha 'Abd al-Ra'üf Sa'd, Cairo n.d., p. 25.
15. Abrahamov, 'Ibn Taymiyya on the Agreement', p. 271f.
16. Ibid., p. 272.
17. See above Chapter 5, p. 35.
CHAPTER 7: SUMMARY
I. For rationalist trends iri early Shafi'ism, see Madelung, Religzous
Trends, p. 28.
APPENDIX 1
1. Al-Lalaka'i, Sharh usúl, vol. 1, pp. 176ff. Blessings of God and the
Prophet are omitted. T h e numbers of sections are mine. For transla-
tion of some creeds, see Watt, Islamic Creeds.
2. This dogma reflects the opposition to the teaching of the extreme
sects of the Murji'a, which state that belief is only saying the shahüda
and the knowledge of God (Al-Ash'ari, Maqülat, pp. lyff.), and also to
the teaching of Abü Hanifa, who is said to have belonged to the
Murji'ites. Wensinck, The Muslim Creed, pp. 125, 131ff.Since action is
included in belief, belief can increase o r decrease.
3. Since the Qur'an is God's speech and God's speech is one of His
attributes, which are not created but eternal, the Qur'ari is not
created. T h e authors seem to mean by 'in al1 its aspects' the different
NOTES T O A P P E N D l X 1 95
12. Cf. Wasiyyat Abi Hanija, Wensinck, ibid., p. 130, art. 21. Al-Rasa'il al-
sab'a, p. gq. Al-Ghazali, Ihyü', vol. 4, p. 520f. (sifat al-mizün, T h e Descrip
tion of the Balance).
13. This is the Basin which the Prophet will be given in Paradise. Al-Ajüri,
al-Shan'a, pp. 352-7. Al-Ghazali, ibid., pp. 528-30. EIz, vol. 3, p. 286.
14. Both the traditionalists a n d the Mu'tazilites believe in the intercession
of the Prophet. However, they disagree o n the application of it.
According to the traditionalists, the Prophet rnay intercede with God
for the sinner who is in Hell, whereas the Mu'tazilites state that h e
may d o so only for the repenter. Manakdim, Sharh, p. 688. In al-Ajurí's
view, the Mu'tazilites hold sucti a notion, since they rely o n the ambi-
guous verses of the Qur'an a n d on their reason instead of relying on
traditions. Al-Shañ'a, pp. 331-9. Wensinck's statement that the
Mu'tazilites rejected al1 intercession ( T h e Muslim Creed, p. 182) is mis-
leading. It is worth noting that not only may Muhammad intercede
with God for the sinner but so too may other prophets, angels, saints,
pious scholars, rnartyrs and any person who has high standing in
God's eyes. Al-Ajúri, ibid., pp. 349-52 Al-Ghazali, ibid., p. 526.
15. O n this dogma, there is general agreement among the Muslims.
Husayri Ibn Iskandar al-IJanaA, al-Jawhara al-munvafi sharh wasiyyat al-
imám al-akam Abi Hanifa Al-Rasa'il al-sabá, p. 96. Wensinck, The Muslim
Creed, p. 130.
16. See the following note.
17. Cf. Fiqh Akbar, Wensinck, ibid., p. 103, art. I. Daiber, Belief; pp. 33ff.
Wasiyyat Abi Hanva, Wensinck, ibid., p. 125,art. 4. Al-Rasü'il al-sabra, p.
77. Ibn Abi al-'Izz, Sharh, vol. 2, p. 524. Contrary to the Mu'tazilites,
who brand the grave sinner a n unbeliever, unless h e repents of his sin,
and to the Kharijites, who regard the grave sinner as an unbeliever
and sometimes even as a pagan, the traditionalists, following the
Murji'ites, entrust the judgernent of the grave sinner to God and d o
not exclude him from the Muslim community. Cf. Cook, Early Muslim.
Dogma, chs 5, 7. Watt, The Formative Period, p. 126f.
18. This article and the following ones (18-20) deal with the obligation to
obey the leaders of the community, be they just o r unjust, and to
cooperate with them in carrying out precepts for which they are
responsible o r which are relevant to them, such as the Holy War, the
~ i l g r i m a ~giving
e, alms, division of spoils, and the Friday prayer. Al-
Lalaka'i, Sharh, pp. 160f., 167f., 182f. In the creed of 'Ali ibn al-Madini,
it is stated that people must have an imam. Ibid., p. 167
19. Whoever follows the Qur'an and the Sunna has fixed dogmas which
cannot change, therefore one should refrain from dealing with debates
and controversies. Cf. ibid., pp. 165, 175
2 0 . This is again an article aimed against the Kharijites, who excommuni-
cate anyone who commits a grave sin.
