Revising Semiotic Theory
Revising Semiotic Theory
Revising Semiotic Theory
Abstract
Translation can only take place from one community to another when their
horizons can be fused. If the disparity is too great, then one horizon is distorted
in order to fit into that of the target language and culture. In substantiating this
claim, several concepts are discussed. First, translation theory is predicated on
the assumption that signs are translated from one community to another through
language. This involves the use of signs, but traditional semiotics has conflated
meaning and form into a sign function that make translation more difficult.
Hence, the concept of traditional semiotics needs to be rehabilitated. Second, a
model of language is presented that separates signs into epistemological and
ontological realms. This implies a Cartesian model of translation in which
thoughts and ideas are separated from their objects. This emphasis on
consciousness is balanced with a rehabilitated model of consciousness proposed
by Gadamer. This means that translation not only involves consciousness but
also epistemological distance. Third, a practical philosophy of hermeneutics is
employed in the translation of the traditional culture of Hawai’i. Translation
assumes that horizons are fused, but when disparate cultures are brought
together, this is not the usual outcome.
.
1.1 INTRODUCTION
Hans-Geog Gadamer (1989) argued that translation involves interpretation. This
is because each community has a horizon and people come from different backgrounds
and it is not possible to totally remove oneself from one’s background, history, culture,
education, and language. Each community, in other words has an entirely different
system of attitudes, beliefs, and ways of thinking. A horizon designates everything from a
particular position or point of view. Each horizon is situated. Understanding occurs
when one tries to stand within the horizon of another community. Gadamer (1889: 304)
treats understanding as a conversation or dialogue in which translators from different
communities attempt to interpret texts or stories that are based on their past experiences
and value-laden traditions (Vorurteil). The problem is that people have a “historically
effected consciousness” (wirkunggeschiches Bewußtsein) and this means that they are
embedded in the particular culture that shaped them. Hence, interpreting a text involves a
fusion of horizons where translators find a way to articulate the text of the other through
their own background. The success of this task is the focus of this essay.
It is argued that in order to translate from one language to another, one needs a
1
workable model of semiotics. Unfortunately, traditional semiotics hinders translation
rather than enhance it. For this reason, traditional semiotics is rehabilitated so that it can
provide a better access to other sign system and cognitive frames across languages. This
is the focus of the first part of this essay.
The second part has to do with the philosophy of language and the role that
language plays in thinking. Gadamer argues that language is the medium of human
experience. One exists within a language. Language is the fundamental way in which one
exists in the world. Hence, one is situated in language and understanding takes place in
that situation of linguisticality (Sprachlichkeit). He is not saying that language is an
instrument of thought but has a more Heideggerian view of language in that language
serves the object in that it lets it come into being (Erscheinung). For Gadamer,
experience is not wordless. It becomes an object by being named. One seeks the right
word that belongs to the thing. Hence, for Gadamer, the word belongs to the thing. In
this section of the essay, the dialogue between Gadamer and Habermas will be revisited
as this divergence of thought plays a major role in translating scientific concepts.
In part three, a practical philosophy of hermeneutics is employed in the translation
of the traditional culture of Hawai’i into American culture. The focus of this application
has to do with the Hawaiian Wedding Song. It is argued that the disparity between these
two horizons is significant and what purports to be a translation amounts from one culture
into another is more of a distortion of the source towards the target language and culture.
The author assumes that most translations are of this nature.
2
not as physical objects. In this regard, he has omitted the realm of ontology from his
model. His forms were mental objects. Such a model of semiotics limits sign systems
only to epistemology and does not account for ontological signs. In such a model,
symbols are grounded as mental objects and not as physical objects. These assumptions
merit re-investigation. The meaning, it is argued in this reanalysis, should belong to the
realm of epistemology and the form should belong to the realm of ontology. This was the
rationale behind glossematics (Hjelmslev, 1969).
The relationship between epistemology and ontology can also be found in a reformulation
in the triadic concept of the sign proposed by Peirce (1992). More will be said about this
later. What was implicit in the writings of Hjelmslev was the claim that the concept of the
sign needed to be reformulated. This shift involves moving from Hjelmslev’s
semiological planes to philosophical realms.
3
2.4 THE SOCIAL CONSTRUCTION OF REALITY
The social construction of reality by Peter Berger and Thomas Luckmann (1966)
characterizes a sociological concept that was slowly emerging among European scholars.
However, it was Berger and Luckmann who not only articulated the new paradigm but
coined the terms that are characteristically associated with this movement. One of the
major premises of this new school of thought is that knowledge is socially constructed.
