Continental Philosophy Review Volume 10 Issue 4 1977 (Doi 10.1007 - bf01248839) Joseph Bien, Peter Kirk Augustine - On N
Continental Philosophy Review Volume 10 Issue 4 1977 (Doi 10.1007 - bf01248839) Joseph Bien, Peter Kirk Augustine - On N
Continental Philosophy Review Volume 10 Issue 4 1977 (Doi 10.1007 - bf01248839) Joseph Bien, Peter Kirk Augustine - On N
The aim of this paper, then, is to examine the Discourse on Inequality in the
light of this thesis. The fundamental hypothesis underlying this effort is that,
if Rousseau is to be understood as having intended "man's destiny is to be
x" whenever he wrote "man is by nature x " - - f o r precisely that appears to
be Cassirer's claim, then a close inspection of the contexts in which "na-
ture," "natural," "by nature," and "naturally" occur should confirm that
claim--or at least allow it.
Let us look, then, at Rousseau's usage in the Discourse on Inequality
beginning with the term "naturellement." This term's first occurrence is in a
context in which Rousseau is criticizing earlier theoreticians of the state of
466
ROUSSEAU'S DISCOURSE ON INEQUALITY
nature for having attributed to men in that condition ideas and knowledge
they could in fact have acquired only through a social existence. Speaking
specifically of the want of an acceptable definition for natural law, Rousseau
complains
Aussi toutes celies qu'on trouve dans les livres, outre le d6faut de n'~tre
point uniformes, ont-elles encore celui d'&re tir&s de plusieurs connaissances
que les hommes n'ont point naturellement [our emphasis], et des avan-
rages dont ils ne peuvent concevoir l'id6e qu'apr~s &re sortie de l'&at de na-
ture. a
The only plausible rendering of this sentence would seem to be one in which
"naturellement" is read as equivalent in meaning to "originally," or "in
their primitive condition."
Footnote (i) provides the only context in the entire essay in which the
claim is advanced that man is "naturally good," and this passage accordingly
is worthy of particular attention. Rousseau writes
Here the use of the verb "d6praver" seems dearly to indicate a transition
from a prior and somehow better to a subsequent and worse condition. And
though the logic of the use of that verb does not demand that the prior
and better state be identical to man's original condition, the larger context
makes this the most reasonable supposition.
There are other cases, however, in which "naturellement" seems to mean,
not "originally," but rather "in the ordinary course of events," "if nothing
unusual intervenes." So, at least, do we interpret the term in contexts such
as the following
9 . .on salt que la plupart des animaux, sans en excepter l'homme, sont
naturellement ~our emphasis] paresseux, et qu'ils se refusent ~t toutes sortes
de soins qui ne sont pas d'une absolue n6cessit6. 5
While it seems likely that this was meant to apply to men in their primitive
c.ondition, there is no suggestion that it could no equally well apply to men
living in society as well. The verbs are all in the present tense, and there is
no prior/subsequent distinction analogous to that introduced in the previous
467
JOSEPH BIEN / PETER KIRK AUGUSTINE
example by the use of "drprav&" On the other hand, it does not seem
plausible that "naturellement" could be read here as referring to man's
destiny, though to our knowledge Rousseau never excluded the notion that
men were destined to be lazy.
Does this mean that Rousseau's use of "naturellement" in the second
Discourse never can be interpreted as referring to destiny ? That is not quite
the case, as there is one instance in which, it seems to us, a reasonable person
might have some legitimate grounds for feeling that Rousseau was bringing
nature and destiny into a close relation
Ce n'est donc pas par l'avilissement des peuples asservis qu'il faut juger des
dispositions naturdles [our emphasis] de l'homme pour ou contre la servi-
tude, mais par les prodiges qu'on faits tousles peuples libres pour se garantir
de l'oppression, s
468
ROUSSEAU'S DISCOURSE ON I N E Q U A L I T Y
r~gles que la raison est ensuite forc& de r&ablir sur d'antres fondements,
quand, par ses d&eloppements successifs, die est venue ~ bout d'&ouffer la
nature. 12
l'une, que j'appelle nat~relle [our emphasis] ou physique, parce qu'elle est
6tablie par la nature... ; l'antre, qu'on peut appeler in6galit6 morai ou po.li-
tique, parce qu'elle d4pend d'une sorte de convention, et qu'elle est &ablie
ou du moins autoris& par le consentement des hommes) 4
Here the meaning seems to be clear : that which is natural is "pre-social."