21. That is because one cannot know whether his belief is right in the eyes
of God. This article is divided into three parts: (1) O n e should not say
that h e is a believer, for belief in the present creed is composed of
saying and actions, and one cannot be sure that he carries out good
deeds. Abu Hanifa's teaching that faith consists only of belief (tasdiq)
and knowledge lies in the background of this part. (2) O n e should say:
NOTES T O A P P E N D I X 1 97
'1 arn a believer, if God wills', for one cannot know what his destiny is.
It seems that the first two parts deal with rnan's status with respect to
belief, whereas the third one is a rnere declaration; o n e says that his
statement of belief in God is tme, that is, one does not refer to his
objective status as a believer, but to his subjective estirnation. Cf. Al-
mi,Mafátih alghayb, vol. 15, p. 121f.(Qur'an 8.4). Wensinck, The Muslim
Creed, pp. 138-40. Al-Rasü'il al-sabra, p. 77.
22. God's foreknowledge irnpairs man's free will, since if God knows
beforehand what o n e will do, one rnust act in accordance with God's
knowledge, otherwise God has no knowledge of one's acts, which is an
absurdity. Most of the Qadarites (we mean by this appellation the
groups which were the forerunners of the Mu'tazila) held that God's
foreknowledge has the function of remernbrance and not of causa-
tion. Van Ess, AnJange, p. 116f.,pp. qq, qg of the Arabic text. Cf. Schwarz,
'The Letter', p. 29f.
23. T h e reason for this appellation is either their holding the view that
the Qur'án is created o r generally their cancellation of the attributes.
See above, n. 3.
24. This pejorative narne is generally applied to thern because they rejected
the first two caliphs, Abu Bakr and 'Uinar. Abraharnov, 'Al-Qasim ibn
Ibrahirn's Theory of the Irnarnate', p. gq, n. 70.
25. They are so called probably because they deviate from the teachings
of rnost Muslirns concerning the status of the grave sinner, the obliga-
tion to rebel against an oppressive leader and so on. Al-Baghdadi, al-
Farq, p. 45.
26. See n. 3 above.
27. T h e text here is not in order.
28. Al-Lalaka'i, Sha. usiiI, vol. 1, p. 152 (the creed of Suban al-Thawri [d.
161/778]) and p. 183 (the creed of Sahl al-Tustari [d. 283/896]). This
article appears as follows in Wasiyyat Abi Hanqa (Wensinck, The Muslim
Creed, p. 129, art. 16. Al-Rasü'il al-sab'a, p. 89): 'We confess that the
moistening of shoes is obligatory for those who are at home diiring a
day and a night, for travellers during three days and nights. This rule
is founded o n a tradition. Whosoever should reject it would be in
danger of unbelief, this tradition being nearly equivalent to an abso-
lutely reliable report.' T h e Shi'ites and the Kharijites opposed wiping
off the shoes instead of washing the feet as it is ordered in Qur'án 5.6.
Contrary to this practice, the traditionalists introduce pieces of
evidence which prove that the Prophet used to wipe off his shoes after
the revelation of Qur'an 5.6. Wensinck, ibid., p. 158. For the develop-
ment of this article in the schools of law, see ibid., p. 15gf.
29. Al-Lálaká'i, ibid., .p. 152 (the creed of Sufyan al-Thawri). Al-Baghawi,
-
APPENDIX 11
1. This is a treatise of 'Abd al-Jabbár (d. between qi4-16/1023-5), o n e of
the eminent scholars of the Mu'tazila. See, on him, Peters, God's Created
Speech, pp. 6-23. In the following, 1 shall translate some passages from
his introduction to the Mukhtasar. T h e text was edited by Muhammad
'Imára in Rasá'il al-'adl wa'l-taruhid, Beirut and Cairo 1988, part i, pp.
i97ff.
2. This terrn can also be rendered as 'theology'.
3. By taruhid, 'Abd aljabbar rneans several theological issues: (1) proving
the creation of the world; (2) proving the existence of the Creator; (3)
explaining the attributes which H e deserves; (4) the knowledge of the
attributes of the created things which cannot be applied to Him; and
(5) proving His unity. Ibid., p. 202.