They argued, for example, that what one considers to be real in one culture may not be so
in another. What is real to an American businessman may not be seen as real, for
example, to a Buddhist monk. Each of these individuals has constructed different social
realities. They went on to demonstrate that these social values were constructed through
several concomitant sociological processes (externalization, reification, and
internalization). They noted that ideas, thoughts, and feelings cannot be shared with
others unless they are first externalized through language.
4
A thought without a form is ineffable. Meanings must have a form or pattern of existence
in order to be shared with others. Once ideas, thoughts, and feelings are encoded into a
language, they become objectified or reified. They exist as objects or things outside of the
speakers who produced them. It is interesting to note that most linguists only study this
aspect of language, viz., dictionary meanings and grammatical rules. Finally, linguistic
codes exist in a social context among members of a speech community and these coded
forms influence them. Once this happens, the social and cultural language patterns are
internalized. Berger and Luckmann created this model of simultaneous processes because
they noted that the leading linguistic models only focused on linguistic codes. What is
important about their model is that it establishes a relationship between meaning and
form and it implies a resolution of the dichotomy between epistemology (knowledge
structures) and ontology (world of things). This model also accounts for the triadic sign
proposed by Peirce (1955) in which an the content of a sign is split into two parts: one is
connected to an object in the real world (ontology) and the other is connect to the effect
of the sign in the mind of a potential interpreter (Noth, 1995). The dynamic interaction
between the externalizing of epistemological markers of feeling, ideas, and concepts and
the internalization of ontological markers (indices, icons, symbols and cultural artifacts)
emerge as socio-cultural practices. They constitute reality-loops in that they form bonds
between epistemic signs that are externalized as ontological forms and vice versa.
Something that is socially constructed and participates in reality-loops is considered to be
real and meaningful. In the philosophy of structural communication, meanings are
externalized and expressed as ontological forms. These same forms are also interpreted
and internalized as epistemic signs. What is important about these reality-loops is that
they involve both form and
content. One cannot exist
without the other.
Ontological signs are created
during the process of
semiosis (sign making) and
during the process of
structural hermeneutics (sign-
interpretation). The former is
characteristically associated
with the creation of
ontological signs and the
latter with epistemological
signs. Hence, there are two
kinds of social and cultural
relations associated with
signs. Hence, there are two
kinds of culture: one is
associated with the structure
of meaning (epistemology) and is called culture in the mind (Shore, 1996) and the other
can be found as the expression or the externalization of ideas (ontology) and is called
cultural materialism (Harris, 2001).
5
The process of taking meanings and making them into tangible and visible forms
(language, art, architecture, music, dance, and social behavior) is called Structural
Semiosis. Once a form has been externalized, it exists as an ontological marker (index,
icon, or symbol), At this stage, it is objectified and is treated as an object. The reverse pr
ocess of taking objects and assigning meaning to them is known as structural
hermeneutics. These patterns of externalization and internalization form reality-loops.
Together, they constitute the social construction of reality (St. Clair, 2006). There are a
myriad of such reality-loops that make up the culture of the mind (epistemology) and the
culture of material form (ontology). It is this dynamic interaction between the two realms
(epistemology and ontology) that was the focus of activity theory (Leontiev, 1979). It
was the connection of the ego pole of the self to the object pole of reality that was the
focus of the phenomenology of Husserl (1980). Reality-loops affirm cognitive interaction
with the human environment.They create ontological markers through the externalization
of concepts and develop knowledge frameworks in the process of internalizing them.
This activity creates a bond between the subjective realm of epistemology and the
objective realm of ontology. However, the interpretant in this model differs from that of
Peirce in that an interpretant is required in structural semiosis (from meanings to objects)
and another interpretant is involved in the process of structural hermeneutics (from object
to meaning).