This is confirmed when Rousseau, in discussing the period of the most
rudimentary forms of social organization, claims that it was extremely happy
and durable, "quoique... la piti6 naturelle [our emphasis] eut d6j~ souffert
quelque alt6ration,"15 and that the laws established in society "d&ruisirent
sans retour la libert4 naturelle. ''1~ These "natural" things must have ante-
dated society, for otherwise they could not have been subsequently "altered"
or "destroyed,"
469
JOSEPH BIEN / PETER KIRK A U G U S T I N E
47O
ROUSSEAU'S DISCOURSE ON INEQUALITY
Here we find that the human soul can ("pour ainsi dire") change its nature,
but that the resulting artificial man has no true foundation in nature. This
seems confirmed elsewhere, as Rousseau discusses the purpose of the essay
as being to "d~mdler ce qu'il y a d'originaire et d'artificiel dans Ia nature ac-
tuelle de l'homme. T M Hence there is no assertion that man has any "eternal"
nature : it varies from epoch to epoch, and Rousseau's concern is to study "la
nature actuelle" of man. Further notice that artificial elements can be in-
cluded in man's nature, along with original elements. Thus to determine that
x is a part of man's nature is not to determine that x is natural; it can be
non-natural and yet be natural to man, in the sense of being a part of his
nature. Consequently the conclusion noted above that reason is contrary to
nature--should not be interpreted to imply that reason is contrary to man's
nature. It is, of course, contrary to natural man's nature, but natural man is
not the only man. The man to whom reason is natural is himself contrary to
nature; his nature is non-natural.
This, it seems, has familiar overtones : man emerges from (impersonal)
nature and, through a socio-historical process, develops his own nature. The
471
JOSEPH BIEN / PETER KIRK AUGUSTINE
9 . .Rousseau did not demand from the community that it should increase
man's happiness, well-being, and pleasure--nor did he expect these benefits
to result from the establishment and consolidation of a future community--
but that it should secure his freedom and thus restore him to his true
destiny. 2z
Does this indeed represent what Rousseau wrote ? W e think not. In discussing
that earliest-social condition of man--already out of the state of nature, but
prior to the introduction of property, prior to. the establishment of laws,
and prior to any full development of morality--Rousseau wrote unequivocally
Plus on y r6fl&hit, plus on trouve que cet 6tat 6tait le moins sujet aux
r6votutions, le meilleur a l'homme [our emphasis], et qu'il n'en a dfi sortir
que par quelque funeste hasard, qui, pour l' utilit~ commune, edt d~ ne jamais
arriver [our emphasis]. L'exemple des sauvages qu'on a presque tous trouv~s
k ce point, semble confirmer clue le genre humain &ait [ait pour y rester
toujours [our emphasis]...28
472
ROUSSEAU'S DISCOURSE ON INEQUALITY
NOTES
1 Cassirer, Ernst : T h e Question o~ Jean-Jacques Rousseau. Translated and edited by Peter Gay.
NY, C o l u m b i a U n i v e r s i t y Press, 2954. P. ~26.
2 Cassirer, Ernst : Rousseau, K a n t , Goethe : T w o Essays. Translated by James G u t m a n n et al.
Princeton, Princeton U n i v e r s i t y Press, ~945, P. 2o.
8 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques : CEuvres completes, t. 2 : CEuvres philosophiques et politiques : des
premiers dcrits au Contrat social ~735-1762. Paris, Editions du Seuil, I97I. p. 21o.
4 Ibid., p. 25I.
5 Ibid., p. 256.
6 Ibid., p. 256.
7 Ibid., p. 235.
8 Ibid., p. 238.
9 Ibid., p. 2~o.
10 Ibid., p. 2Io.
111 Ibid., p. 21o.
12 Ibid., p. 2io.
i13 Ibid., p. 234.
:14 Ibid., p. 2:~1.
15 lbid., p. 23I.
!1,6 Ibid., p. 234.
17 Ibid., p. 257.
9 8 Ibid., p. 246, for example.
19 Ibid., p. 256.
2o Ibid., p. 227.
21 Ibid., p. 227.
22 Ibid., p. 213, 249.
2a Ibid., p. 210.
24 Ibid., p. 216.
25 Ibid., p. 246.
2~ Ibid., p. 2o~.
27 Cassirer, The Question of Jean-Jacques Rousseau, p. ~o6.
~8 Rousseau, p. 23i.
29 Cassirer, The Question of Jean-Jacques Rousseau, p. 64.
so The authors wish to acknowledge the helpful suggestions of A n t o n i o Cue and Louis W h i t e
Beck.
473