4. Answering the following question, 'Do you not (meaning the
Mu'tazilites) hold five principles in addition to the taruhid a n d 'udl, in-
cluding the prornise and the threat (al-wa'ú wa'l-wa'id), the interrnedi-
ate position (manzila bayna al-manzilatayn) and the command o r the
urge to d o what is approved a n d the prohibition against doing what is
reprehensible (al-amr bi'l-marnif rua'l-nahy 'un al-munkar)?', 'Abd al-
Jabbar states that these three principles are subsunied urider the prin-
ciple of God's justice ('adl). Ibid., p. 198.
5. T h e text has al-'ama1 bi'l-taqlid, which seems to be erroneous.
6. These verses and others of the same contents are also used by philoso-
phers and other thinkers to prove that the Qur'an urges people to
examine existence. See, for example, Ibn Rushd, Fasl al-maqül ftma
bayna al-hikma wa'l-shañ'a min al-ittisál, ed. Muhamniad 'Imara, Cairo
1969, p. 22f. Muhammad 'Abduh, al-Arnuilal-Kümila li'l-invim Muhamrnad
'Abduh, ed. Muhammad 'Irnára, Beirut 1972,vol. 3, pp. 278-81.
APPENDIX 111
I. These are passages from al-Báqillani's al-Taqnb wa'l-irshad al-saghir, vol.
I , pp. 228ff. Cf. Aljuwayni, al-Burhán, p. i 10, art. 54.
2. T h e word ahküm, which is usually rendered as 'niles' o r 'precepts'
must be rendered here as 'principles', for as we shall imrnediately see,
ahküm applies to dogmas and not to religious laws.
3. ahdatha means exactly to bring something into being, and hudúth al-
'ülam is the fact that the world was brought into being. Very probably,
the source of this term stenis from verses in the Qur'an (18.70, 20.113,
21.2, 26.5, 56.1) in which the verb ahdatha occurs with the meaning of
'to bring something new'.
4. Cf. Aljuwayni, al-[rshüd, p. 301.
5. According to al-Baqillani, what God orders is good and what H e for-
bids is evil. Thus rationai considerations are not involved in evaluating
the moral state of man. Cf. Al-Juwayni, ibid.
6. Cf. Al-Juwayni, ibid., p. 301, 1. I to p. 302, 11. 1-4.
7. T h e following is a t r a n s l a t i ~ nof a part of this chapter which occurs in
t h e Mu'tazilite Abü al-Husayn al-Basri, al-Mu'tamad, vol. 2, p. 886-9.
8. T h e knowledge that God is o n e a n d wise does not serve as a conditioii
100 NOTES
of knowing the soundness of Tradition, for even if there were two wise
gods, they would not send a liar as a prophet.
APPENDIX IV
t. This work is ascribed to the Zaydite theologian al-Qasirn ibn Ibráhirn
(d. 246/860). Its authenticity is regarded as suspect by Madelung (Dm
Imam, p. 100). However, for our purpose the question of the
genuineness of the treatise is not relevant, because we are concerned
only with operation of reason in it. As we shall see, reason occupies
the highest place in the description of the roots of law. In the follow-
ing, sorne passages of the treatise will be translated. The text appears
in 'Irnára's Rasü'il al-adl wa'l-tawhid, part 1, pp. 124.ff.
2. The author here states that (1) the principie of Consensus occurs in
each of these proofs and ( 2 ) it derives frorn each of thern.
3. For tanal as equivalent to zühir (plain rneaning), see Abraharnov, Anthro
pomorphism, p. 33.
4. For selfevident verses and arnbiguous ones, see ibid., pp. 25-9.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENT
1 would like to tharik Mr David Brauner for correcting rny English.
102 REFERENCES A N D ABBREVIATIONS
'Aqa'id al-salaf; ed. 'Ali Sarni al-Nashshar and 'Arnmár al-Tálibi, Alexandria
'97'
Al-Ash'ari, Abü al-Hasan 'Ali ibn Isrna'il, al-Ibana 'un usü1 al-diyana, Idarat
al-Tiba'a al-Muniriyya, Cairo n.d. (= al-Ash'ari, al-Ibüna)
- Kitüb al-luma' fz'l-radd 'ala ahl al-zaygh wa'l-&da: ed. and tr. R. J.
McCarthy, The Theology of al-Ashári, Beimt 1953. (= al-Ash'ari, al-Luma?