6
Structural Semiosis Structural Hermeneutics
This is the process of taking an
This is the process of taking a ontological form and providing
Function meaning and providing it with an it with meaning (placing it
ontological form. within a system of meaningful
forms)
Property semiosis interpretation
Transition from meaning to form from form to meaning
from the epistemological realm to from the ontological realm to
Mapping
the ontological realm the epistemological realm
Symbolic Interactionism Ethnomethodology
Realm Epistemological Ontological
Social Practices are tied to
System Meaning are tied to reality-loops
ontological markers
How practices within the
How meanings function within an sociology of everyday life
Function
epistemological system function within an ontological
system
One can best understand how these systems operate by considering the difference
between two sociological theories: symbolic interactionism (Blumer, 1969; Adler and
Adler, 1980) and ethnomethodology (Garfinkel, 1967; Mehan and Wood, 1975). When
Blumer (1969) coined the term "symbolic interactionism" he used it to demonstrate how
people act toward things based on the meaning those things have for them. He also noted
that these meanings are derived from social interaction and modified through
interpretation. What is important about this concept is for the purpose of renovating sign
theory is that it is housed within the realm of epistemology. Symbolic interactionism has
to do with meanings and meaning systems. Whether one is creating forms from meaning
or interpreting forms in order to assign them meaning, the focus is, nevertheless, on
meaning. Ethnomethodology, on the other hand, is concerned with the procedures by
which that social order is produced, and shared. It has to do with the meaningful,
patterned, and orderly character of everyday life. Itis is something that one must work to
achieve and this means that one has a method for doing so. Hence, ethnomethodology
belongs to the realm of ontology. Symbolic Interactionism Ethnomethodology Realm
Epistemological Ontological System Meaning are tied to reality-loops Social Practices
are tied to ontological markers Function How meanings function within an
epistemological system How practices within the sociology of everyday life function
within an ontological system What is important about this dichotomy between meaning
systems and social practices is that the study of culture exists within and across these two
realms. One cannot describe a culture only from an epistemological perspective. It must
include the objects, things, behaviors, and social patterns created by that culture. A
system of meanings based on signs is the original meaning of the dyadic sign of Saussure
(1974). With the addition of the ontological realm, one can map an epistemological
system into objects in the ontological realm. This is the rationale behind material
7
cultures. Hence, one can describe a culture in terms of its system of meanings as well of
its system of social practices, cultural artifacts, and social scripts. The problem with such
a systemic analysis, however, takes on a very different concept of system when signs
function not as exosemiotic processes but as endosemiotic processes (Gudwin, 1996).
What one finds in endosemiotic processes are closed systems in which communication
takes place between the compontents of the system through a system of signs. This
system could be a mathematical system (Gudwin, 2002), a computational system
(Gudwin, 1996), an organizational system (Van Heusen and Jorna, 2002), or a
biosemiological system (Barbieri, 2003). Endosemiotic systems differ substantially from
exosemiotic systems in their mapping functions. It is now time to consider how the
concept of self form reality-loops. It is by means of reality-loops that the two realms are
integrated as sign systems.
2.6 REALITY-LOOPS
As noted earlier, the concept of reality-loops is characteristically associated with a
structural philosophy of communication. The processes of Externalization and
Internalization espoused by Berger and Luckmann (1966) have been revised and
recodified. The process of taking meanings and externalizing them into tangible and
visible forms (language, art, architecture, music, dance, and social behavior) begins with
Structural Semiosis. Once a form has been externalized, it exists as an ontological sign. It
is objectified and becomes associated with ontology as an entity within a system of
entities. The reverse process of taking objects and internalizing them by assigning
meaning to them begins as structural hermeneutics. Hence, both structural semiosis and
structural hermeneutics are part of an internal system of signs referred to as the structural
philosophy of communication. These patterns of externalization and internalization are
stablished as bonds of practical consciousness, they form reality-loops. Together, they
constitute the social construction of reality. What is socially or culturally real is that
which has been socially constructed to interface with the ontological realm and the
navigation and the negotiation of meanings in that realm is profoundly related to the
epistemological realm. There are a myriad of such reality-loops that make up the culture
of the mind (epistemology) and culture expressed in material form (ontology).