- Risülat istihsün al-khawd f z 'ilm al-kalam, ed. and tr. R J. McCarthy, The
Theology of al-Ashári. (= al-Ash'ari, Risalat istihsün)
Al-Baghawi, Abü Muhamrnad al-Husayn ibn Mas'üd al-Farra', Sharh al-
sunna, ed. Shu'ayb al-Arna'üt a n d Muhamrnad Zuhayr al-Shawish, Bei-
rut 1983. (= al-Baghawi, Sharh al-sunna)
Al-Baghdádi, Abü Mansür 'Abd al-Qahir ibn Tahir, G ü l aldin, Istanbul
1928. (= al-Baghdadi, UsüC)
Al-Baqillani, Abü Bakr Muhammad ibn al-Tayyib, Kitüb al-tamhid, ed. R J.
McCarthy, Beirut 1957. (= al-Baqillani, al-Tamhid)
- al-Taqñb wa'l-irshüd al-saghir, ed. 'Abd al-Hamid ibn 'Ali, alQasim 1993.
(= al-Baqillani, al-Taqnb)
Al-Barbahari, Abü Muharnmad al-Hasan ibn 'Ali, Kztüb sharh al-sunna, ed.
Muharnrnad ibn Sa'id al-Qahpni, Makka AH 1414 [AD 19931. (= Al-
Barbahari, Sharh al-sunna)
Al-Bayhaqi, Abü Bakr Ahmad ibn al-Husayn, al-I'tiqüd wa'l-hidüya ila sabil
al-rashüd 'ala madhhab al-saúzf wa-ashüb al-hadith, ed. Al-Sayyid al-
Jurnayli, Cairo 1988. (= al-Bayhaqi, al-I'tiqüd)
Al-Bazdawi, Abü al-Yusr Muharnrnad ibn Muharnmad, Kitüb usül aldin, ed.
H. P. Linss, Cairo 1963. (= al-Bazdawi, QÜ1 aldin)
Al-Bukhári Muhamrnad ibn Isrna'il, Khalq afal al-'ibüd, in 'Aqü'id al-salaJ
Alexandria 1971.
Al-Daraqutni, 'Ali ibn 'Umar, Akhbar 'Amr ibn Ubayd, ed., tr. and cornmen-
tary J. van Ess ( Traditionistische Polemik gegen Xmr B. Ubaid), Beimt 1967.
Al-Darirni, 'Uthman ibn Sa'id, al-Radd áúi al-jahmiyya, in 'Aqü'id al-salaf;
Alexandria 1971.(= al-Darimi, al-Radd 'ala aljahmiyya)
- al-Radd 'aúi al-Mansi al-'unid, in 'Aqü'id al-salaf; Alexandria 1971. (= al-
Darimi, al-Radd 'ala al-Marisi)
Al-Fürabi on the Perfect State: A& N.;r al-Fürabi's Mabüdi' Ara' Ahl al-Madina
al-Füdila, ed., tr. and cornmentaiy R. Walzer, Oxford 1985.
Al-Ghazali, Abü Hámid Muhammad ibn Muharnmad, Faysal al-tafnqa
bayna al-islám wa'l-zandaqa, ed. Muhamrnad Badr al-Din al-Na'sani,
Cairo 1907. (= al-Ghazali, Faysal al-tafnqa)
- Ihyü' rulüm aldin, Cairo (Al-Maktaba al-Tijariyya al-Kubrá) n.d. (= al-
Ghazáli, Ihyü)
- al-Maqsad al-asna, Sharh asma' alúih al-husnü, ed. Muharnrnad Mustafa
Abü al-'Ala', Cairo n.d.
- TahÜJut al-faúisifa, tr. S. van d e n Bergh (The Incoherente of the Philoso-
phers), London 1954.
- al-Iqtisüd fz'l-i'tiqüd, Cairo (Maktabat al-Husayn al-Tijariyya) n.d. (= al-
Ghazali, al-Iqtisüd) ed. 1. A. Cubukcu and H. Atay, Ankara 1962.
Ibn 'Abd al-Barr, Abü 'Umar Yüsuf, Jümi' bayün al-'ilm wa-fadlihi, ed. Abü
al-Ashbál al-Zuhayri, Riyadh 1994. (= Ibn 'Abd al-Barr, Jümi?