8
2.7 PHEMONENOLOGY OF REALITY-LOOPS
Peirce (1955) argued that one of the divisions within philosophy consists of the
study of phenomena (the world of appearances). This follows the Kantian distinction
between Noumena (things that cannot be known of the real world) and Phenomena
(things that can be known of the real world (Kant, 2000). Why is this important? It is
significant because Peirce argued that all that one can know of the real world is its
appearances, its qualities. He placed a high value on the role of qualities in his model of
semiotics. Out of the nine categories that Kant developed in his philosophy of pure
reason, Peirce only kept three of them and the most important of these was that of quality
which he referred to as Firstness (the domain of thought that governs qualities). Another
reason why Peirce places a high premium on qualities can be found in his definition of
reality. It is a term, he argues (House and Kloesel, 1998), that was invented in the
thirteenth century to signify having properties. Hence, he argued that “real” is a way to
say that a thing is real if its predicates are true. Although he makes a distinction between
existence and reality,
9
be found in human languages. Its qualities can be described as adjectives’ the things that
are occur in the ontological realm are designated as nouns or substantives; nd its actions
are best described in terms of verbs. Unfortunately, Peirce limited his ontological markers
to qualities. He should have included nouns, verbs, adjectives, adverbs, aspect markers,
and other basic grammatical forms into his theory of categories. Another difference
between Peirce and the philosophy of structural communication has to do with the
concept of the interpretant. It is a vague term created by Peirce that needs to be further
articulated. There is agency involved in the creation of ontological markers (structural
poesis) and there is agency involved in the interpretation of previously formed
ontological markers (structural hermeneutics). They are not the same. The first is
associated with the human ego and the latter with the social self. They do different things
and perform different functions. The human ego is associated with creativity. It is
associated with feelings, moods, thoughts, and ideas. When one attempts to externalize
these epistemological markers, they are limited by linguistic codes. The richness that
exists within the system is difficult to articulate due to the given limitations of language
codes (grammar, morphology, syntax, semantics). The social self, on the other hand, is
connected with adjusting to the social environment. It must deal with social roles, social
scripts, and other forms of practical knowledge. There is a disparity between these two
forms of self and the ego must learn to adjust to the social self. Society functions as a
parent and the ego as a child (parent-child relationship). The concept of the individual
presented in this essay involves three main components: the ego, the biographical self,
and the social self. The ego contains the id. This inclusion of the id within the ego is
necessary as it plays an important role in works of Jacques Lacan (Mcgowan, Restuccia,
and Kunkle, 2004). The role of the social self is well known as it plays a central role in
symbolic interactionism (Hewitt, 1976). What is different in this model of the self can be
found in the placement of the biographical self interacting between the ego and the social
self. The biographical self provides an individual with a sense of his own personal
history. It forms the basis for the construction of the social self and it is the source of
most of human agency. It provides the individual with the self as a psychological object.
Another difference between Peirce and the current model has to do with ontology.It is
treated as an endosystem much in the way that it is done within the philosophy of the
embodied mind (Merleau-Ponty, 1942, 1945, 1964; Lakoff and Johnson, 1999;
Rodriguez, St. Clair, and Joshua, 2005). There are biological transducers that connect
human beings to their environments. These transducers create special epistemological
markers within the human being. These markers are further organized by modules
(Fodor, 1983). Hence, there are no simple isomorphic mappings between the endosystem
and the morphological markers. In this model, the concept of recursive signs as proposed
by Peirce will not work.
10
understanding played a major role in his model of interpreting texts. He noted that
people interpret texts in two ways: one is grammatical and the other is psychological.
With a focus on the latter process, he defined hermeneutics as the art of moving inside
the thought of another person and understanding their thought from that perspective.
Gadamer (1989: 197) found this approach to hermeneutics to be rather limiting because it
only focused on the historical worldview of these texts. Consequently, he was not able to
transcend the interpretation of these texts. He was limited by his focus on psychology.
Wilhelm Dilthey (1966, 1970) saw in hermeneutics the possibility of establishing a
framework for the human sciences (die Geisteswissenschaften). Disciplines, he argued,
are created by human beings. They have an espistemology. Dilthey made a distinction
between explanations (Erklärung) and understanding (Verstehen). The process, he
reasoned, takes place from the inner life of understanding to the outer life of forms that
are used as explanations. The natural sciences are content with explanations but the
human sciences require understanding. In addition, the human sciences are temporal.
They understand themselves in what they create historically. They create things as
expressions of life. For Dilthey, language provides the fullest expression of human life.
Although Dilthey made an imporovement to the study of hermeneutics, Gadamer felt that
he was still concerned with deciphering the historical past and not involved in
understanding the human experience. He placed too heavy an emphasis on historicality.
Gadamer’s ideas on hermeneutics are close to those of Martin Heidegger (1927)
in that he sees understanding as the way in which human beings exist in the world and
not as a method for grasping psychological or historical meaning. Every act of
interpretation, Gadamer argues, is based on human understanding. Furthermore,
understanding is ontological. It is an integral part of being.
11
3.5 HISTORICAL CONSCIOUSNESS
One’s knowledge of a historical event is characterized by distance. The past is
objectified and task of historical consciousness is to reconstruct the world of the
historical object in order to grasp its meaning. This is what Schleiermacher did with his
method of hermeneutics. He wanted to return to the original circumstances in order to
grasp its meaning. Because human beings are finite and historical beings, they can never
return to such original circumstances. Hence, Gadamer (1989: 168-169) says that one
must inegrate these past events into contemporary life. He accomplishes this through
what Heidegger halls fore-having (Vorhabe). In order to understand a thing, one must
have the thing in advance. Every interpretation involves a fore-concept (Vorgriff). Every
understanding must already be a part of a decision on how to perceive that thing
(Gadamer, 1989: 269). Everything, he claims, has this fore-sight (Vorsicht) and this is
what makes understanding possible (Gadamer, 1988: 276). This assemblage of ideas is
similar in many ways to the concept of conceptual frames used in cognitive linguistics
(Lakoff, 2004). A frame is a mental construct that influence thinking. It sets up a
situation and then provides scenarios that operate within that configuration. Certain
words invoke that frame. If one denies a frame, the frame continues to exist. Hence, the
frame is a structure that the concept carries with it to provide content to that frame.
Cognitive linguistics, however, goes beyond frames and includes metaphors that are used
through analogical reasoning to create concepts and the frames that contain them. It
should be noted that the avatar of frame analysis is Erving Goffman (1986).
3.5 TRADITION
Gadamer states that tradition is really a part of being human. He expresses this
concept of tradition as the handing over of the past (überlieferung) because the past is
always present within a tradition. Hence, people should be addressed within their
tradition. Historical consciousness recognizes that it is part of a living tradition and that
it was formed by that tradition. What this means for Gadamer that the subject as a
knower does not act in the Cartesian sense, but only participates in an event within a
tradition. If one is to fully understand the language of a community, then one must come
from the tradition in which that language was spoken. However, a tradition is also alien
and strange and hermeneutic consciousness requires a play (Spiel) between familiarity
and strangeness. In other words, it requires interpretive distance that facilitates the
filtering out of understanding across disparate horizons. It requires a fusion of these
horizons (Horzontverschmetzung). . It should be noted that play for Gadamer is a mode
of being-in-the-world. One loses himself in play; he does not objectify it and hold it at a
distance. When one is absorbed in play, he is no longer a subject. He acts the play. He
enjoys a sense of freedom associated with being-in-the-world even though plays have
rules because play is a form of self-representation. One represents himself for someone.
In play, one is transformed. He becomes a different person. Each celebration in art,
music, or drama is a repetition in which the past is brought into the present and made
contemporary. The original essence is always something different (Gadamer, 1989: 123).
12
When one interprets another culture, one does so through language. All
interpretation presupposes language. This is because the medium of human experience is
language. One is situataed within language and a translator is a person who is
comfortable in the laguages being translated. He makes what is spoken in one language
intelligible in another. He finds the best way to make the subject that he is translating
intelligible in the second language. For Gadamer (1989: 388), language is not a tool. For
an example of how language is used as a tool, one should look at the work of Serge
Vygotsky (1963; 1978)
For Vygotsky, intelligence had to do with the capacity to learn from instruction with
tools. Hence, the teacher plays a central role in this context. The teacher is there to help
the student go beyond his current level of competence. Hence, intelligence is an index of
what a student can do and is capable of doing while interacting with adults. The move
from the present level of development to the new potential level of development is called
the Zone of Proximal Development (ZPD). This zone is too difficult for a child to
manage alone and for this reason it is done with a mentor, a teacher, helping adult. The
use of apprenticeship in education is called scaffolding. The teacher helps the student to
move to the next rung on the ladder of ZPD.
X Transitional Stage, Y
Old Configuration Guided by Instruments of New Configuration
Knowledge
One moves from position X to position Y with the help of a mentor or teacher. The task is
determined by the teacher as a ZPD. One the task is accomplished, a new task is
arranged. This series of tasks is called “scaffolding.”
Gadamer argues that language goes beyond being an instrument of thought, it is the
medium of thought. Just as the air that one breathes is a medium in which one lives, so
too is language a medium in which ones thinks and lives. Humans exist in the medium of
language. It is the preferred object of interpretation (Gadamer, 1989: 389). Objects have
a being in language. The process of understanding is fundamentally one of
linguisticality. Hence, when one enters into a language one is bound by its horizons.