Ibn Abi aLCIzz,'Ali ibn 'Ni, Sharh al-'aqida al-tahawiyya, ed. 'Abdallah ibn
'Abd al-Muhsin al-Turki and Shu'ayb al-Arna'üt, Beirut 1991.(= Ibn Abi
'O4 REFERENCES A N D A B B R E V I A T I O N S
- Ma'ünj al-wusül ilü al-marrifa anna usül aldin warfuniáha qad bayyanahü
al-rasiil, in Majmü'at al-Rusü'il al-kubw Cairo n.d.
- Iqtida' al-sirüt al-mustaqim mukhülufat ashüb al-jahim, ed. 'Isarn al-Din al-
Sababati, Cairo AH 1412[AD 19911.(= Ibn Tayrniyya, Iqtidü) [annotated
tr. by M. Muhamrnad Urnar, Ibn Taymiyya's Struggle Against Popular Reli-
gion, Paris 1976.1
- Dar' ta'ürud al-'ql wa'l-nql, ed. Muharnrnad Rashad Salirn, Riyadh 1979
(10 vols) (= Ibn Tayrniyya, Dar?
- aLrAqida al-wüsitiyya, ed., tr. and cornmentaiy H. Laoust, La Profesion de
foi d 'lbn Taymiyya, Paris 1986.
- Raf al-rnalam 'un a6a'imma al-a'lüm, ed. Abü Mus'ab Muharnrnad Sa'id al-
Badri, Cairo and Beirut 1991.(= Ibn Tayrniyya, Raf'al-malam)
- h a 2 1 wa-fatüwü shaykh al-islam, ed. Muharnrnad Rashid Rida, Cairo 1992
(repr.).
- Sha. haúith al-nuzüi, ed. Muhamrnad Ibn 'Abd al-Rahrnan al-Kharnis,
Riyadh 1993.
Al-Jassas, Abü Bakr Ahrnad ibn 'Ali, a l - l j m : ed. Zuhayr Shafiq Kabbi, Bei-
rut 1993. (= al-Jassas, al-4-7
Al-Jurjani, 'Ali Ibn Muharnrnad, Kttüb al-ta'ñfat, Beirut 1978 (repr. of
G. Flügel's Leipzig 1847 edn). (= aljurjani, K al-taiifat)
Al-Juwayni, Abü al-Ma'ali 'Abd al-Malik ibn 'Abdallah Irnarn al-Haramayn,
al-Irshad ilii qawüti' al-adilla ji usül al-i'tiqüd, ed. As'ad Tarnirn, Beirut
1985. (= al-Juwayni, al-Irshad)
- al-BurhünJt usül al-Jiqh, ed. 'Abd al-'Azirn Muhamrnad al-Dib, al-Mansüra
1992. (= al-Juwayni, al-Burhün)
Al-Khayyat, Abü al-Husayn 'Abd al-Rahirn ibn Muharnrnad, Kitüb al-intisür
wa%radd 'ala Ibn al-Riiwandi al-Mulhid, ed. H. S. Nyberg, Cairo 1925,
with A. A. Nader's tr. into French, Beirut 1957.(= al-Khayyat, al-Intisür)
Al-Ldaka'i, Abü al-Qasim Hibat Allah ibn al-Hasan, Sha* usül irtiqüd ahl
al-sunna wa'ljamüa min al-kitüb wa'l-sunna wa-+ir al-sahüba wa'l-tabitn
min ba'dihim, ed. Ahmad Sa'd Hamdán, Makka AH 1402 [AD 19811.(=
al-Lalaka'i, Sha. usü0
Manakdirn Ahrnad ibn al-Husayn, Sharh al-usül al-khamsa, ed. 'Abd al-
Karirn 'Uthrnan (as a work of 'Abd al-Jabbar), Cairo 1965. ('Abd al-
Jabbar, Sha.)
Al-Maqdisi, Abü Hárnid Muhamrnad (d. 888/ 1483), Risülu 3'1-radd 'ala al-
rüjida, ed. 'Abd al-Wahhab Khalil al-Rahrnan, Bornbay 1983.
A-Maturidi, Abü Mansiir Muharnrnad ibn Muharnrnad, Kitüb al-tawhid, ed.
Fathallah Kholeif, Beirut 1970. (= al-Maturidi, K al-tawhzd)
Al-Muhasibi, Abü 'Abd Allah al-Harith ibn Asad, Kitüb mü'iyat al-'aql wa-
ma'nühu wa-ikhtilaf al-nüsfihi, in al-'Aql wa-fahm alqur'ün, ed. Husayn al-
Quwwatili, Beirut 1982. (= al-Muhasibi, K m'iyat al-$0
Al-Munjidji al-lugha wa'l-a'lam, Beirut 1973. ( = al-Munjid)
al-Nasafi, Abü al-Mu'in Maymün ibn Muharnrnad, Tabsirat al-adillaji u ~ ü 1
aldin, ed. C. Salarné, Darnascus 1990.