3.7 FACTUALNESS
13
The object of understating has its life within language. Gadamer reduces all
understanding to language. It is the real medium of human beings. Language is a mirror
of culture. It constitutes a Zeitgeist. If something is factual, it is because it is recognized
and deemed to be a significant by humans. The world that comes into language is a
world that is significant to humans (Gadamer, 1988: 456). Factualness shows that human
beings do not control the world of their experience. Humans facilitate the development
and the growth of the world by things. Things and people are able to enter into language
and so become a part of the human world. It is in language that the human world is
disclosed. Linguisticality constitutes human communication. Language is the horizon of
all experience. One belongs to language. It is the space of human belonging
(Zugehörigkeit). Through language, one is taken into a common world that is shared with
others. It is a space in which people belong together. It is a wold in which subjects are
not isolated. It is a non-Cartesian world.
14
Portuguese immigrants from the Azores in the 19th century, Hawaiian music took on a
new style with the arrival of the braga from Portugal and the cavaquinho from Brazil.
These were the prototype for the Hawaiian instrument known as the ukulele. Finally, the
slack-key guitar became an integral part of Hawaiian music. By the time that Charles
King wrote the Hawaiian Wedding Song, tonal music was already a part of Hawaiian
music culture. Hence, the Wedding Song is written from the perspective of Western
culture. It is written as tonal music. Obviously, the two horizons can be merged because
they were already similar to each other. If this song were to be done as a mele hula, for
example, the disparity between their ethnomusicology would make translation rather
difficult.
15
I will string and bind
Me ke ala pua pikake
Like the fragrant jasmine flower
A o `oe ku`u pua (`O `oe ku`u pua)
You are my blossom (you, my blossom)
Ku`u pua lei lehua (lehua)
My lei of lehua (lehua)
A`u e li`a mau nei ho`opa`a
My desire is always to be with and close
Ia iho k ealoha
To my love
He lei (he lei)
My lei (my lei)
`Oe na`u (`oe na`u)
You're mine
He lei `oe na`u
My lei, you're mine
Hawaiian differs from English with regard to word order. It would appear that this is a
problem, but it is not. Hawaiian is a verb initial language (VSO) in which the subject (S)
occurs before the object (O). English is a verb initial language (VSO) in its deep
structure but a verb medial language (SVO) in its service structure. Hence, the
placements of elements within a sentence differ in a predictable manner. Both, for
example place their question markers (QM) at the beginning of the sentence.
Hawaiian English
Word Order [Ua ‘ike] [ke kanaka] [‘i ke ali’i’] [The man] [saw] [the chief]
Saw the man OM the chief S V O
V S O
What is different between these languages, however, is their patterns of stress. Hawaiian
is a syllable-timed language. It has a staccato rhythm. English, on the other hand, is a
stress-timed language and is places a heavy emphasis on certain positions within word
phrases. This problem was overcome by the composer of the song by diminishing the
chanting rhythm of the Hawaiian language and replacing it with more melodic tones.
Once again a translation has taken place but at the expense of the source language.
English grammatical terminology is based on Latin which marks events as either being
completed or not-completed. A completed event is marked by the Latin perfective and a
non-completed event is marked by the imperfect. In the Romance languages derived
from Latin, one finds the same grammatical terminology and it is concomitant with the
16
Latin concept of the perfect and the imperfect aspect markers.
Perfective Imperfective
Latin The action was carried out The action was not carried
out
Spanish Cantó (he sang) Cantaba (he was singing)
Hawaiian English
e + Verb + nei
Present Tense ke hana nei au I work
Present Iterative ke hana nei au I am working
e + Verb + ana
Past Iterative e hana ana au I was working
ua + Verb
Past Tense ua hana au I worked
Present Durative ua hana au I have worked
17
ua + Verb + e
Past Durative ua hana e au I had worked
i + Verb
Past Tense i hana au I worked
(used in negative
constructions)
Nominative i hana Having worked
e +Verb
Future Tense e hana au I will work
e + Verb
Imperative e hana au You work!
The aforementioned chart on Hawaiian verbs and aspect markers is confusing because
Hawaiian is a language that is not overly concerned with durative and iteratives.
However, it turns out to be just the opposite. In Hawaii, one is concerned with whether an
action is completed or not completed but it is not overly concerned with tense. That is,
aspect markers show whether the verb is completed or incomplete. Hence, aspect markers
do not indicate tense outright; they are used to create equivalent structures to
tenses. Obviously, the Latin terminology of perfect and imperfect aspect makes more
sense for Hawaiian than it does for English.
Hawaiian Aspect
E +verb + ana + Subject Incomplete action, state not achieved
Verb + Subject Completed action, achieved state
No aspect marker + Verb + Subject Simple present tense, generic and timeless
i + Verb + Subject Completed action, achieved state
Another more functional kind of aspect has to do with the proximity that one has from the
speaker. These are used with present tense markers.