Al-Naysabüri, Abü Sa'id 'Abd al-Rahrnan, al-Ghunya fi usül aldin, ed.
'Irnad al-Din Ahrnad Haydar, Beirut 1987.
Al-Nazzarn, Ibrahirn ibn Sayyár, Kitüb al-nakth, in J . van Ess, Das Kitab an-
Nakth des N a m m und seine Rmeptiun im Kitab alFutyü des &his Gottingen
1972.(= al-Nwzarn, K al-nakth)
REFERENCES A N D ABBREVIATIONS 'O5
SECONDARY SOURCES
'Abd al-Rahman ibn Salih al-Mahmüd, M a w q q I h Taymiyya min al-Asharira,
Riyadh 1995.
Abrahamov, B., 'Al-Qasim ibn Ibrahim's Argument from Design', Onens
29-30 (1986), PP. 259-84.
- 'Al-Qásim ibn Ibrahim's Theory of the Imamate', Arabica 34 (1987). PP.
80-105.
- 'The Barahima Enigma: A Search for a New Solution', Die Welt des O n a t s
'8 (1987)>PP. 72-91.
- 'A Reexamination of al-Ash'ari's Theory of Kasb according to Kitab al-
Luma", Journal ofthe @al Asiatic So&ty (198g),pp. 210-21. (= Abrahamov,
'A Re-examination')
- Al-Qüsim i h Ibrahim on the Proof of God's Existence Kitüb al-Dalil al-Kabir,
Islamic Philosophy and Theology Texts and Studies vol. 5, Leiden 1990.
(= Abrahamov, al-Qüsim)
- 'Ibn Taymiyya o n the Agreement of Reason with Traditiori', The Muslim
World 82:3-4 (1992)~ PP. 256-72. (= Abrahamov, 'Ibn Tayrniyya')
- 'Abd aljabbar's Theory of Divine Assistance ( L u v )', Jerusala Studies in
Arabic and Islam 16 (1993)~PP. 41-58. (= Abrahamov, "Abd aljabbar's
Theory')
- 'Al-Ghazalí's Supreme Way to Know God', Studia Islamica 77 (1gg3), pp.
141-68. (= Abrahamov, 'Al-Ghazali's Supreme Way')
- 'Necessary Knowledge in Islamic Theology', British Journal of Middb East-
m Studies 2 0 (1993)~ p p 20-32. (= Abrahamov, 'Necessary Knowledge')
- 'The Appointed Time of Death (Agal) according to 'Abd al-Gabbar',
Israel Oriental Studies 13 (1993)~pp. 8-38.
- 'The Ri-la Kayfa Doctrine and its Foundations in Islamic Theology',
Arabica 42:3 ( 1 ~ g 5 )pp.
, 365-79. (= Abrahamov, Bi-la Ka3lfa)
- Anthropomo~phismand Interpetation of the Qur'an in the Theology of al-Qüsim
ibn Ibrühim - Kitüb al-Mustarshzd, Islamic Philosophy Theology and Science
Texts and Studies, vol. 26, Leiden 1996. (= Abrahamov, Anthropomorphism)
Arberry, A. J., Reuelation and Reason i n Islam, London 1971.(= Arberry, Reu-
elation and Reason)
- The Koran Interpeted, Oxford 1983.
Bello, 1. E., The Medieual Ishmic Controversy between Philosophy and Orthodoxy:
REFERENCES A N D ABBREVIATIONS 1°7
Ijrná' and Ta'wil in the Conflict between Al-Ghazüli and Ibn Rushd, Islamic
Philosophy and Theology Texts and Studies, vol. 3, Leiden 1989.
Berriand, M., 'L'Igma' chez 'Abd al-Gabbar et l'objection d'an-Nazzam',
Studia Islamica 30 ( 1 9 6 9 )pp.
~ 27-38.
- L'Accord unanime de la communauté comme f o n d e v t des statuts kgaux de
li'slam d 'aplis Abzi al-Husain al-Basn, Collection Etudes musulmanes XI,
Paris 1970.
- 'Nouvelles remarques sur l'i@ü'chez le Qadi 'Abd al-Gabbar', Araúica 19
(1972) P P 78-85.
9