Hawaiian English
Close to the Speaker ke + Verb + nei Speaking to the person here
Distant from the Speaker ke + Verb + ala Speaking to the person there
More distant from the Speaker ke + Verb + la Speaking to the person over there
18
this conflation of tense and aspect.
These examples are indicative of the problems associated with the translation from a
polynesian language into a Germanic Creole (English).
19
Agency in this rehabilitated model of semiotics includes the Id, the Ego, and the
Superego. The Id plays a minor role in this model, but the Ego functions as the Self and
the Superego functions as the Social Self. The socially constructed self is an expansion of
the Mirror Self in Lacan (1999). What began as the mirror image model of the self is
transformed over time into a socially constructed model of the self. In the aforementioned
figure, it portrays the self as an artist who is part of an intellectual community. He models
himself for that community. It is his cognitive frame. His social scenarios are addressed
to that community. His works of art (structural semiosis) is addressed to that group. His
interpretations of art (structural hermeneutics) are based on that audience. Since there are
many frames in ones social life, the interaction of the self is best expressed in terms of
graph theory in which there are vertices and edges associated with aristocratic circles of
contacts and plebian contacts in small world theory (Chartrand, 1985; Watts and Duncan,
1998).
The vertices, in this case, do not represent people, but cognitive frames. The activities
20
within those frames are articulated social scripts. Traditional semiotics cannot handle
this kind of complexity in dealing with the interface between meaning systems and
ontological forms or expressions.
21
Rene Descartes (1999) placed too strong an emphasis on self-consciousness. This
led Edmund Husserl (1965) to attempt to transcend the ego and account for the existence
of the world. He argued that ideas are real (Husserl, (1962) because they involve
intention. Heidegger (1927) redefined the experience of being human away from man as
a rational being into one who is a being-in-the-world. He did not want to accept human
beings as agents in the world and focused his attention on the experiences of being.
Gadamer (1989) had a philosopher that was similar to Heidegger but his concern was
with using hermeneutics as a method to arrive at his truth of the world. What has
happened in this transition from Descartes, the father of modern philosophy, to Gadamer,
a postmodern philosopher, is a denial of the significance of self-consciousness and
agency in language. He argued that language is not a tool. Tools require human agents.
Instead, he placed great emphasis on language being a medium of human experience.
The model of structural philosophy proposed by St. Clair (2010) argues that agency has a
role in human experience. Postmodernism cannot divorce itself from modernism.
Human beings are agents in the world as well as beings-in-the-world. The limitations of
philosophical hermeneutics are most evident in the debate between Habermas (1985) and
Gadamer. Science and technology are part of being human. There are more avenues to
knowledge than those provided only by language. However, language is a primary
instrument of thought as well as a medium of thought. This is why the concept of reality-
loops go well beyond the linking of thought and experience. They constitute the social
construction of reality.
This essay began with the realization that traditional semiotics could not
adequately be used as an instrument of translation and interpretation across linguistic
communities. The work of Gadamer on philosophical hermeneutics was used to
investigate how language and experience are involved in the experience of being human.
Although Gadamer did not see language as an instrument of thought, it is. It is also a
medium of human experience. Both are required in translation. The social self plays a
strong role in the social construction of self. Agency may be human, but it is also social.
People act in the presence of others. They exist for others. Intentionality is connected
both to agency and to the experience of being-in-the-world. Language, it has been argued
(Rodrigues, St. Clair, and Joshua, 2005)) is provides human beings with schemas, frames,
and the modern equivalent of the Kantian categories.
6.0 REFERENCES
Adler, Peter and Patricia Adler. (1980). "Symbolic Interactionism." In Jack Douglas,
Patricia Adler, Peter Adler, Andrea Fontana, C. Robert Freeman, and Joseph A.
Katorba (Eds.), Introduction to the Sociologies of Everyday Life. Boston, Mass.:
Allyn and Bacon.
Arnheim, Rudolf. (1988). The Power of the Center: A Study of Composition in the Visual
Arts. Berkeley: University of California Press.
22
Barbieri M. (2003). The Organic Codes: An Introduction to Semantic Biology.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Berger, Peter and Thomas Luckmann. (1966). The Social Construction of Reality.
Garden City, New York: Anchor Books.
Debord, G. (1995). The society of the spectacle. Cambridge, MA: Zone Books.
23
Schleiermacher's system as philosophy. Second part: Schleiermacher's system
as theology.] Aus d. Nachl. hrsg. und Einführung Martin Redeker
(Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht)
Dondis, Donis A. (1972). A Primer of Visual Literacy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Durkheim, Émile. The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life. (1915). Translated by
Joseph Ward Swain. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd.
Durkheim, Emile. (1984) The Division of Labor in Society. NY: The Free Press.
Fodor, Gerald. (1983). The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge, MA: The MIT press.
Gadamer, Hans-Georg. (1989), Truth and Method, 2nd rev. edn. (1st English edn,
1975), trans. by J. Weinsheimer and D.G.Marshall, New York: Crossroad.
24
Harris, Marvin. (2001) Cultural Materialism: The Struggle for a Science of Culture.
New York: Thomas Y. Crowell Company.
Heidegger, Martin. (1927.) Sein und Zeit. Translated as Being and Time by John
Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. Oxford: Basil Blackwell,.
Hewitt, John P. (1976). Self and Society: A Symbolic Interactionist Social Psychology.
Boston: Allyn and Bacon
Houser, Nathan and Kloesel, Christian, (Eds.). (1998). The Essential Peirce. Selected
Philosophical Writings. Vol. 1 (1867-1893), 1992, vol. 2 (1893-1913),. Bloomington and
Indianapolis, Indiana: Indiana University Press.
Husserl, Edmund. (1962). Ideas. (Translation of Ideen auf einer reinen Phänomenologie
und phänomenologischen Philosophie) New York, Collier Books.
Jones, L. Y. (1981). Great expectations: America and the baby boom generation. New
York: Ballantine.
King, Charles E. (1926, 1943). The Hawaiian Wedding Song. Honolulu, Hawaii: King's
Blue Book
Lakoff, George. (2004). Don’t Think of an Elephant: Know Your Values and Frame the
Debate. White River Junction, VT: Chelsea Green Publishings.
Lakoff, George and Johnson, Mark. (1999). Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied
25
Mind and Its Challenge to Western Thought. NY: Basic Books.
Mcgowan, Todd, Restuccia, Frances L., and Sheila Kunkle. (Editors). (2004). Lacan
and Contemporary Film. NY: Other Press, LLC.
Mehan, Hugh and Houston Wood. (1975). The Reality of Ethno-methodology. New
York: John Wiley and Sons.
Peirce, Charles Sanders. (1955). Philosophical Writings of Peirce. Selected and edited
with an introduction by Justus Buchler. New York: Dover Publications.
Rodríguez, Walter E., St. Clair, Robert N., and Irving Joshua. (2005). Esquemas
fisiológicos, creación cognitiva y el teatro de la mente encarnada. Círculo de
Linguística Aplicada a la Comunicación 21, febrero.
http://www.ucm.es/info/circulo/no21/esquemas.htm Saussure, Ferdinand de. (1916).
Cours de linguistique générale Paris: Payot.
St. Clair, Robert N. and Song, Wei. (2009). The Many Layers of Culture within each
City: A Theory of Cultural Geography. New York: Lewiston. The Edwin Mellon
Press.
St. Clair, Robert N. (2006). Language and the Sociology of Knowledge. New York:
Lewiston. The Edwin Mellon Press.
St. Clair, Robert N. 2002. The Major Metaphors of European Thought – Growth, Game,
Language, Drama, Machine, Time and Space. NY: Edwin Mellen Press.
St. Clair, R. N., Thomé-Williams, A. C., and Su, L. (2005). The Role of Social Script
Theory in Cognitive Blending. Intercultural Communication Studies XIV (1).
26
Schleiermacher, Friedrich. (1998). Hermeneutics and Criticism, And Other
Writings. Translated and edited by Andrew Bowie. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Shore, Brad. (1996) Culture in Mind: Cognition, Culture, and the Problem of Meaning.
Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
Van Husen, B. and Jorna, R. J. (2002). "Reconsidering the Standard: A Semiotic Model
of Organizations." In K. Liu, R. J. Calrke, P. B. Anderson & R. K. Stamper
(Editors), Coordination and Communication using Signs: Studies in
Organizational Semiotics 2. Dordrecht: Klluwer Academic Publishers. Pages 153-
167.
Vygotsky. L. S. (1963). Thought and Language. Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press. 1963
Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in Society: The Development of Higher Psychological
Processes. Cambridge, Harvard University Press. .
Watts, Duncan J.; Strogatz, Steven H. (June 1998). "Collective dynamics of 'small-world'
networks". Nature 393 (6684): 440–442.
27